Salahaddin University-Hawler Postgraduate Studies Board (Applied Linguistics/Master) General Linguistics BOOK REVIEW A FIRST-PHASE SYNTAX GILLIAN CATRIONA RAMCHAND Reviewer: Joanna Ismail Omer (M.A Student in Applied Linguistics) Instructor Assist. Prof. Dr. Himdad Abdul-Qahar Muhammad 2011 Introduction 0 The title of the book is Verb Meaning and the Lexicon by Gillian Catriona Ramchand. It is first published in 2008 by Cambridge University Press and it is part of Cambridge Studies in Linguistics. The relationship between the meaning of words and the structure of sentences is an important area of research in linguistics. This book arrives at a modular classification of verb types within English and across languages, studying the connections between lexical conceptual meaning and event structural relations. Ramchand treats the lexical/syntactic representation of verbs within a broad perspective that addresses central claims and sentence types that have been put forward in studies on valency and aspect from a range of theoretical approaches and places her analyses in a Minimalist syntactic framework she refers to as a first-phase syntax. The book is structured as follows: in chapter one which is the introductory chapter, Ramchand treats a number of approaches to the lexicon with special reference to the status of semantics, syntax and encyclopedic knowledge and classifies her proposal as generativist-constructivist. The second chapter is devoted to a wide range of sentence types Ramchand introduces as basic verbargument structures, which in chapter three she places in a syntactic model, a first-phase syntax. Chapter four applies this first-phase syntax to English verbs and demonstrates how they may be classified on the basis of the position they occupy in the projected syntactic structure. Chapters five and six take a more indepth and cross-linguistic look at two phenomena that receive specific treatment in the model, results/paths and causitivization, respectively, and the programmatic chapter seven explores further possibilities of the proposed analysis and indicates open questions. 1 Chapter One/ Introduction Except its introductory part it consists of two sections. Ramchand devotes the main and introductory part of this chapter to show that her first task is to define the relation between the mental lexicon and the syntax, to which she devotes the main part of this introductory chapter. She sets the stage by putting forth the claim that lexical behaviour is systematic and generalizable, this is due to syntactic modes of combination. In brief, Ramchand distinguishes two conceptions of the nature of the lexicon; the 'lexical-thematic approach' and 'the generativist-constructivist approach' and both have an extreme and a more Capturing argument-structure generalizations section consists of two other subsections: The lexical–thematic approach; which conceives of the lexicon as a bundle of information in which each verb is stored with fixed information about its arguments. Most notably (Dowty, 1990) instantiated in the syntax through linking rules with no lexicon-internal manipulations prior to insertion (the static lexicon view). A moderate reading of the lexical-thematic approach leads to a view in which, although verbs in the lexicon are thought of as carrying information about argument structure these are determined by regular processes in the lexicon (the dynamic lexicon), as when it comes to aspect specification. Generative–constructivist approach; refers to the lexical roots that contain no syntactically relevant information at all. The generativist-constructivist approach has two versions as well: in the first one the verb is stored without any specification of its argument structure and is just a bundle of cognitive and encyclopedic information (the 'naked roots view'), for example; 2 RUN continuous directed motion undergone by animate entity motion involves rapid movement of legs, no continuous contact with ground . . . Associations: exercise, boredom, heart attacks etc. In addition, Borer (2005), for the English verb (Siren), offers the following examples; (a) The fire stations sirened throughout the raid. (b) The factory sirened midday and everyone stopped for lunch. (c) The police sirened the Porsche to a stop. (d) The police car sirened up to the accident. (e) The police car sirened the daylights out of me. The second includes the one in which at least some information about valency and semantic roles is stored with the lexical entry (the well-dressed roots view). It needs to be observed that the main distinction between the static lexicon view and the well-dressed roots view lies in the theoretical framework in which it is embedded, de-compositional versus constructivist. Ramchand does not readily subscribe to any of these views. In her interpretation of the lexicon a lexical entry is nothing more than the memorized link between chunks of conceptual structure and conditions of insertion. This could be regarded as a moderate version of the generative-constructivist view, in which verbs with limited syntactic labels are associated with particular constellations in a 3 generative syntactic structure but it should be noted that these should not be seen as properties