Paper for the Critical Perspectives on Accounting Conference, Toronto, 2014 (ref. CPA2014-202) Critical Realist Accounting Research: Whence and Whither? Sven Modell Manchester Business School University of Manchester and NHH – Norwegian School of Economics, Bergen Address: Manchester Business School University of Manchester Crawford House Booth Street West Manchester M15 6PB United Kingdom E-mail: Sven.Modell@mbs.ac.uk Acknowledgements: I am grateful for the constructive feedback and advice provided by Max Baker and Kari Lukka on an earlier version of this paper. 1 Critical Realist Accounting Research: Whence and Whither? Abstract Over the past decade, a small but growing body of accounting research explicitly informed by critical realism has started to emerge and be employed to diverse research tasks. This paper offers a review and critique of this emerging strand of accounting research against the backdrop of broader developments in the critical realist research programme in the social sciences. It is argued that the use of critical realism in the accounting literature has thus far been rather piecemeal and only partially geared towards developing an explicitly critical or politically engaged research agenda aimed at advancing radical social critique. Whilst these features can partly be traced to internal divisions within the larger critical realist project in the social sciences, I elaborate on how emerging accounting studies can be developed into a more coherent and integrative research programme drawing on diverse strands of critical realist thought. In doing so, I pay particular attention to how such research can be imbued with more clearly articulated, critical intent by incorporating explanatory critiques pivoting on the twin concepts of retroduction and retrodiction into empirically and historically informed research interventions. I discuss some implications and challenges of nurturing such an approach as a basis for critical accounting scholarship. Key words: accounting, critical realism, emancipation, explanatory critique, retroduction, retrodiction. 2 Critical Realist Accounting Research: Whence and Whither? Introduction Since its emergence in the late 1970s, critical accounting research has evolved into a vibrant area of scholarship that has benefited substantially from the incorporation of a plurality of philosophical and theoretical approaches. Whilst occasionally generating controversies about the suitability and efficacy of particular approaches for the furthering of critical scholarship (e.g., Cooper, 1997; Neimark, 1990; Tinker, 1999, 2005), there seems to be some emerging consensus that, as a whole, the field has been enriched by the flourishing of diverse strands of critical thought (Cooper and Hopper, 2007; Merino, 1998; Roslender and Dillard, 2003). Critical accounting research also continues to evolve and accommodate novel strands of research drawing on hitherto unexplored or under-utilised intellectual resources. One of the more recent research genres to emerge and generate a growing body of conceptual, methodological and empirical work is that informed by critical realism. Whilst tracing its origins to the pioneering works of Bhaskar (1975, 1979) and exercising increasing influence on cognate areas of scholarship, such as organisation and management studies (e.g., Fleetwood and Ackroyd, 2004; Reed, 2005, 2009; Tsang and Kwan, 1999; Tsoukas, 1989), the more explicit incorporation of critical realism into the accounting literature is a relatively new phenomenon. However, over the past decade a small but growing body of accounting research has started to apply it to debate paradigmatic and methodological issues (Brown and Brignall, 2007; Llewellyn, 2007; Modell, 2009, 2013, in press), examine processes of accounting change (Ashraf and Uddin, 2013; Mutiganda, 2013; Stergiou et al., 2013) and advance critical commentaries on emerging accounting policies and practices (Burrowes et al., 2004; Smyth, 2012). A number of more broadly based literature reviews have also singled out critical realism as a promising way forward for critical accounting research but do not elaborate in any greater detail on how this may materialise (Goddard, 2010; Kilfoyle and Richardson, 2011; Roslender, 2013). The present paper offers a more focused review and critique of the emerging use of critical realism in accounting research against the backdrop of broader developments in the critical realist research programme in the social sciences. It is argued that the use of critical realism in 3 the accounting literature has thus far been rather piecemeal and only partially geared towards developing an explicitly critical or politically engaged research agenda aimed at advancing radical social critique and human emancipation. This fragmented use of critical realism and lack of wholehearted embrace of its more critical dimension can partly be traced to internal divisions within the larger critical realist research programme. However, critical realism offers a philosophical approach capable of transcending some key controversies in the critical accounting literature, such as those pivoting on the varying degrees of determinism and radicalism ascribed to various research genres, whilst linking concerns with enlightenment and emancipation to a model of explanatory, social critique. Whilst the achievements of critical realism in this regard are not uncontested, I explicate how a research agenda recognising some of the major criticisms levied at it may be advanced. Key criticisms of critical realism concern its propensity to abstract from the historical contingencies conditioning the possibilities of emancipation and its relative neglect of engagement with the lived experiences of research subjects as they participate in emancipatory discourses. To address these criticisms, I elaborate on what I see as a refined notion of explanatory critique. Such critiques pivot on the mobilisation of theoretically informed explanations whilst preserving their sensitivity to the historically contingent, objective conditions as well as subjective processes of identity formation and reflexivity that shape the possibilities of emancipation. I also pay attention to the wider, epistemic premises that need to be filled if critical realist accounting research is to entail more concerted efforts to advance such explanatory critiques. The remainder of the paper proceeds as follows. I start by outlining some basic tenets of critical realism, such as its origins and ontological foundations and some key epistemological and methodological implications, and revisit critiques and debates concerning its development into a genuinely critical research programme. This leads me to specify the constitutive elements of refined explanatory critiques, which are then used as a basis for evaluating the achievements of critical realist accounting research. I conclude the paper by outlining some future directions and challenges for such research. Critical Realism 4 Origins and ontological foundations What has come to be known as critical realism originally evolved as a reaction against positivist and post-positivist research principles in the natural sciences (Bhaskar, 1975) and was subsequently extended to a critique of the applicability of such “naturalistic” principles to the social sciences (Bhaskar, 1979).1 At the heart of this critique lay a pronounced scepticism of conceptions of the social world as some immutable entity constituted by law-bound regularities which might, at least in principle, be captured and accurately explained in their entirety by some perceiving subject. Whilst not denying the existence of some objective reality whose presence is independent of our knowledge of it, Bhaskar (1975) was at pains to emphasise the separation of such intransitive objects of knowledge from the transitive realm of human beings and their senses. In contrast to the empirical realism permeating positivist research, critical realists reject the notion of human beings having some unmediated access to or knowledge of the material and social mechanisms constituting the objective, or objectified reality which they inhabit. The human senses are rarely, if ever, capable of fully capturing the workings of such mechanisms but are nevertheless affected by them and, as such, involved in filtering experiences of the mechanisms at work into particular patterns of action. Explaining the actions of human beings thus becomes a matter of understanding how objective mechanisms interact with subjective experiences and how such interactions shape the capacity and propensity for agency (Elder-Vass, 2010; Reed, 2009). To Bhaskar (1975), the key to explaining empirically observable patterns of events, such as those manifest in regularities in human action, was to situate them within a “stratified”, threetiered ontology made up of the domains of the real, actual and empirical. In the domain of the real, we find the aforementioned objective mechanisms with the capacity to generate certain patterns of events with some degree of regularity. This generative capacity resides in the causal powers inherent in particular mechanisms. However, whether such causal powers are activated often depends on the interplay between multiple mechanisms, which may both reinforce and counteract each other and thus co-determine the occurrence of specific events in the domain of the actual. For instance, particular economic mechanisms, such as wage rates, have the causal Whilst Bhaskar (1975) initially referred to his research programme as “transcendental realism”, the term critical realism has gradually come to be widely accepted among its adherents and endorsed by Bhaskar himself (see Bhaskar, 1998). 1 5 power to generate unemployment, but whether changes in unemployment actually occur also depends on the activation of causal powers embedded in other, related mechanisms, such as industrial relations regulations influencing wage movements. Hence specific events do not automatically follow from the mere existence of particular mechanisms, but rather form less law-bound regularities, or tendencies, which may or may not repeat themselves across different instances of time and space. Similarly, human beings are often only able to empirically experience a sub-set of the tendencies occurring in the domain of the actual and the underlying mechanisms and causal powers responsible for such tendencies. For instance, human beings will be able to experience certain manifestations of unemployment but are not necessarily able to fully observe and explain the full width of tendencies towards rising and falling unemployment or the exact workings of the mechanisms generating such tendencies. Tendencies towards changing unemployment can also occur without being immediately observable or knowable to individual human beings. In other words, events and tendencies occur independently of and are not necessarily conjoined with empirical experiences. Hence the need to not only distinguish actual events and tendencies from the generative mechanisms residing in the domain of the real, but also separate the domain of the actual from that of the empirical. Building on these ontological premises, a more refined understanding of how human agency interacts with objective social structures was first advanced through Bhaskar’s (1979, 1986) extension of critical realism to the social sciences and then further developed into Archer’s (1995) morphogenetic approach to social development. Whilst insisting on the notion that social structures have an objective ontological status that is independent of human experiences, Bhaskar (1979, 1986) outlined how such structures condition human agency and the propensity for social stability and change. This rests on the premise that some form of social structure always pre-exists the exercise of human agency, whilst human beings either reproduce or transform such structures through their interactions with them. Consistent with his stratified ontology, however, Bhaskar (1979, 1986) sees social structures as only partially knowable and never reducible to the people experiencing their instantiation. The prevalence of structural mechanisms with the causal powers to affect stability and change are postulated as a necessary condition for structural reproduction and transformation although such powers often depend on human beings for their activation. As such, social structures constrain as well as enable the propensity for human agency. However, structural mechanisms are still viewed as residing at an ontological level that is only partially within the realm of human cognition and influence. 