Moral Realism and Epistemic Inaccessibility An investigation into the relationship between Moral Realism and Epistemological Moral Scepticism By Pieter Fritschy 3390306 pieter_fritschy@hotmail.com Master’s thesis Research Master Philosophy June 2014 First supervisor: Prof. Herman Philipse Abstract The relationship between epistemological moral scepticism and moral realism is often presented as a matter of logic: because we cannot draw metaphysical conclusions about the existence of moral facts on the basis of the question whether we can have epistemic access to such moral facts, so the argument runs, epistemological moral scepticism and moral realism are compatible meta-ethical positions. In this thesis, however, I will argue that the relationship between moral realism and epistemological moral scepticism is a far from trivial one. Indeed, in this thesis I will argue that the epistemic inaccessibility of moral facts, which should lead one to endorse epistemological moral scepticism, not only creates an extra burden of proof for the moral realist, but that it also fatally undermines the most important positive arguments in favour of moral realism. For these reasons, or so I will argue, moral realism is rendered a wholly unattractive and unconvincing meta-ethical position if it is coupled with an acknowledgement of epistemological moral scepticism. i Table of contents Part I: Introduction p. 1 1. p. 2 Introduction Part II: Moral Realism and Moral Anti-Realism p. 4 2. Moral Realism p. 5 Introduction The intuitive case in favour of moral realism The analogy with scientific realism The Frege-Geach Problem p. 5 p. 6 p. 9 p. 10 Moral Anti-Realism p. 14 Introduction G.E. Moore and the open-question argument Metaphysical and motivational worries Moral disagreement Evolutionary debunking arguments Moral explanations p. 14 p. 15 p. 18 p. 21 p. 22 p. 24 2.1 2.2 2.3 2.4 3. 3.1 3.2 3.3 3.4 3.5 3.6 Part III: Moral Epistemology p. 27 4. Anti-Realism and Moral Epistemology p. 28 Introduction An analysis of knowledge Non-cognitivism and epistemology Moral subjectivism and epistemology Error theory and epistemology p. 28 p. 28 p. 30 p. 33 p. 34 Moral Realist Epistemology p. 36 Introduction Moral intuitionism Coherentism Reflective equilibrium Two forms of epistemological naturalism Bridging the is/ought gap Moral reliabilism p. 36 p. 36 p. 38 p. 40 p. 42 p. 42 p. 43 4.1 4.2 4.3 4.4 4.5 5. 5.1 5.2 5.3 5.4 5.5 5.5.1 5.5.2 ii Part IV: The Relationship between Moral Realism and Epistemological Moral Scepticism 6. p. 45 The Meta-Ethical Consequences of Epistemic Inaccessibility p. 46 6.1 6.2 6.3 7. 7.1 7.2 7.3 Introduction A matter of logic? Identifying overriding considerations p. 46 p. 47 p. 48 Epistemic Inaccessibility and Moral Discourse p. 51 Introduction Moral discourse and suspension of judgment Epistemic inaccessibility and the intuitive case in favour of moral realism p. 51 p. 51 p. 53 Part V: Conclusion p. 56 8. p. 57 Bibliography Conclusion p. 58 iii Part I Introduction 1 Chapter 1 Introduction “[R]ealism is a metaphysical thesis about what is real and therefore it might be thought to be insulated from mundane concerns about whether we puny humans are or are not able to know that reality.”1 Much of the attention in twentieth-century meta-ethical debate has, in addition to matters of semantics, metaphysics and ontology, been devoted to issues of epistemology (such as the question whether a satisfactory moral realist epistemology has been formulated). Unfortunately, however, very little has been said about the relationship between epistemological moral scepticism2 (the view that we cannot or do not have knowledge of firstorder moral propositions) on the one hand and moral realism3 (a metaphysical view about the nature of moral facts) on the other hand. Indeed, the few philosophers that have said something about this relationship have often characterised it as a matter of logic whether epistemological moral scepticism and moral realism are compatible meta-ethical positions: “[S]kepticism about moral truth cannot be based on skepticism about moral knowledge, since lack of knowledge does not imply lack of truth. For similar reasons, skepticism about moral truth also cannot be based on skepticism about justified moral belief. Instead, skepticism about moral truth is usually based on views of moral language or metaphysics.” 4 So most often the discussions about this relationship are concluded with the observation that it does not seem possible to construct a logically cogent argument (starting from the premise that no moral knowledge can be had, leading to the conclusion that no moral facts exist) against moral realism on the basis of epistemological moral scepticism. This in turn means, so the argument goes, that the two are compatible: one can, in theory, simultaneously be a moral realist and an epistemological moral sceptic. This view has far-reaching consequences for the importance of epistemology for the moral realism/moral anti-realism debate. Indeed, if this view would be correct, this would mean that, even if the moral realist would be wholly incapable of presenting a convincing moral epistemology, moral realism could be salvaged on, for example, metaphysical and semantic grounds. In other words: if epistemological moral scepticism and moral realism are indeed compatible, this means that epistemological matters will be of less direct importance to the moral realist. If, on the other hand, the two turn out to be irreconcilable, then the moral realist task of defending a convincing epistemological theory against the attacks of epistemological moral scepticism has proved to be central to the moral realism/moral anti-realism debate. 1 K. DeLapp, Moral Realism, Bloomsbury Academic, 2013, p. 116. See chapter 6 for a more detailed discussion of epistemological moral scepticism. 3 See chapter 2 for a more detailed discussion of moral realism. 4 W. Sinnott-Armstrong, Moral Skepticisms, Oxford University Press, 2006, p. 11. Emphasis added. 2 2 In this thesis, I will argue that the epistemic inaccessibility5 of moral facts, which should lead one to endorse epistemological moral scepticism, not only creates an extra burden of proof for the moral realist, but that it also fatally undermines the most important positive arguments in favour of moral realism. For this reason, or so I will argue, moral realism is rendered a wholly unattractive and unconvincing meta-ethical position if it is coupled with an acknowledgement of epistemological moral scepticism. In order to be able to make this argument, I will start (in Part II of this thesis, which consists of chapters 2 and 3) by distinguishing carefully moral realism and moral anti-realism. In this discussion of the core commitments of (the most important forms of) moral realism and moral anti-realism I will also examine briefly the main arguments that are usually put forward in favour of these two meta-ethical views. The discussion of these arguments will be used in part IV of this thesis in order to assess the overall impact of epistemological moral scepticism on the moral realist position. After that, in Part III, I will turn to moral epistemology. More specifically, I will discuss the epistemological consequences and commitments of both moral realism and moral antirealism. This part of the thesis is necessary to get clear on what epistemological moral scepticism is and how attractive a position it is in the light of the current debates in moral epistemology. Then, in Part IV, the relationship between epistemological moral scepticism and moral realism will be discussed. It is in this part that I will adduce several arguments for my earlier claim that a combination of moral realism and epistemological moral scepticism together forms a wholly unconvincing meta-ethical position. Finally, in Part V of this thesis, I will end with a brief recapitulation of this thesis and with an overview of its most important conclusions. 5 See chapter 6 for a more detailed discussion of epistemic inaccessibility. 3 Part II Moral Realism and Moral AntiRealism 4 Chapter 2 Moral Realism “The realism/anti-realism debate in ethics has been around ever since people began thinking critically about their moral convictions. The problem has always been to make sense of these convictions in a way that does justice to morality’s apparent importance without engaging in outrageous metaphysical flights of fancy. Some have thought it can’t be done; they’ve held that the apparent importance of morality is mere appearance. Others have thought it can be done; they’ve held that whatever metaphysics is necessary is neither outrageous nor fanciful.” 6 2.1 Introduction The debate between moral realists and moral anti-realists, construed in its broadest form, concerns the nature of morality. The way this debate should be characterised in more detail is itself already a source of dispute. Some have argued that moral realism is best to be understood as analogous to scientific realism, which holds that “scientific theories should be understood as putative descriptions of real phenomena, that ordinary scientific methods constitute a reliable procedure for obtaining and improving (approximate) knowledge of the real phenomena which scientific theories describe, and that the reality described by scientific theories is largely independent of our theorizing”. 7 Such an account therefore distinguishes, in a manner analogous to scientific realism, (i) the truth-aptness of moral statements, (ii) the mind-independent truth or falsity of moral statements, and (iii) the reliability of moral reasoning as a method of attaining moral knowledge. The first aspect (the acknowledgement of the truth-aptness of moral statements) concerns semantics and is known as moral cognitivism. Moral non-cognitivism can therefore be characterised as the anti-realist thesis that moral statements are not descriptive in character: moral statements are expressions of non-cognitive attitudes (such as desires). As we will see in chapter 3, one of the main strategies of moral anti-realists has been to attack moral cognitivism and to argue in favour of moral non-cognitivism. The second aspect concerns the ontological status of moral facts, and the third aspect is epistemological in nature. Other philosophers have characterised moral realism as the view that “moral standards, or specific moral judgments, are correct in a way that does not depend on human endorsement or on the implications of human commitments”.8 Again others have appealed to the notion of objectivity in order to define moral realism: “moral questions have correct answers, […] moral facts are determined by circumstances, and […], by moralizing, we can discover what these objective moral facts determined by the circumstances are”.9 G. Sayre-McCord, “The Many Moral Realisms,” Southern Journal of Philosophy, Spindel Conference Supplement, 1986, p. 2-3. 7 R. Boyd, “How to be a moral realist”, in: R. Shafer-Landau (ed.), Metaphysics, vol. II, Routledge, 2008, p. 312. 8 R. Shafer-Landau, Metaphysics, vol. I, Routledge, 2008, p. 8. 9 M. Smith, “Realism”, in: P. Singer (ed.), A Companion to Ethics, Blackwell, 1990, p. 399. Emphasis added. 6 5 It is this diversity in conceptions of moral realism that has led to what can indeed be called “the many moral realisms”.10 But despite the differences it is possible to formulate a more or less conventional (yet rather general) version of moral realism. According to such a conception, which will be the conception of moral realism I will use throughout this thesis, (i) moral claims purport to report moral facts in virtue of which these moral claims are either true or false (i.e., moral claims are truth-apt), and (ii) at least some of these moral claims are mindindependently11 true. By accepting moral realism’s commitment to the mind-independent existence of moral facts, I am restricting my definition of moral realism to what has become known as robust moral realism. This means that so-called minimal moral realism, which shares all other characteristics of robust moral realism apart from its metaphysical commitment to the mind-independent existence of moral facts, will not be included in the definition of moral realism I will use throughout this thesis. I will rather discuss this view, as is often done12, as a form of anti-realism called moral subjectivism13. Finally, it is important to note that my definition of moral realism does not make any reference to the epistemological aspects of moral realism, like for example Boyd’s definition does. The reason is that an epistemologically neutral definition of moral realism is needed to inquire, as I will do in part IV of this thesis, whether moral realism and epistemological moral scepticism are compatible. In this chapter, however, I will not yet discuss moral realist epistemology. This chapter will be concerned with the other grounds on which moral realism has been defended. This chapter will therefore revolve around the most important14 non-epistemological arguments that are usually put forward in defence of moral realism. In the following chapter (chapter 3) I will do the same for the most prominent anti-realist theories. In this way these two chapters, which together form part II of this thesis, provide a rough outline of both the central theses of the main meta-ethical theories and of the most important arguments that are employed in current meta-ethical debates. 2.2 The intuitive case in favour of moral realism The most important argument in favour of moral realism is founded on the role morality and moral judgments play in our ordinary, quotidian lives. This argument concerns semantics: it takes as its starting point the fact that our ordinary moral claims (at least seem to) purport to report (moral) facts. We do not merely claim that we think that genocide is wrong; we claim that it is wrong. So moral realism invites us to take claims like “genocide is wrong” at face value (i.e., as claims that purport to report moral facts). If this declarative form of our moral G. Sayre-McCord, “The Many Moral Realisms,” Southern Journal of Philosophy, Spindel Conference Supplement, 1986. 11 See paragraph 3.1 for a more detailed discussion of the concept of “mind-independence”. 12 R. Joyce, “Moral Anti-Realism”, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2009 Edition), E.N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2009/entries/moral-anti-realism/>. 13 Moral subjectivism will be discussed in more detail in sections 3.1 and 4.4. 14 I will of course not aim for a complete overview of all the arguments that have been put forward in favour of moral realism. I will, therefore, restrict myself to the arguments that are most often used by moral realists, and that are, to my view, the strongest arguments in favour of moral realism. 10 6 judgments is taken at face value, then the conclusion that in ordinary moral discourse we purport to report moral facts seems warranted. Furthermore, we usually engage in debates about moral questions, during which we often feel as though we can separate moral mistake and moral insight. Such debates are typically meant to discover, as much as possible, moral truth. This is difficult to reconcile with the moral subjectivist view that moral facts are constituted by our moral attitudes and moral opinions. In short: our ordinary sense of morality is one that seems to presuppose the reality of the moral facts which are at the centre of our moral discourse. But if such moral facts would not exist, so the moral realist argument runs, all these ordinary moral claims would be false. Our moral discourse would be fundamentally mistaken and we would be forced to become error theorists.15 So the fact that moral realism “explains the point and nature of moral inquiry” is therefore taken to provide it with its “intuitive appeal”.16 In other words: “[I]t is distinctive of moral practice that we are concerned to get the answers to moral questions right. But this concern presupposes that there are correct answers to be had. It thus seems to presuppose that there exists a domain of moral facts about which we can form beliefs and about which we may be mistaken.”17 So according to the moral realist both of the two core commitments of moral realism formulated earlier (the truth-aptness of moral claims and the mind-independent truth of at least some of our moral claims) are reflected in our everyday moral discourse. After all, our moral discourse is aimed at moral truth and thereby shows a belief in the mind-independent existence of moral facts. This, so the moral realist often claims, should lead us to accept at least an argumentative presumption in favour of moral realism: “We begin as (tacit) cognitivists and realists about ethics. Moral claims make assertions, which can be true or false; some people are more perceptive than others; and people’s moral views have not only changed over time but have improved in many cases (e.g., as regards slavery). We are led to some form of antirealism (if we are) only because we come to regard the moral realist’s commitments as untenable […]. Moral realism should be our metaethical starting point, and we should give it up only if it does involve unacceptable metaphysical and epistemological commitments.”18 So both the phenomenology19 behind and the form and content20 of our moral statements seem to presuppose a firm belief in objective moral truth. This means that, if we reject moral realism, we have to take our moral semantics as “misleading and inappropriate”. 21 We would have to be error theorists or offer an alternative interpretation and explanation of our moral discourse. 15 Error theory will be discussed in detail in paragraph 3.3. D. Brink, Moral Realism and the Foundations of Ethics, Cambridge University Press, 1989, p. 8. 17 Ibid., p. 263 18 Ibid., p. 23-24. Emphasis added. 19 J. Mackie, Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong, Penguin: 1977, chapter 1. 20 D. Brink, Moral Realism and the Foundations of Ethics, Cambridge University Press, 1989, p. 26. 21 Ibid., p. 26. 16 7 But is this, as the proponents of moral realism claim, indeed sufficient to establish something like an argumentative presumption in favour of moral realism? The first thing to notice about this question is that, even if one accepts that our moral phenomenology and our moral discourse are best interpreted as bearing an assumption of cognitivism, one can hold that this does not single out moral realism as enjoying the privilege of best explaining this phenomenon. After all, an error theorist likewise acknowledges the fact that moral claims purport to describe reality. So even if one accepts that the character of our moral discourse generates a prima facie burden of proof for the non-cognitivist, this does not as such create such a burden for all forms of anti-realism. Indeed, the error theorist combines an acknowledgement of cognitivism with the anti-realist claim that all our moral claims are false, because as it turns out there are no moral facts. The moral realist can, however, of course argue that this second claim puts the error theorist in a position similar to the non-cognitivist’s, because it too implies that our moral discourse is somehow fundamentally misguided. This, so the moral realist argument would run, is a conclusion which likewise bears the burden of being highly counterintuitive. But even if we ignore the error theorist for a moment, and rather restrict our focus to the noncognitivist, it seems that he has two ways of answering the question whether the relevant moral phenomena give moral realism a prima facie advantage. The first option is to accept such a prima facie advantage, but to argue that there are overriding considerations in other relevant meta-ethical fields (e.g., moral metaphysics or moral epistemology) which point in the direction of non-cognitivism. This strategy does not directly challenge our intuitions concerning our moral judgments, but it rather tries to establish the non-cognitive character of our moral judgments on other meta-ethical grounds. Most non-cognitivists in fact choose to accept this argumentative burden.22 However, this strategy is often coupled with a trivialisation of such a concession. Such non-cognitivists argue that the importance of moral phenomenology and moral language as intuitive devices should not be overstated. After all, the inference from these moral appearances to moral realism is one that requires substantial argumentation. As a result, the non-cognitivist conclusion is that what has merely been accepted is a defeasible burden of proof in favour of the moral realist. It is of course subject of debate how strong23 such defeating considerations must be (or, stated in other words, how strong a presumption in favour of moral realism or cognitivism is created by the form and content of our ordinary moral discourse). This question, however, is in effect nothing more than a question about the relative weight of different arguments in meta-ethics. Moral anti-realists will be inclined to attach less weight to the intuitions that are reflected by our moral discourse, and more weight to, for example, problems of moral disagreement and the perceived lack of a satisfactory moral realist metaphysics. So although there is something to be said for singling out our moral intuitions as giving rise to an argumentative burden of proof (it is after all not completely arbitrary to take one’s pre-theoretical judgments as the R. Joyce, “Moral Anti-Realism”, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2009 Edition), E.N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2009/entries/moral-anti-realism/>. 23 Cf. D. Brink, Moral Realism and the Foundations of Ethics, Cambridge University Press, 1989, p. 24: “[…] only if there are powerful objections to moral realism”. 