“Fire and the Cogito: Dreams and Imaginings” Virginia Tech Conference Submission “Fire and the Cogito: Dreams and Imaginings” Virginia Tech Philosophy Graduate Conference Submission 2997 Words Abstract: Historically, philosophers have assumed that dreams deceive – that my belief that p is epistemically threatened by the possibility that it is cased by a dream that p. I argue that dreams do not typically cause us to have false beliefs – rather, dreams should be understood as imaginings. Dreams are experienced the same way that fictions are. I offer three arguments for this conclusion, and I draw on contemporary work in the philosophy of imagination to explain how imagination can accommodate the phenomenology of dreaming. One philosophical upshot is that Descartes’s ‘dream scenario’, as originally conceived, does not threaten knowledge. But another is that a modification of it threatens knowledge in a deeper way that Descartes realized – it even threatens our certainty in the cogito. “Fire and the Cogito: Dreams and Imaginings” Virginia Tech Conference Submission Descartes assumes in the Meditations that dreaming is like hallucinating – that when we dream, we have sensations and form beliefs. This is why he thinks that dreams can deceive us.1 I reject this orthodox model of dreaming in favor of an imagination model, according to which dreams are less like hallucinations and more like fictions.2 I will argue that when I dream that there is a fire before me, I do not thereby believe that there is a fire before me, or experience redness or heat – rather, I imagine that there is a fire before me, and experience the imagination-counterparts of those sensations. A consequence of the imagination model is that Descartes is wrong about the way in which the dream scenario leads to skepticism – my imaginings are not false beliefs. Nevertheless, the imagination model will not assist in a Cartesian project to overcome skepticism – rather, I suggest that a proper understanding of dreams will demonstrate a deeper threat of error against not only Descartes’s meditator’s knowledge of the fire, but even his cogito argument for his certainty of his own existence. My claim is that we do not experience sensations and form beliefs in our sleep when we dream. But clearly, we do something like these activities3. I believe that we perform and experience the imagination-correlates of these events, much as we do when we sit down and deliberately engage in a vivid daydream. (Throughout, I will follow 1Descartes, Meditation I, p. 105 2The suggestion of an application of an imagination model of dreams to Descartes’s project is from Ernest Sosa. Kendall Walton (1990) also mentions the possibility, but does not consider it in any depth: “Perhaps (as Descartes assumes) dreamers believe what is only fictional in their dreams, as well as imagining it. We needn’t decide.” (Walton p. 50) 3This is not entirely uncontroversial. For instance, it has been denied, I think rather implausibly, by Norman Malcolm. “Fire and the Cogito: Dreams and Imaginings” Virginia Tech Conference Submission Gregory Currie4 and use the superscript I to denote the imaginary version of a mental state. I will also use R to denote the non-imaginary version.) Is this plausible? After all, dreams (sometimes) seem to really feel like waking life. There’s clearly some explaining to be done if the imagination model is to be taken seriously. This is my project. I dream it, therefore it is true. In general, dreamed things do not entail their actual counterparts. The following is utterly implausible: I dream that p. Therefore, p. At issue is whether the inference is valid for beliefs and sensory experiences. What if we limit the inference to conscious mental states? Consider volitions. Ernest Sosa has suggested an ethics-based reductio against that inference: If I dream that I form an intention to succumb to temptation, I haven’t done anything wrong. If I formed that intention, I would have done something wrong. Therefore, the inference, ‘I dreamed I formed intention X, therefore I formed intention X,’ is invalid. Is believing like dreaming in this respect? It would be at least a little odd to insist on there being an important difference. I do not see any way to posit a difference between intending and believing that would justify treating them differently with respect to this inference. Once we accept that dreaming believing and intending does not entail really doing so, a similar argument demonstrates false the inference for sensory experiences – that dreaming having conscious experience e implies actually having it: Let e be the experience as if a lion were chasing me. Then if I have e in a dream, I would be epistemically required to form the 4Currie (1997), p. 67 “Fire and the Cogito: Dreams and Imaginings” Virginia Tech Conference Submission belief that a lion is chasing me, and prudentially required to form the intention to run away. Failure to form that belief and intention would constitute irrationality. But I am not irrational in failing to form the belief and intention, therefore the inference is invalid.5 Long-Standing Beliefs. Another line of reasoning that favors the imagination model of dreaming