In 2003 the results of a national survey on biotechnology showed that “American opinion of the acceptability of GM foods is split. Half of the public approves of plantbased GM foods, while only about a quarter approves of animal-based GM foods. Approval of GM food has declined somewhat in the past two years and more people are uncertain what they think of these products.” (Food policy institute, 2003) These results show evidence towards the trend of declining consumer acceptance of genetically modified products in the United States, a country that has conventionally led the way with support for transgenic food. This trend exemplifies the problem with the FDA’s precarious position: if it loses its legitimacy as a regulatory body, what will happen to the public acceptance of its decisions? This is how the normative need for legitimacy is tied to the instrumental outcome of acceptance. The issue of public acceptance is especially salient for the AquAdvantage salmon as it is the first animal product up for human consumption. “Public reaction is an important social dimension in these [technical] conflicts, with citizen opinion shaping the trajectory of scientific development and technological adoption” (Brossard, 2004). As I have shown the FDA is failing to regulate the salmon in a way that promotes public acceptance, the question becomes, how to improve this process? Public Trust A way to improve acceptance through legitimacy would be to raise public trust in the regulatory process. The link between trust and acceptance is something that has been picked up by regulators, as the UK government has concluded that ‘in order to handle 1 risks to the public effectively government needs to win and retain public trust’ (Cabinet Office, Strategy Unit 2002, 76). Losteft’s defines trust as “An expression of confidence between parties in an exchange transaction” (153). Losteft continues to argue that public trust is based on competency, fairness, and efficiency (156). Trust results in the acceptance of decisions without questioning the rational behind it. Public trust is especially important in regulatory bodies as these bodies are seen as watchdogs that are supposed to protect the population from the disruptive and destructive consequences of science. To conclude, acceptance is contingent on trust, so to get acceptance, it is necessary that there is trust in the regulatory process. Trust in scientific regulation stems directly from the perceived objectivity of science. Nevertheless, using the competency, fairness and efficiency formula for trust, it is clear that the failings of the FDA add up to a scenario where public trust is low. First, competency is lacking if not all concerns are addressed. However, if the FDA itself made a judgment based on wider concerns it would lose its basis of “objective science”, which would make the decision lack fairness. Finally, the efficiency of the FDA concerning this decision itself been criticized, but its inability to respond to the public has caused the decision to halt. This leads back to the main puzzle of the salmon: if the science is political, how to fix issues of trust to ultimately get acceptance in decisions? The solution is to find a way to institutionalize science politics. In this section I plan to lay out the normative reasoning for participation, its practical failings in the realm of science and technology policy, and how deliberative models could potentially fix these failings. I 2 hope to demonstrate that a deliberative, participatory body would result in higher acceptance in the final decision than the current regulatory path. One way to institutionalize science politics would be to have experts regulate social and ethical issues that are beyond the FDA’s mandate, to improve the perceived competency of the decision. This idea is that academic ethicists can make decisions on controversial issues free of conflicts of interests. Bioethics, the study of controversial ethics brought out by advances in biology and medicine, is a field that has institutionalized the examination of ethical issues in science and technology police. The ethical framing in the United States has pushed official bioethics towards utilitarian considerations based on balancing risks and benefits, which coincides with market orientated framing of regulatory issues around biotechnology (Jasanoff, 175). Conversely, a problem with ethics board is that “Where morality is used as a judgment or as a way of framing the central issues concerning a subject, this has the capacity to limit the way that it becomes politicized … A further level of criticism might be about the danger of bioethicists becoming shapers of moral discourses” (Miah, 412). In the case of the salmon, while ethicists could address some of these issues, they would also serve to further isolate the public from the discourse surrounding the salmon. This isolation creates gaps in knowledge, furthering the “mutually tolerable ignorance” between expert and citizen. While expert ethicists would help to more of the issues surrounding the salmon, they do not completely solve the problems of legitimacy that face the FDA. While it deals with the competency aspect of trust, it does not help with fairness, which is engaging 3 those who will be effected by the decision. Furthermore, I have