22 8 starting point of one’s investigation), it is important to realise that the outcome of the moral realism/moral anti-realism debate depends on “how well realism fares vis-à-vis its competitors across the whole range of criteria for theoretical adequacy in metaethics”.24 As useful as our intuitions might be as the starting point of meta-ethical inquiry, it therefore seems there is no reason to treat them as argumentatively privileged compared to other types of meta-ethical arguments. So we have seen that the first option for the non-cognitivist is to accept a prima facie advantage in favour of the cognitivist, while arguing for non-cognitivism on the basis of other meta-ethical considerations. The second option is to deny that moral phenomenology and moral language pose a challenge to the non-cognitivist in the first place. This non-cognitive line of argument directly challenges our intuitions concerning our moral judgments, by inviting us to reconsider our meta-ethical intuitions: if, after careful reflection, it turns out that a non-cognitivist interpretation of our moral discourse somehow makes better sense of our moral practice, then the non-cognitivist has succeeded in shifting the burden of proof. If one is to employ this strategy, one has to provide an argument for the claim that, despite appearances, our moral judgments are not declarative, but are rather, for example, expressions of (dis)approval or as imperatives. In chapter 3 I will go deeper into the different varieties of anti-realism and the arguments that are usually put forward in their defence. For the purposes of this paragraph it is sufficient to note that the anti-realist (or cognitivist, if one is not persuaded by the moral realist argument that the error theorist likewise bears an argumentative burden of proof) can either accept or reject the “intuitive case for moral realism” without having to surrender his anti-realism. 2.3 The analogy with scientific realism Another important argument in favour of moral realism departs from the fact that most philosophers nowadays accept scientific realism, i.e. “the doctrine that the methods of science are capable of providing (partial or approximate) knowledge of unobservable (‘theoretical’) entities, such as atoms or electromagnetic fields”.25 Scientific realists are, therefore, not only realists with regard to the observable, external world, but also with regard to unobservable entities. This scientific realism is usually taken to be the best explanation of the success of the natural sciences. Indeed, as Boyd claims, scientific methodology is “reliable at producing further knowledge precisely because, and to the extent that, currently accepted theories are relevantly approximately true”.26 For this reason moral realists want to draw an analogy between scientific realism and moral realism. If scientific theory is best explained on the assumption that it approximates the truth, then could that not, in a similar fashion, apply to moral theory and unobservable moral entities? Moral anti-realists have often given a negative answer to this question in one of two ways: they have either stressed the difference between superficial scientific disagreement and 24 R. Shafer-Landau, Moral Realism: A Defence, Oxford University Press, 2003, p. 234. Emphasis added. R. Boyd, “How to be a moral realist”, in: G. Sayre-McCord (ed.), Essays on Moral Realism, Cornell University Press, 1988, p. 188. 26 Ibid., p. 190. 25 9 (what appears to be) deep, irresolvable moral disagreement, or they have placed emphasis on the disanalogy between the objective character of the natural sciences and the subjective and personal nature of moral discourse. These two challenges, however, have not prevented moral realists from hanging on to the analogy between scientific realism and moral realism. With regard to the first anti-realist response, moral realists have sometimes tried to argue that scientific disagreements can also be of a deep, irresolvable nature, and, more often, they have tried to explain away deep moral disagreement. In paragraph 3.4 I will discuss these strategies in more detail. With regard to the second anti-realist claim, moral realists contend that, although moral discourse can be said to be at least partially based on moral presuppositions, the natural sciences are also deeply theory-laden, and are therefore “partners in guilt”27: “In science, agreement in those observational judgments that involve ascriptions of real physical properties such as mass may depend upon agreement in background theory. In this sense observations are ‘theory-laden’”.28 So what we take to be objective and “real” scientific knowledge seems to be compatible with theoretical presuppositions. For this reason moral realists have held that a moral methodology like the search for reflective equilibrium29 can therefore likewise be defended as a legitimate way of attaining moral knowledge through the use of theoretical presuppositions. It is not surprising that both moral realist answers have in turn been challenged by the moral anti-realist. The question whether these challenges to the moral realist analogy between scientific and moral realism are successful is beyond the scope of this thesis, but it is important to note that if the moral anti-realist proves incapable of providing us with good reasons to place more emphasis on the differences rather than on the similarities between the natural sciences and moral discourse, the moral realist will have found a strong argument in favour of moral realism. 2.4 The Frege-Geach Problem As we have seen in paragraph 2.3, one of the most important arguments for moral realism derives from the nature of our moral discourse. In this paragraph we will see that the nature of our moral discourse has also led to the formulation of one of the most important arguments against non-cognitivism (and therefore, in an indirect way, to an important argument in favour of moral realism): the Frege-Geach Problem. In this paragraph the Frege-Geach Problem will be discussed, in order to show why “[m]uch if not all of the recent innovations in noncognitivist theorizing stem from attempts to answer the Frege-Geach objection”30 and why it D. Brink, “Moral Realism and the Sceptical Arguments from Disagreement and Queerness”, Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 1984: 62, p. 124. 28 A. Goldman, Epistemology and Cognition, Harvard University Press, 1986, p. 171. 29 Coherentist epistemologies like the search for reflective equilibrium will be discussed in paragraph 5.3. 30 M. van Roojen, “Moral Cognitivism vs. Non-Cognitivism”, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2013 Edition), E,N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2013/entries/moral-cognitivism/>. 27 10 is considered one of the most important arguments in favour of cognitivism (and hence, by significantly diminishing the appeal of one of its main anti-realist rivals, in favour of moral realism). A useful starting point for a discussion of the Frege-Geach Problem is a characterisation of the nature of non-cognitivism. Non-cognitivists usually make three claims concerning the nature of moral statements: “The first claim is that moral sentences do not have truth-values. The second claim is that moral assertions do not describe the world. The third claim is that moral assertions do express emotions or other non-cognitive states, such as attitudes or desires.” 31 Many different forms of non-cognitivism have been developed over the course of the twentieth century. One can for example point to emotivism (Ayer), prescriptivism (Carnap, Hare), expressivism (Stevenson) and quasi-realism (Blackburn, Gibbard). Some of these varieties of non-cognitivism do not (expressly) endorse the third claim: prescriptivism, for example, places emphasis on the non-descriptive character of moral statements rather than on any supposed emotional origin. In chapter 3 more will be said about these different varieties of non-cognitivism, but for now it is sufficient to note that most forms of non-cognitivism share the three characteristics formulated above. Now, the key motivation behind the Frege-Geach Problem is the fact that non-cognitivism has difficulties to explain how moral terms can function the way they do in moral discourse and yet be non-descriptive. For example, it seems as though “everything you can do syntactically with a descriptive predicate like ‘green’, you can do with a moral predicate like ‘wrong’, and when you do those things, they have the same semantic effects”.32 The non-cognitivist commitment to the non-descriptive character of moral terms, however, leads to substantial difficulties when moral terms are being used in semantically complex sentences (sentences in which moral terms are embedded). For this reason the Frege-Geach Problem is also known as “the embedding problem”. The perceived problem is that a sentence like “it is wrong to steal”, understood as a nondescriptive expression of a non-cognitive state, cannot explain the semantic properties of embedded sentences in which “it is wrong to steal” occurs. For example, how are we to understand an embedded sentence like “I wonder whether it is wrong to steal” in the framework of Ayer’s theory of meaning? It seems as though such a sentence cannot be satisfactorily explained by interpreting “wrong” as the expression of “a special sort of moral disapproval”33. Similar worries arise for conditionals: (P1) (P2) If tormenting the cat is bad, getting your little brother to do it is bad Tormenting the cat is bad 31 W. Sinnott-Armstrong, Moral Skepticisms, Oxford University Press, 2006, p. 18. M. Schroeder, “What is the Frege-Geach Problem?”, Philosophy Compass, Vol. 3, July 2008, p. 704. 33 A. J. Ayer, “The Emotive Theory of Ethics”, in: G. Sher (ed.), Moral Philosophy: Selected Readings, Harcourt, Brace & Howe, 1996, p. 124. 32 11 Ergo, getting your little brother to torment the cat is bad34 The reason this modus ponens argument is valid, according to Geach, is that “tormenting the cat is bad” has a constant meaning in embedded and unembedded contexts. This is the socalled “Frege Point”, due to which the embedding problem is now also known as the FregeGeach Problem: “A thought may have the just the same content whether you assent to its truth or not; a proposition may occur in discourse now asserted, now unasserted, and yet be recognizably the same proposition.”35 The crucial part of the Frege-Geach Problem is the claim that the non-cognitivist cannot hold that the meaning of “tormenting the cat is bad” is constant in the first and the second premise. After all, it makes no sense to treat the unasserted use of “tormenting the cat is bad” in the first premise as an expression of an emotion or as an imperative. If, however, it turns out that we can make valid arguments on the basis of a combination of asserted and unasserted components of complex sentences like conditionals, then it seems that, in line with the Frege Point, we are forced to the conclusion that the meaning of the phrase “tormenting the cat is bad” has to remain constant in the first and the second premise. But this is exactly what the non-cognitivist cannot accept: the unasserted antecedent in the first premise cannot be taken in the same way as the asserted second premise is to be understood (i.e. as the expression of a non-cognitive state). Therefore, the non-cognitivist cannot explain the validity of the use of modus ponens in Geach’s example. The worry can be put more generally in terms of truth-functionality. As we have seen, noncognitivists reject the view that moral statements are truth-apt. In other words, they claim that moral statements do not carry a truth value.36 The problem, however, is that such truth values are usually taken to provide the key to explaining the workings of predicate expressions and logical connectives in complex sentences. The Frege-Geach problem is therefore not just restricted to the perceived incapability of non-cognitivism to explain validity, but also extends to “semantic properties” as such: “The problem is that noncognitivists must provide us with recipes for how to construct the meanings of any kind of complex sentence from the meanings of their parts, and that these recipes must ‘get things right’, in the sense that they must allow for an explanation of the features that the resulting complex sentences have, in virtue of their meaning. These are […] ‘semantic properties’.”37 Logicians and truth-conditional semanticists have captured these semantic properties in truth tables. These truth tables are meant to provide a truth function, which in turn specifies how the truth value of a composite sentence is a function of the truth values of its component P. Geach, “Assertion”, Philosophical Review, 74, 1965, p. 463. P. Geach, “Assertion”, Philosophical Review, 74, 1965, p. 449. 36 G. Frege, “Über Sinn und Bedeutung“, Zeitschrift für Philosophie und philosophische Kritik, 1892, p. 25-50. 37 M. Schroeder, Noncognitivism in Ethics, Routledge, 2010, p. 54 34 35 12 sentences. In this way, complicated sentences can be assigned truth conditions by formulating logical operators like “and”, “or”, “not” and “if…then” in terms of their truth values. These truth-conditional recipes for the workings of logical operators provide, for example, an explanation of the internal inconsistency in the sentence “it is wrong to steal and it is not wrong to steal”. This, so the moral realist claims, is something non-cognitivism is unable to explain, because of the fact that non-cognitivists refuse to assign truth-values to moral statements. The Frege-Geach Problem is an important reason why more and more philosophers have been tempted to abandon non-cognitivism and accept either moral realism or other (anti-realist) cognitivist theories like Mackie’s error theory. But although the Frege-Geach Problem has proved to be a persistent one, many non-cognitivists have tried to supplement their theories with answers concerning the problem of embedding. One can for example point to the acceptance of a minimalist (or deflationary) account of truth38, the attempt to formulate a logic of (higher-order) attitudes39 and the use of possible world semantics in order to explain the functioning of normative language40. All of these attempts to salvage non-cognitivism are worth a thesis-length discussion in their own right. For the purposes of this thesis, however, it is sufficient to note that these attempts have not succeeded in reducing the Frege-Geach Problem to a peripheral problem for non-cognitivism: it is still widely considered to be one of the most convincing arguments in favour of cognitivism and moral realism.41 38 See paragraph 4.3 for a discussion of such a deflationary conception of truth. S. Blackburn, “Attitudes and Contents”, Ethics: 98, 1988, p. 501-517. 40 A. Gibbard, Wise Choices, Apt Feelings. A Theory of Normative Judgement, Clarendon Press, 1990. 41 R. Shafer-Landau , Metaphysics, vol. I, Routledge, 2008, p. 13. 39 13 Chapter 3 Moral Anti-Realism “But how could it be that a discourse that is familiar to a group of perfectly intelligent people – one that they employ every day without running into any trouble or confusion – is so mistaken?”42 3.1 Introduction In the previous chapter I have tried to elucidate the development of moral realism and the arguments that have been put forward in its defence. This chapter, however, will be concerned with the meta-ethical negation of moral realism: moral anti-realism. In chapter 2 the three most important forms of anti-realism have already been discussed briefly. Firstly, there is non-cognitivism. Non-cognitivists hold that moral judgments do not even aim at moral truth; they are to be understood as something radically different from descriptive judgments like “the cat is on the mat”. On this view moral judgments are not to be taken as expressions of beliefs but rather as “expressive vehicles”.43 Secondly, we have come across Mackie’s error theory. Error theorists, like moral realists, subscribe to the semantic thesis that our moral judgments purport to describe real moral facts, but in addition they hold that all such moral judgments are in fact false, because no such moral facts exist. According to the error theorist, therefore, our moral judgments are all predicated on the same mistaken ontological presupposition: that moral facts exist in the first place. Thirdly, and lastly, there is moral subjectivism, which holds that moral facts exist in a mind-dependent manner. It is important to note that the notion of “mind-independence”, although frequently used to delineate moral realism and moral anti-realism, is notoriously ambiguous: “Something may be mind-independent in one sense and mind-dependent in another. Cars, for example, are designed and constructed by creatures with minds, and yet in another sense cars are clearly concrete, non-subjective entities. Much careful disambiguation is needed before we know how to circumscribe subjectivism, and different philosophers disambiguate differently.” 44 Similar worries arise for non-physical entities like legal systems. Legal systems are likewise constructed and designed by the (mental) activities of human beings, and can therefore be taken to be, in one sense, mind-dependent, but they are also objective in the sense that their existence and their content is not dependent on my attitudes towards or my opinions about them. Robust moral realism, as we have seen, is the view that there is no sense in which moral facts can be taken as mind-dependent. Indeed, one important implication of my definition of moral realism as robust moral realism is that, pace some forms of moral subjectivism, “an individual or even an entire culture might be “wrong” about moral matters”.45 42 R. Joyce, The Myth of Morality, Cambridge University Press, 2001, p. 2. R. Shafer-Landau, Moral Realism: A Defence, Oxford University Press, 2003, p. 18. 44 Ibid., p. 18. 45 K. DeLapp, Moral Realism, Bloomsbury Academic, 2013, p. 1. 43 14 In the remainder of this thesis, I will therefore take moral subjectivism to be the view that the existence of moral facts, at least in some way, depends on our (mental) activity. Moral subjectivists therefore disagree with the robust moral realist thesis that moral facts are real, objective facts, which do “not depend on human endorsement or on the implications of human commitments”.46 On this subjectivist view “moral laws are human laws, made by, and for, humans”.47 In this chapter I will start by discussing the developments that led to the emergence of moral anti-realism. After that, in paragraphs 3.3 – 3.6, I will examine the most important arguments for the three different anti-realist positions I have distinguished here. In this chapter I will not yet go specifically into epistemological matters, even though the perceived failure of the proponents of moral realism to provide a satisfactory moral epistemology is often used as an important argument in favour of anti-realism. The reason I will not yet discuss such epistemological arguments in this chapter is the same reason I did not touch upon moral epistemology in the previous chapter: these epistemological matters will be the subject of detailed, critical scrutiny in later chapters of this thesis. 3.2 G.E. Moore and the open-question argument In order to understand the emergence of moral anti-realism, it is instructive to start by looking at perhaps the most important event in meta-ethical history: the publication of G.E. Moore’s Principia Ethica. This publication sparked the development of moral anti-realism by discrediting “moral naturalism”, the view that was then seen as the most attractive form of moral realism. In this paragraph I will discuss G.E. Moore’s so-called “open-question argument” and the way it has influenced twentieth-century meta-ethical debate. In 1903 G.E. Moore’s Principia Ethica was published.48 In this book, and especially by means of his “open-question argument”, Moore propounds a thoroughly non-naturalist metaethical theory. In order to get a grasp on Moore’s open-question argument, it is important to distinguish firstly naturalism and non-naturalism, both of which are varieties of moral realism. Now, most often “non-naturalism” denotes “the metaphysical thesis that moral properties exist and are not identical with or reducible to any natural property or properties in some interesting sense of ‘natural’”.49 Moral naturalism, on the other hand, holds that such an identity or reducibility relation does exist between moral and natural properties. So both views hold that moral properties exist; the difference between the two lies in their answers to the question whether these moral properties are identical with or reducible to natural properties. Shafer-Landau, for example, holds that moral properties are best described as ontologically sui generis: although moral properties are constituted by natural properties, they are not identical to them.50 This can be compared to the realisability-vocabulary which is 46 R. Shafer-Landau , Metaphysics, vol. I, Routledge, 2008, p. 8. R. Shafer-Landau, Moral Realism: A Defence, Oxford University Press, 2003, p. 1. 48 G.E. Moore, Principia Ethica, Cambridge University Press, 1993. 49 M. Ridge, "Moral Non-Naturalism", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2014 Edition), E. N. Zalta (ed.), forthcoming URL = <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2014/entries/moral-non-naturalism/>. 50 R. Shafer-Landau, Moral Realism: A Defence, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2003, p. 73. 