DRAFT VERSION The Problems with Renouncing Power One method of empowering students has been to renounce (denounce?) the instructor’s power in the classroom. In this method, instructors hand over some measure of their classroom control: syllabi creation, grade determination, collaborative learning, and other manifestations of instructor power. Bartholomae has already discussed many problems with removing the instructor–student power differential from academic writing. Its limitations are something that critical-democratic instructors do not refute; Shor, for example, acknowledges that “the critical-democratic character of such pedagogy is limited by the institutional authority I bring to the class and by the institutional setting which frames our work (such as the requirement that I give letter grades)” (pp. 74). Though the classroom Shor and his students create is probably one of the truest examples of critical pedagogy, he cannot deny the limitations of an institutionalized setting. The limits come into stark reality over the issue of grading, and he explains: “But, still, the critical-democratic character of such pedagogy is limited by the institutional authority I bring to the class and by the institutional setting which frames our work (such as the requirement that I give letter grades)” (pp. 74). When outside power structures reveal the limits of his critical-democratic classroom, he spends several passages confronting his discomfort with his own power. Similarly, Straub and Lunsford Most of the problems that manifest from renouncing power stem from its artificiality. As Shor acknowledged (pp. 74), the instructor retains many forms of power in a classroom setting—even a critical-democratic classroom. Temporally, the instructor has generative power to choose the type of pedagogy students will experience in the class, maintenance power as the “expert” in the room, and final “veto power” over students’ ideas in the form of grades. Physically, the instructor retains power through their location in the room, mannerisms, and “outsider” body (clothing, age, and socioeconomic status come to mind). Shor notices, for example, that even his presence in a “democratically” circularstructure room displaces students who want to be away from the locus of control (pp. 65), and he uses his physical presence to redirect students who have gone “off topic” during collaborative group work (pp. 48). This artificiality leads to the second problem: student rejection. Students resist indoctrination into a power structure unless it is something they achieve for themselves. Shor notes this happens even with his critical-democratic pedagogy: “As the teacher, I am inviting and allowing the students to practice democracy rather than they having won this right for themselves…. This makes power-sharing and social critique risky Utopian leaps for them….” (pp.74, emphasis in original). Unless students achieve power through some struggle, they mistrust it and resist it as something coming from a power source. Students usually resist indoctrination through forms of “underlife.” Underlife, as paraphrased from Brooke, consists of the undisclosed1 acts of resistance to the normative roles resulting from a power differential (1987). In fact, Brooke locates critical pedagogy Brooke might call these acts “unconscious,” but I prefer “undisclosed” because they are not entirely unconscious—some are even premeditated. However, even premeditated acts often remain unvoiced: subordinates and superiors rarely discuss their strategies of resistance with each other. 1 itself as a disruptive form of underlife (overtly disrupting the power structure) enacted by instructors (pp. 723 and 728). He also identifies three student acts that constituted contained underlife behaviors (resisting roles without demanding radical change to the structure): creative use of classroom ideas, game playing, and evaluations of the classroom (pp. 723 and 724–728).2 Brooke calls for making the underlife acts conscious—indeed, he claims that making students “conscious of their differences from their normal roles” is the goal of writing instruction (pp. 731). But the third problem of teachers renouncing power is that we cannot make students’ strategies conscious (in my term, “voiced”) unless we acknowledge their efforts as legitimate rhetorical acts. Bartholome (1985) astutely notes that students continually strategize to adapt to the discourse community of their different instructors (pp. 606). In doing so, he notes that they simultaneously appropriate the discourse and are appropriated by the discourse community. This link is important. When instructors disdain the significance of their own power in a classroom, they simultaneously dismiss the significant underlife strategies students have taken to negotiate the instructor–student power structure. This dismissal is phrased in many ways: for examples, “Many have learned to manipulate the teacher for a good grade by mimicking the teacher’s opinions” (Shor, 1996, pp. 51). “When the teacher makes his agenda for a piece of writing known, the student is likely to attempt to give the teacher what he wants. Why should she do otherwise?” (Straub & Lunsford, 1995, pp. 8). “[College students] spend many hours in school mastering Engfish. The fact that the teacher and the textbook sometimes employe Engfish suggests