6 Similar to Bhaskar (1979, 1986), Archer (1995) conceives of objectified social structures as existing at a somewhat higher level of abstraction that is distinct from the exercise of human agency but argues that both social structures and human beings have the causal power to influence particular patterns of events in society and do so by forming intricate and inherently indeterminate patterns of interaction. Archer (1995) also places more explicit emphasis on the need for human reflexivity as a precursor of agency and, by implication, structural change and persistence. Rather than being forced into particular patterns of action by the causal powers embedded in social structures, individual and groups of agents intentionally engage with such structures and thereby devise more or less deliberate strategies for their reproduction (morphostasis) or transformation (morphogenesis). Through such emergent processes of morphostasis and morphogenesis the evolution of real, objectified structures is continuously mediated by human agency. To avoid the widespread tendency to conflate notions of structure and agency in social theory, however, Archer (1995) makes a strict analytical and temporal distinction between the two. Through this separation of agency and structure tendencies towards both downwards conflation (ie. deterministic conceptions of agency as subsumed under social structures) and upwards conflation (ie. more voluntaristic conceptions of social structure as some unmediated product of agency) are eschewed. Rather, human agency is seen as an autonomous analytical entity constantly interacting with extant and emerging structures but at no point in time being fully determined by or the sole source of such structures. Also, through the temporal separation of the causal powers inherent in human beings and social structures tendencies towards central conflation, or the propensity to view agency and structure as essentially inseparable and mutually constitutive at any given point in time, are suppressed. Whilst the aforementioned works of Bhaskar and Archer provide an ontological basis for explaining how objective social structures evolve in constant interaction with human agency, Archer’s subsequent works have primarily aimed at unpacking the more subjective, actorcentric dimensions of this interplay (e.g., Archer, 2000, 2003, 2007). These works have foregrounded the inherently reflexive processes associated with agents’ deliberations on the world and how such processes generate individual strategies of social mobility and change. Of central importance in this regard are the “internal conversations” or the on-going, internal dialogues that individual human beings have with themselves about their objective life conditions and the opportunities of shaping their lives. It is through such subjective processes of identity formation that individuals make sense of the world and forge personal strategies for action. Through extensive empirical work, Archer (2003, 2007) has developed a nascent 7 typology of how individuals’ internal conversations and reflexivity manifest themselves under diverse structural conditions. Yet, these works have been criticised for ceding too much terrain to the notion that human beings possess a universal capacity for reflexivity (Elder-Vass, 2007, 2010) and underplaying the extent to which social structures shape subjective identities (Mutch, 2004) whilst paying insufficient attention to how individual agency translates into collective action (Vandenberghe, 2005). To fully address such criticisms requires some re-engagement with Archer’s (1995) earlier, conceptual discussion of how reflexivity is conditioned by evolving social structures as well as how individual and groups of agents strive to produce stability or change by coming together as collective, or corporate agents with the capacity to exercise more powerful influence on social structures. Notwithstanding Archer’s somewhat unfinished project of integrating objective social structures and processes of subjective identity formation and reflexivity into a dynamic model pivoting on their recursive and reciprocal interplay, several scholars have hailed critical realism as a promising avenue for transcending the ontological divide between empirical realism and social constructivism in the social sciences (e.g., Ackroyd and Fleetwood, 2000; Delbridge and Edwards, 2013; Elder-Vass, 2012; Fleetwood, 2004, 2005; Reed, 2005, 2009; Sayer, 2000). According to Elder-Vass (2012), critical realism offers an ontology that combines elements of moderate realism with moderate social constructivism. By insisting on the existence of objective and reasonably durable social structures possessing a degree of independence from human cognition and agency, critical realists preserve a distinctly realist identity. However, by accepting that such structures are fundamentally human constructions that are not indefinitely immutable, they also acknowledge the importance of subjectively induced agency and change. This marrying of realist and social constructivist elements also enables critical realists to eschew tendencies towards either extreme determinism or voluntarism. Whilst emergent social structures may gradually progress towards an increasingly objectified and seemingly stable state, such processes of objectification need to be conceived of as indeterminate as individual and corporate agents with a strong interest in and capacity to bring about change may, in principle, emerge at any point in time. But the capacity for human agency is never unconstrained and always conditioned by extant structures. Hence critical realism is a distinctly non-deterministic philosophy, but not one that ascribes an unbounded capacity to agents to act out their free will. 8 Judging from recent debates within the wider, inter-disciplinary accounting research community, of which critical accounting research is part 2 , there would seem to be some preparedness to accept an ontological position that combines moderate variants of realism and social constructivism (see e.g., Ahrens, 2008; Kakkuri-Knuuttila et al., 2008a, 2008b; Lukka and Modell, 2010; Modell, 2010).3 Similarly, it has long been recognised that various subgenres of critical accounting research have tended to straddle the objectivist/subjectivist divide and be less far apart than commonly assumed insofar as ontological assumptions are concerned (see e.g., Cooper and Hopper, 2007; Hopper and Powell, 1985). Nevertheless, as recurring controversies between accounting scholars with especially Marxist and post-structuralist sympathies demonstrate, there are still limits to this ontological entente. According to Neimark (1990, 1994), early post-structuralist advances drawing on Foucault, tended to present a rather caricatured version of Marxism as embodying an objectivist view of the world grounded in a rather deterministic form of historical materialism. In response to such charges, Foucaultinspired accounting scholars have sought to defend a position that foregrounds relatively indeterminate notions of subjectivity and their intertwining with evolving discursive practices without negating the existence of some objectified, material reality (Grey, 1994; Hoskin, 1994). Whilst such controversies may now have faded into the background as a result of the continuous blurring of the boundaries between various strands of critical accounting research and the waning influence of Marxism (cf. Roslender and Dillard, 2003) they have not been fully resolved. For instance, writing over a decade after their initial eruption, Tinker (2005) continued to chastise post-structuralist accounting researchers for reading too much historical determinism into Marx’s works and hence failing to recognise their radical potential, only to be rebutted by Sikka and Willmott (2005) for understating the possibilities of pursuing a more incremental agenda of social critique and change in a fundamentally indeterminate world. Through its combination of moderate realism and social constructivism, critical realism provides an ontological starting point capable of transcending such controversies. According to some commentators, it guards against overly deterministic readings of Marx (e.g., Joseph, 1998, 2002; Lovering, 1990) whilst offering a conception of social structures that is compatible The distinction between critical accounting research and the wider genre of “alternative”, or inter-disciplinary, accounting research is admittedly somewhat arbitrary (see e.g., Baxter and Chua, 2003; Roslender and Dillard, 2003). Following the definitions advanced by Chua (1986) and Hopper and Powell (1985), however, the notion of critical accounting research is here confined to areas of scholarship that are united by some explicit emancipatory intent and, by implication, ambition to advance radical social critiques and change. 3 Although there are dissenting voices cautioning against the paradigmatic rapprochement that might follow from such an ontological position, these criticisms have tended to be concerned with the epistemic and political ramifications of such rapprochement for the inter-disciplinary accounting research community rather than its philosophical tenability per se (see Parker, 2012). 2 9 with at least some post-structuralist thinkers such as Foucault (e.g., Al-Amoudi, 2007; Joseph, 2004). As we shall see later in this paper, however, neither of these paths of rapprochement is entirely uncontroversial. Nor do they automatically lead to more politically engaged scholarship. Epistemological and methodological implications Whilst the most distinguishing features of critical realism are arguably attributable to its ontology (Fleetwood, 2004, 2005), its core ontological assumptions have important epistemological and methodological implications. Most importantly, the stratified ontology underpinning critical realism prevents it from subscribing to any stronger correspondence theory of truth as an epistemological basis for explaining social phenomena (Bhaskar, 1975; Niiniluoto, 1999). Such correspondence theories of truth posit that our knowledge of the world is a direct and reasonably complete reflection of the world. To critical realists, however, such equating of the nature of the world with our knowledge of it is tantamount to committing the epistemic fallacy of treating ontological questions as epistemological ones (Archer, 2007; Bhaskar, 1975). As noted in the foregoing, critical realists reject the possibility of any unmediated conceptions of reality as a result of the inability of human beings to fully observe and explain the workings of intransitive or partially knowable mechanisms. The epistemological implication of this is to fall back on theory as an indispensable resource for making sense of how causal powers are activated in particular instances of time and space whilst accepting that any theoretical knowledge claims are always partial and only capable of explaining a sub-set of the actual and potential tendencies emanating from such powers. Rather, any knowledge of the world, regardless of how well-informed on theoretical grounds, is always under-determined and hence potentially fallible (Kaidesoja, 2007; Niiniluoto, 1999). The problem of under-determination is exacerbated by the indeterminacy of the social world when examined as an open system. Given the complex and often unique interplay between causal powers embedded in social structures and human agency, our knowledge of this interplay and its resultant tendencies needs to be conceived of as context- and time-dependent. To advance such contingent knowledge claims, researchers need to situate their theoretically informed understandings of the world in specific contexts and combine abstract theorising with empirically grounded observations (Ackroyd, 2004; Lawson, 1997; Tsoukas, 1989). However, this does not rule out the possibility of at least some causal powers being activated in such a 10 way that they generate reasonably stable or similar tendencies across time and space and allow researchers to draw more general inferences about their prevalence (Tsang and Kwan, 1999; Tsoukas, 1989). The concrete methodological procedures through which abstract theorising and empirical observations are brought together in critical realist analyses are encapsulated in the twin concepts of retroduction and retrodiction (see e.g., Elder-Vass, 2010; Lawson, 1997). Retroduction denotes the process of abstracting from empirically observable tendencies by developing theoretical postulates about what individual mechanisms might be responsible for such tendencies. In social science inquiries, this implies a process of working “backwards” from empirical observations of surface events and regularities in society to develop a theoretical understanding of the deeper