47 15 sometimes used in the philosophy of mind to characterise the relationship between mental and physical properties. But even with this difference in metaphysical outlook in mind, it remains unclear what exactly is meant by “natural”. According to Shafer-Landau, there are two ways to construe the dichotomy between natural and non-natural: “The first [path] tries to identify some distinctive feature of the natural, that possessed intrinsically by all and only natural properties, and the feature in virtue of which they count as natural. The second is a disciplinary approach, which defines the natural in terms of the subject matters of various disciplines. I prefer the second path.” 51 So the first path is by attempting to find the necessary and sufficient conditions for a certain property to be a natural one. For example, the property of being material or of being a feature of the world. But attempting to find such a property has turned out to be a highly unfruitful task. Therefore, most philosophers take the disciplinary approach and hold that naturalism is the view that “all real properties are those that would figure ineliminably in perfected versions of the natural and social sciences”.52 With this distinction in mind, let us now turn to Moore’s open-question argument. This argument is meant to show that moral properties cannot be analysed in natural terms. This is of course in line with his claim that moral naturalists are guilty of a “naturalistic fallacy”, since they draw conclusions concerning moral properties on the basis of premises concerning natural properties. The idea here is that “evaluative conclusions require at least one evaluative premise – purely factual premises about the naturalistic features of things do not entail or even support evaluative conclusions.”53 Moore’s open-question argument is construed as follows. Taking the hedonist’s account of the nature of the good as an example (“pleasure is good”), Moore argues that it always remains an open question whether something pleasant is, indeed, good. In other words: a competent moral agent can always question whether a certain natural property is really morally good. If to say that something is pleasant would simply be another way of saying that something is good, the question would not be an open one. If that would be the case, it would be similar to asking whether pleasure is pleasant: “[W]hoever will attentively consider with himself what is actually before his mind when he asks the question “Is pleasure (or whatever it may be) after all good?” can easily satisfy himself that he is not merely wondering whether pleasure is pleasant.” 54 So, unlike the question whether pleasure is pleasant, the question whether any proposed natural property N really is M (a certain moral property) will always remain a conceptually open question. 51 Ibid., p. 58. Ibid., p. 59. 53 M. Ridge, "Moral Non-Naturalism", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2014 Edition), E. N. Zalta (ed.), forthcoming URL = <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2014/entries/moral-non-naturalism/>. 54 G.E. Moore, Principia Ethica, Cambridge University Press, 1971, p. 16. 52 16 Moore therefore concludes that moral properties like “goodness” cannot be captured in natural terms. In contrast, they are “simple”, unanalysable and non-natural properties: “If I am asked, “What is good?” my answer is that good is good, and that is the end of the matter. Or if I am asked “How is good to be defined?” my answer is that it cannot be defined, and that is all I have to say about it. [...] My point is that good is a simple notion, just as yellow is a simple notion; that, just as you cannot, by any manner of means, explain to anyone who does not already know it, what yellow is, so you cannot explain what good is.” 55 Much can be said about this argument and about whether it should be considered persuasive. Although a detailed discussion of this argument would therefore be beyond the scope of this thesis, I will make a few brief comments on the strength of the argument. Firstly, it is clear that the argument can be read as a question-begging one. After all, the premise that the relevant questions are open questions seems to entail the falsity of moral naturalism. So what remains of Moore’s argument if the moral naturalist would simply deny this main premise and hold that such questions would not be open questions? For this reason, it seems warranted to hold that the open-question argument must be interpreted as an inference to the best explanation: “On this interpretation, the main premise of the argument is not that the relevant questions are conceptually open, but the much more modest premise that they at least seem conceptually open to competent users of moral terms. The argument then proceeds to claim that the best explanation of its seeming to competent users of the terms that these questions are open is that they really are open. [...] This argument does not beg the question insofar as the opponent of non-naturalism can grant that the relevant questions do seem open without thereby contradicting their position—the main premise of this argument does not directly entail non-naturalism.”56 This, however, still does not go so far as to establish what Moore claims it does. After all, Moore implicitly assumes that moral naturalism has to take a conceptually reductionist form. His attack is therefore limited to such reductionist forms of moral naturalism.57 But besides that, a crucial (and highly contestable) assumption in Moore’s argument is that the answer to the question whether two terms are synonymous is also an answer to the question whether the things these terms refer to are identical. In other words: Moore uses synonymy as a criterion for property identity. After all, his argument is that because the good cannot be given a naturalistic definition, the good cannot be identical to any natural property. This means that Moore requires identity relations to be true by definition. But it is not at all clear whether such an account of property identity should be accepted. If, for example, one is tempted to accept Kripke’s causal theory of reference, with its account of necessary a posteriori truths (“water = H2O”), one will be inclined to reject Moore’s synonymy criterion of property identity. 55 G.E. Moore, Principia Ethica, Cambridge University Press, 1971, p. 12-13. M. Ridge, "Moral Non-Naturalism", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2014 Edition), E. N. Zalta (ed.), forthcoming URL = <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2014/entries/moral-non-naturalism/>. 57 For further reading on this point, see S. Ball, “Linguistic Intuitions and Varieties of Ethical Naturalism,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 51, 1991, p. 1-30. 56 17 Unfortunately a more detailed discussion of Moore’s argument against moral naturalism is beyond the scope of this thesis58, but it should be clear that the success of Moore’s openquestion argument is, to say the very least, highly disputed. Some philosophers even go so far to claim that it “is nowadays widely regarded as having failed of its ultimate purpose”.59 But although the open-question argument has been subjected to fierce criticism, historically it has attracted wide support. As the argument that was taken to have discredited moral naturalism, it is hard to overestimate the influence of Moore’s open-question argument and his Principia Ethica in general on the development of meta-ethics in the twentieth century. Indeed, as Thomas Baldwin rightly puts it: “[A]lthough Moore was taken to have refuted ‘ethical naturalism’, Moore’s own brand of ‘ethical non-naturalism’ was thought to make unacceptable metaphysical and epistemological demands; so the only recourse was to abandon belief in an objective moral reality and accept an emotivist, prescriptivist or otherwise anti-realist, account of ethical values”.60 So the combination of the perceived strength of Moore’s argument against moral naturalism and the “unacceptable metaphysical and epistemological demands” of moral non-naturalism, led many philosophers to doubt moral realism altogether: “In reaction, and in the name of removing mystery, [some] have questioned the idea that our moral claims are meaningful in the way Moore supposes. We might steer clear of the Naturalistic Fallacy and avoid a commitment to strange non-natural properties, they point out, by rejecting the assumption that in calling something good we are describing it. […] On this theory, to say of something that it is good is (roughly) to recommend it, and to show one’s approval of it, but not to report any fact about it. It thus neatly eliminates the need to introduce non-natural properties into our ontology, but it does so by abandoning the notion of moral facts.” 61 3.3 Metaphysical and motivational worries As we have seen in the previous paragraph, one of the most important motivations behind moral anti-realism is the perceived metaphysical failure of moral realism. This perceived failure is due to a moral realist dilemma G.E. Moore unintentionally created: either accept moral naturalism and find a way to answer (among other things) the open-question argument, or resort to moral non-naturalism and try to take away the worries about its perceived mysterious and “metaphysically outrageous”62 character. According to the anti-realist both these horns of the dilemma ultimately lead to insurmountable obstacles for the moral realist. Indeed, in the previous paragraph I have already explained why most moral anti-realists considered Moore’s open-question argument a good reason to abandon naturalist versions of For such detailed discussions, see W.K. Frankema, “The Naturalistic Fallacy”, Mind, 1939: 48, p. 464-477, F. Jackson and P. Pettit, “Moral Functionalism and Moral Motivation,” Philosophical Quarterly, 1995: 45, p. 20– 40. 59 R. Shafer-Landau , Metaphysics, vol. I, Routledge, 2008, p. 3. 60 T.Baldwin, G.E. Moore, Routledge, 1990, p. 66. 61 G. Sayre-McCord, “The Many Moral Realisms,” Southern Journal of Philosophy, Spindel Conference Supplement, 1986, p. 4. 62 Ibid., p. 2-3. 58 18 moral realism. In this paragraph I will – in addition to a general metaphysical worry about moral realism – also discuss a metaphysical objection which is specifically aimed at moral non-naturalism. Now, one of the reasons moral non-naturalism is taken by many to be an unacceptable position is that the non-naturalist has problems explaining moral supervenience. In order to elaborate on this argument, it is instructive to firstly get clear on the concept of supervenience. A supervenience thesis is the thesis that “there could be no difference of one sort without differences of another sort”.63 Applied to morality, moral supervenience can therefore be defined as the view that there can be no difference in moral properties without a difference in natural properties. So if one accepts that moral properties supervene on natural properties (as indeed most, if not all, philosophers do), one thereby claims that if two properties are identical in all natural respects, they cannot differ in their non-natural (i.e., moral) respects. The problem for the non-naturalist is how to explain such a supervenience relation between two distinct types of properties: “As Hume might ask, Whence this necessary connection between distinct existences? Moore himself wrote, “If a thing is good (in my sense), then that it is so follows from the fact that it possesses certain natural intrinsic properties.” Just what the connection is, and in what sense moral properties “follow from” natural ones, Moore was never able to explain. The [nonnaturalist], then, seems to be saddled with what Blackburn calls “an opaque, isolated, logical fact, for which no explanation can be proffered”, an extra law of metaphysics.” 64 So the charge is that non-naturalists cannot meet the explanatory demand that is created by posing the existence of non-natural properties in the light of the plausibility of moral supervenience. This explanatory demand consists in the fact that the existence of a supervenience relation between moral and natural properties seems to be difficult to reconcile with the non-naturalist insistence on the fundamental distinctness of these properties. In addition, moral realists in general have been attacked on the grounds of metaphysical and psychological worries about motivational force. A first version of this attacks starts by claiming that moral realism posits the existence of “qualities or relations of a very strange sort, utterly different from anything in the world”.65 This attack has become known as Mackie’s Argument from Queerness. The argument is that if objective moral properties would exist, they would be metaphysically queer: their existence would require us to acknowledge the existence of “objective prescriptions”66, which are to be found nowhere else in the fabric of the world. Moral properties would be “intrinsically prescriptive entities or features of some kind”67, which would, by their very nature, carry motivational power. In other words: moral properties would, necessarily, have the power to “supply both a categorical reason for action for everyone, and the motivation to pursue such action to anyone who rightly appreciated 63 D. Lewis, On The Plurality of Worlds, Blackwell, 1986, p. 14. J. Dreier, “The Supervenience Argument Against Moral Realism, The Southern Journal of Philosophy, 1992: 30, p. 17. 65 J. Mackie, Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong, Penguin: 1977, p. 38 66 Ibid., p. 29. 67 Ibid., p. 40. 64 19 it”.68 It is this characteristic of moral properties as sui generis entities which is taken by Mackie to provide a puzzle for the moral realist. More usually, however, the debate about the supposed mysterious nature of morality’s motivational force has not revolved around the role of moral properties, but of moral judgments.69 Moral judgments (e.g. judgments like “giving to charity is a morally virtuous act”) are taken by many to necessarily carry a certain motivational force. Those who hold that such a necessary or conceptual connection holds between sincere moral judgment and moral motivation are called moral judgment internalists.70 Wedgwood, for example, holds that “there are powerful reasons in favour of […] the view that there is an essential or “internal” connection between normative judgments and practical reasoning or motivation for action”.71 One such powerful reason is that only moral judgment internalism is taken to provide a convincing explanation of why changes in moral judgment ordinarily lead to changes in moral motivation.72 It is, however, a source of dispute between moral judgment internalists how strong this intrinsic connection is (for example, whether it is an all-things-considered connection or whether it merely establishes that insofar as someone is rational (i.e. insofar as the possibility of akrasia is excluded), he is defeasibly motivated to act in accordance with that moral judgment). Now, the intrinsic motivational force of moral judgment is usually taken to provide a powerful argument in favour of anti-realism. After all, it seems that representational judgments, which aim to describe reality, are in much less good a position to explain moral motivation than, for example, non-cognitivist theories like expressivism: “The practical character of morality is often thought to call for an antirealist, especially noncognitivist, construal of moral claims. If moral judgments merely purported to state facts, it is claimed, they could not fulfill the action-guiding function they do. To fulfill this function, moral judgments must concern or express affective, fundamentally noncognitive, features of people’s psychology.”73 This argument is largely predicated on a Humean theory of motivation. According to Hume, mere belief (a cognitive state) cannot explain why people are motivated to act. In order to give such an explanation, what at the very least is needed is, in addition to this belief, a desire or some other relevant non-cognitive state.74 The anti-realist argument concerning moral motivation is therefore predicated on a combination of such a Humean account of motivation with moral judgment internalism.75 So the anti-realist argument concerning moral motivation – which Shafer-Landau calls “the Non-cognitivist Argument”76 – is the deductive inference that moral judgments cannot merely be beliefs (as the moral realist claims), since moral 68 R. Shafer-Landau, Moral Realism: A Defence, Oxford University Press, 2003, p. 82. C. Rosati, , “Moral Motivation”, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2014 Edition), E.N. Zalta (ed.), forthcoming URL = <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2014/entries/moral-motivation/>. 70 This view is – rather unsurprisingly – to be contrasted with motivational externalism, which is the view that no such necessary connection between moral judgment and motivation exists. 71 R. Wedgwood, The Nature of Normativity, Oxford University Press, 2009, p. 5. 72 M. Smith, The Moral Problem, Blackwell, 1994, p. 71-76. 73 D. Brink, Moral Realism and the Foundations of Ethics, Cambridge University Press, 1989, p. 37. 74 D. Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature, 1739: III, i, p. 457-463. 75 R. Shafer-Landau, Moral Realism: A Defence, Oxford University Press, 2003, p. 121. 76 Ibid., p. 121. 69 20 judgments necessarily motivate (moral judgment internalism) and beliefs do not carry motivational force (motivational Humeanism). The anti-realist conclusion is that therefore beliefs have to be taken as non-cognitive “expressive vehicles”77 rather than as beliefs. In the previous paragraph I have already discussed a metaphysical argument directed specifically at naturalist forms of moral realism. In this paragraph I have discussed a metaphysical challenge which is aimed specifically at moral non-naturalism: the challenge that non-naturalists are unable to explain satisfactorily the existence of a supervenience relation between moral and natural properties. Furthermore, I have discussed the general metaphysical78 and psychological arguments about motivational force that are usually employed by anti-realists. 3.4 Moral disagreement One of the most important arguments in favour of anti-realism, the argument from moral disagreement or the argument from relativity, “has as its premiss the well-known variation in moral codes from one society to another and from one period to another, and also the differences in moral beliefs between different groups and classes within a complex community”.79 But even if it is accepted that such variation exists to any significant extent, this obviously does far too little to justify the anti-realist conclusion that moral realism, therefore, has to be false. What is needed in addition to the empirical premise is an argument which convincingly shows that the non-existence of objective moral truth is to be considered the best explanation for the phenomenon of moral disagreement. Such an inference to the best explanation is usually supported by comparing moral inquiry to scientific investigation. In the sciences there too exists disagreement (although the degree of consensus can surely be claimed to be much higher in scientific than in moral matters), but those disagreements do not seem to be intractable: at the very least “we have some way of determining when theories fail to match up with the reality they are intended to describe”. 80 This seems to be different for moral inquiry. Whereas phlogiston theory has been refuted decisively by consistent empirical evidence against it, it seems that similar progress is not to be expected for moral investigation, since it is unclear how refutation of a certain moral view could ever take place. Is, therefore, the conclusion not warranted that “unlike successful scientists, moral interlocutors are simply registering their personal opinions, unfettered by an external moral reality that might check them”?81 Moral realists have tried to resist this line of argument at several points. Some moral realists deny the empirical premise that there is in fact a “well-known variation in moral codes”82. A first way to deny this premise is to marginalise, on empirical grounds, the extent to which 77 See footnote 1. Mackie’s Argument from Queerness is predicated on the “queer” character of moral properties as carrying objective prescriptions. 79 . Mackie, Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong, Penguin: 1977, p. 36. 80 R. Shafer-Landau, Moral Realism: A Defence, Oxford University Press, 2003, p. 216. 81 Ibid., p. 216. 82 See footnote 33. 78 21 moral disagreement can be found in the world.83 A second strategy is to hold that what we take to be genuine moral disagreement is merely a consequence of “procedurally irrational thinking” or of a lack of clarity about the relevant non-moral facts.84 Other realists, however, have accepted the empirical claim that genuine moral disagreement is indeed disanalogous to scientific disagreements. These realists do not deny the premise, but they resist the conclusion that such moral disagreement is best explained by “the truth of nihilism and the falsity of moral realism”.85 Brink provides us with a good example of such an argumentative strategy: “Some interlocutors may be so systematically mistaken that although our dispute with them concerns a matter of objective fact, we cannot, and should not be expected to be able to, convince them of true claims. […] [Furthermore] even a moral realist can maintain that some genuine moral disputes have no uniquely correct answers. Moral ties are possible, and considerations, each of which is objectively valuable, may be incommensurable.” 