Language use as principle: The politeness principle Shaozhong Liu, Ph.D. (Pragmatics) / Ph.D. (Higher Education) College of Foreign Studies, Guilin University of Electronic Technology Homepage: www.gxnu.edu.cn/Personal/szliu Blog: cyrusliu.blog.163.com Email: shaozhong@hotmail.com 11/2/2011 essentials in pragmatics, fall 2011 1 The problem • Why do people speak indirectly or directly, which they both do? Examples: 1) Take a look at this. 2) Clean up the kitchen. 3) Pass the salt. 4) Have some more cake. 5) Peel these potatoes. 11/2/2011 essentials in pragmatics, fall 2011 2 More examples 6) Set the table. 7) Can you set the table? 8) Could I possibly ask you to set the table? … 11/2/2011 essentials in pragmatics, fall 2011 3 The literature gap • Austin, Searle, Grice, none addressed the above question: why do people speak directly or indirectly? How to explain the above discreet utterances in terms of the CP, or SAT? 11/2/2011 essentials in pragmatics, fall 2011 4 Synopsis 1. The Principles of Pragmatics 2. With the CP already, why the PP? 3. What is the PP? 4. The explanatory adequacy of the PP 5. Foundations of the PP 6. Issues of the PP 7. References 11/2/2011 essentials in pragmatics, fall 2011 5 1. The Principles of Pragmatics • In 1983, with R. H. Robins (University of London), and G. N. Leech (University of Lancaster) as General editors, Longman Publisher Ltd published Longman Linguistics Library series which consists of 30 titles, including The Principles of Pragmatics. 11/2/2011 essentials in pragmatics, fall 2011 6 • Here’s the Contents of The Principles of Pragmatics: 1. Introduction ( 1.1 historical preamble, 1.2 semantics and pragmatics, 1.3 general pragmatics, 1.4 aspects of speech situations, 1.5 rhetoric) 2. A set of postulates (2.1 semantic representation and pragmatic interpretation, 2.2 rules and principles, 2.3 convention and motivation, 2.4 the relation between sense and force, 2.5 pragmatics as problem-solving, 2.6 conclusion) 11/2/2011 essentials in pragmatics, fall 2011 7 3. Formalism ad functionalism (3.1 formal and functional explanation, 3.2 biological, psychological, and social varieties of functionalism, 3.3 the ideational, interpersonal, and textual functions of language, 3.4 the ideational function: discreteness and determinacy, 3.5 examples of ‘overgeneralization’, 3.6 conclusion) 4. The interpersonal roles of the Cooperative Principle (4.1 the CP and the PP, 4.2 maxims of quantity and quality, 4.3 maxim of relation, 4.4 the hinting strategy and anticipatory illocutions, 4.5 maxim of manner) 11/2/2011 essentials in pragmatics, fall 2011 8 5. The Tact Maxim (5.1 varieties of illocutionary function, 5.2 Searle’s categories of illocutionary acts, 5.3 Tact: one kind of politeness, 5.4 pragmatic paradoxes of politeness, 5.5 semantic representation of declaratives, interrogatives and imperatives, 5.6 the interpretation of impositibves, 5.7 pragmatic scales, 5.8 tact and condescension) 11/2/2011 essentials in pragmatics, fall 2011 9 6. A survey of the Interpersonal Rhetoric (6.1 maxims of politeness, 6.2 metalinguistic aspects of politeness, 6.3 irony and banter, 6.4 hyperbole and litotes, 6.5 conclusion) 7. Communicative Grammar: an example (7.1 communicative grammar and pragmatic force, 7.2 remarks on pragmatic metalanguage, 7.3 some aspects negation and interrogation in English) 11/2/2011 essentials in pragmatics, fall 2011 10 8. Performatives (8.1 the performative and illocutionary-verb fallacies, 8.2 the speech act theories of Austin and Searle, 8.3 illocutionary performatives: descriptive and non-descriptive approaches, 8.4 illocutionary performatives and oratio obliqua, 8.5 the pragmatics of illocutionary performatives, 8.6 the performative hypothesis, 8.7 the extended performative hypothesis, 8.8 conclusion) 11/2/2011 essentials in pragmatics, fall 2011 11 9. Speech-act verbs in English (9.1 locutionary, illocutionary, and perlocutionary, 9.2 a survey of speech-act verb classes, 9.3 is there a separate class of performative verbs? 