of individual lexemes since similar patterns are found crosslinguistically. The idea in Excursus on the role of encyclopedic knowledge section is to make a strict and principled distinction between linguistic meaning and encyclopedic content.The writer states that a clear- cut distinction between the two cannot be made because they are interwoven; he argues that Constructionalsemantic and lexical-encyclopedic contributions are unified to form a proposition at the interface with the cognitive/interpretive systems of the mind/brain. For example; The entry for run is an idealization of the distributed nature of the information involved. Here the strong links of mental association can be seen; RUN Label seen by PF: / r ∧ n / Label seen by narrow syn–sem computation: v,V continuous directed motion undergone by animate motion involves rapid movement of legs, no continuous contact with ground . . Chapter Associations: exercise, boredom, heart attacks Two is entitled The Empirical Ground In this chapter, the writer argues that although some verbs, e.g. 'eat' may be applied in a wide range of sentence types (transitive, intransitive, causative, 4 way-constructions etc.) the use of other verbs is much more constrained, as one can see in, Selection versus variability section that Ramchand mentions that the specification of syntactic complementation can account for the difference between transitive and intransitive verbs, for example; John saw the lizard./*John saw. *John dined the tortellini./John dined. Or for the difference between the verbs that take CP complements vs. IP complements on the other, for example; John hoped that the rain would fall./ *John hoped the rain to fall. –*John got that the rain would fall./ John got the rain to fall. The strategy Ramchand would pursue is first of all to reject the existence of formal selectional features in the lexicon, but attempt to account for what rigidity there is in terms of purely syntactic or categorial features, made possible by a more articulated view of the functional sequence within the verb phrase. The first step is to establish and motivate the primitives that are empirically necessary in a decomposition of verbal meaning. This sketch is intended as a basic outline of the important distinctions that need to be made in the face of the broadest empirical patterns, not as a complete exegesis of verb types. In doing so, Ramchand in Causation section argues that the first component of verbal meaning that has received much empirical support in the literature is that of causation. Causation has been shown to be a relevant parameter in verbal differences and shows up veryoften as overt morphology within the verbal inventory of human languages.Moreover, she mentions the intransitive verbs and states that the intransitive verbs that possess an external argument can be demonstrated by their ability to take X’s way objects under certain circumstances as it can be seen in the following examples; (a) He stank his smelly way home. (b) The water spewed its way along the corridor. 5 (c) John ran his way into history. While in mentioning transitive verb types, she states that among transitive verbs, external arguments can be volitional agents (as in a, b sentences), instrumentals (in sentence 'c'), abstract causes/sources (in'd, f' sentences), showing the generality and abstractness of the external argument relation. (a) John broke the window. (b) John built that house. (c) The hammer broke the window. (d) The videotape from the secret camera demonstrated the truth of the matter. (e) The storm broke the window. (f) John’s money built that house. In Nonaspectual arguments section Ramchand introduces a range of sentence types that have been adduced in the argument structure literature on the basis of the following reoccurring semantic roles: Initiator (an entity whose properties/ behaviour are responsible for the eventuality coming into existence), Undergoer (argument that is interpreted as undergoing the change asserted by a dynamic verb), Resultee (direct argument related to a result state), Path and Rheme. The latter two are the most distinctive in Ramchand's proposal. Ramchand assumes that these are the basic semantic roles of arguments, accounting for such verb features as 'causality' and 'telicity', which she considers to be secondary. Chapter Three: A first-phase syntax This chapter gives a first overview of Ramchand's model, which she stresses to be programmatic rather than definitive. On the basis of the sentence types introduced in the second chapter she distinguishes three subevents in the event-structure: ''a causing subevent, a process-denotiong subevent and a 6 subevent corresponding to result state''. Each of these subevents is ordered in the hierarchical embedding relation as shown in the example below: initP (causing projection) procP(process projection) DP2 subj of ‘process’ init proc DP3 subj of ‘cause’ resP (result proj) DP1 subj of ‘result’ res XP These are interpreted as three projections: the initiation phrase (initP), of which the subject position is taken by the subject of a cause, or INITIATOR. This phrase may head a process phrase (procP), the subject of which is the subject of a process, or UNDERGOER, which in turn