86 These two claims both try to resist the conclusion that moral disagreement is best interpreted as evidence in favour of anti-realism. It is important to note that Brink’s first argument, which concerns the possibility of people having such a fundamentally different (and mistaken) moral outlook that it is impossible “to convince them of true moral claims”87, is different from Wedgwood’s account of “procedurally irrational thinking”, which invokes the possibility of fallacious reasoning in order to explain away what we take to be moral disagreement. In contrast to such explaining away of moral disagreement, both Brink’s first and his second argument are meant to secure the conclusion that we can perfectly well explain the occurrence of genuine moral disagreement on moral realist assumptions. Even though in recent years the argument from disagreement “has been widely rejected” 88, it is still considered to be one of the most fundamental and one of the most intuitively appealing arguments against moral realism. It is therefore not surprising that the argument is “perhaps the longest standing argument”89 in the realism/anti-realism debate. Especially in the light of the work of philosophers who use recent developments in analytic philosophy to strengthen the force of the argument from disagreement90, there seems to be very little reason to assume that the debate concerning moral disagreement has been decided definitively in favour of the moral realist. 3.5 Evolutionary debunking arguments D. Loeb, “Moral Realism and the Argument from Disagreement”, Philosophical Studies, 1998:90, p. 283. R. Wedgwood, The Nature of Normativity, Oxford University Press, 2009, p. 259. 85 D. Brink, Moral Realism and the Foundations of Ethics, Cambridge University Press, 1989, p. 197. 86 Ibid., p. 202. 87 Ibid., p. 199. 88 D. Loeb, “Moral Realism and the Argument from Disagreement”, Philosophical Studies, 1998:90, p. 283. 89 G. Sayre-McCord, “Moral Realism”, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2011 Edition), E. N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2011/entries/moral-realism/>. 90 Cf. D. Loeb, “Moral Realism and the Argument from Disagreement”, Philosophical Studies, 1998:90. 83 84 22 In recent years anti-realists have often employed so-called “evolutionary debunking arguments” (EDA’s) against robust moral realism. EDA’s can be defined as arguments “that appeal to the evolutionary origins of certain evaluative beliefs to undermine their justification”.91 It is, however, important to differentiate between different types of EDA’s: some EDA’s are global in the sense that they try to show that all our moral intuitions are best explained by a form of anti-realism (such as error theory or constructivism), and some EDA’s are local because they attempt to debunk certain first-order moral intuitions on evolutionary grounds (for example, by showing that our intuitions concerning the “trolley-scenario” are based on our “evolutionary and cultural history”92 rather than on “a rational basis”93). So EDA’s are founded on the view “that descriptive knowledge of the genealogy of morals (in combination with some philosophizing) should undermine our confidence in moral judgments.”94 Now, how does the genealogy of morals lead to such anti-realist meta-ethical consequences? EDA’s usually depart from the empirical observation that it is clear that the contents of our most fundamental moral beliefs (such as the belief that we have an obligation to care for our children), which can be found in all cultures, enhance human evolutionary fitness. If, however, evolutionary biology teaches us that the causal origins95 of the contents of our moral beliefs are evolutionary in nature, then it becomes difficult for the moral realist to explain the relationship between these evolutionary causal origins of our moral beliefs and independent moral truths. This problem is captured adequately by the so-called “Darwinian Dilemma”96: “(S1) The robust realist has to hold either (A) that there is no relation between evolutionary influences on the contents of our moral beliefs and the independent moral truths, or (B) that there is a relation, because the evolution of our moral beliefs is truth-tracking. (S2) Horn (A) implies either the sceptical conclusion that probably most of our moral beliefs are off-track, due to the distorting pressure of Darwinian forces, which seems to be absurd, or that a detailed coincidence took place, which is extremely unlikely. (S3) Horn (B) is implausible as well, because with regard to our moral beliefs an adaptive link account is scientifically superior to a truth-tracking account, if at least the truth of moral beliefs is construed on the independence model. (S4) Hence, robust meta-ethical realism cannot accommodate the fact that Darwinian forces have influenced deeply the content of our moral convictions. As a consequence, we should conclude that robust meta-ethical realism is false.”97 So if the moral realist refuses to acknowledge a relationship between evolutionary influences and independent moral truths, then these evolutionary influences will “have nothing G. Kahane, “Evolutionary Debunking Arguments”, Nous, 2011: 45, p. 103. P. Singer, “Ethics and Intuitions”, The Journal of Ethics, 2005: 9.3-4: p. 349. 93 Ibid. 94 R. Joyce, The Evolution of Morality, MIT Press, 2006, p. 223. 95 G. Kahane, “Evolutionary Debunking Arguments”, Nous: 45, p. 106. 96 S. Street, “A Darwinian Dilemma for Realist Theories of Value”, Philosophical Studies, 127, p. 109. 97 H. Philipse, “God, Ethics, and Evolution”. In: H. A. Harris (ed.), God, Goodness and Philosophy, Ashgate, 2011, p. 154-159. Cf: S. Street, “A Darwinian Dilemma for Realist Theories of Value”, Philosophical Studies, 127, p. 109. 91 92 23 whatsoever to do with the evaluative truth”98, or they will have to accord in a purely coincidental manner. But if there is a relation between the two, then the moral realist will have to come up with arguments to show that the evolutionary causal origins of our moral beliefs are to be understood as truth-tracking than as “off-track”.99 It is, however, difficult to see how such a truth-tracking account could explain why truth would be needed to enhance human fitness. The adaptive link account100 of course perfectly explains the link between past evolutionary, selective processes and the content of our moral beliefs: on such an account our current moral beliefs are explained by their fitness-enhancing nature. In contrast, the truth-tracking account does not seem to offer any explanation as to how and why moral truth would be needed to account for the evolutionary success of our moral beliefs. Furthermore, one could apply a “principle of parsimony”101 in favour of the adaptive link account by showing that the truth-tracking account needs to posit something extra (i.e. independent evaluative truths) compared to the adaptive link account. It is for these reasons that moral realism seems to be facing an account “distinctly superior to the tracking account”.102 3.6 Moral explanations The last argument in favour of anti-realism I will discuss is concerned with the supposed explanatorily superfluous nature of moral facts. The argument, which was formulated for the first time by Gilbert Harman103, consists of two claims. The first claim is that we only have reason to believe in some claim if “the truth of that claim is necessary for the best explanation of some independent fact”.104 This is the requirement that, for us to be justified in believing some claim, it is needed that this claim plays a certain explanatory role. This “Explanatory Criterion” therefore consists of the claim that “the only hypotheses we are justified in believing are those that figure in the best explanations we have of our making the observations that we do”.105 The second claim is that putative moral facts never play such an explanatory role. Indeed, Harman claims, moral facts are never included in the best explanation of a certain independent fact. This is what distinguishes supposed moral facts from physical facts: “The difference is that you need to make assumptions about certain physical facts to explain the occurrence of the observations that support a scientific theory, but you do not seem to need to make assumptions about any moral facts to explain the occurrence of […] so-called moral observations […]. In the moral case, it would seem that you need only make assumptions about S. Street, “A Darwinian Dilemma for Realist Theories of Value”, Philosophical Studies, 127, p. 108. G. Kahane, “Evolutionary Debunking Arguments”, Nous, 2011: 45, p. 104. 100 S. Street, “A Darwinian Dilemma for Realist Theories of Value”, Philosophical Studies, 127, p. 121. 101 R. Joyce, “The Evolutionary Debunking of Morality”, in: Reason and Responsibility, J. Feinberg and R. Shafer-Landau (eds.), Cengage, 2013, chapter 16. 102 S. Street, “A Darwinian Dilemma for Realist Theories of Value”, Philosophical Studies, 127, par. 6. 103 G. Harman, The Nature of Morality, Oxford University Press, 1977, p. 5-9. 104 W. Sinnott-Armstrong, “Moral Skepticism”, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2011 Edition), E.N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2011/entries/skepticism-moral/>. 105 G.Sayre-McCord, “Moral Theory and Explanatory Impotence”, Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 1988:12, p. 442. 98 99 24 the psychology or moral sensibility of the person making the moral observation. In the scientific case, theory is tested against the world.” 106 So the difference, according to Harman, between scientific facts and moral facts is that the former are needed to explain scientific observations, whereas the latter are redundant when it comes to explaining our “moral observations”: such moral observations are perfectly well explained by “assumptions about the psychology or moral sensibility of the person making the moral observation”107 alone. Both steps in Harman’s argument can be, and have been, challenged. One can question, for example, whether the Explanatory Criterion really is as self-evident as Harman seems to suppose. After all, it is not at all clear whether “beliefs about mathematics or colors are or must be grounded in this way, although such beliefs still seem justified”.108 Alternatively, one can question Harman’s first step by arguing that “an a posteriori defense of moral realism does not obviously require that moral facts explain nonmoral facts in order for them to be explanatory”.109 It does, however, seem that this second strategy misses the point Harman is trying to make: the problem with supposed moral facts is that they do not help to explain any of our observations. Even if Harman therefore concedes that (supposed) moral facts explain other (supposed) moral facts, it seems that Harman’s point about the “psychology or moral sensibility of the person making the moral observation” would remain valid. But secondly, and this is the road most realist philosophers have in fact taken, one can question whether moral facts are indeed explanatorily impotent. The most important defender of the view that moral facts are necessary for the best explanations of non-moral facts is Nicholas Sturgeon. In his “Moral Explanations”110 Sturgeon argues in favour of exactly this point. Indeed, in attempting to explain the atrocities committed by Hitler, Sturgeon claims that “if Hitler hadn’t been morally depraved, he wouldn’t have done those things, and hence the fact of his moral depravity is relevant to an explanation of what he did”.111 So, according to Sturgeon, Hitler’s morally depraved character is central to rather than superfluous for a successful explanation of the atrocities Hitler committed. This reply of course invites the moral anti-realist to enter into a debate about the relationship between explanatory relevance and moral supervenience. After all, Sturgeon’s argument raises the question whether the fact that Hitler was morally depraved, which surely supervenes on certain natural properties, can, for explanatory purposes, be wholly replaced by non-moral, natural descriptions. If it can, and if our best explanations never suffer an explanatory loss if we replace the supervenient moral facts by the subvenient natural properties, then it seems that moral facts are explanatorily superfluous after all. So why, the 106 G. Harman, The Nature of Morality, Oxford University Press, 1977, p. 5. See footnote 77. 108 W. Sinnott-Armstrong, “Moral Skepticism”, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2011 Edition), E.N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2011/entries/skepticism-moral/>. 109 D. Brink, Moral Realism and the Foundations of Ethics, Cambridge University Press, 1989, p. 183. 110 N. Sturgeon, “Moral Explanations”, in: R. Shafer-Landau (ed.), Metaphysics, vol. II, Routledge, 2008, p. 312. 110 R. Shafer-Landau, Metaphysics, vol. I, Routledge, 2008, p. 270-294. 111 N. Sturgeon, “Moral Explanations”, p. 288. 107 25 anti-realist asks, would we talk about the explanatory role of South Africa’s racial injustice rather than about its specific social, political and legal institutions if “it is just such social, political and legal arrangements that constitute South Africa’s racial injustice?”.112 Harman indeed contends that such injustice adds nothing to the explanation that is available by means of the natural facts which constitute the injustice.113 Moral realists, however, have argued that the higher-order, moral explanations are in fact irreducible to lower-order, natural explanations.114 Such accounts argue, on the basis of the difference between identity and constitution, that “constituted facts are (after all) something over and above their bases”.115 I will, however, not go deeper into this debate about the explanatory power of higher-order, supervenient facts vis-à-vis the lower-order properties by which they are constituted. For the purposes of this chapter it is sufficient to show that the perceived explanatory impotence of moral facts is one of the main continuing anti-realist impetuses. 112 D. Brink, Moral Realism and the Foundations of Ethics, Cambridge University Press, 1989, p. 191. Emphasis added. 113 G. Harman, “Moral Explanations of Natural Facts – Can Moral Claims Be Tested Against Moral Reality?”, The Southern Journal of Philosophy, 1986:24, p. 62-64. 114 D. Brink, Moral Realism and the Foundations of Ethics, Cambridge University Press, 1989, p. 193. 115 Ibid., p. 193-194. See also, for an analogy between explanations in ethics and in the special sciences: B. Majors, “Moral Explanation and the Special Sciences”, Philosophical Studies, 2003: 113, p. 121-152. 26 Part III Moral Epistemology 27 Chapter 4 Anti-Realism and Moral Epistemology “If we were aware of [objective values], it would have to be by some special faculty of moral perception or intuition, utterly different from our ordinary ways of knowing everything else.” 116 4.1 Introduction In part II of this thesis I have tried to characterise moral realism and (the various forms of) anti-realism, and discuss the most important arguments that have been put forward in their defence. In this part I will turn to moral epistemology. I will take moral epistemology, in its broadest form, to be concerned with the question whether, and if so, how, moral knowledge, or epistemic moral justification, is ever possible. It is important to note that, at least for the purposes of this part of the thesis, the conception of “moral knowledge” I employ is neutral between moral particularism (the view that “moral knowledge […] is incapable of being formulated in universal propositions or moral rules”117) and moral generalism (the opposite view that moral knowledge is only concerned with (more or less) universal principles and standards). This part of the thesis will consist of two chapters. In this chapter I will look at the relationship between anti-realism and moral epistemology. After that, in chapter 5, I will discuss four different attempts to construct a satisfactory moral realist epistemology. These discussions about the central epistemological question formulated above will be used as the framework for my discussion about the relationship between epistemological moral scepticism and moral realism in part IV. Now, this chapter will be concerned with anti-realism. But before I will turn to anti-realism and its relation to moral knowledge, it is necessary to start with a discussion about the nature of knowledge itself. The nature of knowledge will therefore be the subject of paragraph 4.2. After that, I will look at the most important anti-realist responses to the central epistemological question formulated earlier. Indeed, in paragraphs 4.3 – 4.5 the epistemological aspects of non-cognitivism, moral subjectivism and error theory will be subjected to detailed scrutiny. 4.2 An analysis of knowledge In order to discuss the relationship between anti-realism and questions of epistemology, it is necessary to ask firstly how we are to understand the concept of “knowledge”. After all, if we want to ascertain how the anti-realist usually answers the question whether, and if so, how, moral knowledge is possible, we need to be able to give an account of what knowledge is in the first place. 116 117 J. Mackie, Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong, Penguin: 1977, p. 38. R.L. Arrington, Rationalism, Realism, and Relativism, Cornell University Press, 1989, p. 161. 28 Now, epistemology in twentieth-century analytic philosophy has directed a lot if its attention on formulating an adequate analysis of propositional knowledge (knowledge of the form “S knows that p”). According to the traditional analysis of knowledge, there are three individually necessary and jointly sufficient conditions for knowledge. This has become known as the “Tripartite Analysis of Knowledge”: S knows that p iff i. ii. iii. p is true; S believes that p; S is justified in believing that p.118 So on this view, knowledge requires justified true belief. It is largely uncontroversial to hold that knowledge requires truth. Most philosophers also hold that the requirements of belief119 and justification are in fact necessary for an adequate analysis of knowledge. They do, however, strongly disagree on the nature of epistemic justification. The debate between proponents of internalist and externalist conceptions of epistemic justification is an example of a fundamental debate about the very nature of such justification. According to internalists, epistemic justification is determined by factors “that are internal to the believer’s conscious states of mind, where these states are at least in principle accessible to conscious reflection”.120 On the other hand, externalists maintain that a belief is epistemically warranted if and only if it is produced by a type of process which makes it probable that it is true, “even though the subject is not, or cannot be, aware of whether the belief has been produced by such a process”.121 The best-known example of an externalist conception of epistemic justification is process reliabilism, according to which a belief is epistemically justified if it is produced by a reliable type of process. But apart from this intramural debate which takes place within the Tripartite Analysis of Knowledge, the analysis itself has also been put to an extremely influential challenge. This challenge was formulated by Edmund Gettier in his 1963 paper “Is Justified True Belief Knowledge?”. Gettier asks us to suppose that Smith has strong evidence for the proposition “Jones owns a Ford”. He infers from this the truth of the two disjunctive propositions “Either Jones owns a Ford, or Brown is in Boston” (proposition (g)) and “Either Jones owns a Ford, or Brown is in Barcelona” (proposition (h)).122 Since Smith is justified in believing that Jones owns a Ford, he is justified in believing the two disjunctive propositions. “But imagine now that two further conditions hold. First Jones does not own a Ford, but is at present driving a rented car. And secondly, by the sheerest coincidence, and entirely unknown to Smith, the place mentioned in proposition (h) happens really to be the place where Brown is. If J. J. Ichikawa and M. Steup, “The Analysis of Knowledge”, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, E.N. Zalta (ed.), forthcoming URL = <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2014/entries/knowledge-analysis/>. 119 The expression “I can’t believe they won the cup” is of course not to be taken literally: in such cases one does believe they won the cup. 120 R. Feldman, “Bonjour and Sosa on Internalism, Externalism and Basic Beliefs”, Philosophical Studies, 2006, p. 713. 121 H. Philipse, God in the Age of Science, Oxford University Press, 2012, p. 68-69. 122 E. Gettier, “Is Justified True Belief Knowledge?”, Analysis, 1963: 23, p. 121-123. 118 29 these two conditions hold, then Smith does not know that (h) is true, even though (i) (h) is true, (ii) Smith does believe that (h) is true, and (iii) Smith is justified in believing that (h) is true.” 123 So Gettier invites us to have the intuition that Smith does not know proposition (h), although the three elements of the Tripartite Analysis of Knowledge are all in place. Most philosophers indeed share Gettier’s intuition on this point, which has led to the acceptance of the “Gettier problem”. As a result, the Tripartite Analysis of Knowledge is nowadays usually taken to be defective. Different philosophers have, in response, attempted to modify the Tripartite Analysis of Knowledge by adding to it a fourth condition, which is meant to somehow secure a proper kind of relation between the justification and the truth of the relevant belief. After all, the reason we feel Smith does not know proposition (h) is that his justification (his evidence for the proposition that Jones owns a Ford and his grasp of the logical relation between this proposition and the disjunctive proposition (h)) does not stand in the right relation to the truth of proposition (h). Proposition (h) is true in virtue of the – accidental – fact that Brown is in Barcelona, while Smith’s epistemic justification is in no way related to this fact. It is this problem that the search for a fourth, so-called “Gettier-condition” tries to remedy. In the remainder of this thesis I will take this analysis of knowledge (justified true belief plus the Gettier-condition) to be the correct one. It is with this conception of knowledge in mind that we can turn to anti-realist answers to the central epistemological question formulated at the start of this chapter. 