9.4 a semantic analysis of some illocutionary verbs, 9.5 assertive verbs, 9.6 conclusion) 10. Retrospect and prospect 11/2/2011 essentials in pragmatics, fall 2011 12 • Notice that this book is about principles of language use, implying there are many apart from the CP and the PP. Among them are the Irony Principle (p.79-83), the Banter Principle (p. 144). But Leech chooses to elaborate on the relationship between the CP and the PP and how these two can be combined to form a robust pragmatic theory. 11/2/2011 essentials in pragmatics, fall 2011 13 2. With the CP already, why the PP? 1) Please appreciate Leech’s Preface as an abstract of his book. 2) Leech’s definition of pragmatics: Pragmatics can be usefully defined as the study of how utterances have meanings in situations. (Preface) 11/2/2011 essentials in pragmatics, fall 2011 14 3) Leech’s purpose in The Principles of Pragmatics: Present a complementary view of pragmatics within an overall program for studying language as a communication system, namely studying the use of a language as distinct from, but complementary to, the language itself seen as a formal system treated in grammar. 11/2/2011 essentials in pragmatics, fall 2011 15 To do this, it is necessary to develop theories and methods of description peculiar to pragmatics itself and show that these are different from those appropriate to grammar. In this way, it is hoped that the domain of pragmatics is delimited from grammar and at the same time the two fields combine within an integrated framework for studying language. (Preface) To postulate principles and maxims to explain the relation between sense and force in human communication (p.131) 11/2/2011 essentials in pragmatics, fall 2011 16 4) Pragmatic framework: Literature review • Up to the early 1980s, there were little literature on the development of pragmatic paradigms. • Austin-Searle formulated a view of meaning in terms of illocutionary force. • H.P. Grice formulated another view of meaning in terms of conversational implicature. • These are the strongest influences on the formation of pragmatic theories. • But Leech tried to be novel, creative and original. 11/2/2011 essentials in pragmatics, fall 2011 17 5) With the CP already, why the PP? • Pp.79 onward, 4.1 discusses the need of the CP and meanwhile the insufficiency of the CP, in interpersonal communication. • We need the CP to help account for the relation between sense and force, and this kind of explanation is particularly welcome where it solves puzzles which arise in a truth-based approach to semantics. 11/2/2011 essentials in pragmatics, fall 2011 18 • However, the CP can’t explain: i) why people are often so indirect in conveying what they mean; and ii) what is the relation between sense and force when no-declarative types of sentence are being considered. • Grice himself, and others who have invoked the CP, have understandably reflected the logician’s traditional concern with truth, and hence with propositional meaning; whereas Leech in interested in a broader, socially and psychologically oriented application of pragmatic principles. 11/2/2011 essentials in pragmatics, fall 2011 19 • Objections to Grice’s CP on the grounds that it doesn’t stand up to the evidence of real language use: 1) Conversational constraints such as the CP don’t work because most declarative sentences don’t have an information-bearing function (Larkin & O’Malley, 1973). 2) Maxims of the CP are not universal to language, because there are linguistic communities to which not all of them apply (Keenan, 1974). 11/2/2011 essentials in pragmatics, fall 2011 20 • Leech: My first observation on these criticisms is that they are not necessarily so damning as they look. To reject the CP on purely quantitative grounds would be to mistake maxims for statistical norms—which they are not. And no claim has been made that the CP applies in an identical manner to all societies. Indeed, one of the main purposes of socio-pragmatics, as I envisage it, is to find out how different societies operate maxims in different ways, for example by giving politeness a higher rating than cooperation in certain situations, or by giving precedence to one maxim of the PP rather than another. 