may head a result phrase (resP), the subject of which is a RESULTEE. The object position of the lowest phrase may both be taken by a PATH or a RHEME. This structure is the first pillar on which the theory rests. Two other main components are the notions 'merge' and 'monotonicity'. In Ramchand's proposal the capitalized roles above are not monolithic, but can be combined to form complex roles. Ramchand characterizes the syntactic operation with which this is done through the central Minimalist term merge, which she conciliates with more traditional interpretations of the theoretical construct by stating that: ''if merge is conceived of asset information, then nothing prevents a particular item from being a member of more than one set''. (1-6) are examples of these 'pure' and 'combined' roles: 1. The key opened the door ('the key' = initiator) 2. The ball rolled (= undergoer) 3. Ariel ate the mango ('the mango' = path) 4. Katherine ran her shoes ragged ('her shoes' = result) 7 5. The diamond sparkled (= undergoer-initiator) 6. Katherine broke the stick ('the stick' = resultee-undergoer) Ramchand would assume the causing subevent to be a state but leave it open whether further investigation of the data might require relaxing this position to admit any eventuality more generally. In the semantic interpretation of structure, the writer states that the semantics of event structure and event participants is read directly off the structure, and not directly off information encoded by lexical items. Ramchand assumes a regular connection between the subevents in macro-events which can be 'decomposed' into the subevents indicated by the phase types and the semantic roles of the core and external arguments which are derived from argument positions in the structure. Based on formalizations proposed by Roger Schwarzschild, Ramchand conceives of the relation between these two as property sets that have to be 'monotonic' and a relation between two structured domains is said to be monotonic if it preserves the ordering from one domain to the other. In the Rhematic material section the writer illustrates that rhematic material always occur in complement position to an eventive head, and will never occur in the specifier position of an eventive head. She mentions definitions of some basic terms as in the following; Initiators are the individuated entities that possess the property denoted by the initiational subeventuality, which leads to the process coming into being. (a) The key opened the lock. Pure initiator Undergoers are individuated entities whose position/state or motion/ change is homomorphically related to some path. Undergoers are ‘subjects’ of process,while paths are complements of process. (a) Karena drove the car. Pure undergoers Resultees (Figures of result) are the individuated entities whose state is described with respect to the resultative property/Ground. 8 (a) Katherine ran her shoes ragged. Pure resultees Grounds of Result possess an inherent nongradable property which describes the result state. (a) Karena entered the room. Ground of result Undergoer–initiator is a composite role which arises when the same argument is the holder of initiational state and holder of a changing property homomorphic with the event trace of the proc event. (a) Karena ran to the tree. Undergoer–initiators Ramchand assumes that a composite role comprising of a rhematic position anda role in specifier position is not attested. However, she has left it open that such movements might be possible in special circumstances. According to the writer the most important point in the Agents and experiencers: the special case of mental states section is that animate/humanreferring DPs have the option of being interpreted as volitional causers, and as experiencers of static or changing mental states. There is an analogue in the psychological domain for every sub-predication and role type in specifier position that has been discussed in this section. In this section Ramchand talks about the difference between the pure ‘Causes’ and actual ‘Actors’ which is that an actor is related to both initiation and process, whereas cause is a pure specifier of initiation. The psychological version of a pure cause is an ‘intentional initiator’; the psychological version of ‘actor’ is a volitional agent with continuous experiential involvement in the process. So for the different types of subject there are two distinct dimensions: i. The first involves the difference between pure initiators and undergoer– initiators, the latter of which are continually involved in the process and are represented as such. 9 ii. The second dimension is that of encyclopedic content either via the verb’s own lexical-encyclopedic information or through the perception of the referential properties of the DP participant. In the Stative predications section Ramchand mentions that stative verbs consist of an init projection, with rhematic material projected as the complement of init instead of a full processual procP. Since the init does not have procP as its complement in this case, it is not interpreted as causational, but simply as a state. The next chapter that follows, Ramchand argues that there will never be more than two arguments licensed