4.3 Non-cognitivism and epistemology In the previous section we have seen that (moral) knowledge at least requires justified true belief. It would appear that on this view non-cognitivism, which asserts both that moral judgments are not truth-apt and are not, properly speaking, beliefs, is incompatible with the existence of moral knowledge and epistemic justification in the moral domain. After all, if moral judgments are nothing but non-cognitive expressions of feelings or imperatives, then our moral discourse is not even in the business of attempting to attain propositional knowledge by representing reality. But this conclusion sits rather uncomfortably with our everyday moral judgments and moral sentences. Indeed, if “we have in ethics nothing but the clash of desires, attitudes, and emotions then there is something misleading about the way ethical demands present themselves to us”.124 For this reason there have been non-cognitivist attempts to soften this counterintuitive conclusion. A first strategy has been to invoke a deflationary conception of truth, which is meant to provide a justification for talking about “true” moral beliefs in some sense of the word. Indeed, “recent versions [of non-cognitivism] often allow some minimal kind of moral truth while denying that moral beliefs can be true or false in the same robust way as factual 123 124 E. Gettier, “Is Justified True Belief Knowledge?”, Analysis, 1963: 23, p. 122. S. Blackburn, Ruling Passions: A Theory of Practical Reasoning, Clarendon Press, 1998, p. 280. 30 beliefs”.125 Such a conception of truth therefore rejects the view that truth is captured by, for example, correspondence to objective facts, or by coherence with a given set of beliefs, or by whatever other theory about the nature of truth. According to Alfred Tarski’s semantic conception of truth, “S” is true if and only if S.126 In other words: there is nothing more to be said about the claim “the cat is on the mat” than that it is true if and only if the cat is on the mat. In the past Gottlob Frege has also hinted at such a minimalist conception of truth: “It is worthy of notice that the sentence ‘I smell the scent of violets’ has the same content as the sentence ‘it is true that I smell the scent of violets’. So it seems, then, that nothing is added to the thought by my ascribing to it the property of truth.” 127 Some non-cognitivists therefore accept, by embracing a semantic, deflationary conception of truth, that moral sentences can be (in a non-metaphysical, non-realist way) minimally true, which subsequently opens up a realm in which the non-cognitivist can talk about moral knowledge in some (minimal) sense of the word. It is of course the question to what extent it is possible for the non-cognitivist to acknowledge the existence of minimal moral truth without surrendering his position to the cognitivist and the moral realist. In other words: it is unclear in what sense one can speak of moral truth on such a non-cognitivist account. Indeed, any acknowledgement of moral truth seems to be difficult to reconcile with “the distinctive negative semantic claim that moral judgements are never true and not the kind of thing that can be true or false”128, which, as we have seen, lies at the very heart of non-cognitivism. It is therefore not surprising that doubts have raised about the possibility of combining non-cognitivism and a minimalist conception of truth: “The [non-cognitivist] program to vindicate as much of ordinary moral practice might [...] endanger non-cognitivism when carried to this extreme. Success would leave us with no way to distinguish plausible non-cognitivism from cognitivism.” 129 If, for this reason, the non-cognitivist does not feel tempted to accept a deflationary conception of truth, he can choose another strategy to capture some aspects of our ordinary moral discourse. This strategy consists of the attempt to develop a non-cognitivist conception of moral justification. This strategy, therefore, does not attempt to open up a realm of moral truth by invoking a deflationary conception of truth, but it rather attempts to say something more about the justificatory differences that follow from perceived qualitative differences in moral expressions, feelings and projections. Simon Blackburn, for example, attempts to steer a middle position between the relativist “that is just your opinion” and the realist claim that “our opinion conforms to the independent order W. Sinnott-Armstrong, “Moral Skepticism”, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2011 Edition), E. N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2011/entries/skepticism-moral/>. 126 A. Tarski, “The Semantic Conception of Truth”, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 1944, 4:341375. 127 G. Frege, “Thoughts”, in: Logical Investigations, Blackwell, 1977. 128 M. van Roojen, “Moral Cognitivism vs. Non-Cognitivism”, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, E. N. Zalta (ed.), forthcoming URL = <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2014/entries/moral-cognitivism/>. 129 Ibid. 125 31 of reason”.130 Indeed, according to Blackburn, there are qualitative differences between different moral views (pace the relativist), although these differences do not correspond to “an independent order of reason” (pace the realist). These differences are, according to Blackburn, to be taken as invitations to engage in moral argumentation: “Our actual practices of argument and persuasion require only the hope that there is nothing else for decent people to think. […] To try to show that something must be thought is no more, but no less, than to try to show that it is the right thing, or the best thing, to think. […] What we hope to show, as we persevere with analyses of social phenomena, deploying analogies, turning the values involved around in our minds, is that there is nothing else for good, decent people to think.” 131 Although the moral arguments by which we defend our moral views may not be “well directed at the objective truth”132, they can show, according to Blackburn, that “there is nothing else for good, decent people to think”. This is not, however, to be taken epistemically. Indeed, although Blackburn intends this claim as a claim about “what must be thought ethically, […] the necessity is itself ethical”.133 In moral discourse, there are no meta-ethical epistemological questions to be asked about the powers of reflective ethical thought. Blackburn’s non-cognitivist model of the justificatory role of moral deliberation is therefore ethical rather than epistemic in nature. Another example of such a strategy can be found in the work of Allan Gibbard. Gibbard too tries to supplement his non-cognitivist (expressivist) meta-ethical theory with an account of normative authority, which he phrases in terms of rationality. The starting point for his analysis of rationality is wholly expressivistic in nature: to call a thing rational, according to Gibbard, is not to state a matter of fact, but it is rather a way to “express one’s acceptance of norms that permit it”.134 This acceptance, however, is open to challenges of consistency and challenges about what it makes sense to do as a human being. According to Gibbard, such challenges at the very least get us some way toward a conception of normative authority: “My own hopes are that hard inquiry can bring us toward a resolution of our broadly moral impulses, a resolution that adds to the richness of life. If we think both deeply and broadly about what can be had from morality, and about what really matters in life and to whom, we should find devices of thought that get us somewhere.”135 So Gibbard, like Blackburn, attempts to formulate ways in which his non-cognitivist theory can be reconciled with our intuitions that there are good and bad moral feelings and moral arguments. Both these philosophers, therefore, attempt to construct something like an account of moral justification. It is important to note, however, that these accounts are not concerned with epistemic moral justification. After all, both their meta-ethical theories revolve around 130 S. Blackburn, Ruling Passions: A Theory of Practical Reasoning, Clarendon Press, 1998, p. 305. Ibid., p. 304. 132 Ibid., p. 300. 133 Ibid., p. 304. 134 A. Gibbard, Wise Choices, Apt Feelings: A Theory of Normative Judgment, Clarendon Press, 1990, p. 7. 135 Ibid., p. 326. 131 32 feelings and projections rather than proper beliefs. Their models of justification are therefore not epistemic, but ethical in nature. 4.4 Moral subjectivism and epistemology In this paragraph I will look at the relationship between the form of anti-realism called moral subjectivism and questions of moral epistemology. As was explained in part II of this thesis, moral subjectivism is the view that although there are moral facts, they do not exist independently of our (hypothetical) moral stances. On this view, moral facts are nothing more than products of our own making. So this view is called moral subjectivism because it accepts the mind-dependence rather than the mind-independence of moral facts. This does not, however, mean that the moral subjectivist has to be a relativist136. After all, relativism holds that “moral claims contain an essential indexical element, such that the truth of any such claim requires relativization to some indexical or group”. 137 The subjectivist, however, can – and in fact often does – hold that, although moral facts are determined solely by human moral activity, they do apply equally to all of us in virtue of us all possessing some same morally relevant characteristic. Examples of such absolutistic forms of subjectivism are Roderick Firth’s ideal observer theory138 and Christine Korsgaard’s Kantian meta-ethical theory139. So there are many different forms of moral subjectivism. Some hold that moral facts are constituted by the moral attitudes of actual moral agents, which often leads to a relativistic form of subjectivism140, whereas other, more absolutistic forms of moral subjectivism often hold that idealised human attitudes in fact determine which moral facts exist. In short: “[T]he subjectivism vs. objectivism and the relativism vs. absolutism polarities are orthogonal to each other, and it is the former pair that matters when it comes to characterizing anti-realism.”141 What all forms of moral subjectivism have in common, however, is that they all seem to be in an epistemologically more attractive position than the moral realist. After all, the moral realist faces the task of explaining how we can ever attain knowledge of mind-independent moral facts. This means that the moral realist has to give an account of the relationship between these mind-independent facts and our cognitive faculties. As we will see in the next chapter, it has proven to be a difficult task to provide a satisfactory, non-mysterious account of this relationship. The moral subjectivist, however, has the much simpler task of explaining how we can attain knowledge of moral facts that we ourselves in some way have produced. It 136 There are of course many types of relativism. One can for example point to individualistic relativism and cultural relativism. What is important here is that it is possible for the moral subjectivist not to be a relativist in any of these senses. 137 R. Joyce, “Moral Anti-Realism”, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, E. N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2009/entries/moral-anti-realism/>. 138 R. Firth, “Ethical absolutism and the ideal observer”, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 12, p. 317-345. 139 C.M. Korsgaard, The Sources of Normativity, Cambridge University Press, 1996. 140 Cf. G. Harman, “Moral Relativism Defended”, The Philosophical Review, 1975: 85, p. 3-22. 141 R. Joyce, “Moral Anti-Realism”, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy , E. N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2009/entries/moral-anti-realism/>. 33 seems that the moral subjectivist position, much like the idealist position in the historically important debate about the reality of the external world, is in a better position to explain epistemic access than its realist opponent: “Realists about the external world claim that things such as mountains and fish exist in a robustly objective sense, according to which they do not owe their existence or nature to human cognitive activity. Antirealists about these things often respond by pointing out that if entities such as mountains and fish were to exist in this sense, then, for one or another reason, it would be impossible to gain epistemic access to them. According to the antirealists, realism engenders skepticism about the external world.”142 So whereas Kant argues that “if we treat outer objects as things as themselves, it is quite impossible to understand how we could arrive at a knowledge of their reality outside us”143, the moral subjectivist can hold that, similarly, the moral realist faces the arduous task of explaining how knowledge of mind-independent moral facts could ever be possible. This is different for the moral subjectivist. If moral facts are, as the subjectivist claims, human products, then it seems rather clear that we can have epistemic access to these moral facts. If, for example, one believes that moral facts are determined by the actual moral attitudes in a given community, then one should be able to ascertain empirically (“this is how we do it”144) which (mind-dependent) moral facts exist in any given community. Or if, alternatively, moral facts are taken as products of evolutionary, Darwinian forces, it seems one will be able to grasp these truths by inquiring into the fitness-enhancing nature of certain of our moral beliefs.145 So it seems that whatever form of moral subjectivism one proposes, the moral subjectivist will be able to give an account of moral knowledge and epistemic moral justification. This is something that indeed comes naturally to those who hold that moral facts are human products. In contrast, and as we will see in the subsequent chapter, the moral realist has much more difficulty explaining how epistemic access to moral facts could ever be possible. 4.5 Error theory and epistemology Error theory is the final important form of anti-realism to be discussed in this chapter. Unlike non-cognitivism, however, the relationship between error theory and questions of moral epistemology is rather straightforward. As we have seen, Mackie’s error theory takes our everyday moral discourse at face value and therefore concludes that our moral judgments are cognitive in character: in making moral judgments we literally aim at a robust form (correspondence with objective moral facts) of moral truth. However, on metaphysical (the Argument from Queerness) and epistemological (the Argument from Disagreement) grounds T. Cuneo, “Moral Realism, Quasi Realism, and Skepticism”, in: The Oxford Handbook of Skepticism, Oxford University Press, 2009, p. 176. 143 I. Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, A 378. 144 S. Blackburn, Ruling Passions: A Theory of Practical Reasoning, Clarendon Press, 1998, p. 279. 145 See paragraph 3.5 for a discussion of evolutionary debunking arguments (EDA’s). 142 34 we are forced to the conclusion that no such moral truth exists: all our moral judgments are simply false. Because of the fact that knowledge at the very least requires truth, it follows that on this account there is no such thing as moral knowledge either. Furthermore, because we can know that moral facts do not exist on the basis of philosophical (i.e. metaphysical and epistemological) arguments, it seems we cannot be epistemically justified in believing moral propositions either. On this picture, then, all we can do is give an explanation as to why we make moral judgments and why we believe in objective moral facts. Indeed, Mackie believes that an evolutionary, Darwinian explanation of these phenomena is largely correct. 146 But the epistemological question I formulated at the start of this chapter is of no concern to the error theorist, because it has already been answered by Mackie’s metaphysical thesis that there is nothing to attain knowledge of in the first place. 146 J. Mackie, Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong, Penguin, 1977, p. 113. 35 Chapter 5 Moral Realist Epistemology “[A]ttempts to justify moral beliefs merely by “commonsense” will risk begging the question, resulting in an uninformative circularity where one is justified in believing something simply because one believes that thing.”147 5.1 Introduction As we have seen in the previous chapter, knowledge at least requires justified true belief. It is therefore not surprising that much of the twentieth-century debates in epistemology have been concerned with the nature of epistemic justification. These debates have centered around the question under which circumstances one is justified in holding a certain proposition to be true. Two fundamentally different accounts of epistemic justification have dominated these epistemological debates. On the one hand, there is foundationalism, which holds that “one’s belief p is justified just in case p is either (a) foundational (i.e., noninferentially justified or self-justifying) or (b) based on the appropriate kind of inference from foundational beliefs”. 148 So the distinguishing feature of foundationalism is the view that some beliefs are basic beliefs which carry independent justificatory force. On the other hand, there is coherentism, which holds that epistemic justification consists in the way our beliefs hang together (or cohere) so as to produce a mutually supportive, coherent set of beliefs. So, on this view, “nothing can count as a reason for a belief except another belief”.149 As a third alternative, the method of reflective equilibrium has gained popularity over the last decades. I will discuss this method in paragraph 5.4. Finally, in paragraph 5.5, I will discuss a fourth approach to moral epistemology, which has become known as (epistemological) naturalism. It is important to note that my (often critical) discussions of these different attempts to provide a moral realist epistemology are not meant to be conclusive. These discussions are rather meant to provide the relevant background knowledge for the next part of this thesis, which is concerned primarily with epistemological moral scepticism. 5.2 Moral intuitionism It has long seemed axiomatic to hold that justified moral beliefs cannot be based solely on non-moral premises. As we have seen in chapter 3, such beliefs were held to run afoul of the so-called naturalistic fallacy. This means, however, that the justification of moral beliefs has to start from moral premises. But how is this possible without being guilty of either circularity or of an infinite regress? As we have seen in the previous paragraph, foundationalism provides one possible answer to this question: some beliefs are warranted in a non-inferential manner. In the moral domain, moral intuitionism is usually taken to be the most attractive 147 K. DeLapp, Moral Realism, Bloomsbury Academic, 2013, p. 130. D. Brink, Moral Realism and the Foundations of Ethics, Cambridge University Press, 1989, p. 101. 149 D. Davidson, “A Coherence Theory of Knowledge and Truth,” in Truth and Interpretation, E. LePore (ed.), Blackwell, 1986, p. 307–319. 148 36 form of foundationalism. Indeed, almost every moral foundationalist has been an intuitionist.150 Now, moral intuitionism aims to resolve the sceptical regress by focusing on the noninferential justification of certain moral beliefs: “If we can work back to some moral claim that we are justified in believing without depending on any inference from any other belief (normative or non-normative, moral or non-moral), then there is no new premise to justify, and the regress goes no further.” 151 So moral intuitionism proposes that there are certain basic moral beliefs which are directly warranted. There are of course many variants of moral intuitionism. Some moral intuitionists appeal to the self-justifying character of moral beliefs, whereas other intuitionists choose to centralise the self-evidence or even the indubitable nature of certain moral beliefs. But despite these differences, two traditional arguments have consistently been put forward against all forms of intuitionism. Firstly, there is the charge that intuitionists appeal to a mysterious faculty of moral intuition. The appeal to this mysterious faculty, so the arguments runs, raises sceptical questions about the nature and the reliability of this faculty of moral intuition.152 And even if the intuitionist refuses to recognise a faculty for moral perception153, the appeal to moral “intuitions” itself remains mysterious in the sense that it is unclear why trust should be placed in such intuitions. Secondly, and related to this first concern, is the worry that the existence of persistent moral disagreement at the very least seems to raise serious doubts about the reliability of our moral intuitions. After all, if human beings frequently disagree on matters of morality, then it seems we have little reason to assume the existence of a well-functioning faculty of moral intuition. These problems can be seen clearly in attempts to ground the justification of moral beliefs on their supposed self-evident nature. Shafer-Landau, for example, argues that we can know moral principles on the basis of them being self-evident.154 A proposition p is self-evident if “p is such that adequately understanding and attentively considering just p is sufficient to justify believing that p”.155 Now, according to Shafer-Landau, there are multiple self-evident moral propositions: “It seems to me self-evident that, other things equal, it is wrong to take pleasure in another’s pain, to taunt and threaten the vulnerable, to prosecute and punish those known to be innocent, and to sell another’s secrets solely for personal gain. When I say such things, I mean that once one really understands these principles […], one doesn’t need to infer them from one’s other beliefs in order to be justified in thinking them true.” 156 150 D. Brink, Moral Realism and the Foundations of Ethics, Cambridge University Press, 1989, p. 102. W. Sinnott-Armstrong, Moral Skepticisms, Oxford University Press, 2006, p. 184. 