has to do with long-standing beliefs. I currently have the beliefR that I cannot fly. Suppose I have a dream in which I can fly. If the orthodox view is correct, I will form the real beliefR that I can fly. What happens to my old beliefR, that I cannot fly? If I still have it while asleep, I now seem to have contradictory beliefs. Intuitively, this is not correct – it is no more irrational for me to dream that I am flying then it is for me to deliberately imagine it. It is therefore incumbent upon the orthodox theorist to posit a mechanism whereby my long-standing beliefs disappear and reappear in response to dreams. This seems difficult. One might attempt to ‘explain away’ my intuition that it is not irrational for me to dream that I can fly by characterizing it as an intuition that I am not epistemically blameworthy for dream-based contradictory beliefs. We do not blame people for irrationality issuing from involuntary circumstances – when, for instance, I am forcibly drugged and hallucinate. It may be, the objection goes, that when we dream things that contradict our beliefs, we are blamelessly irrational. But dreaming is not like being forcibly drugged with respect to rationality and epistemic blameworthiness. As a rational agent, I should take measures to ensure that I do not find myself in circumstances in which I am likely to be irrational. I fail 5 Technically, the prescription of practical irrationality will depend on certain desires in addition to beliefs. But unless one wishes to claim that when I dream, I lose my desire not to be eaten by a lion, this complication is peripheral to my point. “Fire and the Cogito: Dreams and Imaginings” Virginia Tech Conference Submission epistemically and am also blameworthy if I voluntarily ingest hallucinogenic drugs, knowing that they will lead to irrationality. But since my interest in being a rational agent does not require me to take steps to avoid dreaming, the objection fails. Confusion in introspection. We do not always remain aware of the fact that we are dreaming, as we remain aware of conscious imaginings. The imagination model seems committed to the counter-intuitive view that we can mistake our imaginings for other mental states. However, there is independent reason to think that we can and sometimes do confuse beliefs, sensations, desires, etc., for their imagination counterparts. I will briefly mention three such cases in order to demonstrate reasonable the suggestion that imagination could be confused with reality. 1. Desires in Fiction. I watch an episode of Buffy: the Vampire Slayer and think, I hopeR Buffy doesn’t die. I may be conscious of that thought, and come to believe that it is true. I could sincerely utter: “I hopeR Buffy doesn’t die.” But I know that Buffy is going to die – I’ve seen this episode before. I do not hopeR that Buffy doesn’t die – instead, I hopeI that she won’t die6. If my alleged desire were realized, and Buffy did not die, I would be confused and upset. And Buffy the television show would be inferior if Buffy lived, and I don’t desireR that state of affairs. So I have confused my desireI for a desireR. 2. Imagery and Sensation. I close my eyes and imagine seeing a tree. I do not have the visual sensationsR associated with seeing a tree, but I have the associated sensationsI. Empirical research has demonstrated that subjects sometimes mistake one 6This point is made by Currie and Ravenscroft (§1.4), Walton (ch. 7), and Currie (1990) (§5.3). But the emphasis in these works is on the nature of the propositional attitude, not our error about it. “Fire and the Cogito: Dreams and Imaginings” Virginia Tech Conference Submission for the other. In one early experiment7, subjects were asked to visualize an object on a screen. Unbeknowst to them, there were actual faint images being projected to the spot where their eyes were focused. A description by Roger Brown and Richard Herrnstein: They were, in short, seeing a picture and calling it an image. ... In every case the answer left no doubt that the experiment succeeded in passing off stimuli as images without the subject’s awareness.8 The Cornell study demonstrates that sensationsR can be taken for sensationsI. There is also evidence suggesting that the reverse is true. In one case study9, a blind woman denied that she was completely blind. The researchers concluded that she had retained visual imagery (visual sensationI), and took herself to be experiencing visual sensationR. She mistook her imaginings for genuine perception. 