in specifier position, in the description of the verb types in English. Chapter Four is entitled “Deriving verb classes” The purpose of this chapter is to explore the ways in which this system can be used to analyze different possible verb types. Here the emphasis is on the flexibilities and constraints on the system itself. The first-phase syntax relates in systematic ways to particular verb types, although the association between the two should more be seen a pattern rather than a one-to-one correspondence. The present chapter explores these patterns and analyses a wide range of English sentence types that have been adduced in the argument structure, construcionist and Aktionsart literature. Systematic correlation between aspect/Aktionsart and certain constellations in the syntactic structure are indicated, for example ''when a single lexical item identifies both process and result, the event expressed is punctual''. Ramchand has also discussed the debate in the literature concerning the direction of the causative–inchoative alternation. Recalling that Levin and Rappaport Hovav (1995), Chierchia (2004) and Reinhart (2002) all agree in deriving theinchoative alternant from a lexically causative base. In the Initiation–process verbs section Ramchand examines the argument structure of verbs which have an initiation component as well as a process 10 component. Firstly verbs should be distinguished in which the initiator and undergoer are distinct, from ones in which the initiator and undergoer are filled by the same DP constituent. Secondly, genuine undergoer arguments need to be distinguishing from those which are ‘rhematic’ paths within the process phrase. In the Initiation–process–result verbs section she states that there are a number of verbs in English including the transitives such asbreak, throw, find, explode, enter, and intransitives such as arrive, disappear that seem independently able to identifythe result state of a process. In the Transitivity alternations section she mentions that English has the causative–inchoative alternation where a major point of ontention has been the direction of lexical derivation for the alternation. According to Levin and Rappaport Hovav (1995), there is distinction between the two types of intransitive verb: (i) Those which embody internal causation. (ii) Those which involve external causation. (the externally caused verbs include break and open and other verbs that participate in the causative inchoative alternation in English) Rmchand also addresses the systematic difference between ‘unaccusative’ alternants of such verbs and productive processes like passive which also create non-initiator predications. She more explains concerning passive and said that, while the ‘agent’ is absent, it is somehow still semantically present and can control purpose clauses, and permit certain agentive adverbial phrases not possible with real unaccusative verbs. She gives the following examples to more clarify the point; - The ball was thrown to annoy Alex. - *The stick broke to annoy Alex. She believes that with passive, the transitive verb still retains and projects its [init] feature, although the passive morphology existentially binds off the actual initiator position. 11 In Conflation verbs section she claims that conflation is the type of verbs that is derived by abstract incorporation into the head of the verbal projection from complement position, subject to principles of syntactic movement. In the Double object verbs section the writer argues that there are verbs that can take two objects, but as Oehrle (1976) and Jackendoff (1990) which show the semantic predicational relations for the two structures are actually subtly different. To illustrate, the contrast described by Oehrle (1976) shows that there is an animacy requirement on the first object of a double object construction which does not carry over to the complement of to in the dative alternant. In order to more elaborate she gives the following examples; The editor sent the article to Philadelphia. ??The editor sent Philadelphia the article. In the Statives section she states that the stative verbs are the most important stative verbs usually refer to a state or condition which is not changing or likely to change. Statives differ from other classes of verbs in that they are static; that is, they have undefined duration and cannot normally be used in the continuous (BE + ING) forms. They can be divided into verbs of perception or cognition (which refer to things in the mind), or verbs of relation (which describe the relationships between things). In the Summary section Ramchand closes this chapter with the idea that the many different types of verbs and verb classes can be put together with a relatively impoverished set of primitives, and that the different possibilities for verbal event-structure meanings/behaviours can be predicted by syntactic form, and some general principles of lexical association. Chapter Five/ Paths and results 12 In this chapter, Ramchand takes up the issues of path construction and causative formation respectively in more detail, and attempt to make some more substantive proposals. In the PPs: paths and places section the writer states that there is an