152 As we have seen earlier, Mackie in fact uses a version of this argument to argue in favour of his error theory. 153 As indeed R. Price has done in 1787 in A Review of the Principle Questions in Morals. 154 The appeal to self-evidence is a “paradigmatic form of internalism” (R. Shafer-Landau, Moral Realism: A Defence, Oxford University Press, 2003, p. 278). I will go deeper into the epistemic internalism/externalism dichotomy later on in this thesis. 155 R. Shafer-Landau, Moral Realism: A Defence, Oxford University Press, 2003, p. 247. 156 Ibid., p. 248. 151 37 The problem for such an account, however, is that it has difficulties in dealing with conflicting intuitions. Indeed, as Shafer-Landau himself points out, “I don’t believe that it is possible to prove or demonstrate the existence of [self-evident moral] propositions”.157 But if this is indeed impossible, then how is the proponent of an epistemological theory based on selfevidence supposed to answer someone who disagrees with the suggested instances of alleged self-evident moral propositions? Taking the example of the sadist as someone who disagrees, Shafer-Landau answers in the following way: “[T]he friend of self-justification must insist that if p really is self-evident, then the sadist does have an epistemic reason to believe it. A proposition may be self-evident even if one’s other beliefs conspire to defeat its justification. Though the weight of tradition leans in the other direction, self-evident beliefs may be defeasible.”158 The obvious problem, however, is that what the sadist is questioning is exactly whether p is self-evident! So the conditional “if p really is self-evident, then the sadist does have an epistemic reason to believe it” can be accepted by the sadist, as long as he insists that p is, in fact, not self-evident. Here the argumentative bleakness of the appeal to self-evidence comes to the fore: since Shafer-Landau admits that he “[doesn’t] know how to argue for the selfevidence of these (or other) propositions”159, there is no way to face this sadist challenge. All one can do is simply insist that p is self-evident, and that, self-evidence being a normative rather than a psychological notion, everyone has a strong epistemic reason to believe p. Even if one’s opponent goes so far as to claim that “not p” is self-evident, one does not have an argumentative strategy to counter his appeal to self-evidence. But this can hardly be called a satisfactory moral epistemology. If an appeal to self-evidence cannot be defended in any way, then the invocation itself becomes vacuous. Argumentative strategies such as Shafer-Landau’s invocation of self-evident moral principles, therefore, do not seem to help the moral realist in establishing the existence of moral knowledge. 5.3 Coherentism Coherentism is an influential and popular position in moral epistemology. As we have seen in paragraph 5.1, coherentists argue that epistemic justification is conferred on a belief in virtue of it cohering with other beliefs. So the coherentist answer to the sceptical regress argument is that one can avoid a regress by accepting circularity. This circularity, according to the coherentist, need not be vicious: if a certain belief fits into a certain web of beliefs, and if the size of the web is large enough, then the holistic nature of the web can confer justification on the belief. So “the fact that our beliefs cohere can establish their truth, even though each individual belief may lack justification entirely if considered in splendid isolation”.160 C.I. Lewis, for example, compares this to the way agreeing testimonies can take away all 157 R. Shafer-Landau, Moral Realism: A Defence, Oxford University Press, 2003, p. 247. Ibid., p. 258. 159 Ibid., p. 248. 160 E. Olsson, “Coherentist Theories of Epistemic Justification”, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, E. N. Zalta (ed.), forthcoming URL = <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2014/entries/justep-coherence/>. 158 38 reasonable doubt, even though any single testimony to that effect would have been insufficient.161 Now, what constitutes coherence? Under which circumstances does a belief sufficiently hang together which other beliefs in order for it to be called a justified belief? According to SayreMcCord, this requires consistency, connectedness and comprehensiveness.162 Consistency at the very least requires the absence of logical incompatibilities. One cannot hold two beliefs which cannot simultaneously be true. The element of connectedness is meant to secure that the different beliefs stand in a relation of relevance with each other. Although the beliefs that grass is green and that the capital of Uruguay is Montevideo are consistent, they do nothing to reinforce each other because the one (at least appears to be) irrelevant for the other. Finally, there is the requirement of comprehensiveness, which is concerned with the number of beliefs (or, put differently, with the size of the web of beliefs) which together are meant to carry justificatory force. There are many objections to coherentism as a theory of epistemic justification, but one seems particularly pressing for the moral coherentist. The perceived problem is that the moral coherentist, in taking our everyday moral beliefs as the coherent set which is meant to confer a justified status on any belief coherent with that set, is begging the question against some forms of strong anti-realism: “Even maximal coherence cannot rule out moral nihilism or other extreme alternatives because the moral assumptions in the coherent system beg the question against such extreme opponents, and moral nihilism can be as coherent as its denial.” 163 The worry is that, in a sense, coherentism is simply an exercise in self-congratulation. If we add more and more beliefs with the same background assumptions into our set of coherent beliefs, then surely we will end up with consistent, connected and comprehensive beliefs. But the debate about epistemic justification is concerned with the question how we can justify our firmly held beliefs when they are challenged by others who happen not to share these beliefs. If, however, such challenges (such as moral nihilism) can be captured by equally coherent sets of beliefs, then that does seem to raise the question on what grounds the moral coherentist can hold that his set of beliefs carries justificatory force. If, on the other hand, he holds that both coherent sets are justified, then both justified sets can function as each other’s epistemic defeaters, which leaves them, paradoxically, both without justification. Coherentists have responded to this challenge by pointing to the distinction between systematic and contextualist justification. Whereas systematic justification requires all justifying beliefs to be themselves justified, contextualist justification is content with treating some background beliefs as if they were systematically justified.164 And indeed, “in normal contexts of justification, we do not consistently apply the epistemological requirement that 161 C.I. Lewis, An Analysis of Knowledge and Valuation, LaSalle: Open Court, 1946. G. Sayre-McCord, “Coherence and Models for Moral Theorizing”, Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 1985: 66, 170-190. 163 W. Sinnott-Armstrong, Moral Skepticisms, Oxford University Press, 2006, p. 250. 164 D. Brink, Moral Realism and the Foundations of Ethics, Cambridge University Press, 1989, p. 123. 162 39 justifying beliefs be justified”.165 It is important to note, however, that resorting to a contextualist form of justification entails the acceptance of a form of weak foundationalism, since it holds that some basic, justifying beliefs do not stand in need of justification. The difference with full-blooded foundationalism is of course that the coherentist does not hold that such justifying beliefs itself are justified, but nevertheless it is committed to holding that somehow these justifying beliefs “already have some initial, perhaps miniscule, degree of warrant”.166 If not, the coherentist faces the challenge that the relevant set of beliefs is incapable of justifying beliefs “from nothing”167, since it begs the question against radically different sets of coherent beliefs. But if the coherentist does hold that some justifying beliefs from his coherent set “already have some initial, perhaps miniscule, degree of warrant”, such as for example Rescher168 and BonJour169 do, he thereby faces the problematic consequence of both having to explain why some beliefs are assigned such a special role, and why the foundationalist problems diagnosed in paragraph 5.3 do not apply to his proposal. 5.4 Reflective equilibrium The concept of “reflective equilibrium”170, applied to the moral realm, refers to a harmonious end-point of a deliberative process which revolves around our considered judgments, general moral principles and (non-moral) background theory. The method of reflective equilibrium (MRE), on the other hand, can be characterised as a type of moral epistemology, which “consists in working back and forth among our considered judgments (some say our “intuitions”) about particular instances or cases, the principles or rules that we believe govern them, and the theoretical considerations that we believe bear on accepting these considered judgments, principles, or rules, revising any of these elements wherever necessary in order to achieve an acceptable coherence among them”.171 The first thing to notice about this characterisation of MRE is that the possibility of revising of our moral beliefs (our considered moral judgments, our moral principles and any other relevant (non-moral) theoretical background belief) plays an important role in MRE. Indeed, MRE requires one to engage in “trading-off between these various categories of moral belief in order to achieve a harmonious “equilibrium””.172 This means that there are no beliefs which are principally privileged in the sense that they are immune to revision. 165 Ibid. E. Olsson, “Coherentist Theories of Epistemic Justification”, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, E. N. Zalta (ed.), forthcoming URL = <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2014/entries/justep-coherence/>. 167 W. Sinnott-Armstrong, Moral Skepticisms, Oxford University Press, 2006, p. 245. 168 N. Rescher, The Coherence Theory of Truth, Oxford University Press, 1973. 169 L. BonJour, The Structure of Empirical Knowledge. Harvard University Press, 1985. 170 J. Rawls, A Theory of Justice, Harvard University Press, 2nd edition 1999, p. 20. For the purposes of this paragraph I will take “reflective equilibrium” in the wide rather than the narrow sense, which means that I will take the method of reflective equilibrium as a broad process which is concerned with all the relevant moral and non-moral (theoretical) background beliefs as well as considered judgments and moral principles. Cf. Rawls, p. 43. 171 N. Daniels, “Reflective Equilibrium”, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, E. N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2013/entries/reflective-equilibrium/>. 172 R. Boyd, “How to be a moral realist”, in: R. Shafer-Landau (ed.), Metaphysics, vol. II, Routledge, 2008, par. 2.2. Emphasis added. 166 40 Secondly, and this is a related point, MRE is usually considered to be a coherentist moral epistemology173: “Because we are expected to revise our beliefs at all levels as we work back and forth among them and subject them to various criticisms, this coherence view contrasts sharply with a variety of foundationalist approaches to justification. Some foundationalists at least claim that some subset of our moral beliefs are immediately or directly justified (perhaps even “self-evident”) or warranted […]. Reflective equilibrium […] singles out no group of privileged or directly justified beliefs, distinguishing itself from all these forms of foundationalism.” 174 But this is a rather one-sided way to look at MRE. Indeed, an important aspect of MRE is that our considered judgments (our moral intuitions), although they are, in the end, liable to revision, are given a privileged position as “initially credible”175 starting-points in the search for equilibrium. As Rawls himself puts it, “we take [these considered judgments] provisionally as fixed points”.176 It is this privileged position of our considered judgments, as the defeasible foundations of MRE, which is underestimated by those who regard MRE simply as a form of coherentism. Indeed, MRE can be said to be predicated partly on this special status of our considered moral judgments. This is not to say that MRE is to be treated as a form of moral intuitionism. After all, because of the fact that MRE allows considered judgments to be revised, and because these considered judgments are used to select and modify other moral and non-moral beliefs (which, in turn, are then used to select and modify the total set of our considered moral judgments), MRE should be regarded as a partly coherentist epistemological strategy as well. But what at the very least should be clear is that, much like the weak foundationalist forms of moral coherentism discussed in paragraph 5.3, the proponent of MRE needs to address the issue how our considered judgments can “already have some initial, perhaps miniscule, degree of warrant”.177 It is for exactly this reason that Hare178 and Brandt have argued rightly that MRE faces a similar challenge as moral intuitionism, because it too treats considered judgments as having pre-theoretical “evidential force”.179 Indeed, it is unclear how the “mutual adjustment”180 of considered judgments and moral principles can produce warrant if one lacks a proper justification for treating our considered judgments as the “fixed points”181 which constitute the foundation of MRE. If, however, the advocates of MRE insist that considered judgments 173 Cf. D. Brink, Moral Realism and the Foundations of Ethics, Cambridge University Press, 1989, p. 303: “Rawls has advocated a coherentist moral epistemology according to which moral and political theories are justified on the basis of their coherence with our other beliefs, both moral and nonmoral.” 174 N. Daniels, “Reflective Equilibrium”, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, E. N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2013/entries/reflective-equilibrium/>. 175 N. Daniels, “Wide Reflective Equilibirium and Theory Acceptance in Ethics”, The Journal of Philosophy, May 1979, p. 272. 176 J. Rawls, A Theory of Justice, Harvard University Press, 2nd edition 1999, p. 18. Emphasis added. 177 E. Olsson, “Coherentist Theories of Epistemic Justification”, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, E. N. Zalta (ed.), forthcoming URL = <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2014/entries/justep-coherence/>. 178 R.M. Hare, “Rawls’ Theory of Justice”, Philosophical Quarterly, 23, p. 144-155. 179 R. Brandt, “The Science of Man and Wide Reflective Equilibrium”, Ethics, 100, p. 271. 180 J. Rawls, A Theory of Justice, Harvard University Press, 2nd edition 1999, p. 18. 181 See footnote 61. 41 do not play any sort of special or foundational role in its search for equilibrium, then they are faced with the (anti-coherentist) challenge how “simply making “coherent” a set of beliefs that have no “initial credibility” [can] produce justification”182. 5.5 Two forms of epistemological naturalism Another epistemological option is to accept what has become known as naturalism.183 As with so many philosophical terms, it is not immediate clear what is meant with epistemological naturalism. In this paragraph I will therefore discuss two different approaches to the question of moral epistemology, both of which have been defended as forms of (epistemological) naturalism. 5.5.1 Bridging the is/ought gap Naturalism is sometimes defined as the view that moral conclusions can be derived from nonmoral premises.184 As such, it rejects the Humean view that it “seems altogether inconceivable, how this new relation [ought or ought not] can be a deduction from the others [is and is not], which are entirely different from it”.185 According to Hume, moral conclusions can only be derived from premises which contain at least one moral premise. Mark Nelson, however, has argued that we can derive moral conclusions, and therefore attain moral knowledge, from entirely non-moral premises: “My argument is as follows: N1. N2. N3. ‘Bertie (morally) ought to marry Madeline’ is one of Aunt Dahlia’s beliefs. All of Aunt Dahlia’s beliefs are true. Therefore, Bertie (morally) ought to marry Madeline.” 186 According to Nelson, N1 and N2 are both examples of “is-premises”, which together lead to a logically valid moral conclusion. Although N1 contains a moral term, “that is not enough to make it a normative premise, since the word is mentioned in a report of someone’s belief, and is not in a normative proposition as such”.187 For this reason, Nelson claims, the is/ought gap has been bridged, and the possibility of deriving moral conclusions from entirely factual premises has been established. N. Daniels, “Reflective Equilibrium”, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy , E. N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2013/entries/reflective-equilibrium/>. 183 This view is not to confused with naturalism about the nature of moral properties, which has been discussed in chapter 3. 184 W. Sinnott-Armstrong, Moral Skepticisms, Oxford University Press, 2006, p. 135. 185 D. Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature, Cambridge University Press, 1988, p. 469. 186 M. Nelson, “Is it always fallacious to derive values from facts?”, Argumentation, 1995: 9, p. 555. 187 Ibid. 182 42 The first thing to notice about this argument is that non-cognitivists will reject N1 out of hand. But, as Nelson rightly says, he can still aim his argument “at cognitivists who believe in the Is/Ought gap, such as Prichard, Harman, Mackie, and […] Pigden”.188 Secondly, however, it should be clear that this example fails as a method for attaining moral knowledge. Indeed, even if one accepts the validity of the argument189, the premises themselves obviously still stand in need of justification. This means, however, that even if it is conceded that Nelson has succeeded in providing us with a successful example of how the is/ought gap can be bridged (after all, the is/ought gap is concerned with validity only), it falls far short of a successful naturalistic example of how to attain moral knowledge. Indeed, in order to show that N2 is justified, one would need to show, exactly because of N1, that we have reason to believe that Bertie morally ought to marry Madeline. This, however, would require moral assumptions or moral argumentation, something which would, surely, violate “the self-imposed limits of naturalism in moral epistemology”.190 5.5.2 Moral reliabilism Another form of moral epistemology draws its inspiration from a broader development in modern epistemology, which aims to somehow connect epistemology to the methodology of the natural sciences. In the previous chapter I have already briefly discussed one of the most important forms of epistemological naturalism: process reliabilism. According to process reliabilists, a belief is epistemically justified if and only if it is produced by a type of process which makes it probable that it is true, “even though the subject is not, or cannot be, aware of whether the belief has been produced by such a process”. 191 Reliabilism therefore only invokes “naturalistically respectable terms”.192 The advantage of such an epistemological account for the moral realist is the fact that a “moral belief needn’t be traced back to some other belief, itself in need of justification, but instead might terminate in a citation of the reliable process through which the belief was formed”.193 This means that reliabilism, as an externalistic account of epistemic justification, has to make no reference to (the adequacy of) the grounds for having the relevant belief. All that reliabilism requires for epistemic justification is that a certain belief is produced by a generally reliable (i.e. truth-tracking) process of belief-formation. The advantages and disadvantages of reliabilism are subject of a fierce debate between internalists and externalists. The most persistent and, indeed, most convincing criticism that has been leveled against reliabilism is that any given process can be described on various levels of generality. This worry has therefore become known as the “generality problem”. 188 Ibid. Something which can, and indeed has been, disputed. Cf. W. Sinnott-Armstrong, Moral Skepticisms, Oxford University Press, 2006, p. 142-152. 190 W. Sinnott-Armstrong, Moral Skepticisms, Oxford University Press, 2006, p. 151-152. 191 H. Philipse, God in the Age of Science, Oxford University Press, 2012, p. 68-69. 192 R. Feldman, “Naturalized Epistemology”, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2012/entries/epistemology-naturalized/>. 193 R. Shafer-Landau, Moral Realism: A Defence, Oxford University Press, 2003, p. 274. 