Epistemological Issues in International Development

advertisement

Bereket Kebede

School of International Development

University of East Anglia

London (UEA London)

10 December 2011

10:00 a.m. – 5:00 p.m.

Outline

1.

An excursion into a history of economics

2.

Dominant epistemologies

3.

Mathematics and formalism

4.

Observational data and econometrics

5.

Experimental methods

1. An excursion into a history of economics

 Publication of A. Smith’s Wealth of Nations in 1776

(‘birth of economics’) and subsequent classical economists (Ricardo, Malthus, Marx, Mill, etc.)

 Economics was not yet a really distinctive and unified discipline (political economy, moral philosophy, etc.)

 The marginalist revolution and the rise of neoclassical economics (Jevons, Menger, Walras,

Marshall) – dominant school after end of 19 th century

1. An excursion into a history of economics (cont’d)

 Economics as we know it, based on neoclassical school, emerged after WWII (the ‘formalist revolution’)

 Hick, Value and Capital (1939)

 Samuelson, Foundations of Economic Analysis (1947)

 Arrow, Social Choice and Individual Values (1951)

 von Neumann and Morgenstern, Theory of Games and

Economic Behaviour (1953)

 Debreu, Theory of Value (1959)

1. An excursion into a history of economics (cont’d)

 With the dominance of modern conventional economics, issues of methodology and epistemology were left in the background

 Economic epistemologists (philosopher rather than economists) separate from standard economists

 Recent revival of interest in epistemological and philosophical problems of economics

Development economics: a separate discipline or a branch of main stream economics?

2. Dominant epistemologies

Positivism: the application of methods of natural sciences to the study of social reality (Bryman, 2004)

Phenomenalism: knowledge confirmed by the senses can genuinely be warranted

Deductivism: theory to generate testable hypotheses to identify laws; e.g., economic theory

Inductivism: gathering of facts to provide basis for laws; e.g., survey data and econometrics

Objective: science should be conducted as value free

Positive vs. normative: the latter prescriptive; e.g., efficiency vs. income distribution

2. Dominant epistemologies

(cont’d)

Post-positivism: knowledge based on probabilistic propositions rather than certainty; approximate truth; the ‘uncertainty principle’

Methodological individualism – both an organising strategy for neoclassical economics and an ontological commitment

 Recent interest in alternative epistemological approaches in economics: e.g., Lavoie, ed., Economics and Hermeneutics

3. Mathematics and formalism

“Those who have handled sciences have been either men of experiment or men of dogmas. The men of experiment are like the ant, they only collect and use; the reasoners resemble spiders, who make cobwebs out of their own substance. But the bee takes a middle course: it gathers its material from flowers of the garden and of the field, but transforms and digests it by a power of its own … Therefore from a closer and purer league between these two faculties, the experimental and the rational (such as has never yet been made), much may be hoped.”

Francis Bacon, 1620

3. Mathematics and formalism

(cont’d)

 The reasoners/spiders/theoretical economists? – use simplified and formal models

 The bees/empirical economists? – use mainly econometrics to analyse data testing theories

 (Wo)Men of experiments/experimentalists? – both random controlled trials (RCTs) and experimental economics

3. Mathematics and formalism

(cont’d)

 Modern mainstream theoretical economics uses simplified, abstract, formal mathematical models

 Starting from simple axioms and assumptions builds an internally consistent logical system

 Theoretical models are understood as simplified representations of important real economic relationships

 Idealisation as a price worth paying to understand important economic relationships

(ontological problem?)