11/2/2011 essentials in pragmatics, fall 2011 21 So it must be admitted that the CP is in a weak position if apparent exceptions to it can’t be satisfactorily explained. It is for this reason that the PP can be seen as not just another principle to be added to the CP, but as a necessary complement, which rescues the CP from serious trouble. (p.80) 11/2/2011 essentials in pragmatics, fall 2011 22 6) Leech’s hypothesis or thesis: Pragmatics as well as communication is problemsolving or goal-oriented and evaluative. A speaker or communicator has to solve the problem: ‘Given that I want to bring about suchand-such a result in the hearer’s consciousness, what is the best way to accomplish this aim by using language?’ 11/2/2011 essentials in pragmatics, fall 2011 23 A hearer has another kind of problem to solve: ‘Given that the speaker said such-and-such, what did the speaker mean me to understand by that?’ (Preface) 11/2/2011 essentials in pragmatics, fall 2011 24 7) Method of study: rhetorical approach to pragmatics, whereby the speaker is seen as trying to achieve his aims within constraints imposed by principles and maxims of ‘good communicative behavior’, which embody, among others, Grice’s CP, and others such as politeness and irony principles. (Preface) 11/2/2011 essentials in pragmatics, fall 2011 25 3. What is the PP? 1) Far from being a superficial matter of ‘being civil’, politeness is an important missing link between the CP and the problem of how to relate sense and force (p.104). 2) Politeness concerns a relationship between two participants whom we may call self and other. In conversation, self will normally be identified with s, and other will typically be identified with h and other third-person pronouns. 11/2/2011 essentials in pragmatics, fall 2011 26 3) The maxims of the PP tend to go in pairs as follows (p. 132): (I) Tact maxim (in impositives and commissives) (a) Minimize cost to other [(b) Maximize benefit to other] (II) Generosity maxim (in expressives and commissives) (a) Minimize benefit to self [(b) Maximize benefit to other] (III) Approbation maxim (in expressives and commissives) (a) Minimize dispraise of other [(b) Maximize praise of other] 11/2/2011 essentials in pragmatics, fall 2011 27 (IV) Modesty maxim (in expressives assertives) (a) Minimize praise of self [(b) Maximize praise of other] (V) Agreement maxim (in assertives) (a) Minimize disagreement between self and other [(b) Maximize agreement between self and other] (VI) Sympathy maxim (in assertives) (a) Minimize antipathy between self and other [(b) Maximize sympathy between self and other] 11/2/2011 essentials in pragmatics, fall 2011 28 4. The explanatory adequacy of the PP • Tact maxim: examples on pages 104-130. • Other maxims: Pages 131-151. 11/2/2011 essentials in pragmatics, fall 2011 29 5. Foundations of the PP 1) Rhetoric 2) The CP, especially Grice’s suggestion to try other factors including politeness and relevance, etc.. 3) Criticisms of the CP 4) Brown and Levinson’s (1978) study of politeness, face, and FTA 5) Cross-cultural communication studies (pragmatic failure (Thomas, 1982) 11/2/2011 essentials in pragmatics, fall 2011 30 6. Issues of the PP 1) Too many maxims 2) Short-circuitedness of the PP maxims in crosscultures or languages 11/2/2011 essentials in pragmatics, fall 2011 31 7. References H. P. Grice: Logic and conversation. In Grice (1968/1975): Studies in the way of words. Harvard University Press. G. N. Leech: Principles of Pragmatics. London: Longman. P. Brown and S. Levinson: Universals in language usage: politeness phenomena. In E. N. Goody (ed.) (1978): Questions and Politeness: Strategies in Social Interaction. Cambridge: CUP. 11/2/2011 essentials in pragmatics, fall 2011 32