interaction between full prepositional phrases and resultative formation. So in this section path and result sentences are further illustrated and path phrases are decomposed in a path phrase heading a place phrase (following Ray Jackendoff's distinction between path and place prepositions). Ramchand demonstrates the cross-linguistic relevance of the proposed structure by introducing constructions from Korean (in which path phrases need not be introduced by a preposition), Swedish, Norwegian, Russian (demonstrating the interaction between aspect prefixes and argument structure in the language) and Indic languages. In the APs: paths and results section there is an explanation that in English AP results with selected objects are always formed from adjectives that are gradable and closed scale (Wechsler, 2001). So Ramchand argues that gradable adjectives represent the property analogue of a scalar path which is equivalent to Path Ps in the prepositional domain and incremental theme objects of consumption verbs. In the Types of resultatives in the first phase section Ramchand argues that verbs which contain both initiation and process can usually be systematically augmented in English by means of a secondary predicate (adjective or particle) which describes afinal-result property or location arrived at by a thematic argument. Chapter Six/ Causativization In its introductory part, Ramchand explains that causativization is one of the important factors underlying verb alternations in English, and one which is 13 built in to the interpretation of verbal decompositional structure in a fundamental way. In the An analytic causative in Hindi/Urdu part the she picks out one particular construction in Hindi/Urdu that has received some attention in the literature, the causative construction, and demonstrates that the first-phase syntax may account for the alternations found in the language. At the same time, the comparison between English and Hindi/Urdu will allow us to formulate some specific hypotheses about the nature of parametric variation in constructing verbal meaning. The larger picture will be, frstly, that there is explicit evidence for decomposition from morphological and analytical constructions, and secondly, languages vary only in the ‘size’ of their lexical items, not in the fundamental building blocks of meaning. In the Overview of Hindi/Urdu transitivity alternations part (Kachru 1980, Hook 1979, Masica 1991, Saksena 1982) state that Hindi/Urdu verbs that undergo morphological causativization fall into three classes; i. Older stage of causativization in the language consists in a strengthening process applied to the internal vowel of the root. ii. The addition of the -aa suffix to the root; and iii. The addition of the -vaa suffix to the root, representing direct and indirect causation respectively. In the Transitive–intransitive pairs via vowel alternation part Ramchand concerns with the class of alternations, since he believes that it is the primary source in the language for nonsuffixed transitive verbs. According to Panini and the ancient grammarians, causatives were formed by root ‘strengthening’, while Saksena (1982) and Bhatt (2003a) argue on the basis of predictability that the phonological alternation must go in the direction of ‘transitive → intransitive’ like, (aa →a, ii →i, uu →u,o →u,e →i). Saksena (1982) argues that there are cases of innovated intransitive forms in the history of Hindi/Urdu, back-formed from certain transitives, Thus, the vowel alternating roots will be considered 14 ‘causativization’ and is important in so far as both transitive and intransitive alternants which will be input to the suffixing causatives –aa and -vaa. In the Status of the causee part the writer states that under certain conditions, a -se-marked (instrumental) adjunct is licensed in Hindi/Urdu causatives. Causees, in Hindi/Urdu causatives, in the sense of instrumental (-se) case-marked nominals interpreted as an ‘intermediate agent’ are always optional; i.e. with -vaa causatives they are always possible while with –aa causatives they are possible only when the base is a transitive. In the Status of causer part she mentions that both the -aa and -vaa causative are also used, and in each case only the –aa causative is possible with the particular choice of subject. As in [ban-aa-naa/ban-vaa-naa ‘build’] The Analysis part includes the subsections as, Representing the verb classes in Hindi/Urdu, Direct vs. indirect causation, Direct causativization in –aa, ‘Indirect’ causativization in –vaa, In which the difference between direct and indirect causation for the two morphemes is captured by the difference in lexical specification for category features of the two different morphemes. Chapter Seven/ Conclusion This is the last chapter of the book in which Ramchand summarizes the study and further specifying the relation between tense, aspect and verbal decomposition, the book concludes with a number of open questions, among which the place of case in the system and stative verbs. On the terms 'constructivist', 'constructionalist' and 'constructionist', the influence of construction grammar (esp. Goldberg, 1995) can be felt throughout this study. In his book Ramchand attempts to implement