3.1 Memory of Dreamt Color. The room for error is even more pronounced when we have to rely on memory of past visual experiences. A consideration of dreamt color sensation10 will suggest widespread error about sensation in dreams. I believe we should conclude that our memories are extremely unreliable about the phenomenology of dreaming, and that it is inappropriate to reject the imagination model based solely on reports of the phenomenology of dreaming. Almost all Americans report dreaming in color. In the 1940s and ‘50s, most people believed that visual experience in dreams was a primarily black-and-white phenomenon. This is a difficult discrepancy for the orthodox theorist to accommodate. Assuming that 7Perky (1910) 8Brown and Herstein, pp. 46-47 9Goldenberg et al. (1995) 10I take this data and much of the analysis from Eric Schwitzgebel (2002). “Fire and the Cogito: Dreams and Imaginings” Virginia Tech Conference Submission our dreams didn’t actually become colorized in the late 1950s, he must conclude that either (a) almost everybody in the ‘40s and ‘50s was wrong about the nature of visual experience in dreams, or (b) almost everybody today is. So if the orthodox view is correct, then some people are deeply mistaken about what color sensations they have in their dreams. This counts against rejecting the imagination model on phenomenological grounds.11 3.2 Color in Fiction. Even once we say that at least one group has been seriously mistaken about the nature of visual experience in dreams, we are still left with something of a puzzle: which group is mistaken? The imagination theorist need not choose either one – if there are no sensations, the question of whether they’re color sensations is senseless. Eric Schwitzgebel explicitly discusses the advantages in adopting a fiction model of dreaming as an alternative: Consider, as an analogy, a novel. While novels surely are not in black and white, it also seems a little strange to say that they are ‘in color’. ... Perhaps dream-objects and dream-events are similar to fictional objects and events, or to the images evoked by fiction, in having, typically, a certain indeterminacy of color….12 Once we accept that we can be and are mistaken about sensation experiences as basic as color, it is plausible to generalize the non-sensation sensationR of color to nonsensationR in general. Once we let go of colorR, it won’t be too difficult to let go of coldR, painR, the auditory sensationR associated with an oboe playing a concert A, etc. Wittgenstein on Agency and Imagination. Once we see that sometimes we 11 Schwitzgebel’s proposed explanation of the discrepancy is based on the prevelance of black-and-white media during the 1940’s and ‘50’s. The idea is that we project our experiences of films to experiences of dreams. Whether this is correct is immaterial to my project. 12Schwitzgebel 655-56 “Fire and the Cogito: Dreams and Imaginings” Virginia Tech Conference Submission confuse imagination with reality, the question becomes pressing: how do we tell mental statesR from mental statesI? Ideally, we will eventually be in a position to tell a positive story of how it could come to be that we can imagine without realizing it when we dream. Some insights from Wittgenstein will put us in a position to sketch the beginning of that story. Wittgenstein focuses on visual imagery, but this generalizes to other kinds of imagination as well.13 Wittgenstein develops a positive account based on a sense of agency. The difference between imagery and sensation is that sensations, unlike imagery, tell us something (true or false) about the external world. Sensation is something that happens to us, while imagery is something that we do.14 He points out that imagining something is the kind of thing that it makes sense to be told to do (or stop doing). Imagining is active, while seeing is passive. It is easily objected against Wittgenstein’s view that imagery, and imagination in general, are not always voluntary. We sometimes are surprised at what we imagine, and we sometimes have difficulty expelling imagery from our heads. I paraphrase Malcolm Budd’s response15 to this objection: the fact that sometimes we have images against our will doesn’t mean we’re not active in Wittgenstein’s sense in creating them. Consider the difference between a case in which I am being prodded against my will and a case in which I am thinking about something unpleasant against my will. My thinking, unlike my being prodded, is something I do, not something that merely happens to me. 13For an argument that imagery is a kind of imagination, see Currie and Ravenscroft, ch. 2. 14Wittgenstein, Zettel §621 et seq. 15Budd p. 109 “Fire and the Cogito: Dreams and Imaginings” Virginia Tech Conference Submission I am not suggesting that we always are in conscious control of our imaginings – only that they do in fact issue from within, and that in typical cases, the phenomenology of imagining reflects this; imagining feels a certain way, and the way it feels seems to have to do with agency.16 This is the understanding behind Wittgenstein’s observation that imagining is something that it makes sense to be told to stop doing – you’re the one doing it, even if you can’t get yourself to stop. Schizophrenia and Loss of Agency. Suppose Wittgenstein is right, and the way we distinguish imagery from sensation is through the sense of agency that accompanies imagery. It follows, then, that if we lost that sense of agency, we’d lose access to the fact that we are merely imagining. Gregory Currie has developed a theory of schizophrenia which capitalizes on this result: schizophrenic delusions are best understood as issuing from confusion of one’s own imaginings as beliefs. And this confusion is caused, Currie suggests, by a loss of a sense of agency17. On Currie’s model, subjects imagine things, but are not aware of their own agency