3. Mathematics and formalism

(cont’d)

 “Ultra-empiricism”- postulates, assumptions, axioms and basic principles in economic models should be testable

 Friedman (1953) – “ultra-empiricism” would eliminate much useful theorising

 Basic assumptions of theoretical models neither should be true nor testable

 Usefulness of models depends on predictive reliability

(pragmatism, instrumentalism, indirect empiricism)

 Judged on fit with parallel theorising

3. Mathematics and formalism

(cont’d)

Formalism: an approach (mathematical or otherwise) to theorising that aims at making explicit the logical structure of a theory; set-theoretic formalism widely accepted in economic theory

 Formal models as simplified representation of economic reality; also remember Friedman

 Formal models as training tools; improves perception and analytical skills of economists

3. Mathematics and formalism

(cont’d)

 Formalism and mathematics still important in recent critiques of conventional economics

New Institutional Economics: instead of individual agency the role of institutions emphasised; a dominant part of the school retains and prioritises formalistic methods

Behavioural Economics: using insights from psychology, relaxes the assumption of the hyper-rational economic agent of conventional economics; mostly widened the scope of formal economic models

3. Mathematics and formalism

(cont’d)

Complexity and computational economics: economic interactions are too complicated for capturing in neat closed models

 E.g., agent-based computational economics: economies as dynamic systems of interacting agents; agents can range from active data-gathering decision-makers with sophisticated learning capabilities or as passive with no cognitive functioning

 Difficult to analytically solve the outcome of these complex interactions; left for computer algorithms including artificial intelligence

4. Observational data and econometrics

 Most empirical analysis in economics in general and development economics in particular uses observational rather than experimental data – need for quasi-

experimental method, mainly econometrics

 ‘Recreating’ an experimental set-up without experimental data – controlling for confounding variables and orthogonal residuals

4. Observational data and econometrics (cont’d)

 Tension between theory-led and data-led econometrics (the LSE school); difference on how knowledge is to be attained rather than ontological differences in economic entities

 Single econometric tests rarely make significant changes; accumulated weight of evidence is required to bring paradigm shift

(a la Lakatos)

5. Experimental methods

 Economics considered as non-experimental discipline at least until the 1980s

 Recent trends:

Randomised control trials (RCTs): identifying project/treatment effects by randomising interventions

Lab experiments (experimental games): ‘players’ making decision under incentivised and controlled situation

(laboratory)

5. Experimental methods (cont’d)

 Increasing interest in the epistemology of experimental economics (e.g., Santos, 2010)

The social epistemology of experiment (SEE):

 Experimental facts generated through material and social processes

Material processes: ‘phenomenal model’ (experimenter’s view of how the world works), ‘instrumental model’ (view on how the experimental apparatus works), ‘material procedure’ (actually how the experimental apparatus works)

Social processes: the experimental subjects and the experimentalist

5. Experimental methods (cont’d)

 The direct participation of human subjects is the major source of epistemic value; but participants may ‘resist’ expectations of economists

 Experimental games are amenable to scrutiny by wide audience

 SEE pays special attention to scientists predisposition to obtain confirmation of prior beliefs

(‘confirmation bias’)

References

 Boettke, Peter J.; Christopher J. Coyne; John Davis; Francesco Guala; Alain

Marciano; Jochen Runde and Margaret Schabas. 2006. "Where Economics and

Philosophy Meet: Review of the Elgar Companion to Economics and

Philosophy with Responses from the Authors." Economic Journal, 116(June),

F306-F25.

 Bryman, Alan. 2004. Social Research Methods. Oxford: Oxford University

Press.

 Davis, John B.; Alain Marciano and Jochen Runde eds. 2004. The Elgar

Companion of Economics and Philosophy. Cheltenham, UK, Northampton,

MA, USA: Edward Elgar.

 Friedman, Milton. 1953. Essays in Positive Economics - the Methodology of

Positive Economics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

References

 Hoover, Kevin D. 2006. "The Methodology of Econometrics," T. C.

Mills and K. Patterson, Palgrave Handbook of Econometrics:

Econometric Theory: Econometric Theory. New York: Palgrave

Macmillan,

 Hoover, Kevin D. 2010. "Pragmatism, Perspecitval Realism and

Econometrics," Durham, NC: Duke University,

 Lavoie, Don ed. 1990. Economics and Hermeneutics. London and

New York: Routledge.

 Sagal, Paul T. 1977. "Epistemology in Economics." Journal for

General Philosophy of Science, 8(1), 144-62.

 Santos, Ana Cordeira dos. 2010. The Social Epistemology of

Experimental Economics. London and New York: Routledge.

Download