social structures imbued with causal powers, or the potential, to produce particular tendencies. Retrodiction, by contrast, is the process of examining the activation of such causal powers in specific empirical contexts by asking how diverse mechanisms interact to generate particular tendencies. Returning to the example of explaining unemployment, for instance, we may initiate retroductive theorising by identifying wage rates and industrial relations regulations as two plausible generative mechanisms. By examining how these two mechanisms interact in particular empirical contexts deeper, retrodictive insights into why and how unemployment actually occurs may subsequently be advanced. Through continued empirical probing we may also observe more fine-grained nuances in the phenomenon of original interest, such as distinct kinds of unemployment (e.g., involuntary under-employment), begging additional or complementary explanations. This would, in turn, trigger a new sequence of retroduction and retrodiction through which the workings of specific mechanisms potentially responsible for such nuances are first theorised and then explored empirically through further inquiries or re-examination of existing data. Retroduction and retrodiction are thus complementary methodological procedures which need to be conceived of as intimately interlinked throughout the multiple cycles of moving back and forth between theorising and empirical observation. The repeated cycles of retroduction and retrodiction render critical realist analyses heavily theory-dependent, but also open up the possibility of a nearly endless number of theoretical postulates about the workings of generative mechanisms being advanced and investigated (Kaidesoja, 2007). At one level, it would be fair to conceive of theorising in a critical realist mode of inquiry as lacking any definite or natural end-point as researchers always need to be prepared to investigate the causal powers with the potential to generate unanticipated events or 11 nuances in observed tendencies in diverse empirical contexts. Such continuous theorising would find support in Bhaskar’s (1975) conception of critical realism as a philosophical “under-labourer” capable of supporting the application of a vast range of substantive theories (and methods). It is also consistent with his rather bold claim that critical realism effectively resolves the problem of ontological incommensurability between diverse theoretical interpretations of a particular empirical phenomenon as individual theories and methods are independent of the ontological status of the phenomenon per se (Bhaskar, 1975, 1986). Whilst different theories may be more or less comprehensive and possess varying degrees of ontological depth, they are still fallible human constructions and thus better conceived of as ascribing potentially conflicting, complementary or overlapping properties to the real world than being seen as incommensurable on ontological grounds. This creates considerable openness to applying a diverse set of theories to investigate various social phenomena and partly explains why critical realism has evolved into a rather versatile and tolerant philosophy of science accommodating a broad range of substantive theories, methods and subject areas (see Collier, 1994; Reed, 2009; Sayer, 2000). As noted by Kaidesoja (2007), however, it also raises the question of how to adjudicate between multiple and possibly competing theoretical explanations. In actual research practice, this problem is often resolved through recourse to the received value systems, beliefs and structures of authority permeating the epistemic communities of which individual scholars are part. Rather than engaging in endless processes of theorising, researchers often tend to settle for theoretical explanations that are broadly consistent with received bodies of knowledge sanctioned by such socio-political mechanisms. Whilst this phenomenon is by no means unique to critical realism (see e.g., Lukka, 2010; Lukka and Modell, 2010), critical realists openly affirm the epistemic relativism associated with such practices (see e.g., Bhaskar, 1986; Elder-Vass, 2012; Sayer, 2000). Leading critical realists, such as Bhaskar, have repeatedly emphasised how the epistemic contexts in which researchers are embedded reinforce the value-laden nature of the social sciences without abandoning the notion that scientific research practices per se should strive towards preserving a degree of neutrality or impartiality (see Lacey, 1997, 2002). Whilst value judgements ineluctably frame the choice of research questions and theories and, by implication, the outcomes of scientific inquiries it is still possible to uphold the ideal of researchers adjudicating between different theories and explanations on relatively value-neutral grounds when exploring their veracity through empirical inquiries. This rests on the premise that the process of examining multiple 12 theoretical explanations will, over time, establish certain explanations as “truer” than others when confronted with some objective reality and thus contribute to stabilise or change the beliefs and value systems guiding particular epistemic communities. Such interactions between the process of determining the veracity of diverse theories and evolving value systems will, in turn, influence the range of theories available to researchers when articulating new research questions. Hence critical realists should arguably aspire to a “weak” form of epistemic relativism according to which particular knowledge claims are always recognised as conditioned by the epistemic contexts in which researchers are embedded although the truth of such claims is ultimately verifiable in relation to some objective reality (Elder-Vass, 2012). However, the extent to which such relativism actually permeates critical realist inquiries in specific fields, such as organisation and management studies, has recently been subject to some debate (Al-Amoudi and Willmott, 2011). As explicated below, the issue of whether critical realism has fully come to terms with its own epistemological commitments and espoused ambition to evolve into a politically engaged research programme is also of central concern for appreciating its potential as a foundation for critical scholarship. Critical realism as a critical research programme Debates about the possibilities of developing the critical realist project into a genuinely critical research programme have largely pivoted on how procedures of scientific knowledge formation such as those described in the foregoing may be translated into changes in value systems, beliefs and concrete, practical actions conducive to human emancipation. The aspirations to develop critical realism in such a direction can arguably be traced to the centuries-old Enlightenment conception of knowledge as emancipatory in and of itself (Hammersley, 2002). According to Bhaskar (1986), the use of critical realism as philosophical under-labourer for the advancement of scientific knowledge claims forms the basis for explanatory critique which may, in turn, release the emancipatory impulse that is arguably inherent in the social sciences. By advancing theoretically informed explanations of the causal powers underpinning social phenomena, such as the persistence of oppressive social orders, researchers will be in a better position to critique such phenomena and envisage plausible alternatives grounded in the activation of other causal powers than is the case where knowledge is conflated with ideological orthodoxy. Through the mobilisation of retroductive and retrodictive theorising a range of postulates about the actual and potential workings of generative mechanisms and how 13 they reinforce and alleviate such conditions may be advanced and explored empirically. This may, in turn, enlighten social actors of ways in which oppressive social orders may be altered and provide a basis for turning such insights into social actions geared towards transforming underlying structures and contributing to the process of emancipation. However, such conceptions of human emancipation as a relatively unmediated outcome of explanatory critique does not enjoy unreserved support among critical realists (see e.g., Elder-Vass, 2010; Sayer, 1997). Bhaskar’s insistence on the role of critical realism as a universally applicable underlabourer in the advancement of such critiques has also come under attack for representing a new form of orthodoxy originating in some allegedly hegemonic ambition to clear the path for enlightenment and emancipation (Cruickshank, 2004; Magill, 1994). In addition to the disagreements about the role and status of explanatory critique among critical realists, the extent to which critical realism has actually succeeded in evolving into an effective programme of radical social critique and political activism has been questioned by both Marxist and post-structuralist scholars. Whilst supporters of Bhaskar’s prescriptions for the advancement of explanatory critique have sought to demonstrate how it may mitigate against overly deterministic readings of Marx (Joseph, 1998, 2002; Lovering, 1990), both Brown et al. (2002) and Roberts (1999, 2002) argue that the very research procedures underpinning such critiques tend to blunt the radicalism of Marxism by abstracting too much from the rich, historical contingencies explaining the prevalence of oppressive social orders. To Brown et al. (2002), this tendency towards excessive and essentially reductionist forms of abstraction is inherent in the role of retroduction as a central analytical procedure in critical realism. Due to its grounding in particular empirical events and regularities, retroductive theorising is arguably more concerned with the current and the local than the historical and thus detracts from more systematic and holistic abstractions taking the totality of history into account. Similarly, Roberts (1999, 2002) argues that critical realists often subscribe to rather general and apolitical notions of history that abstract from the explicitly ideological dimension of concepts such as emancipation and render them ineffectual as a basis for political activism in the face of potentially powerful and historically contingent constraints such as social class. The end result is a critical realism that is more concerned with explaining the world than changing it. Similar concerns that critical realists tend to privilege the development of explanatory models of society over the pursuit of radical social critique and change have been raised by scholars with post-structuralist sympathies. Willmott (2005), for instance, contrasts critical realism with the post-structuralism of Laclau and Mouffe (1985) and argues that the latter provide a more 14 refined understanding of the interest-driven political processes involved in engendering emancipation. This is so as they foreground the socially constructed, relational space in which political processes are played out and democratic discourses conducive to emancipation evolve rather than insisting on the need to trace such events back to social structures residing in some objective reality. According to Willmott (2005), this is due to Laclau and Mouffe’s refusal to be governed by dualisms between agency and structure such as those underpinning critical realism. However, other writers debating the possibilities of rapprochement between critical realism and post-structuralism have defended the possibilities of upholding such dualisms with reference to Foucault (Al-Amoudi, 2007; Joseph, 2004). Similar to the position taken by Foucault-inspired accounting scholars such as Grey (1994) and Hoskin (1994), a prerequisite for such rapprochement is the acceptance of the centrality of discourse without rejecting its relationship to some objective referents in the world. Rather than dissolving the distinction between the two and denying the existence of any reality outside of discourse, as tends to be the case in much post-modernist thought, Al-Amoudi (2007) demonstrates how a Foucauldian conception of discourse as a source of power with both constraining and enabling properties is compatible with the stratified ontology endorsed by critical realists. This argument rests on the premise that the effects of such power on the world are not a direct, unmediated consequence of discourse but also dependent on the structural context in which such effects unfold. In other words, the discourses mobilised by various agents are distinct from but interdependent with the social structures conditioning and resulting from the formation of discursive practices. According to Joseph (2004), such recognition of the interdependent nature of social structures