in causing them. The imaginings feel like things that happen to them. If Wittgenstein’s model of imagination recognition is correct, then it is not surprising that these subjects would fail to recognize imaginations as such. The 16 Not all imaginings, of course, issue purely from within. When I watch a movie or read a book, I imagine the events of the fiction, and those events do not come from within me – they come from the fiction. I have no control, perceived or otherwise, over whether Desdemona will survive. To see the sense in which a sense of agency is relevant here, consider Kendall Walton’s understanding of works of fiction as invitations to imagine. If this even makes sense, then imagining is something we control. My going along with the film, play, or novel – my seeing it as a story instead of a projector screen and a pattern of color and sounds – constitutes the imagining. And that is something that I do. So it makes sense for someone to tell me to continue to watch the movie but to stop imagining the story – this, presumably, is a skill that film editors develop. 17 Loss of sense of agency has been independently proposed as characteristic of schizophrenia by Colin Firth (1992). “Fire and the Cogito: Dreams and Imaginings” Virginia Tech Conference Submission agency loss is able to provide explanation of schizophrenic delusions18. Agency and Dreams. If we can give a satisfactory account of an agency-based imagination model of schizophrenia, may we do the same for dreaming? If, when we dream, we ‘lose track’ of our roles as creators – that is, we lose our sense of agency, we fail to recognize that we’re only imagining. In ordinary dreaming, I do not consciously control what I dream (although obviously my dreams are still issuing from me). If Wittgenstein’s account is correct, then, it is not surprising that I fail to recognize them at the time as imaginings. Note the continuity with daydreams and other imaginings in this respect. Just as we ‘get lost’ in dreams, it is possible to get lost in daydreams which begin as deliberate imaginings. We focus not on the fact that we are imagining, but on the content of our imaginings. Note that it is possible to so fully engage in a daydream that we do lose conscious awareness of the fact that our impressions are only imagination – it can be jarring to be pulled from a reverie, just as it can to be pulled from a dream.19 This fits well with the imagination model – according to my view, the phenomenology of dreaming is continuous with that of daydreaming – both are acts of imagination. Summary: The Case for the Imagination Model. I have offered three lines of 18This also may account for the hitherto-inexplicable phenomenon of “thought insertion”, whereby schizophrenic patients report experiencing other people’s thoughts . The following description of thought insertion is from John Campbell (1999): “...there is, the patient insists, a sense in which the thought is not his, a sense in which the thought is someone else’s, and not just in that someone else originated the thought and communicated it to the subject; there is a sense in which the thought, as it were, remains the property of someone else.” (p. 610) When we imagine propositions, we do ‘insert’ them into our minds, and a person with limited awareness of his own agency in that insertion might describe the phenomenon in this way. 19Kendall Walton (p. 50) hints at this point, drawing a connection between dreaming, daydreaming, and imagining. “Fire and the Cogito: Dreams and Imaginings” Virginia Tech Conference Submission reasoning in favor of the imagination model of dreaming. First, since we can explain dreams in a compelling way without reference to beliefs and sensations, we find no reason to suppose that there are such experiences in our dreams. Second, counterintuitive attributions of immorality and irrationality follow from the orthodox model of dreaming, but not from the imagination model. Third, lack of sensations in dreams may be the best explanation for phenomena like the disagreement about color in dreams. In addition, I’ve sketched out a positive story which may help explain why our dreams don’t feel like typical imaginings. I will conclude with a discussion of some epistemological consequences of the imagination model of dreaming. Moore. I have argued that the inference I dream p, therefore p is invalid, even when p is an occurrent mental state. This might tempt us to reconsider G. E. Moore’s response to the dream scenario: But what I am in doubt of is whether it is logically possible that I should both be having all the sensory experiences and the memories that I have and yet be dreaming. The conjunction of the proposition that I have these same experiences and memories with the proposition that I am dreaming does seem to me to be very likely self-contradictory.20 If what I am saying about the nature of dreaming is correct, then maybe Moore’s move has more plausibility than it at first appears. According to the imagination model, I do not have sensations during dreams the way I do when awake. From this it follows that there is a valid argument, “I am having visual sensations, therefore I am not dreaming.” Does Moore’s