an old idea in the light of current, accumulated knowledge concerning the nature of 'lexical' generalizations and patterns. This knowledge refers to the constructionist approach, but it is the old idea which makes Ramchand's book a valuable and innovative contribution to the constructionist debate, although the author 15 explicitly distances herself from constructionism: so the view proposed here will be generative-constructivist in spirit, but not constructionist. This reaction appears to be addressed to what Ramchand calls the 'radical constructionalist approach' to the lexicon in which no lexical information is present at all, but lexical items are inserted into syntactic contexts according to compatibility with encyclopedic and real-world knowledge. One may question if this is an accurate depiction of Radical Construction Grammar approaches in the sense of Croft (2001) in which the notion of insertion is irrelevant since there is simply no fundamental distinction between conventionalized meaning on the level of lexemes or on the level of phrases, which reduces the difference of opinion to a rather more fundamental theoretical position on the nature of the required operations in the grammar. But the main distinction between her model and construction grammar models Ramchand aims to stress is that unlike the constructional grammar of Goldberg (1995) event-compositional semantics will not be associated with arbitrarily large syntactic objects, but constructed systematically on the basis of primitive recursive syntactic relationships. It seems that Ramchand defines 'constructivist' as a systematic way of deriving meaning from structure, whereas by 'constructional' she refers to surface structures which receive their meaning from syntax internal operations, which, she argues, are overlooked in current construction grammar approaches. However, in another place the author does use the term 'constructional' to refer to her own model, because she believes that this is a constructional system, the wide variety of different verb types and role types will be derived from the different combinatoric possibilities of the syntax. Here, the term according to her refers to the entire syntactic structure from which meaning is derived. These remarks are not as contradictory as Ramchand leads us to believe in her first chapter, in fact, the notions are quite well-matched while the model outlined in 16 the present chapter is a specific account of constructional meaning and as such forms part of a larger constructionist debate. Conclusion The book is written in a goog style, although it is somehow complex , but it is designed in a systematic way helping readers make sense of what is written.The smooth movement from a chapter to another is a good technique used by the author to make the link stronger among the chapters. It is a good source for gaining some knowledge about other levels of linguistics such as syntax and semantics. For me, it is a great experience, being acquainted with such subject. The book constitutes a contribution to the Minimalist Program to others, but the ways in which in the proposed first-phase syntax multiple roles may be combined in a Merge operation to form complex semantic collection certainly seems an interesting alternative to monistic Principles & Parameters proposals and fully in the spirit of simplicity as I understand it. But above all, Ramchand's study opens a dialogue between constructionist approaches to grammar and formal grammar models. If simplicity is to be interpreted as a step towards union in linguistic theory, just as constructionist approaches to language structure might be seen, having come to permeate formal and cognitive-functionalist grammars alike, the volume is of potential interest to a wide range of readers. It may serve as an excellent starting point for opening up a discussion between currents in theoretical linguistics about a topic every linguistic theory has to address. 17 In this work of Ramchand, one can find a fascinating study in which the author builds up her argument carefully, unveiling her proposal layer by layer while raising profound and interesting questions in the process. The model she presents is descriptively elegant and Ramchand applies it to a collection of phenomena and structures, many of which have not been previously treated in an integrated account. However there is a clear prediction that can be made and tested on the basis of the proposed structure. The author argues for the model based on English and then applies it to a number of selected examples from other (mainly IndoEuropean) languages. On the other hand, the volume does shed new light on the non-English examples as well. For example, the proposed link between argument structure and Russian aspect prefixes is an interesting and innovative proposal in the study of aspect, although I would be curious to see how min some languages would have to be treated under this view. Finally, an understanding of the morpho-syntax and of the semantic primitives involved in the buildup of linguistic forms goes hand in hand. This crucially involves separating out the semantic elements that are structural from those that are purely conceptual or lexical encyclopedic. 18