and discourse may serve to radicalise Foucauldian analyses in that it clarifies the contingent, structural conditions under which the constraining and enabling effects of discourses prevail and condition the possibilities of emancipation. But similar to Neimark’s (1990, 1994) and Tinker’s (1999, 2005) charges that much Foucault-inspired accounting research has effectively failed to develop such emancipatory insights, Joseph (2004) acknowledges that such a trajectory may only materialise if the radical ambitions behind critical realism are taken seriously and turned into politically engaged, explanatory critiques. Hence the use of critical realism as a vehicle of radical social critique cannot be taken as a given, but needs to be continuously nurtured through the adoption of an epistemological stance conducive to critical scholarship. Criticisms of critical realism such as those outlined above remind us of the necessity of situating explanatory critiques in their historical context as well as in relation to the local, lived 15 experiences of research subjects for them to constitute effective vehicles of emancipation. Some attention to the historical contingencies conditioning the possibilities of emancipation is necessary to at least partly accommodate the Marxist critique that critical realist analyses based on retroductive theorising abstracts too much from such contingencies. However, without some empirical grounding of critical realist analyses in current, local conditions where emancipatory, democratic discourses take shape, researchers would seem to have few opportunities to engage in effective political activism aimed at changing the world. This would seem to require more direct engagements with the subjective experiences of agents exposed to more or less oppressive social orders than is perhaps forthcoming in Bhaskar’s oeuvre. As noted by Mutch (2005), much of the critique of critical realism for lacking critical intent and efficacy has tended to concentrate on his exclusively conceptual works whilst predating or largely ignoring empirical advances such as Archer’s (2003, 2007) more recent studies of how individual reflexivity is translated into strategies of emancipation. As argued in the foregoing, however, such strategies also need to be situated in their larger structural context to offer a more complete understanding of how subjectively induced reflexivity is conditioned by objective, pre-existing structures and how individual agency translates into collective agency in the process of structural reproduction and transformation. To sum up, a refined, critical realist mode of explanatory critique would thus need to combine empirical inquiries into how processes of structural reproduction and transformation obstruct and engender opportunities for emancipation with historically informed procedures of retroduction and retrodiction. By nurturing a deep, historically informed understanding of the objective conditions influencing the possibilities of reflexivity, researchers may engage with research subjects in such a way that they mediate the process of emancipation without naively ascribing some unfettered capacity for agency to them. However, attention is also required to how more subjective processes of identity formation shape the propensity for reflexivity to enhance our understanding of how social actors may devise individual and collective strategies of emancipation. Finally, deliberations on how researchers may facilitate processes of emancipation must not be detached from considerations of the epistemic premises conditioning the possibilities of advancing explanatory critiques. In particular, researchers need to be cognisant of how the possibilities of advancing such critiques depend on the epistemological priors guiding their work and ways of “seeing” the world. Such epistemological priors are inter alia manifest in the theories and methods sanctioned by the epistemic communities in which researchers are embedded. Some reflexivity on how such priors affect the contents and scope 16 of explanatory critiques is necessary to affirm the significance of epistemic relativism and recognise how it impinges on the possibilities of nurturing an epistemological stance that is conducive to critical scholarship. Review of Critical Realist Accounting Research As noted in the introductory section of the paper, emerging accounting research informed by critical realism falls into three relatively distinct categories; pieces reflecting on various paradigmatic and methodological issues, empirical studies of processes of accounting change and works advancing critical commentaries on emerging accounting policies and practices. In what follows, I review and critique each of these bodies of research. In doing so, I pay particular attention to whether they exhibit elements of refined explanatory critique such as those outlined towards the end of the preceding section. Table 1 provides a summary of this review. _________________ Insert Table 1 here. ________________ Paradigmatic and methodological reflections The use of critical realism to debate various paradigmatic and methodological issues includes works that ponder the linkages between its ontological premises and the use of particular research methods (Brown and Brignall, 2007; Llewellyn, 2007; Modell, 2009) and, more recently, its implications for theoretical pluralism in accounting research (Modell, 2013, in press). An inspection of Table 1 suggests that relatively little of this research has been explicitly concerned with advancing radical social critiques. However, it does provide valuable insights into the more general epistemological and methodological implications of adopting a critical realist ontology. Starting with Llewellyn’s (2007) discussion of how the stratified (or in her words differentiated) ontology of critical realism may inform case study research and the debate following its publication (Llewellyn, 2008; Sayer, 2008; Scapens and Yang, 2008) some initial observations on this matter can be made. Drawing, in particular, on the works of Archer, 17 Llewellyn (2007) argued that reality may be conceived of as differentiated across five levels (the physical, structural, agential, cultural and mental) and that the usefulness of case study methods will vary depending on what level constitutes the main focal point of researchers. Working on the assumption that realities dominated by causal powers embedded in the physical and structural domains will exercise a strongly stabilising influence on social events, she initially questioned the usefulness of case study methods when such forces are of primary interest to researchers. Whilst acknowledging the value of case studies in revealing previously unknown properties of entrenched structures to agents, she saw little merit in their use under conditions of stability. Rather, case studies were portrayed as a preferable method where researchers are concerned with examining processes of accounting change and where their main interest is in explaining agentic powers and the more subjective aspects in which they originate. As noted by Sayer (2008), however, such a position underplays the indeterminacy often characterising seemingly stable states of the world and the fact that case studies may not only provide valuable insights into structural transformation but also into how human agency continuously mediates structural reproduction. In her reply, Llewellyn (2008) also relaxes her earlier claims regarding the suitability of particular methods for examining stability and change, respectively. Hence there would seem to be at least some consensus that overly crude distinctions between ontological conceptions of the world as either dominated by the stabilising forces of social structures or the dynamising powers of human agency constitute an inappropriate basis for the choice of research methods. Indeed, insisting on such a position would be inconsistent with Bhaskar’s (1975) view of the choice of methods as independent of ontological assumptions and might be seen as unduly constraining if critical realism is to fill the role of philosophical under-labourer in advancing our knowledge of evolving accounting practices. A more serious omission in Llewellyn’s (2007, 2008) initial discussion and response to her critics, however, is the lack of attention to the role of theory in case study research and the epistemic premises governing the choice of theories and methods. Whilst clearly aware of role of theory in qualitative inquiries (e.g., Llewellyn, 2003), she is largely silent about how theories are implicated in critical realist modes of explanation through processes of retroduction and retrodiction. This leads to a curious neglect of some key epistemological implications of adopting a critical realist ontology, such as the need to affirm the theory-dependent nature of empirical observations. The neglect of the theory-dependent nature of critical realist knowledge claims becomes obvious as she argues that knowledge of objective conditions, such as those 18 prevailing in the physical world, can be acquired through relatively unmediated, empirical observations and that our “[k]nowledge of the physical world is also independent of the meanings we attribute to it” (Llewellyn, 2008, p. 22). This reveals a rather glaring lack of recognition of how theories condition our ability to ascribe particular properties to intransitive mechanisms and comes dangerously close to committing the epistemic fallacy of equating the ontological status of the world with our knowledge of it. Llewellyn (2008) then goes on to argue that the generation of scientific knowledge of other domains of reality, such as the more subjective aspects of human agency, requires different modes of inquiry but, again, makes no reference to theory as a medium of knowledge formation. This reinforces the impression that scientific knowledge is seen as a relatively unmediated outcome of empirical observations and would seem to signify a relapse to the position that the ontological status of observed phenomena should be taken as the primary basis for the choice of research methods. When considered in isolation from the epistemic premises governing the choice of particular theories and methods, as is the case in Llewellyn (2007, 2008), there is also an imminent risk of such a position reifying a view of scientific knowledge formation as evolving in some socio-political vacuum. If this is indeed the position to which she subscribes, then notions of epistemic relativism are effectively bracketed if not ignored. Somewhat greater recognition of epistemic relativism and its implications for empirical inquiries is discernible in Brown and Brignall’s (2007) and Modell’s (2009) discussions of how critical realism may be used as a foundation for mixed methods research in accounting. Brown and Brignall (2007) advanced some reflections, partly inspired by critical realism, on how their empirical research into differences in the cost-efficiency of central administrative services in UK universities was influenced by certain epistemic contingencies. Whilst more concerned with the methodological than theoretical implications of doing mixed methods research, they provide some interesting insights into how the broader, socio-political context in which such research is conducted may condition the process of scientific knowledge formation. In particular, they detail how the politically motivated reactions among some practitioner audiences to preliminary research findings caused the quantitative part of their analysis to overshadow their qualitative insights despite their best efforts as researchers to place the two on a reasonably equal footing. Whilst mobilising critical realism as a means of transcending notions of empirical realism and social constructivism, Brown and Brignall (2007) reportedly found it difficult to uphold such a position and go beyond the seemingly “objective” findings emanating from their quantitative analysis due to their politically charged nature and allure to key 19 decision-makers. This constrained their ability to complement their quantitative findings with deeper and more nuanced, qualitative insights into the mechanisms responsible for variations in cost-efficiency across research sites and threatened to compromise the neutrality and impartiality of the researchers. These reflections serve as a useful reminder of how notions of epistemic relativism need to be extended beyond concerns with the value systems and authority structures governing particular communities of scholars which have tended to dominate critical realist discussions of the topic (cf. Elder-Vass, 2012; Lacey, 1997, 2002). Clearly, the full implications