response work after all? I do not think that it does. One reason is that the considerations I’ve cited that 20Moore p. 245 “Fire and the Cogito: Dreams and Imaginings” Virginia Tech Conference Submission make the imagination model plausible are also considerations that cast doubt on our ability to introspect occurent mental states. Although “I am experiencing sensationsR, therefore I am not dreaming” is valid, it does not provide apodictic protection from the dream argument. I may take myself to seeR a fire, when I’m actually only seeingI one. Also, although I think there is good reason to believe that the imagination model of dreaming is correct – because it provides the best explanation for what we know about dreaming, I do not think that we have sufficient evidence to justify certainty that it is correct. So Descartes’s dream scenario still succeeds in casting doubt.21 So it does not seem that the imagination model will give the anti-skeptic certainty about the fact that we’re not dreaming – both because we can’t be sure what our experiences are like (whether, for instance, we’re having sensationsR or sensationsI), and because we can’t rule out the possibility that we’re having sensationsR as a result of a particularly unusual kind of dream. And in another way, the imagination model will make things even more difficult. Once we recognize that “I thinkR” can be confused with “I thinkI” (that is, “I imagine that”), we lose perfect certainty even in the cogito. Descartes wants to argue I thinkR, therefore I am, but the premise is no longer certain – he may only thinkI. A quick patch moves Descartes in the right direction, but at a cost: I (thinkR or thinkI), therefore I am is valid, but that premise does not seem to be in a position to obtain certainty either – for anyone who took himself to be asserting the premise could ‘step up’ a hypothetical level and ask, how do I know I’m not just thinkingI 21However, if the imagination view is correct, and we never really do have dreams that are like hallucinations, then there is a sense in which our external knowledge is ‘safer’ the Cartesian project would suggest. The danger that we are having ‘dreams’ that are fundamentally different from ordinary dreams (i.e. dreams about which the orthodox model is correct) seems now to be a more ‘distant’ danger – a danger more like the madman or the evil demon scenario. So there is a sense in which the imagination model helps the anti-skeptic about the external world. Thanks to Ernest Sosa for this point. “Fire and the Cogito: Dreams and Imaginings” Virginia Tech Conference Submission that? Imaginings, unlike beliefs, are not the kinds of things that can be certain. The Cartesian wants to evaluate all of his beliefs – he cannot do this without first knowing what they are. On the whole, I think that because the imagination model is correct, the Cartesian anti-skeptic is in more trouble than he would otherwise be. “Fire and the Cogito: Dreams and Imaginings” Virginia Tech Conference Submission References Brown, Roger and Herrnstein, Richard J. (1981) “Icons and Images”, in Imagery, Ned Block, ed., MIT Press 1981 Budd, Malcolm (1989) Wittgenstein’s Philosophy of Psychology, Routlege 1989 Campbell, John (1999) “Schizophrenia, the space of reasons, and thinking as a motor process”, The Monist, 82 (1999), pp. 609-25 Currie, Gregory (1997) “The Paradox of Caring: Fiction and the Philosophy of Mind”, in Emotion and the Arts, Mette Hjort and Sue Laver, eds., Oxford University Press 1997 Currie, Gregory (2000) “Imagination, Delusion and Hallucinations”, Mind & Language, Vol. 15 No. 1, February 2000, pp. 168-183 Currie, Gregory (1990) The Nature of Fiction, Cambridge University Press 1990 Currie, Gregory and Ravenscroft, Ian. (2002) Recreative Minds - Imagination in Philosophy and Psychology, Oxford University Press 2002 Descartes, René. (2000) Philosophical Essays and Correspondence, Roger Ariew, ed. Kackett Publishing Company, Inc. 2000 Goldenberg, Georg; Müllbacher, Wolf; and Nowak, Andreas. (1995) “Imagery Without Percption – A Case Study of Anosognosia for Cortical Blindness”, Neuropsychologia, Vol. 33, No. 11, pp. 1373-1382 Hume, David. (1988) An Enquiry concerning Human Understanding, Antony Flew, ed. Open Court Press 1998 Malcolm, Norman (1959) Dreaming, Routledge & Kegan Paul Ltd, 1962 Moore, G. E. (1962) “Certainty”, Philosophical Papers, Collier Books, 1962 Perky, C. W. (1910). “An Experimental Study of Imagination”, American Journal of Psychology, 21 (1910), 422-452 Schwitzgebel, Eric. (2002) “Why did we think we dreamed in black and white?”, Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science, 33, 2002 pp. 649-660. Walton, Kendall. (1990) Mimesis as Make-Believe, Harvard University Press 1990 Wittgenstein, (1980) Remarks on the Philosophy of Psychology, vol. II, C.G. Luckhardt and M.A.E. Aue (translation); G.E.M. Anscomb and G.H. von Wright, eds. Oxford University Press 1980 Wittgenstein, (1981) Zettel, second edition, G.E.M. Anscomb (translation); G.E.M. Anscomb and G.H. von Wright, eds. Oxford University Press 1981 Yost, R. M. Jr. And Kalish, D., (1955) “Miss MacDonald on Sleeping and Waking”, Philosophical Quarterly, April 1955 pp. 109-124