189 43 The generality problem starts from the observation that we can always find reliable and unreliable descriptions of the same belief-producing process. So, to take a famous example of Laurence BonJour194, even if one stipulates that a process is reliable under the description of the process of clairvoyance, the actual belief-producing process might be unreliable under certain other descriptions, such as the process of sudden felt belief for which I have no evidence and which does not cohere with my other beliefs. So it seems that the reliabilists has to provide an argument which shows why it is nonarbitrary to pick out exactly a certain description as the relevant one. To offer such an argument would, however, be to do what externalists over time have proved incapable of doing. It seems that the only principled, non-arbitrary way to designate one belief-producing process as the single relevant one is to select the lowest, least abstract kind of beliefgenerating process.195 This least abstract kind of process, however, is exactly the actual beliefproducing process of which there is only one token. The consequence is that justification collapses into truth: the belief-producing process will be reliable only if the belief is true, and will be unreliable if it is false.196 This result is of course unsatisfactory for a theory of epistemic justification. 194 L. BonJour, The Structure of Empirical Knowledge. Harvard University Press, 1985, p. 41. H. Philipse, God in the Age of Science, Oxford University Press, 2012, p. 45. 196 Ibid. 195 44 Part IV The Relationship between Moral Realism and Epistemological Moral Scepticism 45 Chapter 6 The Meta-Ethical Consequences of Epistemic Inaccessibility “[E]ven if we suppose that there are sceptical arguments that have special force against moral realism, the argumentative burden this places on realism depends on holistic considerations.” 197 6.1 Introduction In the previous chapter we have seen that it is not at all uncontroversial whether something like a satisfactory moral realist epistemology has been developed over the years. For this reason, the epistemological doctrine of scepticism (the view that we can198 or do199 not have knowledge about either a certain class of propositions (local scepticism), or about any given proposition (global scepticism)) has become more popular in the moral domain. Indeed, the global epistemological sceptic, who raises doubts about our ability to attain knowledge of any given proposition about the world, is no longer the only type of sceptic who refuses to accept that we can attain moral knowledge. The perceived failure of moral realism to present a convincing moral epistemology has led to the emergence of a local rather than a global form of scepticism: epistemological moral scepticism. Epistemological moral scepticism can, therefore, be defined as the view that we cannot or do not have moral knowledge. In the remainder of this thesis I will refer to epistemological moral scepticism simply as “moral scepticism”. The emergence of this epistemological doctrine of moral scepticism naturally raises the question how this doctrine relates to the moral realism/moral anti-realism debate we have discussed in the previous parts of this thesis. In this thesis I will, therefore, look at the question whether moral scepticism and moral realism are compatible with one another. In other words: can the moral realist simultaneously be a moral sceptic or is moral scepticism incompatible with moral realism? This question is of course an important one: if they prove to be incompatible, then the moral realist will have to show why we should reject moral scepticism. If, however, moral scepticism is compatible with moral realism, this means that epistemological matters will be of less direct importance to the moral realist. So in a sense examining the relationship between moral scepticism and moral realism is an investigation into the importance of epistemology for the moral realism/moral anti-realism debate. Indeed, if it turns out that the moral realist cannot resort to accepting moral scepticism, then it will have been shown that a lack of a successful moral realist epistemology is a central problem for the moral realist. In the remainder of this chapter I will therefore look more closely at the relationship between moral realism and what is usually referred to as the “epistemic inaccessibility”- the view that we are unable to acquire justified moral belief and knowledge”200 – of alleged moral facts. In 197 R. Shafer-Landau, Moral Realism: A Defence, Oxford University Press, 2003, p. 234. This view is known as so-called Academic scepticism. 199 This can be seen as a form of Pyrrhonian scepticism. 200 Ibid., p. 232. 198 46 paragraph 6.2 I will start with discussing a common moral realist response to the question what the relationship between these two is. After that, in paragraph 6.3, I will look at different ways in which the moral realist might try to defend his commitment to moral realism in the face of an acknowledgement of the epistemic inaccessibility of the moral facts he stipulates. 6.2 A matter of logic? In this paragraph I will present and examine the usual moral realist response to the question whether moral scepticism and moral realism are compatible. Before I turn to this response, however, it is important to note that, in paragraph 2.1, I defined moral realism as the view that (i) moral claims purport to report moral facts in virtue of which these moral claims are either true or false (i.e., moral claims are truth-apt), and (ii) at least some of these moral claims are mind-independently true. The reason matters of definition are important here is that “epistemic access is sometimes built into the very definition of realism”201, such as in Boyd’s definition of moral realism.202 In such cases, the answer to the question whether moral scepticism and moral realism are compatible is of course a straightforward one: they are not. It was for this reason that I chose to define moral realism in an epistemologically neutral fashion. Now, if we take this epistemologically neutral definition of moral realism, we can turn to the question of its compatibility with moral scepticism. Most moral realists consider the answer to this question to be a matter of logic: “[S]kepticism about moral truth cannot be based on skepticism about moral knowledge, since lack of knowledge does not imply lack of truth. For similar reasons, skepticism about moral truth also cannot be based on skepticism about justified moral belief. Instead, skepticism about moral truth is usually based on views of moral language or metaphysics.”203 So the moral realist argues that, since metaphysical reality does not require our knowledge of this reality, even our established incapability204 of attaining moral knowledge (i.e. the Academic205 sceptic’s view that we are in principle unable to know moral propositions) would be logically insufficient to by itself lead us to reject moral realism.206 Or, in the words of David Brink: “we may just have no cognitive access to moral facts”. 207 In a similar vein, Russ Shafer-Landau argues that “epistemic inaccessibility” itself does not refute moral realism. Indeed, he rejects the view that “if, on moral realistic assumptions, we are unable to acquire D. Loeb, “Moral Realism and the Argument from Disagreement”, Philosophical Studies, 1998:90, p. 285. R. Boyd, “How to be a moral realist”, in: G. Sayre-McCord (ed.), Essays on Moral Realism, Cornell University Press, 1988, p. 181. 203 W. Sinnott-Armstrong, Moral Skepticisms, Oxford University Press, 2006, p. 11. Emphasis added. 204 This is to be contrasted with the view that at the moment we are unable to acquire moral knowledge. This view allows room for the possibility that in the future we will find a satisfactory moral epistemology. 205 See note 2. 206 Cf. K. DeLapp, Moral Realism, Bloomsbury Academic, 2013, p. 116: “[R]ealism is a metaphysical thesis about what is real and therefore it might be thought to be insulated from mundane concerns about whether we puny humans are or are not able to know that reality.” 207 D. Brink, “Moral Realism and the Sceptical Arguments from Disagreement and Queerness”, Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 1984: 62, p. 111. 201 202 47 justified moral belief and knowledge, then moral realism is (probably) false”.208 Instead, Shafer-Landau argues, we should base our choice for either moral realism or moral antirealism on “holistic considerations”, i.e. on how well “realism fares vis-à-vis its competitors across the whole range of criteria for theoretical adequacy in metaethics”.209 This would mean that, even if the moral realist would be wholly incapable of presenting a convincing moral epistemology, moral realism could be salvaged on, for example, metaphysical and psychological grounds. Now, it is clear that moral realist responses which merely point to the logical gap between a “lack of knowledge” and a “lack of truth” are going too fast. While it is of course true that such a gap exists, much more can be said about the meta-ethical consequences of epistemic inaccessibility. After all, if one considers epistemic inaccessibility in isolation, it seems to be beyond doubt that the best explanation of such inaccessibility is non-existence. Indeed, in the absence of overriding considerations to the contrary (on which I will say more below), it should be wholly uncontroversial to treat a lack of cognitive access as something which is best explained by the hypothesis that there simply is nothing to attain knowledge of in the first place. So even though a logically cogent argument (starting from the fact that no moral knowledge can be had, leading to the conclusion that no moral facts exist) would indeed require “a premise that we would be able to know moral facts if there were any” 210, it seems that an inference to the best explanation strongly suggests that we abandon belief in real, inaccessible moral facts if we accept their epistemic inaccessibility. Indeed, as Brink (himself a moral realist) says, “while moral realism and moral scepticism are compatible […], the standard and most plausible reason for claiming that we have no moral knowledge is the belief that there are no moral facts.”211 Or, in the words of Loeb, “morality could be real but inaccessible, of course, but if so then we would lack the best sort of evidence for believing in it.”212 6.3 Identifying overriding considerations In the previous paragraph it has been observed that, in the absence of strong evidence to the contrary, it seems unobjectionable to say that epistemic inaccessibility is best treated as an indication of irreality or non-existence. So what kind of overriding, “holistic”213 considerations could lead us to abandon this natural stance towards epistemic inaccessibility? In other words: what would be required for us to acknowledge the reality of unknowable moral entities? The moral realist could, for example, try to establish the truth of moral realism on metaphysical grounds. This would require the moral realist to show somehow that we have 208 R. Shafer-Landau, Moral Realism: A Defence, Oxford University Press, 2003, p. 232. Ibid., p. 234. 210 W. Sinnott-Armstrong, Moral Skepticisms, Oxford University Press, 2006, p. 46. 211 D. Brink, “Moral Realism and the Sceptical Arguments from Disagreement and Queerness”, Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 1984: 62, p. 124. Emphasis added. 212 D. Loeb, “Moral Realism and the Argument from Disagreement”, Philosophical Studies, 1998:90, p. 285. 213 See note 11. 209 48 better metaphysical reasons to believe in moral realism than in its anti-realist “competitors”.214 The problem for the moral realist, however, is that it is not sufficient to present merely a plausible moral realist metaphysics. Indeed, in order to establish overriding metaphysical considerations in favour of moral realism, the task at hand is to have us prefer moral realism over moral anti-realism on metaphysical grounds. So even if the moral realist would succeed in taking away the concerns we might have about moral realism’s account of moral supervenience215, he has not provided anything like an overriding metaphysical consideration in favour of moral realism. In order to do so, he would have to provide a better metaphysical account of morality than his anti-realist competitor. It is, however, difficult to see how the moral realist could succeed in doing so, since the anti-realist seems to have a perfectly plausible and natural metaphysical answer to the epistemic inaccessibility of alleged moral facts: there simply are none. It therefore seems that, in order to provide overriding metaphysical considerations in favour of moral realism, the moral realist would have to do much more than simply show how moral realism could be metaphysically possible: the moral realist would have to show why we cannot but believe in the existence of real moral facts. As was said before, it is, however, difficult to conceive how any such metaphysical argument would have to run. A similar argument applies to considerations about moral motivation or morality’s normativity. Indeed, as with moral metaphysics, moral realism is usually taken to suffer special difficulties in accounting for the intrinsic (or at least strong) connection between sincere moral judgment and moral motivation. This means that, even if the moral realist were to “develop a suitable account of morality’s normativity”216, he will have given us very little reason to ignore the moral realist “embarrassment of lacking a plausible moral epistemology”217 and to convert to moral realism despite the epistemic inaccessibility of the moral facts it stipulates. If this worry is formulated more generally, one can say that it is not enough for the moral realist to remedy the perceived defects moral realism has in, for example, presenting a plausible metaphysics and in accounting for moral motivation. What is needed in addition to this, are strong, positive arguments in favour of moral realism. It seems that only then the moral realist can be said to have good grounds to believe in real moral facts despite their cognitive inaccessibility. In other words: only if such arguments exist the moral realist will have reason to hold on to his realism even after the truth of moral scepticism has been established. Now, can such positive arguments be found? In paragraph 2.3 we have already encountered an argument in favour of moral realism which relies on an analogy between moral and scientific realism. Can the moral realist perhaps employ a version of this argument to tip the scale of our holistic considerations in favour of moral realism, despite the inaccessibility of moral facts? 214 See note 11. See paragraph 3.3 216 R. Shafer-Landau, Moral Realism: A Defence, Oxford University Press, 2003, p. 234. 217 Ibid., p. 234. 215 49 Unfortunately, the moral realist cannot. As was said in paragraph 2.3, scientific realism is usually defined as “the doctrine that the methods of science are capable of providing (partial or approximate) knowledge of unobservable (‘theoretical’) entities, such as atoms or electromagnetic fields”.218 Indeed, the whole idea behind scientific realism (and therefore behind the analogy between moral and scientific realism) is that the reliability of our scientific methodology is best explained by the truth-approximation of our scientific theories. In other words: the fact that we seem to be successful in improving “our knowledge of the world”219 and in modifying and improving our existing scientific methodology, is best explained on the assumption that our current theories are relevantly approximately true. It is clear that the moral realist who accepts moral scepticism cannot invoke this analogy to support his moral realism. Indeed, if one accepts moral scepticism then ex hypothesi there is no knowledge or epistemological success which is best explained on realist assumptions. This means, however, that if the moral realist chooses to accept moral scepticism, he not only faces the challenge that epistemic inaccessibility, considered in isolation, seems to be best explained by non-existence, but he thereby also fatally undermines the moral realist argument which relies on an analogy with scientific realism. In this paragraph I have not yet considered “the intuitive case for moral realism”220 as a possible overriding consideration in favour of moral realism. The reason is that, as it is (one of) the strongest and intuitively plausible arguments in favour of moral realism, I will devote the entire chapter 7 to the question whether the perceived intuitive advantage moral realism enjoys can help the moral realist to salvage moral realism in the face of epistemic inaccessibility. R. Boyd, “How to be a moral realist”, in: G. Sayre-McCord (ed.), Essays on Moral Realism, Cornell University Press, 1988, p. 188. Emphasis added. 219 Ibid., p. 190. 220 See paragraph 2.2. 218 50 Chapter 7 Epistemic Inaccessibility and Moral Discourse “[W]e should not believe in facts that we cannot know.”221 7.1 Introduction In the previous chapter the meta-ethical consequences of epistemic inaccessibility have been discussed in a general manner. In that chapter I have tried to show that there is more to be said about the relationship between moral realism and moral scepticism than that they are logically compatible. Indeed, I have argued that, in the absence of overriding considerations to the contrary, moral scepticism is best explained by a denial of moral realism. In this chapter I will look at “the intuitive case in favour of moral realism”, which I characterised in paragraph 2.2 as “the most important argument in favour of moral realism”. If this argument can be upheld in the face of epistemic inaccessibility, then those who are convinced by this argument can perhaps claim to have found an overriding consideration in favour of moral realism. This, then, could render moral realism an attractive position “vis-àvis its competitors across the whole range of criteria for theoretical adequacy in metaethics”.222 If, however, it turns out that accepting moral scepticism makes the intuitive case in favour of moral realism lose its appeal, then there seems to be very little reason left to uphold moral realism in the face of epistemic inaccessibility. In paragraph 7.2 I will start by looking at the consequences epistemic inaccessibility has for our first-order moral discourse. Then, in paragraph 7.3, I will relate this discussion to the “intuitive case in favour of moral realism”. I will argue that an acknowledgement of the epistemic inaccessibility of moral facts should lead us to suspend judgment on substantive, first-order moral questions and that our moral discourse, which is predicated on the assumption that such first-order questions are epistemically accessible, is fundamentally misguided. For this reason, or so I will argue, the intuitive case in favour of moral realism loses its appeal if the moral realist acknowledges the epistemic inaccessibility of moral facts. 7.2 Moral discourse and suspension of judgment Before I will specifically go into the relationship between epistemic inaccessibility and the intuitive case in favour of moral realism, I will discuss the general consequences epistemic inaccessibility has for our first-order moral discourse. As we have seen in the previous chapter, “epistemic inaccessibility” is a term for saying that “we are unable to acquire justified moral belief and knowledge”223. For the purposes of this chapter it is not important whether such inaccessibility is taken as established inaccessibility (i.e. the Academic sceptic’s claim that we can never acquire knowledge) or simply as the view that at the moment we are unable to acquire knowledge (due to the fact that up until now no 221 W. Sinnott-Armstrong, Moral Skepticisms, Oxford University Press, 2006, p. 46. R. Shafer-Landau, Moral Realism: A Defence, Oxford University Press, 2003, p. 234. 223 Ibid., p. 232. 222 51 satisfactory epistemology has been put forward). Indeed, for the purposes of this chapter it is not needed to take a position as to whether we know that moral facts are principally inaccessible or whether we only know that at the moment we lack a method of attaining moral knowledge: it is sufficient to hold that accepting epistemic inaccessibility entails accepting that (at the very least) we are currently unable to acquire justified moral belief and knowledge. An important starting point for a discussion about the consequences of epistemic inaccessibility for our first-order moral discourse is the (Ancient sceptical) observation that “if we cannot confidently claim knowledge, we should hold back from any kind of truthclaim”224. So if we have no reason to favour one belief over another, it seems rational to suspend belief (epochê225) rather than to embrace one of the two without a proper epistemic justification. This epistemological maxim is nowadays still widely accepted. Richard Feldman, for example, holds that in situations of epistemic parity, in which there is no more reason to favour one’s own view over the opposite view that is equally firmly held by one’s epistemic peer226, we should suspend judgment because we cannot confidently claim knowledge.227 Let us now turn to the moral realist’s acceptance of the epistemic inaccessibility of moral facts. It would appear this acceptance has far-reaching consequences for our moral discourse. Indeed, the truth of moral scepticism affects our first-order moral beliefs in a rather fundamental way: because of the fact that moral scepticism establishes the inaccessibility of moral truths, it seems reasonable to suspend belief on such matters. It is important to note that I do not mean that we should suspend belief on (second-order) meta-ethical matters. Rather to the contrary: epistemic inaccessibility should be regarded as an important factor in deciding which second-order view about morality we should embrace. But in fact, up until now I explicitly left open the possibility that there might be strong meta-ethical reasons to accept moral realism, even in the face of epistemic inaccessibility. So when I say that it seems reasonable to suspend belief “on such matters”, I do not mean that we should suspend judgment on the question whether moral facts exist. Indeed, even if we cannot know (the content of) first-order moral facts, we can in theory be justified228 in having the second-order meta-ethical belief that such moral facts exist on the grounds of, for example, metaphysical arguments. The point is rather that our first-order moral discourse (our substantive moral beliefs and moral judgments) cannot be upheld rationally in the face of epistemic inaccessibility: we should suspend judgment on the content of moral facts, which is the subject of first-order moral judgments and moral argumentation. K. Vogt, “Ancient Skepticism”, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2011 Edition), E.N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2011/entries/skepticism-ancient/>. 