Chapter 4 Deep Diagramming: Reasons For and Against In this chapter we will go a bit further in our capacity to accurately diagram reasoning. Until this point in our discussion of how to represent the ways in which reasons relate to conclusions we have only been concerned with reasons insofar as they are intended to support conclusions. But as we all realize when we are presented with someone else’s process of reasoning or when we present our own arguments, we also take into account counter-considerations (reasons against the truth of reasons, reasons against the truth of conclusions and reasons that attack inferences). Indeed this is a fundamental dimension of any extended argument for it can provide a balanced presentation of the issues. When we talk of being able to represent in diagrammatic form the nature of reasons against we are speaking of three possible forms of relationship. There are reasons which counter the truth of other reasons, there are reasons that count against the truth of conclusions and there are reasons which attack the nature of inferences in inductive arguments. In the latter case we assume the truth of the reasons (for the sake of the argument) and we try to think of other reasons which attack the reliability of reaching the conclusion—reasons that weaken the support of those reasons assumed to be true. In all three forms of attack we are thinking ‘outside the box’ since we are trying to see problems in the argument. Let us begin at the simplest level by looking at single premise arguments. 106 Deep Diagramming: Reasons For and Against Attacks Upon the Truth of Reasons Let us suppose we have been presented with the following argument: Example 4.1 It has been argued that (1) the University library contains very few philosophy books. Therefore, (2) the University library should start buying philosophy books. Diagram: (1) (2) But then it might be objected that we ought to doubt whether (1) is in fact true because (3) students at the University are so enthralled with philosophy that (4) the substantial collection of philosophy books in the library are always checked out. The reasoning now has an objection against the truth of (1) that is itself now supported by a reason. The reasoning now reads: Example 4.2 It has been argued that the University library contains very few philosophy books. Therefore, (2) the University library should start buying philosophy books. But this is not the case because (3) students at the University are so enthralled with philosophy that (4) the substantial collection of philosophy books in the library are always checked out. 107 Thinking Things Through: An Introduction to Analytical Skills Diagrammatically we arrive at: (3) (1) (4) (2) One way to think of this is to ask ourselves whether the truth of (4) makes (1) less likely to be true. Here the attack upon the truth of the reason is signaled by the broken inference arrow. Attacks upon the Truth of Conclusions Sometimes instead of attacking the truth of a reason we want to directly deny the truth of a conclusion. When this happens we may remain agnostic about the reasons given for the conclusion (we may want to attack the reasons as well but we don’t need to). Example 4.3 It has been argued that the University library contains very few philosophy books. Therefore, (2) the University library should start buying philosophy books. But (3) the library’s budget is already spent, and moreover (4) philosophy is not even studied at this University. Here we can remain agnostic about the reason given to support (2) and we are simply pointing out that there are reasons which count against the truth of (2). 108 Deep Diagramming: Reasons For and Against Diagram: (1) (3) (4) (2) Once again the attacks represented by (3) and (4) are represented by the broken inference arrow but now the two convergent reasons are drawn directly against the conclusion (2). Attacks upon Inferences Another way in which we can present counter-considerations involves neither attacking the truth of reasons nor necessarily attacking the truth of conclusions but rather attacking the relationship between reasons and conclusions. In this case one can remain agnostic about the truthvalue of reasons and conclusions but can point out that in the internal structure of the argument, even if we assume (for the sake of argument) that the reasons are true, the conclusion is not firmly established. It is important to note here that attacks upon inferences can only occur in inductive arguments and never in valid arguments. This is because in inductive arguments the conclusion is supported with varying levels of strength whereas in valid arguments the reasons, if true, give 100% support for the conclusion. So there can be no successful attack against a valid inference. Suppose in a single premise argument we have: 109 Thinking Things Through: An Introduction to Analytical Skills Example 4.4 (1) Something can exist only if it is a material thing. Therefore, (2) God does not exist. Diagram: (1) (2) This little argument immediately strikes us as odd. The reason for this is that there is a missing premise, namely that God is not a material thing. Nevertheless, let us imagine that (3) God is, in fact, a material thing. In this case if we assume (for the sake of argument) that premise (1) is indeed true, we will have to admit that