Kant Society in Ukraine Department of Philosophy and Religious Studies, Faculty of Humanities, NaUKMA The Antonovychi Library, NaUKMA philosophical discussion War and Peace. Kantian co-Meditations. Peter McCormic (Paris, France) Mykhailo Minakov (Kyiv, Ukraine) Auditorium at NaUKMA Museum 14:00, 23 April 2015 Mykhailo Minakov Peace and Applied Enlightenment Theses for a Dispute with Prof. McCormick at Kyiv-Mohyla Academy April 23, 2015 1. Peace is unnatural for humans, however peace as lasting peace between nations is possible. Kantian paradox: Why peace should be established? Why to ruin the “noble case” of war? Peace is absence of war between humans. War is a natural state, a bottom-line of human history. o Peace makes life to be a practiced value. War refers to dignified life but destroys it. Peace makes dignity to serve to the case of life. o Dignity is a civil virtue. War destroys civil condition. War and dignity cannot be combined. o Kantian thesis: peace is a pre-requisite and a result of global civil situation. o Civility – and those political institutions that we can create – is the key answer. Politics as ‘communication for the common good’ (Aristotle, Politics I) provides humans with a possibility to cease the permanent war and establish permanent peace. Possible solutions: o Monarchy (Augustine, Dante) or Leviathan (Hobbes): end of civil war by the price 2. Peace can be established as a result of human conduct with the use of moral reasoning and political engineering. How can peace be established? Are there dangers of ‘idealization of peace’ just like with the ‘idealization of war’? 3. It is time to review results of the Enlightenment in the Eastern Europe, and make the region to be peaceful. Positive sublime of Peace: In the beginning of the Treatise, Kant defines a paradox: o He repeats the joke of Leibnitz (Codex diplomaticus, 1693) that stipulates doubt if the eternal peace is possible: “We can leave open the question whether this satirical caption to the picture of a graveyard, which was painted on the sign of a Dutch innkeeper, applies to human beings in general, or specifically to the heads of state, who can never get enough of war, or even just to philosophers who dream the sweet dream of perpetual peace.” (IK, 2004, p. 67) o The pathos of the Treatise is on the contrary – practicality of the peace project. Entire structure and argumentation of the Treatise is directed at ‘the practical politicians’. The Treatise concludes that peace can be established. And in the Idea of Universal History Kant sais it is being established in the human history. o This paradox constitutes the positive sublime that as a notion describes the idea of perpetual peace in terms of its super-sensual aesthetic proof, its practical (moral and political) significance, and historical possibility The paradox is based on what I call – following Peter McCormic's expression ‘negative sublime of war’ – positive sublime of peace o By using term ‘positive sublime’ I risk to be correct in using Kantian dictionary: since in the Critique of Judgment, Kant associates sublime mainly with negativity (to contrast positive taste of beauty) For example: “As a matter of fact, a feeling for the sublime in nature is hardly thinkable unless in association with a disposition of mind resembling the moral… And though, like that feeling, the immediate pleasure in the beautiful in nature presupposes and cultivates a certain liberality of thought, i.e. makes our delight independent of any mere enjoyment of sense, still it represents freedom rather as in play than as exercising a law-governed activity, which is the genuine characteristic of human morality, where reason has to impose its dominion upon sensibility. There is, however, this qualification, that in the aesthetic judgement upon the sublime this dominion is represented as exercised through the imagination itself as an instrument of reason. Thus, too, delight in the sublime in nature is only negative (whereas that in the beautiful is positive): that is to say it is a feeling of imagination by its own act depriving itself of its freedom by receiving a purposive determination in accordance with a law other than that of its empirical employment.” (CoJ 99) o Nonetheless, I argue that positive sublime is possible in Kantian terms; and that notion of positive sublime helps understand the possibility and practicality of peace The sublimity of peace corresponds with Kant’s idea of sublime as mind super-ceding the senses of natural affects: “Sublimity, therefore, does not reside in any of the things of nature, but only in our own mind, in so far as we may become conscious of our superiority over nature within, and thus also over nature without us (as exerting influence upon us).” (CoJ 94) The positive sublime of peace is directly connected with sublimity of enthusiasm: “The idea of the good connected with affect is enthusiasm. This state of mind appears to be sublime: so much so that there is a common saying that nothing great can be achieved without it. But now every affect is blind either as to the choice of its end, or, supposing this has been furnished by reason, in the way it is effected—for it is that movement of the mind whereby the exercise of free deliberation upon fundamental principles, with a view to determining oneself accordingly, is rendered impossible. On this account it cannot merit any delight on the part of reason. Yet, from an aesthetic point of view, enthusiasm is sublime, because it is an effort of one’s powers called forth by ideas which give to the mind an impetus of far stronger and more enduring efficacy than the stimulus afforded by sensible representations.” (CoJ 102) Later, Kant connects enthusiastic sublime with peace: “So, for example, a certain poet says* in his description of a beautiful morning: ‘The sun arose, as out of virtue rises peace.’ The consciousness of virtue, even where we put ourselves only in thought in the position of a virtuous man, diffuses in the mind a multitude of sublime and comforting feelings, and gives a boundless outlook into a happy future, such as no expression within the compass of a definite concept completely attains.” (CoJ 145) This enthusiasm is based upon immensity of history’s un-graspable wisdom: even the worst of human feelings can serve to the best of it. One of the greatest Kant’s ideas here is the ‘unsociable sociability’ (ungesellige Geselligkeit) Positive sublime of peace corresponds with Kant’s idea of human progress towards peace as ‘guiding end in history’ This historical vision is parallel to the metaphor of starry skies: “So, if we call the sight of the starry heaven sublime, we must not found our judgement of it upon any concepts of worlds inhabited by rational beings, with the bright spots, which we see filling the space above us, as their suns moving in orbits prescribed for them with the wisest regard to ends. But we must take it, just as it strikes the eye, as a broad and all-embracing canopy: and it is merely under such a representation that we may posit the sublimity which the pure aesthetic judgement attributes to this object.” (CoJ 101) o In the Treatise, the paradox of positive sublime is defined as the following: “To be sure, it does this with a certainty that is not sufficient to foretell the future of this peace (theoretically), but which is adequate from a practical perspective and makes it a duty to work toward this (not simply chimerical) goal.” (Treatise, 92) o Consequently, positive sublime of peace responds to the noble case of life, splendid idea of future, and terrifying doubt if it is reachable in history. Positive sublime of peace makes the hope for peace even in the worst times of war terror reasonable and aesthetically-proven. The enthusiasm that arises from the hope to peace o But it not the peace as absence of war that has the chance for moral ground and durable time-span: “War itself, provided it is conducted with order and a sacred respect for the rights of civilians, has something sublime about it, and gives nations that carry it on in such a manner a stamp of mind only the more sublime the more numerous the dangers to which they are exposed, and which they are able to meet with fortitude. On the other hand, a prolonged peace favours the predominance of a mere commercial spirit, and with it a debasing self-interest, cowardice, and weakness, and tends to degrade the character of the people. So far as sublimity is predicated of might, this solution of the concept of it appears at variance with the fact that we tend to represent God in the tempest, the storm, the earthquake, and the like, as presenting himself in his wrath, but at the same time also in his sublimity, and yet here it would be alike folly and presumption to imagine a preeminence of our minds over the operations and, as it appears, even over the direction of such might. Here, instead of a feeling of the sublimity of our own nature, submission, prostration, and a feeling of utter helplessness seem more to constitute the attitude of mind befitting the manifestation of such an object, and to be that also more customarily associated with the idea of it on the occasion of a natural phenomenon of this kind.” (CoJ, 93) o The peace has positive sublime, practical significance and historical meaning only if it has been established by applying reason. “1. ‘‘No peace settlement which secretly reserves issues for a future war shall be considered valid.’’ For such a treaty would represent a mere cease-fire, a postponement of hostilities, and not peace. For peace signifies the end to all hostilities, and even merely adding the adjective perpetual to the term renders it a suspicious-looking pleonasm… But if, on the basis of ‘‘enlightened’’ concepts of political prudence, the true honor of the state is thought to lie in the continual expansion of its power by any means whatsoever, then such a judgment will surely seem academic and pedantic.” (Treatise, 68) War is natural to humans, while peace is a product of culture: “The state of nature (status naturalis) is not a state of peace among human beings who live next to one another but a state of war, that is, if not always an outbreak of hostilities, then at least the constant threat of such hostilities. Hence the state of peace must be established.” (Treatise, 72) It is up to political creativity of human to construct such a social – economic and political – order where moral and lasting peace was possible. In the Treatise stipulates three pre-conditions of world-wide eternal peace: citizen at individual level; constitutional republic at collective level; federation of nations at global level. Citizen as a citizen of universal moral state: “The validity of these innate rights, which necessarily belong to humankind and are inalienable, is confirmed and elevated by the principle of the juridical relations that a human being can have to higher beings (when he conceives of such beings), by imagining himself, in accordance with precisely the same principles, as a citizen of a supersensible world. For, as concerns my freedom, I have no obligation even with regard to the divine laws, which are known to me by means of mere reason, other than the laws I have myself been able to agree to (for I conceive of the divine will only by means of the law of freedom of my own reason in the first place). ” o (Treatise, 74) Constitutional republic: o “a supersensible world” for citizens o “The republican constitution is a constitution that is established, first, according to principles of the freedom of the members of a society (as human beings), second, according to principles of the dependence of all on a single, common legislation (as subjects), and third, according to the law of the equality of the latter (as citizens of the state).” (Treatise, 74) o republic should be constructed in way that even devils would abbey to its rules; (Treatise, 90) Federation: o “No state shall forcibly interfere in the constitution and government of another state” (Treatise, 70) o “Peoples, as states, can be judged as individual human beings who, when in the state of nature (that is, when they are independent from external laws), bring harm to each other already through their proximity to one another, and each of whom, for the sake of his own security, can and ought to demand of others that they enter with him into a constitution, similar to that of a civil one, under which each is guaranteed his rights. This would constitute a federation of peoples, which would