KEY NOTES: A mental disorder is a syndrome characterized by clinically significant disturbance in an individual’s cognition, emotion regulation, or behavior that reflects a dysfunction in the psychological, biological, or developmental processes underlying mental functioning. Mental disorders are usually associated with significant distress in social, occupational, or other important activities. An expectable or culturally approved response to a common stressor or loss, such as the death of a loved one, is not a mental disorder. Socially deviant behavior (e.g., political, religious, or sexual) and conflicts that are primarily between the individual and society are not mental disorders unless the deviance or conflict results from a dysfunction in the individual, as described above. As a bridge between the issues of treatment and prediction, which will be addressed shortly, let us consider the causal relation between mental disorder and criminal conduct. The most important thing to recognize for lawyers and policymakers is that mental disorders that apparently play a causal role do not turn the person into an automaton. People with mental disorders act for reasons just like people without such disorders. Consider Daniel M’Naghten, for example, a 19th-century Scotsman who was delusional and believed the Tory Party was persecuting him and was attempting to kill him. He intended to kill British Prime Minister Robert Peel to save his own life, and acted on that intent (although, in the event, he killed Peel’s private secretary, Edward Drummond, who was riding in the prime minister’s carriage that day). Abnormal perceptions or beliefs motivate people with mental disorders and they then act on those beliefs. Their criminal acts should not be understood mechanistically, like a fever that spikes as the result of an underlying infection. Causation should be understood in this context in terms of assessing the defendant’s reasons for action. Finally, simply because a mental disorder played a causal role in explaining criminal behavior, it does not follow that the person could not control that behavior. The notion of loss of control of action is notoriously fraught. A minority of jurisdictions have a control test for legal insanity in addition to a cognitive test, and the Supreme Court has approved the use of control criteria for sexual-predator commitments.9 But the meaning of these tests—at least to the extent that a defendant’s control of his behavior is considered independent of his rationality—remains conceptually and empirically unclear. For these reasons, both the American Psychiatric Association and the American Bar Association recommended abolition of control tests for legal insanity. Investigation of good studies discloses a far weaker connection between major mental disorder and criminality than many people stereotypically assume. Most people with mental disorder do not engage in serious criminal behavior and are more likely to be victims of violence than perpetrators. The rate of serious criminal behavior among people with major mental disorder is approximately the same as the population as a whole—about 3% to 4%— unless the person is also abusing substances, which does increase the rate. This is unsurprising because people with serious disorders do have higher rates of substance-use problems, probably because they are self-medicating to deal with the pain of mental disorder and related problems. Nonetheless, even in this co-morbid population—people with major mental disorder and substance abuse—the rate of serious criminal behavior is low.10 Moreover, the association between psychotic states and violent behavior is weak and inconsistent. The strongest association between mental disorder and violent conduct is selfharm, especially suicide by gun.11 This is tragic, but not a criminal justice issue. In short, there are clear cases in which mentally abnormal thoughts and moods may be causally related to criminal conduct, but for the most part, major mental disorder is not a major cause of crime. There is a powerful moral and social argument that better mental-health services should be provided to the population at large and especially to those without the resources to afford private care. It is a mistake, however, to believe that more aggressive mentalhealth care, including increased use of involuntary civil commitment or compulsory treatment, will make much inroad in preventing serious criminal behavior. Such interventions, which often involve substantial deprivations of liberty, may have positive mental-health outcomes for some sufferers, but they will have slight impact on criminal conduct.