criticized the FDA for its current inability to deal with issues raised by the public. Therefore another way of increasing public trust would be to increase public engagement. The Value of Participation Increased participation goes hand in hand with transparency and clarity, which contributes to increased trust and public acceptance of a final decision. There are strong normative and instrumental arguments for using a model that includes public participation in the creation of policy that will regulate genetically modified salmon. The basic normative argument is that in a democratic society, citizens should have the right to have their concerns addressed, which is not currently being done by the FDA. The basic instrumental arguments are decisions that include a mode for participation are more likely to be accepted by the public then does that don’t. Increased public participation in the salmon decision would serve to bring legitimacy back into the decision making progress which would have the consequence of making the final decision more acceptable to the public. This a version of Rollins especially strong stance that “It is both morally and pragmatically essential that the public be a pivotal part of the decision process, for they incur the risks, and they will be asked to accept the results of biotechnology innovation”(95). Public participation by those affected by the decision, that is the public, would increase fairness in the decision, leading to more trust. Traditional democratic values include values of individual autonomy, self development, and the right of those affected by decisions ability to participate effectively. However, these values are becoming increasingly hard to maintain in technological 4 complex societies. The decision to approve the salmon raises fundamental questions about social values, nature, and economic justice In a democratic society there is normative value to addressing the concerns of citizens, it can be concluded that there should be more participation in this regulatory process (Moore, 2010). The instrumental value of increased participation is that citizens are far more likely to accept a decision if their views have been accorded respect and consideration, even if they don’t agree with the decision (Marchant and Scallion, Rollin, Irwin, Hartley). Rollin and Marchant go on to argue that if concerns are not properly addressed at an early stage in regulation, they will grow and burst forth at a later date with potentially devastating consequences. Rollin argues that people see unknown dangers that could harm humans and the environment in biotechnology. They therefore wish to be involved in the decision making process with regards to something new and frightening that they do not understand. When science and governments fail to address these issues, people feel suspicious and suspect they are not being told the truth, and begin to openly distrust the government sciences axis creating distrust in the technology itself (42-46). Equally important, they are far more open to misinformation from selfproclaimed “experts” who paint a negative picture of biotechnology. Hagendijk extends this argument to say that greater participation leads to greater trust in experts, given empirical evidence of consensus conferences. The Politics of Public Knowledge It is impossible to address the issue of incorporating more public input into the salmon decision without considering the politics of public knowledge. There have been 5 many institutional experiments conducted to try to gather data on public understanding of biotechnology, as problems of knowledge are known precursor to gaining social acceptance of GMO policy (Jasanoff 260). “Public Understanding of Science” is a term that first became popular in early 1980’s in the United Kingdom when there was growing concern by parts of the scientific community about the divide that existed between scientists and the rest of society (Durant, 1998). The definition of a public understanding of science is ambiguous, as all three terms can be defined in many ways. However, the term was first used with the normative reasoning that the public should know more about science, for the benefit of both science and the public. This reasoning was based on the idea that there is deficit in public scientific knowledge, and that knowledge dissemination is key in solving this deficit (Durant, 1998). What is implicit in this idea is that public understanding of science is based on knowledge or ignorance of facts. One concept for measuring how well the public understands science is scientific literacy. Scientific literacy can be defined as “the level of understanding of science and technology needed to function as citizens in a modern industrial society”(Miller & Pardo). In the US, levels of scientific literacy are measured by tests and questionnaires, and seem to conclude that the general public is largely ignorant of science and technology (Hagendijk, 2004). These results have created what is known as the “deficit model”, which is that “the public is assumed to be “deficient” while science is “sufficient””( Sturgus & Allum, 2003). This is the basis of an objection to increasing public participation in science policy: the public is scientifically illiterate, gullible and naïve, and unable to understand scientifically