of such relativism for scientific knowledge formation can only be understood by widening the definition of relevant epistemic contexts to include actors in the empirical domains in which scholarly inquiries and interventions are situated. Nevertheless, as Modell’s (2009) discussion of triangulation between qualitative and quantitative research methods makes plain, we still need to take the epistemic barriers embedded in scholarly communities seriously to fully appreciate how critical realist accounting research may become more firmly established. Similar to Brown and Brignall (2007), Modell (2009) saw critical realism as a philosophical alternative offering a promising ontological foundation for transcending ingrained conceptions of paradigms as rooted in either empirical realism or social constructivism. He then took this as a starting point for addressing some pertinent criticisms of triangulation, such as its propensity to suppress context-specific variations in meanings and neglect of the theory-dependent nature of empirical observations, whilst locating the sources of potential resistance to such a position to the inter-disciplinary accounting research community as well as the positivist “mainstream” (see also Modell, 2010). Consistent with a critical realist conception of epistemic relativism, both of these communities were seen as exercising a potentially constraining influence on not only the choice of methods but also the range of theories available to accounting scholars. To overcome such epistemic barriers to the combination of methods and theories, Modell (2009) advanced a mixed methods approach centred on an essentially retroductive mode of theorising and sought to illustrate its plausibility by applying it to two extant exemplars of mixed methods research (Covaleski and Dirsmith, 1983; Hoque and Hopper, 1994, 1997).4 He also endeavoured to re-construct how the generation of knowledge in these inquiries was conditioned by epistemic premises, such as the varying availability of adequate and entrenched theories at the time of their completion. 4 Somewhat confusingly, Modell (2009) used the notion of abduction whilst recognising its close affiliation to the notion of retroduction. See Contu and Willmott (2005) for further discussion of the tendencies of some critical realists to conflate the notions of abduction and retroduction. 20 Whilst cautioning against a view of critical realism as a panacea for resolving interparadigmatic disputes and tensions, he concluded by arguing that its use as a basis for mixed methods research may provide a powerful impetus to overcome epistemic barriers to such research. Such optimistic sentiments regarding the potential of critical realism were recently re-iterated by Modell (2013) in an exchange with Jacobs (2012, 2013) over the possibilities of nurturing theoretical pluralism in public sector accounting research. Similar to Modell (2009), the principal concerns were those of how such pluralism may be justified on paradigmatic grounds and the mobilisation of retroductive theorising in an attempt to demonstrate how the choice of theories need not be seen as governed by ontological assumptions but rather by the epistemic premises conditioning particular research studies. Modell (2013) also extended this line of argument by outlining how critical realism may be used as a philosophical point of departure for the combination of theories with diverse disciplinary origins whilst cautioning against the tendency of public sector accounting researchers to sanction overly eclectic and unreflexive blending of theories as an epistemic community. He also provided some brief commentaries on how epistemic premises guiding the choice of theories may foster critical insights into public sector accounting practices. Similar to Brown and Brignall (2007) and Modell (2009), however, he largely ignored the issue of how historical contingencies and more subjective processes of identity formation interact and shape the possibilities of emancipation and how a more explicit interest in such issues might compel researchers to advance radical social critiques. Hence there is very little critical intent behind these papers. It is only very recently that concerns with developing more radical, social critiques have started to surface in paradigmatic and methodological reflections on the use of critical realism in accounting research. However, Modell (in press) advanced the debate in this direction by elaborating on how accounting research informed by institutional theories may be rendered more critical. In doing so, he mobilised critical realism as a potential remedy to the tendency of such research to concentrate on interests favoured by extant institutions and dominating processes of institutional change whilst ignoring the plight of disadvantaged constituencies and their possibilities of emancipation. Drawing on the works of Archer (1995, 2003, 2007) and, to a lesser extent, Elder-Vass (2007, 2010) he explicated how their conception of the interplay between agency and structure might be reconciled with an institutional conception of agency as intentional yet structurally embedded and how such an ontological position entails varying opportunities of emancipation. Recognising the critique of Archer’s recent works for ascribing 21 a universal capacity for reflexivity to agents, he developed a contingent ontological conception of the circumstances under which agents may emancipate themselves from oppressive social orders and devise strategies of collective action to this end. He also discussed the epistemological ramifications of adopting such a contingent view of the possibilities of emancipation in some detail. This comprised an outline of the varying strategies of intervention potentially available to researchers concerned with facilitating the process of emancipation. Rather than assuming that such interventions unfold in some epistemic vacuum, however, he offered some reflections on how the conservative epistemology allegedly underpinning much institutional research may need to be transformed for it to be imbued with more clearly articulated critical intent. To this end, he advanced some suggestions as to how critical realist principles of inquiry may be used to shed light on the social mechanisms and causal powers underpinning institutionalised research practices and engender greater reflexivity on how researchers may emancipate themselves from such practices. This may be seen as an attempt to turn notions of explanatory critique back onto the epistemic premises conditioning research practices. However, in contrast to his previous work on critical realism, Modell (in press) remained silent about how such critiques may be furthered through more explicit mobilisation of retroduction and retrodiction. Studies of accounting change processes The nascent attempts to apply critical realism to empirical inquiries into accounting change processes encompass studies drawing on different strands of critical realist thought and thus displaying somewhat different analytical procedures and emphases. Both Ashraf and Uddin (2013) and Stergiou et al. (2013) mobilised Archer’s (1995) morphogenetic approach in case studies exploring the more or less successful efforts to change management accounting and control systems in different organisations. The main concern in both studies was to avoid the risk of conflating notions of structure and agency prevailing in much social theory and overcome the objectivist/subjectivist divide separating different genres of accounting research. To this end the authors adopted a longitudinal research approach and sought to tease out the dynamic and recursive interplay between human agency and extant and emerging structures implicated in accounting change processes. Both studies followed the analytical approach proposed by Archer (1995) relatively closely. As recognised by Stergiou et al. (2013), however, this led to some bracketing of the more subjective aspects of agency such as those highlighted 22 in Archer’s (2000, 2003, 2007) more recent works on reflexivity and limited the insights into how the action repertoires and strategies of key actors took shape at a deeper, cognitive level. Also, both studies used the morphogenetic approach as a relatively generic framework without combining it with a wider range of substantive theories to derive explanations in accordance with the principles of retroduction and retrodiction. Somewhat more explicit reliance on such principles is discernible in Mutiganda’s (2013) study of the development of novel governance and accountability practices in the Finnish health care sector. Drawing more heavily on Bhaskar’s (1975) framework, he first mobilised retroductive theorising to identify two overarching, structural mechanisms in the form of political and technical institutions of governance originating in political reforms common to Finnish health care organisations and the professional expertise of health care employees, respectively. These mechanisms were seen as residing in the domain of the real in Bhaskar’s (1975) ontology, whilst their more concrete, empirical manifestations and interactions were then explored through case studies in two health care organisations. Consistent with a critical realist mode of explanation, this was followed by some elaboration on how the causal powers embedded in the two institutions buttressed and counteracted each other to produce specific responses to evolving control practices. These empirical findings were subsequently used to extend Burns and Scapens’ (2000) institutional framework for understanding stability and change in accounting practices. In doing so, Mutiganda (2013) argued that critical realism complements their more “local” model of how institutional structures interact with human agency by drawing attention to how structural mechanisms residing at a somewhat higher level of abstraction condition this interplay.5 In contrast to Ashraf and Uddin (2013) and Stergiou et al. (2013), however, relatively little attention was paid to the concrete, unfolding interplay between agency and structure in the organisations under examination. This also implies that concerns with subjectivity and reflexivity are largely absent in his analysis. Researchers mobilising diverse branches of critical realism to examine accounting change processes thus seem to be drawn towards either advancing theoretically informed modes of explanation that abstract from the detailed interplay between agency and structure or nurturing a more generic, empiricist focus that foregrounds this interplay but offers few specific insights Mutiganda’s (2013) line of argument in this respect is largely consistent with Leca and Naccache’s (2006) attempt to synthesise critical realism and institutional theory and explicate how the interplay between concrete institutional structures and human agency is conditioned by higher-order templates residing in diverse institutional logics. However, he makes no explicit reference to their work. 5 23 into the explanatory potential of a broader range of substantive theories. Bridging the gap between such diverging research interests is important to nurture a more integrative approach that is capable of producing refined explanatory critiques. As noted in the foregoing, such critiques require thorough empirical insights into the structural conditions under which agents may emancipate themselves from oppressive social orders but are also likely to benefit from a historically and theoretically informed understanding of what the potential, but perhaps not immediately observable, opportunities of emancipation might be. Whilst paying varying attention to the historical contingencies shaping the focal change processes (see especially Stergiou et al., 2013), none of the studies reviewed above show any explicit concerns with combining this with theoretical insights geared towards developing radical social critiques. Even though different categories of managerial and professional staff with partly conflicting interests receive ample attention, the three studies do not shed much light on the plight of constituencies that are potentially marginalised or seriously disadvantaged by evolving accounting practices and how it might be remedied. Nor do they exhibit any deeper reflections on which epistemic premises need be filled to nurture more innate concerns with emancipation and the advancement of radical social critique. Similar to much critical realist research in other disciplines, they are thus susceptible to criticisms for being more concerned with advancing novel modes of explaining the world than changing it. I now turn to review some emerging works displaying a more