225 Sextus Empiricus, Outlines of Pyrrhonism, tr. J. Annas and J. Barnes, I 6-7. 226 Epistemic peers “literally share all evidence and are equal with respect to their abilities and dispositions relevant to interpreting that evidence”. See R. Feldman and T.A. Warfield, Disagreement, Oxford University Press, 2010, p. 2. 227 R. Feldman, “Reasonable Religious Disagreements”, in L. Antony (ed.): Philosophers without God: Meditations on Atheism and the Secular Life , Oxford University Press, 2007. 228 Whether we can in fact justifiedly believe in moral facts in the light of epistemic inaccessibility is something that depends on the existence of the “overriding considerations” I discussed in the previous chapter. I will again turn to this issue in paragraph 7.3. 224 52 The important epistemic consequence of epistemic inaccessibility is therefore that rationally one no longer can hold first-order moral beliefs. It is of course possible to, as a person or as a community, take certain things as moral facts for pragmatic reasons, but epistemic inaccessibility does make it impossible to hold first-order moral beliefs in a rational manner. This, however, means that epistemic inaccessibility demands that our first-order moral discourse be radically altered, if not abandoned altogether. After all, if epistemic inaccessibility rationally requires us to suspend judgment on first-order questions of morality, then it seems we should hold back from the usual truth-claims in our substantive moral discourse. 7.3 Epistemic inaccessibility and the intuitive case in favour of moral realism In the previous paragraph I have looked at the consequences epistemic inaccessibility has for our ordinary moral discourse. In this paragraph I will relate this to “the intuitive case in favour of moral realism”, which I discussed in some detail in paragraph 2.2. Now, in order to be able to discuss the relationship between moral scepticism and moral realism’s intuitive appeal, it is instructive to begin with a brief re-formulation of this intuitive argument in favour of moral realism: “Moral judgments are typically expressed in language employing the declarative mood; we engage in moral argument and deliberation; we regard people as capable both of making moral mistakes and of correcting their moral views; we often feel constrained by what we take to be moral requirements that are in some sense imposed from without and independent of us. These phenomena are held to demonstrate the realist or cognitivist character of commonsense morality; morality seems to concern matters of fact that people can and sometimes do recognize and debate about.”229 So, as I already said in paragraph 2.2, both the phenomenology and the form and content of our moral judgments seem to presuppose a firm belief in objective moral truth. In other words: our moral discourse is usually taken by the moral realist to provide a strong indication of our moral realist presuppositions. The problem, however, is that even if our moral discourse shows a firm belief in objective moral truth, that belief is predicated completely on our assumed ability to access these moral truths. Indeed, all the phenomena that are meant to provide the moral realist with an argumentative advantage (“we engage in moral argument and deliberation”, “we regard people as capable both of making moral mistakes and of correcting their moral views”) share a deep commitment to the cognitive accessibility of moral facts. This, however, means that, if one accepts moral scepticism, one is thereby forced to conclude that our moral discourse (e.g. our moral judgments which aim at moral truth and our feelings of moral mistake and moral accuracy) is somehow fundamentally misguided. After all, and as we have seen in the 229 D. Brink, Moral Realism and the Foundations of Ethics, Cambridge University Press, 1989, p. 24. 53 previous paragraph, it is clear that the only rational thing to do with regard to epistemically inaccessible facts is suspend judgment on their content230 altogether. It should by now be clear why the intuitive case in favour of moral realism loses all its appeal if it is coupled with an admission of the epistemic inaccessibility of moral facts. The intuitive case in favour of moral realism takes our moral discourse as an indication of the truth of moral realism, because of the fact that this moral discourse seems to be characterised by a deep commitment to the objective reality of moral facts. This discourse, so the moral realist claims, should be taken seriously and should therefore be considered an important argument in favour of moral realism. But the problem is that whereas the moral realist claims that the anti-realist is problematically forced to consider our ordinary moral judgments as false (and, hence, to embrace a sort of weak error theory with regard to our moral discourse), it seems the moral realist who accepts epistemic inaccessibility is likewise forced to consider our moral discourse as fundamentally misguided. After all, our ordinary moral judgments aim at correctly representing epistemically inaccessible facts, which should be seen as a sign of deep confusion rather than as something indicative of the truth of moral realism. So an acknowledgement of the epistemic inaccessibility of moral facts makes it impossible to take our moral discourse “at face value”, since this discourse exactly consists of (ex hypothesi misguided) attempts to report real moral facts. Indeed, if we cannot attain knowledge of moral propositions because “we are unable to acquire justified moral belief and knowledge”231, then it becomes unclear why for example the declarative form of our moral judgments (“genocide is wrong”) would be something to take seriously as an argument in favour of moral realism. In other words: how can a fundamentally misguided social practice, which revolves around employing certain notions of moral truth and access to moral facts, function as an argument in favour of moral realism? It is this question moral realists face if they acknowledge the epistemic inaccessibility of moral facts. In this paragraph I have attempted to relate the moral realist’s acknowledgement of moral scepticism to the “intuitive case in favour of moral realism”. I have argued that, since an acknowledgement of moral scepticism commits the moral realist to the conclusion that our moral discourse is fundamentally misguided in that it tries to describe and attain knowledge of epistemically inaccessible moral facts, the moral realist cannot accept moral scepticism without surrendering his intuitive argument in favour of moral realism. After all, one cannot consistently claim that our moral discourse reveals valuable insights for the moral realism/moral anti-realism debate if one acknowledges (by acknowledging moral scepticism) that one of the fundamental assumptions of this moral discourse (i.e. the assumption that we can sensibly make moral judgments and moral arguments because we have access to moral facts) is mistaken. This means that, much like the moral realist argument which relies on an analogy with scientific realism232, the intuitive case in favour of moral realism is fatally undermined by an acknowledgement of moral scepticism. Indeed, both of these arguments, which I characterised 230 As opposed to their existence, which is, as I have argued in the previous paragraph, something which is the subject of second-order meta-ethical investigation. 231 R. Shafer-Landau, Moral Realism: A Defence, Oxford University Press, 2003, p. 232. 232 See paragraph 6.3. 54 in chapter 2 as two of the most important arguments in favour of moral realism, rely on an assumption that we can attain justified moral belief or moral knowledge. For this reason the moral realist acknowledgement of moral scepticism has far-reaching consequences: it not only leads to the moral realist facing the challenge of providing overriding considerations in favour of moral realism to remedy the prima facie explanatory disadvantage in accounting for epistemic inaccessibility, but it also undermines two of the most powerful positive arguments the moral realist usually puts forward in favour of his position. This combination is of course a highly uncomfortable one for the moral realist, since these two positive arguments are of crucial importance to the moral realist in formulating possible “overriding considerations”. So even if we take moral realism and moral scepticism as logically compatible, and if we base our choice for either moral realism or moral anti-realism on “holistic considerations”, i.e. on how well “realism fares vis-à-vis its competitors across the whole range of criteria for theoretical adequacy in metaethics”233, the epistemic inaccessibility of moral facts not only creates an extra burden of proof for the moral realist, but it also fatally undermines the most important positive arguments in favour of moral realism. Indeed, even the Frege-Geach Problem (the third important argument in favour of moral realism I discussed in chapter 2) can be said to lose some of its force if the moral realist endorses moral scepticism: if it turns out we should suspend judgment on substantive, firstorder questions of morality, then the perceived incapability of non-cognitivist forms of antirealism to account for some aspects of our moral discourse (e.g. the validity of moral argumentation) becomes less234 problematic. After all, if epistemic inaccessibility leads to the conclusion that our moral discourse is somehow fundamentally misguided, then it is very much the question whether the perceived incapability to make sense of this discourse can still function as an important argument against non-cognitivist forms of anti-realism. The conclusion is therefore that although moral realism and moral scepticism are logically compatible, they can in fact only be combined at the cost of rendering moral realism a wholly unattractive and unconvincing meta-ethical position. 233 R. Shafer-Landau, Moral Realism: A Defence, Oxford University Press, 2003, p. 234. There are of course still difficulties left for the non-cognitivist in this regard. After all, it is a perfectly sensible thing to say, in the light of epistemic inaccessibility, “I wonder whether it is wrong to steal”. And, as we have seen in paragraph 2.5, the moral realist can argue that the non-cognitivist has difficulties in accounting for the semantic effects of moral predicates in such embedded contexts. In appears, then, that not all (perceived) difficulties with regard to the Frege-Geach Problem are undermined by a moral realist acknowledgement of epistemic inaccessibility. 234 55 Part V Conclusion 56 Chapter 8 Conclusion In this thesis I have examined the relationship between moral realism and epistemological moral scepticism. This relationship is usually portrayed as a rather straightforward one: because we cannot draw metaphysical conclusions about the existence of moral facts on the basis of the question whether we can have epistemic access to such moral facts, so the argument goes, epistemological moral scepticism and moral realism can be endorsed simultaneously. In this thesis I have, however, tried to say a bit more about this relationship. More specifically, I have argued that (i) in the absence of strong evidence to the contrary, epistemic inaccessibility is best regarded as an indication of irreality or non-existence, and (ii) that such “strong evidence to the contrary” is not available to the moral realist, since the most important positive arguments in favour of moral realism are undermined fatally by an acknowledgement of epistemic inaccessibility. In order to bolster this second claim, it was necessary both to formulate the most important arguments that are usually put forward in favour of moral realism235 and to examine whether these arguments hold up in the face of epistemic inaccessibility. Chapters 6 and 7 of this thesis were to a large extent designed to fulfill this latter task. Indeed, in these two chapters I have argued (i) that the moral realist argument which relies on an analogy between scientific realism and moral realism cannot be maintained if one accepts the epistemic inaccessibility of moral facts, because accepting epistemic inaccessibility implies ex hypothesi that there is no knowledge or epistemological success which is best explained on realist assumptions, and (ii) that, because an acknowledgement of moral scepticism commits the moral realist to the conclusion that our moral discourse is somehow fundamentally misguided, the moral realist cannot accept moral scepticism without surrendering his intuitive argument in favour of moral realism. Furthermore, as I have argued in paragraph 7.3, even the Frege-Geach Problem can be said to lose some of its force if the moral realist endorses moral scepticism. So, in conclusion, it appears that the epistemic inaccessibility of moral facts, which should lead one to endorse epistemological moral scepticism, not only creates an extra burden of proof for the moral realist, but it also undermines fatally the most important positive arguments in favour of moral realism. For this reason, moral realism is rendered a wholly unattractive and unconvincing meta-ethical position if it is coupled with an acknowledgement of epistemological moral scepticism. 235 See chapter 2. 57 Bibliography Books R.L. Arrington, Rationalism, Realism, and Relativism, Cornell University Press, 1989 T. Baldwin, G.E. Moore, Routledge, 1990 S. Blackburn, Ruling Passions: A Theory of Practical Reasoning, Clarendon Press, 1998 L. BonJour, The Structure of Empirical Knowledge. Harvard University Press, 1985 D. Brink, Moral Realism and the Foundations of Ethics, Cambridge University Press, 1989 K. DeLapp, Moral Realism, Bloomsbury Academic, 2013 R. Feldman and T.A. Warfield, Disagreement, Oxford University Press, 2010 A. Gibbard, Wise Choices, Apt Feelings. A Theory of Normative Judgement, Clarendon Press, 1990 A. Goldman, Epistemology and Cognition, Harvard University Press, 1986 G. Harman, The Nature of Morality, Oxford University Press, 1977 D. Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature, Cambridge University Press, 1988 R. Joyce, The Evolution of Morality, MIT Press, 2006 R. Joyce, The Myth of Morality, Cambridge University Press, 2001 C.M. Korsgaard, The Sources of Normativity, Cambridge University Press, 1996 C.I. Lewis, An Analysis of Knowledge and Valuation, LaSalle: Open Court, 1946 D. Lewis, On The Plurality of Worlds, Blackwell, 1986 J. Mackie, Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong, Penguin, 1977 G.E. Moore, Principia Ethica, Cambridge University Press, 1993 H. Philipse, God in the Age of Science, Oxford University Press, 2012 J. Rawls, A Theory of Justice, Harvard University Press, 2nd edition 1999 58 N. Rescher, The Coherence Theory of Truth, Oxford University Press, 1973 M. Schroeder, Noncognitivism in Ethics, Routledge, 2010 Sextus Empiricus, Outlines of Pyrrhonism, tr. J. Annas and J. Barnes R. Shafer-Landau, Metaphysics, vol. I, Routledge, 2008 R. Shafer-Landau, Moral Realism: A Defence, Oxford University Press, 2003 W. Sinnott-Armstrong, Moral Skepticisms, Oxford University Press, 2006 M. Smith, The Moral Problem, Blackwell, 1994 R. Wedgwood, The Nature of Normativity, Oxford University Press, 2009 Articles A. J. Ayer, “The Emotive Theory of Ethics”, in: G. Sher (ed.), Moral Philosophy: Selected Readings, Harcourt, Brace & Howe, 1996 S. Ball, “Linguistic Intuitions and Varieties of Ethical Naturalism,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 51, 1991 S. Blackburn, “Attitudes and Contents”, Ethics: 98, 1988 R. Boyd, “How to be a moral realist”, in: R. Shafer-Landau (ed.), Metaphysics, vol. II, Routledge, 2008 R. Brandt, “The Science of Man and Wide Reflective Equilibrium”, Ethics: 100, 1990 D. Brink, “Moral Realism and the Sceptical Arguments from Disagreement and Queerness”, Australasian Journal of Philosophy: 62, 1984 T. Cuneo, “Moral Realism, Quasi Realism, and Skepticism”, in: The Oxford Handbook of Skepticism, Oxford University Press, 2009 N. Daniels, “Wide Reflective Equilibirium and Theory Acceptance in Ethics”, The Journal of Philosophy, May 1979 D. Davidson, “A Coherence Theory of Knowledge and Truth,” in Truth and Interpretation, E. LePore (ed.), Blackwell, 1986 59 J. Dreier, “The Supervenience Argument Against Moral Realism, The Southern Journal of Philosophy: 30, 1992 R. Feldman, “Bonjour and Sosa on Internalism, Externalism and Basic Beliefs”, Philosophical Studies, 2006 R. Feldman, “Reasonable Religious Disagreements”, in L. Antony (ed.): Philosophers without God: Meditations on Atheism and the Secular Life , Oxford University Press, 2007 R. Firth, “Ethical absolutism and the ideal observer”, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research:12, 1952 W.K. Frankema, “The Naturalistic Fallacy”, Mind: 48, 1939 G. Frege, “Thoughts”, in: Logical Investigations, Blackwell, 1977 G. Frege, “Über Sinn und Bedeutung“, Zeitschrift für Philosophie und philosophische Kritik, 1892 P. Geach, “Assertion”, Philosophical Review: 74, 1965 E. Gettier, “Is Justified True Belief Knowledge?”, Analysis: 23, 1963 R.M. Hare, “Rawls’ Theory of Justice”, Philosophical Quarterly: 23, 1973 G. Harman, “Moral Explanations of Natural Facts – Can Moral Claims Be Tested Against Moral Reality?”, The Southern Journal of Philosophy: 24, 1986 G. Harman, “Moral Relativism Defended”, The Philosophical Review: 85, 1975 F. Jackson and P. Pettit, “Moral Functionalism and Moral Motivation,” Philosophical Quarterly: 45, 1995 R. Joyce, “The Evolutionary Debunking of Morality”, in: Reason and Responsibility, J. Feinberg and R. Shafer-Landau (eds.), Cengage, 2013 G. Kahane, “Evolutionary Debunking Arguments”, Nous: 45, 2011 D. Loeb, “Moral Realism and the Argument from Disagreement”, Philosophical Studies: 90, 1998 B. Majors, “Moral Explanation and the Special Sciences”, Philosophical Studies: 133, 2003 M. Nelson, “Is it always fallacious to derive values from facts?”, Argumentation: 9, 1995 60 H. Philipse, “God, Ethics, and Evolution”. In: H. A. Harris (ed.), God, Goodness and Philosophy, Ashgate, 2011 G. Sayre-McCord, “Coherence and Models for Moral Theorizing”, Pacific Philosophical Quarterly: 66, 1985 G. Sayre-McCord, “The Many Moral Realisms,” Southern Journal of Philosophy, Spindel Conference Supplement, 1986 M. Schroeder, “What is the Frege-Geach Problem?”, Philosophy Compass, Vol. 3, July 2008 P. Singer, “Ethics and Intuitions”, The Journal of Ethics: 9.3-4, 2005 M. Smith, “Realism”, in: P. Singer (ed.), A Companion to Ethics, Blackwell, 1990 S. Street, “A Darwinian Dilemma for Realist Theories of Value”, Philosophical Studies: 127, 2006 N. Sturgeon, “Moral Explanations”, in: R. Shafer-Landau (ed.), Metaphysics, vol. II, Routledge, 2008 A. Tarski, “The Semantic Conception of Truth”, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 1944 Electronic resources N. Daniels, “Reflective Equilibrium”, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, E. N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2013/entries/reflectiveequilibrium/>. R. Feldman, “Naturalized Epistemology”, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2012/entries/epistemologynaturalized/>. J. J. Ichikawa and M. Steup, “The Analysis of Knowledge”, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, E.N. Zalta (ed.), forthcoming URL = <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2014/entries/knowledge-analysis/>. R. Joyce, “Moral Anti-Realism”, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2009 Edition), E.N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2009/entries/moralanti-realism/>. E. Olsson, “Coherentist Theories of Epistemic Justification”, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, E. N. Zalta (ed.), forthcoming URL = <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2014/entries/justep-coherence/>. 61 M. Ridge, "Moral Non-Naturalism", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2014 Edition), E. N. Zalta (ed.), forthcoming URL = <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2014/entries/moral-non-naturalism/>. M. van Roojen, “Moral Cognitivism vs. Non-Cognitivism”, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2013 Edition), E,N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2013/entries/moral-cognitivism/>. C. Rosati, , “Moral Motivation”, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2014 Edition), E.N. Zalta (ed.), forthcoming URL = <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2014/entries/moral-motivation/>. G. Sayre-McCord, “Moral Realism”, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2011 Edition), E. N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2011/entries/moral-realism/>. W. Sinnott-Armstrong, “Moral Skepticism”, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2011 Edition), E.N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2011/entries/skepticism-moral/>. K. Vogt, “Ancient Skepticism”, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2011 Edition), E.N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2011/entries/skepticism-ancient/>. 62