based arguments against the reality of certain risks. Given this view of the public, involving them in technical decisions, while it would increase fairness, would 6 decrease competency and efficiency of the decision. “The public’s doubts about the value of scientific progress or fears about new or unfamiliar innovations, such as genetically modified organisms […] are due to ignorance of the science behind them. Lacking a proper understanding of the relevant facts, people fall back on mystical beliefs and irrational fears of the unknown” (Sturgis & Allum, 2003). This is the reason why we have experts in the first place – not only is a lay persons knowledge is not adequate to make these highly technical decisions, they will rely on fear to make judgments of things they don’t know. Another theory put forth for understanding public opinion is the low informed public model, which also supports public ignorance. This is the model that individuals aim to simply satisfice on an issue, that is to only understand the bare minimum of information on a topic. If a population has low information, they are likely to rely on their preexisting value judgments (Brossard). “Recent research examining public views of science and technology debates has highlighted the strong heuristic role played by value predispositions and media content in shaping general views about science”(Brossard). A problem with PUS research is that it often concludes by creating a public that is so ignorant and illiterate that they are not capable of performing basic democratic duties. This is not useful. If one believes in democracy, then it follows that one believes in the educability of the public and its insight. After all, the public judges matters of extreme importance in voting and in the jury system. While I do not believe that the conclusion of an examination of public knowledge should be that the public is not able to participate 7 meaningfully, public knowledge and understanding of science do pose a problem for policy concerning genetically engineered products. However, public knowledge does not pose a problem solely for a regulatory model that relies on participation, but for expert models of decision making as well. If the public is falling back on “irrational fears of the unknown”, then it is unlikely that they will accept a decision that approves and does not label a genetically modified animal. In the case of the salmon, an understanding of public knowledge is important to evaluate public trust. As previously explained, trust in an institution results in accepting decisions even if the rational behind it is not understood. Therefore, if participation built trust, it would not matter that much of the public did not understand the rational, or the science, of a decision. Nonetheless, as problems of knowledge are known precursor to gaining social acceptance of GMO policy, they should be examined. (does not make sense) In technology intensive societies, the construction of government credibility necessarily encompasses the public production of scientific knowledge. The institutional background of the United States has constrained the framework in which public knowledge relevant to biotechnology is produced and validated. The FDA, the main regulatory body for GM products, depends on manufacturers to supply information regarding the risks of its products. Therefore the burden of being a primary source of information falls to interested parties, such as the biotechnology industry, academic researchers and environmental groups. As these different groups often present 8 information in a starkly different way, the result in a knowledge landscape that is highly fractured and hard to negotiate. By examining the different ways that basic facts about the salmon are portrayed from different sources (appendix A), the difficulties of forming an unbiased opinion become obvious. * For over a decade, headlines have questioned the safety of biotechnology related food products. Frankenfood, Farmaeddon Biotechnology has also been the launch pad for many popular entertainment depictions of science (Jurassic Park). The use of the word frankenfish Google trend of GM food vs Frankenfood shows the rise of GM food Herring argues that science is inherently vulnerable to framing from different sources because the nature of science itself does not fit with politics. Science is inherently falsifiable, as epistemological commitments preclude ever having a completely definitive argument (Herring, 2011). Therefore the science of the genetic modified salmon is in a difficult position – fish are 99% sterile – can still be disproved. Leaves room for contention. - Politics makes impossible knowledge demands: to disprove negatives . uncertainty/caution makes uncertainty and caution natural and rational - Some science are especially vulnerable: cognitively distant + information costs + uncertainty (genetic energy is very cognitively distant) - This leads to great power in epistemic brokers – place in democracy gives citizens responsibility to inform themselves, but we are still at the mercy of epistemic brokers : those who give knowledge to the public. Problems of knowledge: not very well informed public, fracture information, science that is open to contention. What is the best way to fix this and build trust? 9 10