clearly articulated interest in developing critical realist accounting research in such a direction. Critical commentaries on emerging accounting policies and practices In isolation from other attempts to advance critical realist accounting research, a small number of critical commentaries on emerging accounting policies and practices have also invoked such a philosophical position. Burrowes et al. (2004) offered an analysis of the emergence of the Sarbanes-Oxley Act and its likely effects on auditing and accounting practices. Similar to some of the paradigmatic and methodological reflections reviewed in the foregoing, critical realism was adopted as a means of mitigating against the alleged tendencies of commentaries on accounting policy to either adopt a rather deterministic perspective grounded in empirical 24 realism or subscribing to various forms of social constructivism. In doing so, Burrowes et al. (2004) make a case for making the philosophical assumptions guiding such commentaries explicit and propose critical realism as a vehicle of going beyond observed events to explain the workings of the deeper structures generating them. As such, they display a strong commitment to the ontological foundations of critical realism. They also emphasise the importance of conducting critical realist analyses in such a way that the historical contingencies conditioning the evolution of accounting policies are taken into account and situate their analysis of the emergence of the Sarbanes-Oxley Act in the historical context of accounting regulation and emerging efforts to enhance fiscal probity in the US. However, their subsequent analysis of the effects of the legislative mechanisms put in place by the act is largely void of more systematic attempts to explain its consequences in accordance with the principles of retroduction and retrodiction. Rather than conducting an empirically grounded analysis with these principles in mind, the authors revert to a rather speculative mode of analysis based on an effort to re-construct the espoused intentions behind the act and its potential, unintended consequences. Little explicit attention is paid to exactly how various causal powers embedded in the legislation are activated and how they interact to produce unintended consequences. Nor do the authors engage in any concerted efforts to advance alternative, theoretically informed postulates explicating how such unintended consequences may be mitigated by the workings of legislative mechanisms. A similar lack of systematic attention to retroduction and retrodiction as a means of advancing theoretically informed explanations is discernible in Smyth’s (2012) archival analysis and critique of emerging accountability regimes in the social housing sector in the UK. Similar to Burrowes et al. (2004), he sought to understand the emergence of two alternative and contested accountability regimes in their historical context and identified a number of generative mechanisms underpinning this development, such as the rise of neo-liberalism and resistance to such forces, and their relationships to other mechanisms such as deeper economic conditions and attempts by various elites to assert their power. But whilst describing the interactions between such mechanisms in some detail, he makes no explicit use of retroduction or retrodiction. Also, whilst referring to events and tendencies that would seem to originate in some interplay between structural and agentic powers, he neither makes a clear analytical distinction between them nor does he offer a more systematic, longitudinal analysis of their recursive interplay as recommended by Archer (1995). This seems to limit the possibilities of envisaging how individual and corporate agents may achieve a degree of emancipation from 25 accountability regimes encroaching on their life opportunities. Despite recognising the possibilities of resistance to emerging accountability regimes, Smyth (2012) does not pay much attention to how the causal powers embedded in generative mechanisms may be activated in alternative ways and how this might affect the possibilities of emancipation. The use of critical realism to advance critical commentaries on emerging accounting policies and practices thus falls short of many of the characteristics of refined explanatory critiques proposed in the foregoing. In particular, there are limited efforts to advance more theoretically informed explanations as a basis for highlighting the possibilities of emancipation in the two studies. The use of retroduction and retrodiction to this end is, at best, implicit in the discussion of how generative mechanisms interact and give rise to particular events and tendencies. It is quite possible that the opportunities of advancing explanatory critiques are constrained by the lack of deeper and more direct empirical engagements as both retroductive and retrodictive modes of explanation hinge on the ability of researchers to combine abstract theorising with empirical observations. However, there is also a dearth of efforts to mobilise a broader range of substantive theories as a vehicle of supporting the critiques advanced in the two studies and hardly any reflections on the epistemic premises conditioning the ability of researchers to do so. The relatively shallow empirical engagements also detract from the possibilities of probing into how emancipation is engendered through subjective processes of identity formation and reflexivity. Whither Critical Realist Accounting Research? The review of emerging, critical realist accounting research reveals a rather fragmented body of literature. Whilst the ontological foundations of critical realism seem reasonably wellunderstood and accepted, there are significant variations in researchers’ recognition of the epistemological and methodological implications of adopting such an ontology as well as the extent to which they have strived to translate them into a more radical, politically engaged research programme. On the one hand, scholars engaging in paradigmatic and methodological reflections on the use of critical realism and applying it to empirical inquiries into accounting change processes vary in their emphasis on retroduction and retrodiction to derive theoretically informed explanations but very rarely strive to radicalise the research agenda (but see Modell, in press). On the other hand, researchers advancing critical commentaries on emerging accounting policies and practices mobilise critical realism as a basis for political engagement 26 but do so in a way that is largely detached from deeper empirical inquiries or any concerted efforts to advance more theoretically informed, explanatory critiques. Moreover, similar to the use of critical realism in organisation and management studies (Al-Amoudi and Willmott, 2011), issues of epistemic relativism and how they condition our ability to explain and critique the world are not universally recognised. Whilst increasingly featuring as a central concern in paradigmatic and methodological reflections (Brown and Brignall, 2007; Modell, 2009, 2013, in press), explicit deliberations on how epistemic premises shape research practices are largely absent from empirical inquiries and commentaries on accounting policies and practices. To some extent, this fragmented state of critical realist accounting research is understandable in light of the divisions and varying emphases that have emerged over time within the larger, critical realist research programme. For instance, the use of retroduction and retrodiction as methods of explanation is of central concern in research that follows Bhaskar’s foundational works (e.g., Elder-Vass, 2010; Lawson, 1997), but is much less salient in Archer’s (1995, 2000, 2003, 2007) elaborations on how to examine the interplay between structure and agency and her subsequent, empirical research into subjective processes of identity formation and reflexivity. Whilst empirical inquiries into how reflexivity translates into individual and collective strategies of emancipation are pivotal for explaining how oppressive social orders may be overcome, accounting scholars have only very recently recognised their significance within a broader, critical realist framework (see Modell, in press; Stergiou et al., 2013) and have yet to extend such inquiries to incorporate explanatory critiques such as those proposed by Bhaskar (1986). However, it is also worth recalling that the efficacy of explanatory critiques as a vehicle of emancipation is by no means uncontested among critical realists and that there are doubts about the extent to which a clearly identifiable programme of political engagement and activism centred on such critiques has actually materialised. Against this backdrop it is perhaps not surprising to find emerging accounting research informed by critical realism being divided in its emphasis on deeper empirical work and more politically engaged scholarship and, as a result, remaining somewhat agnostic about the pursuit of explanatory critiques. Nevertheless, I want to argue that much can be gained from nurturing a more integrative approach that draws on diverse strands of critical realist thought and that is explicitly geared towards advancing refined explanatory critiques such as to those outlined earlier in this paper. By mobilising diverse theories through retroductive and retrodictive modes of explanation, researchers may ensure that a wider range of social actors being affected by particular accounting policies and practices are given a voice and are not unduly neglected in the process 27 of advancing such critiques. However, to prevent this from becoming an overly abstract and introvert academic exercise, it is worthwhile to ground such theorising in in-depth engagements with the subjective, lived experiences of agents in the spirit of Archer’s (2003, 2007) empirical work. Doing so may help releasing the emancipatory impulse which Bhaskar (1986) ascribes to the social sciences but which much critical realist research has arguably failed to realise as it may compel researchers to engage in direct interventions and dialogue with diverse social actors about how accounting is implicated in constraining and enabling their possibilities of emancipation. Processes of retroductive and retrodictive theorising may be of considerable help in such interventions as they not only compel researchers (and other actors) to trace the oppressive consequences of accounting to specific, generative mechanisms and explore the interplay between such mechanisms, but also provide a basis for pondering how such consequences might be mitigated if the causal powers embedded in particular mechanisms were activated in different ways. According to Lacey (1997), it may be especially enlightening to confront groups of marginalised social actors with such theorising by soliciting their reactions to theoretical explanations favouring more dominant actors and interests. This may provoke responses highlighting alternative, but previously unrecognised, explanations that may, in turn, stimulate further reflection on the workings of generative mechanisms and their emancipatory potential. Thought experiments pivoting on retroductive and retrodictive theorising may thus reveal unanticipated possibilities of emancipation. They may also engender broader debates about the workings of the mechanisms underpinning particular accounting policies and practices and thus stimulate collective forms of reflexivity with the potential to engender more far-reaching changes. Explanatory critiques pivoting on notions of retroduction and retrodiction should thus be seen as complementary to extended empirical engagements rather than as a mode of inquiry that will inevitably abstract from the phenomena under examination and distance researchers from the pursuit of radical social change. However, in light of the scepticism of some critical realists about the efficacy of explanatory critiques as some unmediated means of emancipation (e.g., Elder-Vass, 2010; Sayer, 1997) it would be fallacious to assume that empirical engagements and researcher interventions will invariably clear the path to this end. Following the tenor of critical realism, any engagement geared towards unlocking the emancipatory potential of social actors needs to consider the structural constraints impinging on this potential. Whilst explanatory critiques pivoting on retroduction and retrodiction may provide some insights into how such constraints may be overcome, it is necessary to recognise that they are often grounded in deeply embedded and 28 rather resilient historical contingencies. Even though some critical realists, such as Archer (2007), have started to question the