the conclusion no longer follows. The argument then looks like this: Example 4.5 (1) Something can exist only if it is a material thing. Therefore, (2) God does not exist. But (3) God is a material thing. In order to diagram an attack upon an inference a broken arrow is drawn from the counter-consideration (or objection) to the unbroken inference arrow. Diagram: (1) (3) (2) 110 Deep Diagramming: Reasons For and Against A heuristic for testing this approach is to assume (1) and (3) are true and then ask ourselves whether the support of (1) to (2) is weakened by (3). If the answer is yes then we have a successful attack upon the inference. Example 4.6 Alice: (1) Nearly all Singaporeans are Chinese. (2) Nora is Singaporean. So probably (3) Nora is Chinese. Diagram: (1) + (2) (3) This inference is inductively strong. But now suppose that Bob objects to Alice’s argument: Bob: But that can’t be right. (4) Nora is a Singaporean Muslim. (5) Nearly all Singaporean Muslims are not Chinese. Notice that the truth of (4)-plus-(5) does not reduce the likelihood that (1) is true. Nor does (4)-plus-(5) count against (2) or (3). So the principle of charity tells us that we should not see Bob as mounting an attack on Alice’s reason or her conclusion. However, assuming that (1) and (2) are true, the truth of (4)-plus-(5) will weaken the inference from (1)plus-(2) to (3). In fact, if (4) is true, this will weaken Alice’s inference greatly, turning it from a strong inference into a weak one. 111 Thinking Things Through: An Introduction to Analytical Skills Diagram: (1) + (2) (4) + (5) (3) In this book we will not deal with reasons for an inference, in other words, a reason given with the intention of strengthening an inference. This means that we will never draw a diagram such as Diagram: (1) (3) (2) How Do We Know What A Reason Attacks? Suppose that you are sure that a reason attacks part of an argument but you are not sure whether it attacks a reason, a conclusion or an inference. Our heuristic is: Suppose that the attacking reason is true. Does this make a reason in the argument attacked less likely to be true? If so then that reason is attacked. Suppose that the attacking reason is true. Does this make a conclusion in the argument attacked less likely to be true? If so then that conclusion is attacked. Suppose that the attacking reason is true and that a reason in the argument attacked is also true. Does the reason in the argument attacked now support the conclusion less strongly? If so then the inference from the reason in the argument attacked to its conclusion, is attacked. 112 Deep Diagramming: Reasons For and Against All-Out Assaults Typically, counter-considerations that attack the truth of reasons or the truth of conclusions or attacks upon inferences are themselves argued for and sometimes in great detail. One of the great benefits of learning how to diagram arguments is that when we start to deal with complex and long chains of reasoning (such as we might find in an article or book) we always know where we are and how we got there because diagramming itself charts the overall flow of reasoning in a transparent way. Let us see how we can apply this by building a longer piece of reasoning step by step. Consider the following short argument: Example 4.7 (1) If I buy a car then I’ll be able to drive from Singapore across the causeway and travel around Malaysia. (2) I have always wanted to visit the Taman Negara National park and (3) to view one of the last remaining pristine jungle environments in Asia. Therefore, (4) I should buy a car. Diagram: (1) + (2) + (3) (4) Let us suppose now that we want to attack the truth of proposition (1). For example, I might think that buying a car in Singapore is too expensive and if I buy a car I will not be able to do any traveling as I’ll need a second job to make the repayments on the car. So we can extract from these considerations two central reasons that attack the truth of ‘If 113 Thinking Things Through: An Introduction to Analytical Skills I buy a car I’ll be able to drive across the causeway and travel around Malaysia.’ They are: ‘Buying a car in Singapore is too expensive’ and ‘If I buy a car I will not be able to do much traveling anyway.’ Strictly speaking we do not have two reasons which oppose the truth of (1) but one reason against the truth of (1) which is itself backed up by a reason. Let us look at this carefully: Example 4.8 (1) If I buy a car then I’ll be able to drive from Singapore across the causeway and travel around Malaysia. (2) I have always wanted to visit the Taman Negara National park and (3) to view one of the last remaining pristine jungle environments in Asia. Therefore, (4) I should buy a car. On the other hand, (5) if I buy a car I will not be able to do much traveling because (6) I’ll need a second job to make the repayments because (7) buying a car is so expensive in Singapore. Diagram: (7) (6) (5) (1) + (2) + (3) (4) 114 Deep Diagramming: Reasons For and Against The attack upon the truth of (1) is represented diagrammatically by the broken inference arrow. Notice that we have a pattern of serial reasoning for proposition (5); while (5) itself directly attacks the truth of (1). Since propositions (1) + (2) + (3) are linked, reason (5) which directly attacks the truth of (1) also indirectly attacks the conjunction