not, however, necessarily be a state of peoples.” (Treatise, 78) o “…the idea of federalism, which should gradually encompass all states and thereby lead to perpetual peace, is practicable …”(Treatise, 80) Once again: “To be sure, it does this with a certainty that is not sufficient to foretell the future of this peace (theoretically), but which is adequate from a practical perspective and makes it a duty to work toward this (not simply chimerical) goal.” (Treatise, 92) It is human duty to build political and economic pre-conditions of peace. It is human reasonable practice that makes peace possible. Fatalism, decadence and laziness ruin preconditions for establishing peace. o It the lesson of Enlightenment that we in Eastern Europe did not learn timely. We perceived that other agents of security can establish and support peace for us. We were wrong. o It is the task of living generations in the nations of Eastern Europe to start the era of the second Enlightenment: return to citizen education, creation of constitutional republics with the rule of law, and establish rights-based mechanisms for the peaceful development of our region. We should return to active creativity in public sphere at national and international levels. “The mechanical course of nature visibly reveals a purposive plan to create harmony through discord among people, even against their own will.” (Treatise, 85) “To be sure, it does this with a certainty that is not sufficient to foretell the future of this peace (theoretically), but which is adequate from a practical perspective and makes it a duty to work toward this (not simply chimerical) goal.” (Treatise, 92) unsociable sociability reaches a limit at the point where human conflict disrupts the stable life of civilization that is needed for the preservation and further development of human faculties. If life and property become insecure, then people have no opportunity to perfect themselves and no incentive to accumulate products of labor, which may be taken from them before they can be enjoyed. At a certain point, therefore, nature’s end of endlessly developing the predispositions of the human species requires a stable and ordered society, a condition of peace with justice. When civilization reaches this point, natural purposiveness requires another device alongside unsociable sociability to balance its counterpurposive effects. This device, which Kant introduces in the Fifth and Sixth Propositions of ‘‘Idea for a Universal History,’’ is the establishment of ‘‘a civil society which administers right universally’’ (IUH 8:22). This civil society, characterized by a coercive power protecting rights and property, is the political state. It is a voluntary creation of human beings themselves and is subject to ideal rational principles (of right or justice) that people are capable of recognizing and obeying; but in promoting the full development of our species predispositions, the establishment of a political state also accords with natural teleology. Allen Wood 252-253 that nature is seen to employ unsociable sociability as the device for unfolding the predispositions of the human species, and the fact that beyond a certain point this device can continue to operate toward nature’s end only if it is counterbalanced by a humanly created order of peace with justice within the political state and between states Wood 254 The natural end of endlessly developing humanity’s species-predispositions leads, for instance, to the specification of unsociable sociability (the human traits of discontent and competitiveness) as the basic mechanism for this development; the historical need, at a certain stage of history, for nations to remain at peace in order to perfect their civil constitutions and continue the development of new human capacities, leads us to recognize the importance of commerce and economic prosperity in making nations powerful, and the reluctance of commercially oriented citizens to turn their lives and property over to warlike heads of state to pursue their greedy and barbaric fantasies of military conquest Wood 259 Idea for a Universal History fourth proposition The means that nature employs in order to bring about the development of all of the predispositions of humans is their antagonism in society, insofar as this antagonism ultimately becomes the cause of a law-governed organization of society. Here I take antagonism to mean the unsociable sociability of human beings, that is, their tendency to enter into society, a tendency connected, however, with a constant resistance that continually threatens to break up this society. This unsociable sociability is obviously part of human nature. Human beings have an inclination to associate with one another because in such a condition they feel themselves to be more human, that is to say, more in a position to develop their natural predispositions. But they 8:21 also have a strong tendency to isolate themselves, because they encounter in themselves the unsociable trait that predisposes them to want to direct everything only to their own ends and hence to expect to encounter resistance everywhere, just as they know that they themselves tend to resist others. It is this resistance that awakens all human powers and causes human beings to overcome their tendency to idleness and, driven by lust for honor, power, or property, to establish a position for themselves among their fellows, whom they can neither endure nor do without. Here the first true steps are taken from brutishness to culture, which consists, actually, in the social worth of human beings. IUH 6-7 Literature: CoJ stands for: Immanuel Kant, Critique of Judgement (tr. by. J. C. Meredith; rev. & ed. by N. Walker; NY, Oxford University Press, 2007). IUH stands for: Immanuel Kant, Idea of Universal History, in: Toward perpetual peace and other writings on politics, peace, and history / Immanuel Kant ; ed. by P. Kleingeld; tr. by D. L. Colclasure/ (New Haven, Yale University Press, 2006) 3-16. Treatise stands for: Immanuel Kant, Toward Perpetual Peace: A Philosophical Sketch, in: Toward perpetual peace and other writings on politics, peace, and history / Immanuel Kant ; ed. by P. Kleingeld; tr. by D. L. Colclasure/ (New Haven, Yale University Press, 2006) 67-109.