ubiquitous presence of historically contingent constraints such as social class in modern society, I have argued that refined explanatory critiques need to reckon with their diverse manifestations in specific social contexts. Doing so is important to prevent processes of retroduction and retrodiction from being overly concerned with current and local conditions affecting the possibilities of emancipation whilst neglecting how such conditions have become more or less entrenched over time. Whilst the attention to historical contingencies varies in emerging critical realist accounting research, their more specific influence on generative mechanisms requires more systematic recognition in future inquiries seeking to imbue such research with some emancipatory intent. It is here that the contingent approach to realising the possibilities of emancipation outlined by Modell (in press) becomes potentially useful. This contingent view explicitly recognises that the ontological possibilities of emancipation will vary with both objective, structural conditions and the subjective processes of identity formation conducive to nurturing an element of reflexivity. As such, it aims to enlighten researchers of the varying opportunities of pursuing explanatory critiques and engaging with accounting policies and practices in such a way that historical (and other) contingencies receive due attention. As noted by Sayer (1997), however, critical realist research interventions also need to be sensitive to the unintended and potentially damaging consequences that may follow from explanatory critiques in a complex and increasingly interconnected world. Recognising such potentialities is necessary given the view of critical realist knowledge claims as always being under-determined by the social realities to which they refer. By situating explanatory critiques in relation to historical contingencies as well as continuously evolving empirical contexts, critical realist accounting research may begin to transcend controversies such as those repeatedly erupting between accounting scholars with Marxist and post-structuralist sympathies. Through their recognition of the potentially durable, structural mechanisms originating in historical contingencies such critiques may preserve some sensitivity to the historical materialism associated with Marxist thought whilst doing so in a way that escapes overly deterministic interpretations of its effects on contemporary society. However, they also affirm the need to ground analyses of the workings of such mechanisms in specific empirical locales where the discursive practices occupying post-structuralists take shape and condition the possibilities of emancipation. Moreover, they are capable of doing so in a way that preserves researchers’ sensitivity to subjective processes of identity formation 29 without downplaying their co-evolution and interactions with objective, structural mechanisms. Hence critical realism has the capacity to take critical accounting research beyond at least some of the ruptures emerging within this broad area of accounting scholarship over the past decades. Apart from offering an ontological alternative that does not force researchers to choose between an objectivist position underpinned by historical materialism and more actor-centric concerns with subjectivity, it also comes with an epistemology that is void of any innate, ideological commitments to specific theories and thus open to a multitude of ways of explaining the world. But herein also lies a potential weakness in so far as the nurturing of critical scholarship is concerned. As noted by Collier (1994), critical realism does not automatically licence theories conducive to human emancipation but is, in principle, capable of supporting any theory including those legitimising policies with potentially oppressive effects. A particular challenge would thus seem to pertain to ensuring that critical realist accounting research is imbued with genuinely critical or emancipatory intent. Addressing this challenge raises a range of epistemic issues of which accounting scholars engaging with critical realism need to be cognisant. Whilst the challenges of maintaining critical intent are of general concern in critical accounting research (see e.g., Arrington and Watkins, 2002; Roslender and Dillard, 2003), a critical realist mode of inquiry such as that outlined above would seem to face some specific issues. A first, overriding issue is that of ensuring that critical realism is brought firmly into the fold of the critical accounting research community such that it is not mainly employed to research tasks without any specific critical thrust or, at worst, in the service of research with a distinctly conservative value orientation. As a relatively novel strand of accounting research it may face the typical challenges of being more widely accepted by particular epistemic communities as a valid and worthwhile project (cf. Lukka, 2010; Lukka and Modell, 2010). However, without some firm endorsement by critical accounting scholars there is a danger of critical realist accounting research losing its not yet fully fledged critical edge. This has arguably been the fate of much critical realist research in other parts of the social sciences and is a risk that needs to be guarded against in an increasingly variegated and, some would argue, eclectic research climate where concerns with theoretical prowess sometimes tend to dominate over methodological consistency and rigour (cf. Modell, 2013; Roslender, 2013). In seeking such endorsement, however, researchers need to restrain any impulses to compromise the distinctive features of critical realism. A particular challenge in this regard would be to resist the strongly empiricist tendencies currently prevailing in parts of the wider, inter-disciplinary accounting research community (Roslender, 30 2013). As noted in the foregoing, critical realist accounting research has not been entirely immune to the allure of such empiricism (cf. Ashraf and Uddin, 2013; Stergiou et al., 2013). But pursuing a strongly empiricist path implies a risk of underplaying the role of critical realism as philosophical under-labourer stimulating systematic employment of a diverse set of substantive theories to explain and critique particular social phenomena. Whilst critical realism affirms the value of empirical research, it does so within the premises of its stratified ontology which compels researchers to go significantly beyond immediate empirical observations to theorise and probe into the partially knowable, generative mechanisms residing in the domain of the real. Sacrificing such analytical depth as a result of some temptation to speak only of what is immediately observable in the empirical domain would seriously compromise the critical potential of critical realist accounting research. Another set of epistemic issues pertain to how the critical intent of such research can be maintained during extended engagements with the empirical contexts where specific inquiries and research interventions are situated. Whilst this matter is receiving increasing attention in the critical accounting literature (e.g., Cooper, 2005; Cooper and Coulson, in press; Neu et al., 2001) there would, again, seem to be some issues that are specific to a critical realist mode of inquiry. One such issue concerns the premises under which explanatory critiques based on repeated cycles of retroductive and retrodictive theorising can be mobilised to uphold critical intent. Whilst I have sought to outline how thought experiments pivoting on such theorising may help unlocking the emancipatory potential of social actors, it is worth noting that the possibilities of doing so may be constrained by social contingencies bearing directly on the content and scope of research interventions. As indicated by Brown and Brignall (2007), the possibilities of deeper probing through the use of alternative theories or methods may be limited by the prevalence of dominant social elites with an interest in promoting certain findings. In other cases, engagements with such elites may be necessary to sustain explanatory critiques. This is especially likely to be the case where extant structures and accounting practices are firmly entrenched by historical contingencies and researchers have little choice but to liaise with the elites favoured by such practices to muster support for emancipatory projects (Modell, in press). This reinforces the contention that notions of epistemic relativism conditioning critical realist knowledge claims and the possibilities of pursuing explanatory critiques cannot be confined to concerns with academic acceptability and endorsement but also need to be understood in relation to the empirical contexts in which research interventions unfold. 31 To conclude, there are reasons for being sanguine about the potential of critical realist accounting research as a basis for critical scholarship. Even though it has yet to evolve into a more coherent and integrative research programme, it rests on a versatile and tolerant philosophy of science that is capable of supporting a multitude of theories and research methods. As such, it is well-positioned to contribute to the continuous efforts to build a critical accounting research community that is open to novel ways of engaging with accounting policies and practices. The challenge, as in many other strands of critical accounting research, is to ensure that it continues to nurture some explicit, critical intent. I have argued that this challenge is primarily related to a range of epistemic issues conditioning whether critical realism will become more widely accepted and recognised by critical accounting scholars and be applied in such a way that it helps unlocking the emancipatory potential of social actors. However, critical realism should not be seen as some panacea in this respect. Recognising the charges against Bhaskar for pursuing an essentially hegemonic agenda of promoting critical realism as a universally applicable under-labourer to the social sciences, it is pertinent to close this paper by cautioning against any tendencies to take it as a carte blanche for suppressing continued debate on how to develop the philosophical foundations of critical accounting research. References Ackroyd, S. (2004) Methodology for management and organisation studies: some implications of critical realism, in Fleetwood, S. and Ackroyd, S. (eds) Critical Realist Applications in Organisation and Management Studies, London: Routledge. Ackroyd, S. and Fleetwood, S. (2000) Realism in contemporary organisation and management studies, in Ackroyd, D. and Fleetwood, S. (eds) Realist Perspectives on Management and Organizations, London: Routledge. Ahrens, T. (2008) Overcoming the subjective-objective divide in interpretive management accounting research, Accounting, Organizations and Society, 33:2-3, 292-297. Al-Amoudi, I. (2007) Redrawing Foucault’s ontology, Organization, 14(4), 543-563. Al-Amoudi, I. and Willmott, H. (2011) Where constructionism and critical realism converge: interrogating the domain of epistemological relativism, Organization Studies, 32(1), 27-46. Archer, M.S. (1995) Realist Social Theory: The Morphogenetic Approach, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge. 32 Archer, M.S. (2000) Being Human: The Problem of Agency. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Archer, M.S. (2003) Structure, Agency, and the Internal Conversation, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Archer, M.S. (2007) Making Our Way through the World: Human Reflexivity and Social Mobility, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Arrington, C.E. and Watkins, A.L. (2002) Maintaining “critical intent” within a postmodern theoretical perspective on accounting research, Critical Perspectives on Accounting, 13, 139157. Ashraf, M.J. and Uddin, S. (2013) A consulting giant; a disgruntled customer: a ‘failed’ attempt to change management controls in a public sector organisation, Financial Accountability and Management, 29(2), 186-203. Baxter, J. and Chua, W.F. (2003). Alternative management accounting research – whence and whither. Accounting, Organizations and Society, 28, 97-126. Bhaskar, R. (1975) A Realist Theory of Science, Leeds: Leeds Books. Bhaskar, R. (1979) The Possibilities of Naturalism. A Philosophical Critique of the Contemporary Human Sciences, Brighton: Harvester Press. Bhaskar, R. (1986) Scientific Realism and Human Emancipation, London: Verso. Bhaskar, R. (1998) General introduction, in Archer, M., Bhaskar, R., Collier, A., Lawson, T. and Norrie, A. (eds) Critical Realism. Essential Readings. London: Routledge. Brown, A., Slater, G. and Spencer, D.A. (2002) Driven to abstraction? Critical realism and the search for the ‘inner connection’ of social phenomena, Cambridge Journal of Economics, 26, 773-788. Brown, R. and Brignall, S. (2007) Reflections on the use of a dual-methodology research design to evaluate accounting and management practice in UK university central administrative services, Management Accounting Research, 18, 32-48. Burns, J. and Scapens, R.W. (2000) Conceptualising management accounting change: an institutional framework, Management Accounting Research, 11, 3-25. Burrowes, A.W., Kastantin, J. and Novicevic, M.M. (2004) The Sarbanes-Oxley Act as a hologram of post-Enron disclosure: a critical realist commentary, Critical Perspectives on Accounting, 15, 797-811. Chua, W.F. (1986) Radical developments in accounting thought, Accounting Review, 61:4, 601-632. Collier, A. (1994) Critical Realism, London: Verso. 