of reasons (1) + (2) + (3), because they need each other to support (4). So (5) attacks the support for (4). One could of course mount the attack on different grounds. One might suggest that even though it may well be true that if I buy a car then I’ll be able to drive from Singapore across the causeway and travel around Malaysia, the conclusion that I should buy a car doesn’t follow because I could hire a car to drive into Malaysia to see the National Park. Example 4.9 (1) If I buy a car then I’ll be able to drive from Singapore across the causeway and travel around Malaysia. (2) I have always wanted to visit the Taman Negara National park and (3) to view one of the last remaining pristine jungle environments in Asia. Therefore, (4) I should buy a car. On the other hand, (5) if I buy a car I’ll not be able to do much traveling because (6) I’ll need a second job to make the repayments because (7) buying a car is so expensive in Singapore. Then again, (8) I could always hire a car to drive into Malaysia. 115 Thinking Things Through: An Introduction to Analytical Skills Diagram: (7) (6) (5) (1) + (2) + (3) (8) (4) We might go even further and argue that I am prohibited by law from buying a car in Singapore. This directly attacks the truth of the conclusion, because being prohibited by law from buying a car is a good reason for not buying a car (assuming that I don’t want to break the law). Example 4.10 (1) If I buy a car then I’ll be able to drive from Singapore across the causeway and travel around Malaysia. (2) I have always wanted to visit the Taman Negara National park and (3) to view one of the last remaining pristine jungle environments in Asia. Therefore, (4) I should buy a car. On the other hand, (5) if I buy a car I’ll not be able to do much traveling because (6) I’ll need a second job to make the repayments because (7) buying a car is so expensive in Singapore. Then again, (8) I could always hire a car to drive into Malaysia. But as a matter of fact (9) I am prohibited by law from buying a car in Singapore. 116 Deep Diagramming: Reasons For and Against Diagram: (7) (6) (5) (1)+ (2) + (3) (8) (4) (9) 117 Thinking Things Through: An Introduction to Analytical Skills Extended Examples Let us look at two further examples to consolidate our understanding of what we have learned in this chapter. Example 4.11 (1) We must stop treating juveniles differently from adult offenders. (2) Justice demands it, since (3) justice implies that people should be treated equally. Besides, (4) the social effects of pampering juvenile offenders include sinister social consequences. (5) The record shows that juveniles who have been treated leniently for offences have subsequently committed serious crimes. Yet (6) it is also quite obvious that juveniles, unlike adults, lack some of the moral understanding necessary to see the consequences of their actions. Aside from that, (7) there is nothing in the concept of justice that insists on treating everybody equally. Diagram: (7) (3) (5) (2) (4) (6) (1) Having produced a diagram, we should now use it to evaluate the argument. This will include evaluating how well it holds up against the reasons that attack it. We would use the same methods explained in chapter 3. Consider reasons against reasons. The inference from the attacking reason against the reason attacked is weak if the truth of the 118 Deep Diagramming: Reasons For and Against attacking reason is largely irrelevant to the falsehood of the reason attacked. It is moderate if the truth of the attacking reason only makes the reason attacked more likely to be false than true, but not make it very likely to be false. It is strong if the truth of the attacking reason makes the reason attacked very likely to be false. It is 100% or in other words, valid, if the truth of the attacking reason makes it a certainty that the reason attacked is false. In such a case it is impossible for the reason attacked to be true if the attacking reason is true. The same goes for reasons against conclusions. How do we evaluate the strength of reasons against an inference? The inference from the attacking reason against the inference attacked is weak if the truth of the attacking reason has little or no effect in weakening the inference. The inference from the attacking reason against the inference attacked is moderate if the truth of the attacking reason makes the inference attacked moderate. The inference from the attacking reason against the inference attacked is strong if the truth of the attacking reason makes the inference attacked weak. The inference from the attacking reason against the inference attacked is 100% if the truth of the attacking reason makes the inference attacked have no strength at all. How strong is the inference from (3) to (2)? To answer this question, we must note the hanging pronoun ‘it’ in ‘justice demands it’ in (2). Demands what? (1) provides the answer—the full meaning of (2) is ‘Justice demands that we stop treating juveniles differently from adult offenders.’ This shows that we often need to look at other parts of the passage in order to read an assertion in its proper context. We may now see that the inference from (3) to (2) is 100%. If justice implies or in other words, demands, that people be treated equally, then it must be true that justice demands that we stop treating juveniles differently from adult offenders, because juveniles and adults are both people. The inference from (2) to (1) is also 100%, assuming that we care about justice. If justice demands that we stop treating juveniles differently 119 Thinking Things Through: An Introduction to Analytical Skills from adult offenders, then we must stop treating juveniles differently from adult offenders, assuming that we must do what justice demands of us. The strength of the attack upon (3) by (7) is 100%. If it is true that there is nothing in the concept of justice that insists on treating everybody equally, then it must be false that this is what justice implies. (7) is just an outright denial of (3). The inference from (5) to (4) is weak. We might allow that committing serious crimes is to be described as ‘sinister.’ We might even be charitable enough to allow that treating offenders leniently counts as ‘pampering.’ But to claim that the commission of serious crimes is an effect of treating offenders leniently is not supported by the fact that offenders who received lenient treatment subsequently committed serious crimes. Just because they first received lenient treatment and then committed serious crimes does little to show that lenient treatment is the cause of serious crime. This is the fallacy of ‘after this, so because of this.’ Perhaps the offenders of serious crime would have committed these crime whatever treatment they received. We need more evidence and this has not been supplied. The inference from (4) to (1) is also weak. In the context of (1), (4) tells us that juvenile offenders are treated leniently, while adult offenders are not. But while we are told that treating juvenile offenders leniently results in bad consequences for society, we are not told anything about the consequences of stricter treatment for adult offenders. For all we know, this might result in worse consequences for society. The inference also makes the deep background assumption that deciding how to treat offenders is a matter of looking at consequences. Not everyone will agree. Some will say that we should not do what has the best consequences if doing it is unjust. The author himself seems committed to this objection. The attack from (6) upon the inference from (4) to (1) is 100% given the background assumption that we should give more lenient treatment to offenders who are incapable of seeing the harm that they produce. Many, although by no means all, will agree with this assumption. 120 Deep Diagramming: Reasons For and Against Granting the background assumptions implicit in both the argument and in the objections to it, we may now add the evaluations to our diagram: Diagram: valid (7) (3) valid (2) valid (5) weak (4) weak (6) valid (1) We are now ready to attempt the difficult job of deciding what is true. We can see that trying to establish the truth of (1) on the basis of (4) is hopeless. Thus it is largely irrelevant whether (4) is true. For the same reason, (5) is largely irrelevant as well, because its role is to support (4), which is itself largely irrelevant. Of course none of this means that (1) is false, only that we have at this point, little reason to think that it is true. Our best hope of establishing that (1) is true is to look at (2). If (3) is true then (2) must be true, and if (2) is true then (1) must be true, assuming that we must do what justice demands of us. So if (3) is true then (1) must be true, assuming that we must do what justice demands of us. Is (3) true? It is at least plausible that justice implies that people should be treated equally. Indeed many will say that the idea of equality is part of meaning of justice. On this view of it (7) is false. But not everyone will be willing to grant the assumption that we must always do what justice demands of us. Utilitarians, in other words, those who think that we must always do whatever produces the best consequences in the long run, will be prepared to act unjustly if doing so has the best overall consequences. On the other side of the controversy, (1) is bound to be false if (7) is true, given the assumption that we should give more 121 Thinking Things Through: An Introduction to Analytical Skills lenient treatment to offenders who are incapable of seeing the harm that they produce. Is it true that juveniles, unlike adults, lack some of the moral understanding necessary to see the consequences of their actions? To decide this mater we might research the findings of developmental psychologists, but from a commonsense perspective it is surely true that as children develop into adulthood, they gain a greater appreciation of the effects of what they do. Example 4.12 (1) The eighteenth-century philosopher David Hume was undoubtedly a finer thinker than his even more celebrated successor Immanuel Kant. (2) Hume was by far the more lucid writer. (3) His contributions were more diverse than Kant's, for (4) he was a first-rate historian as well as a philosopher. Further, (5) Hume's ethical thought did not suffer from the rigidity of Kant's. (6) Hume, unlike Kant, would never have said the duty not to lie is so absolute that we should answer truthfully even when a wouldbe murderer asks where his intended victim is hiding. But this argument is nonsense. (7) Being a better writer does not mean you’re a better thinker. Moreover, (8) being a historian does not mean that you are a better philosopher. And finally, (9) being rigid could be one of the merits of a fine thinker, since (10) strictness is something to be cherished in philosophical thought. 