to them that it’s the official language of the school. They’re learning a new language that prevents them from working toward truths…” (Macrorie, 1985, pp. 299). In these dismissals is disdain for our own academic discourse communities—our own power. Because we find our “Engfish” commonplace, boring, unimaginative, we forget to legitimize the skill students display in “playing” this “game.” The skill becomes a parlor trick—we intone Plato to our students’ Sophists. And we dismiss their strategies, closing the issue without genuine discussion of their merits. If the skills stay unconscious, they become mindless 3. And here is the fourth problem with renouncing our power. Keeping our students’ skills unconscious means we cannot help students learn how to generalize them mindfully and apply them into other power contexts. Bruffee, in discussing “normal” discourse, notes that most discourse happens between peers, and this is why collaborative learning is important (1984). But a great deal of professional discourse happens between subordinates and superiors, and all professional discourse happens within a power structure: someone—the boss, the 2 Many other scholars note students’ underlife resistance, though they do not use that term. In discussing the Siberia Syndrome, for example, Shor notes that students’ dissociation with the instructor (intellectually and physically) is a form of active resistance (pp. 1-28). 3 I’m borrowing this term from Fulkerson, who applied it to what happens when instructors work from unconscious pedagogical values (1979). customer, the editor of a journal—has final “veto power” over a writer’s ideas. The instructor, in a classroom setting, is the expression of these superiors, and students already know how to deal with instructors. Only by legitimizing students’ strategies and incorporating the instructor–student dynamic into our process can we help students generalize the rhetorical skills they already have, develop them further, and apply them elsewhere. FINAL VERSION Problems with Renouncing Power The critical-democratic or “liberatory” method (defined by Shor, 1996) of empowering students has been to confront the instructor’s power in the classroom. In this method, instructors often renounce some measure of their classroom control (e.g., syllabi creation or grade formulation). Shor, for example, gave as much power as he could to his students (1996). Straub and Lunsford, too, claimed that the worst thing an instructor can do is appropriate students’ writing (1995, p. 10). Bruffee supported collaborative learning for its ability to break down instructors’ control (1984). I want to be clear that I agree with the idea of empowering students, including using several of the techniques these scholars suggest. But I also agree with Bartholomae that attempts to remove the instructor–student power differential have fundamental flaws. Briefly, they include (from the most fundamental, or covert, to the most symptomatic, or overt): 1. An “empowering” classroom is artificial. Bartholomae (1985), Bizzell (----), and Trimbur (1994) pointed out that instructors cannot fully empower students within a classroom because the classroom is a fundamentally disempowering. The instructor has generative power to choose the type of pedagogy students will experience in the class, maintenance power as the “expert” in the room, and final “veto power” over students’ ideas in the form of grades. 2. Students resist indoctrination into a power structure unless it is genuine (something they achieve for themselves), so they ultimately reject artificial empowerment and the lesson(s) that come with it. Durst discussed a study he did on a politically oriented English class, where he “found students extremely resistant to the view advocated by the instructor and the course reader…. Students sought and found ways of choosing topics that allowed them to avoid the political subject matter at the center of the course” (as cited in Durst, 2006, p. 1663). 3. Loathing our own power means we do not acknowledge students’ strategies as legitimate rhetorical acts, so we never make them conscious. Brooke claims that making students “conscious of their differences from their normal roles” should be the goal of writing instruction (1987, pp. 731). Because we find our academic discourse commonplace, boring, unimaginative (Marcorie, 1985), we belittle the rhetorical skill students display in “playing the game,” and we dismiss their strategies without genuine discussion of their merits. 4. Keeping students’ skills unconscious means we cannot help students learn how to generalize them consciously and apply them within other power contexts. I should note that critical-democratic instructors recognize these limitations; for example, Shor acknowledged that “the critical-democratic character of such pedagogy is limited by the institutional authority I bring to the class and by the institutional setting which frames our work (such as the requirement that I give letter grades)” (1996, p. 74). But such acknowledgements do not embrace the power structures inherent in all professional writing. Only by legitimizing students’ strategies and incorporating the instructor–student dynamic into our process can we help students generalize the rhetorical skills they already have, develop them further, and apply them elsewhere.