33 Contu, A, and Willmott, H. (2005) You spin me round: the realist turn in organization and management studies, Journal of Management Studies, 42, 1645-1662. Cooper, C. (1997) Against postmodernism: class oriented questions for critical accounting, Critical Perspectives on Accounting, 8 (1), 15-41. Cooper, C. (2005) Accounting for the public interest: public ineffectuals or public intellectuals?, Accounting, Auditing and Accountability Journal, 18, 592-607. Cooper, C. and Coulson, A. (in press) Accounting activism and Bourdieu’s ‘collective intellectual’ – reflections on the ICL case, Critical Perspectives on Accounting. Cooper, D.J. and Hopper, T. (2007) Critical theorising in management accounting research, in Chapman, C.S., Hopwood, A.G. and Shields, M.D. (eds) Handbook of Management Accounting Research, Oxford: Elsevier. Covaleski, M.A., and Dirsmith, M.W. (1983) Budgeting as means of control and loose coupling, Accounting, Organizations and Society, 8, 323-340. Cruickshank, J. (2004) A tale of two ontologies: an immanent critique of critical realism, The Sociological Review, 52(4), 567-585 Delbridge, R. and Edwards, T. (2013) Inhabiting institutions: critical realist refinements to understanding institutional complexity and change, Organization Studies, 34(7), 927-947. Elder-Vass, D. (2007) Reconciling Archer and Bourdieu in an emergent theory of action, Sociological Theory, 25, 325-346. Elder-Vass, D. (2010) The Causal Power of Social Structures, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge. Elder-Vass, D. (2012) The Reality of Social Construction, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge. Fleetwood, S. (2004) An ontology for organisation and management studies, in Fleetwood, S. and Ackroyd, S. (eds) Critical Realist Applications in Organisation and Management Studies, London: Routledge. Fleetwood, S. (2005) Ontology in organization and management studies: a critical realist perspective, Organization, 12, 197-222. Fleetwood, S. and Ackroyd, S. (eds) (2004) Critical Realist Applications in Organisation and Management Studies, London: Routledge. Goddard, A. (2010) Contemporary public sector accounting research – an international comparison of journal papers, British Accounting Review, 42, 75-87. Grey, C. (1994) Debating Foucault: a critical reply to Neimark, Critical Perspectives on Accounting, 5(1), 5-24. 34 Hammersley, M. (2002) Research as emancipatory. The case of Bhaskar’s critical realism. Journal of Critical Realism, 1(1), 33-48. Hopper, T. and Powell, A. (1985) ‘Making sense of research into the organizational and social aspects of management accounting: a review of its underlying assumptions’, Journal of Management Studies, 22, 429-465. Hoque, Z. and Hopper, T. (1994) ‘Rationality, accounting and politics: a case study of management control in a Bangladeshi jute mill’, Management Accounting Research, 5, 5-30. Hoque, Z. and Hopper, T. (1997) ‘Political and industrial relations turbulence, competition and budgeting in the nationalised jute mills of Bangladesh’, Accounting and Business Research, 27, 125-143. Hoskin, K. (1994) Boxing clever: for, against and beyond Foucault in the battle for accounting theory Critical Perspectives on Accounting, 5(1), 57-85. Jacobs, K. (2012) Making sense of social practice: theoretical pluralism in public sector accounting research, Financial Accountability and Management, 28, 1-25. Jacobs, K. (2013) Making sense of social practice: theoretical pluralism in public sector accounting research: a reply, Financial Accountability and Management, 29, 111-115. Joseph, J. (1998) In defence of critical realism, Capital and Class, 65(1), 73-106. Joseph, J. (2002) Five ways in which critical realism can help Marxism, in Brown, A., Fleetwood, S. and Roberts, M.J. (eds) Critical Realism and Marxism, London: Routledge. Joseph, J. (2004) Foucault and reality, Capital and Class, 28(1) 143-165. Kaidesoja, T. (2007) Exploring the concept of causal power in a critical realist tradition, Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour, 37(1), 63-87. Kakkuri-Knuuttila, M-L., Lukka, K. and Kuorikoski, J. (2008a) Straddling between paradigms: A naturalistic philosophical case study on interpretive research in management accounting. Accounting, Organizations and Society, 33:2-3, 267-291. Kakkuri-Knuuttila, M-L., Lukka, K. and Kuorikoski, J. (2008b) No premature closures of debates, please: A response to Ahrens. Accounting, Organizations and Society, 33:2-3, 298301. Kilfoyle, E. and Richardson, A.J. (2011) Agency and structure in budgeting: thesis, antithesis and synthesis, Critical Perspectives on Accounting, 22, 183-199. Lacey, H. (1997) Neutrality in the social sciences: on Bhaskar’s argument for an essential emancipatory impulse in social science, Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour, 27(2/3) 213-241. 35 Lacey, H. (2002) Emancipatory critique and emancipatory movements, Journal of Critical Realism, 1(1), 7-31. Laclau, E. and Mouffe, C. (1985) Hegemony and Socialist Strategy, London: Verso. Lawson, T. (1997) Economics and Reality. London: Routledge. Leca, B. and Naccache, P. (2006), A critical realist approach to institutional entrepreneurship, Organization, 13, 627-651. Llewellyn, S. (2003) What counts as “theory” in qualitative management accounting research? Introducing five levels of theorizing, Accounting, Auditing and Accountability Journal, 16, 662-708. Llewellyn, S. (2007) Case studies and differentiated realities, Qualitative Research in Accounting and Management, 4, 53-68. Llewellyn, S. (2008) Differentiated realities? A response to Andrew Sayer and Bob Scapens and ChunLei Yang, Qualitative Research in Accounting and Management, 5, 21-26. Lovering, J. (1990) Neither fundamentalism nor ‘new realism’: a critical realist perspective on current divisions in socialist theory, Capital and Class, 42, 30-54. Lukka, K. (2010) The roles and effects of paradigms in accounting research, Management Accounting Research, 21, 110-115. Lukka, K. and Modell, S. (2010) Validation in interpretive management accounting research, Accounting, Organizations and Society, 35, 462-477. Magill, K. (1994) Against critical realism, Capital and Class, 18(3), 113-136. Merino, B.D. (1998) Critical theory and accounting history: challenges and opportunities, Critical Perspectives on Accounting, 9, (6), 603-616. Modell, S. (2009) In defence of triangulation: a critical realist approach to mixed methods research in management accounting, Management Accounting Research, 20, 208-221. Modell, S. (2010) Bridging the paradigm divide in management accounting research: the role of mixed methods approaches, Management Accounting Research, 21, 124-129. Modell, S. (2013) Making sense of social practice: theoretical pluralism in public sector accounting research: a comment, Financial Accountability and Management, 29, 99-110. Modell, S. (in press) Making institutional accounting research critical: dead end or new beginning? Accounting, Auditing and Accountability Journal. Mutch, A. (2004) Constraints on the internal conversation: Margaret Archer and the structural shaping of thought, Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour, 34(4), 429-445. 36 Mutch, A. (2005) Critical realism, agency and discourse: moving the debate forward, Organization, 12(5), 781-786. Mutiganda, J.C. (2013) Budgetary governance and accountability in public sector organisations: an institutional and critical realism approach, Critical Perspectives on Accounting, 24(7/8), 518-531. Neimark, M. (1990) The king is dead. Long live the king. Critical Perspectives on Accounting, 1, 103-114. Neimark, M.K., (1994) Regicide revisited: Marx, Foucault and accounting, Critical Perspectives on Accounting, 5, 87-108. Neu, D., Cooper, D.J. and Everett, J. (2001) Critical accounting interventions, Critical Perspectives on Accounting, 12, 735-762. Niiniluoto, I. (1999) Critical Scientific Realism. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Parker, L.D. (2012) Qualitative management accounting research: assessing deliverables and relevance. Critical Perspectives on Accounting, 23 (1), 54-70. Reed, M. (2005) Reflections on the ‘realist turn’ in organization and management studies, Journal of Management Studies, 42, 1621-1644. Reed, M. (2009) Critical realism in critical management studies, in Alvesson, M., Bridgman, T. and Willmott, H. (eds). The Oxford Handbook of Critical Management Studies, Oxford, Oxford University Press. Roberts, J.M. (1999) Marxism and critical realism: the same, similar, or just plain different?, Capital and Class, 46, 21-49. Roberts, J.M. (2002) Abstracting emancipation. Two dialectics on the trail of freedom. In Brown, A., Fleetwood, S. and Roberts, M.J. (eds) Critical Realism and Marxism, London: Routledge. Roslender, R., 2013. Stuck in the middle with whom? (Belatedly) engaging with Laughlin while becoming (re-)acquainted with Merton and middle range theorising. Critical Perspectives on Accounting, 24 (3), 228-241. Roslender, R. and Dillard, J.F. (2003). Reflections on the interdisciplinary perspectives on accounting project, Critical Perspectives on Accounting, 14, 325-351. Sayer, A. (1997) Critical realism and the limits to critical social science, Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour, 27(4), 473-488. Sayer, A. (2000) Realism and Social Science, Thousand Oaks: Sage. Sayer, A. (2008) Case studies and a single, differentiated reality. A reply to Sue Llewellyn (2007), Qualitative Research in Accounting and Management, 5, 11-14. 37 Scapens, R.W. and Yang, C. (2008) Pluralist ontology: comments on Llewellyn (2007), Qualitative Research in Accounting and Management, 5, 15-20. Sikka, P. and Willmott, H. (2005) The withering of tolerance and communication in interdisciplinary accounting studies, Accounting, Auditing and Accountability Journal, 18, 136-146. Smyth, S. (2012) Contesting public accountability: a dialogical exploration of accountability and social housing, Critical Perspectives on Accounting, 23, 230-243. Stergiou, K., Ashraf, J. and Uddin, S. (2013) The role of structure and agency in management accounting control change of a family owned firm: a Greek case study, Critical Perspectives on Accounting, 24, 62-74. Tinker, T. (1999) Mickey Marxism rides again! Critical Perspectives on Accounting, 10, 643670. Tinker, T. (2005) The withering of criticism. A review of professional, Foucauldian, ethnographic, and epistemic studies in accounting, Accounting, Auditing and Accountability Journal, 18, 100-135. Tsang, E.W.K. and Kwan, K-M. (1999) Replication and theory development in organizational science: a critical realist perspective, Academy of Management Review, 24, 759-780. Tsoukas, H. (1989) The validity of idiographic research explanations. Academy of Management Review, 14, 551-561. Vandenberghe, F. (2005) The Archers, European Journal of Social Theory, 8(2), 227-237. Willmott, H. (2005) Theorizing contemporary control: some post-structuralist responses to some critical realist questions, Organization, 12(5), 747-780. 38 Study Concerns with Explicit use of Attention to Attention to Attention to advancing retroduction/ historical subjectivity/ epistemic radical social retrodiction contingencies reflexivity premises critique Paradigmatic and methodological reflections Llewellyn No No No Yes No No No No No Yes Modell (2009) No Partly No No Yes Modell (2013) No Partly No No Yes Modell (in Yes No No Yes Yes (2007, 2008) Brown and Brignall (2007) press) Empirical studies of accounting change processes Ashraf and No No No No No No No Yes No No No Yes No No No Uddin (2013) Stergiou et al. (2013) Mutiganda (2013) Critical commentaries on emerging accounting policies and practices Burrowes et al. Yes No Yes No No Yes No Yes No No (2004) Smyth (2012) Table 1. Elements of refined explanatory critique in critical realist accounting research. 39