122 Deep Diagramming: Reasons For and Against Diagram: (4) (6) (3) (5) (10) (8) (2) (7) (9) (1) First we evaluate the inferences. The inference from (4) to (3) is weak. Reading (3) in the context of (4), we may assume that Kant was a philosopher but not a historian. But the fact that Hume was both, does not itself give much support to the claim that Hume’s contributions were more diverse than Kant’s. For all we are told, Kant may have made contributions in fields other than history that Hume did not, such as mathematics or music. The inference from (3) to (1) is weak. The context of the (9) and (10) shows that ‘thinker’ in (1) is used to mean ‘philosopher.’ But as the objection in (8) shows, the fact that Hume’s contributions were more diverse than Kant’s in being a fine historian as well as a philosopher need not add anything to the quality of Hume’s philosophy. Since the truth of (8) would make the inference from (3) to (1) weak, (8) is a strong objection. Quite generally, just because a person makes contributions in many different disciplines is poor evidence that he excels in any particular one of them. The inference from (2) to (1) is at best moderate. All other things being equal, a philosopher who writes much more lucidly is better than one who does not. But all we are told, things might not be equal. Suppose that although Kant was much less lucid than Hume, he was also more profound, wider in scope, more rigorous, addressed more important questions, and changed the history of philosophy more dramatically. In that case we might well judge Kant a finer philosopher than Hume. The objection in (7) against the inference from (2) to (1) is strong. If it is true that being a 123 Thinking Things Through: An Introduction to Analytical Skills better writer does not make one a better philosopher then the fact that Hume is a better writer than Kant does not make him a better philosopher. Since the truth of (7) would make the inference from (2) to (1) weak, (7) is a strong objection. This of course is not to say that (7) is true. The inference from (6) to (5) is 100% or in other words, valid. To claim that we have a duty to refrain from lying in absolutely all circumstances is a perfectly rigid or inflexible view of the matter. Since Kant but not Hume makes this claim, it follows with certainty that Kant’s ethical thinking in this respect is rigid in a way that Hume’s is not. The inference from (5) to (1) is weak, because there is a missing connection between rigidity of thought and its quality. ‘Rigid’ sounds like a defect, but as the objection in (9) observes, this might not be so. Since the truth of (9) makes the inference from (5) to (1) weak, (9) is a strong objection. The inference from (10) to (9) may be seen as 100%, in other words, valid, if we supply the assumption that being rigid is a form of strictness. For if any form of strictness in philosophical thought is valuable and being rigid in philosophical thought is a form of strictness in philosophical thought, then it must be true that being rigid in philosophical thought is valuable. Granting any needed assumptions in the name of charity, we may add our evaluations to our diagram: 124 Deep Diagramming: Reasons For and Against Diagram: (4) (8) strong (2) moderate (7) strong weak (6) valid (3) weak weak (1) (10) valid (5) strong (9) Now we try to decide what is true. The prospects of establishing that (1) is true look dim. (3) or (5) offer little hope because even if they are true, there is little chance that truth will transmitted down to (1). The next best option is (2). Since the (7) is a strong objection to the inference from (2) to (1), if (7) is true then the inference will be weakened even more. But (7) is false. Surely all other things being equal, being a better writer does indeed make one a better philosopher. A good deal of philosophy consists not just in discussion, careful reading and reflection, but philosophical writing. The better the writing is, the clearer and more persuasive it will be, and this is surely a benefit. Nonetheless the inference from (2) to (1) remains moderate at best for reasons we have given above that are different from (7). Is (2) true? The best way to find out whether Hume was by far the more lucid writer would be to read both Kant and Hume. That would be an enormous amount of work and it would be difficult even for a trained philosopher. The next best option is to see whether there is a consensus on the matter by philosophers who are authorities on both philosophers. In fact such philosophers will all agree that whereas Hume is clear, Kant is notoriously obscure. So in the last analysis, if we were forced at the point of a gun to bet the final conclusion, we should think that it is true, but we certainly should not place any confidence in it being true that we may derive from the argument. Note by the way that once our 125 Thinking Things Through: An Introduction to Analytical Skills diagram was fully evaluated, we did not need to try to decide whether every proposition in it is true. To make a point we have made elsewhere, thinking things through often saves us work. 126