Uploaded by szczepan.wasiluk

The Ethical Implications of Commodifying Emotional Labor

advertisement
Szymon Amałowicz
The Ethical Implications of Commodifying Emotional Labor
In modern society, work culture often requires employees to behave in a certain way while
interacting with co-workers or clients of the company. Many job listings include “positive
attitude” or “being hospitable” requirements from the candidate, especially if the position will
be working directly with customers. The phenomenon when workers must manage their
emotions to fulfill their job requirements, either by suppressing their feelings or expressing
false ones is called emotional labor (Hochschild, 1983). This is particularly visible in serviceoriented industries like hospitality, social work, media, or childcare. Emotional labor raises
concerns about the commodification of personal feelings, which may have a significant impact
on perceiving the authenticity of human interactions as well as on the psychological well-being
of workers. The commodification of emotional labor presents significant ethical challenges,
examined through arguments of coercion and corruption.
Michel Sandel refers to coercion in the context of commodification as a situation when market
transactions that may look voluntary are made with an unequal balance of power (Sandel,
2012). In the commodification of emotional labor, coercion manifests clearly when workers
are directly or indirectly asked to manipulate their emotions to fulfill the customers’ demands,
irrespective of their true feelings. Since the balance of power between the employer and the
employee is usually unequal to the benefit of the first one, even if one employee decides not
to conform to those requirements, he would just be replaced with another one willing to do
it because of the overall high supply of workers given demand. An illustrative example of this
can be found in the hospitality industry. The study by Grandey (2000) highlights how customer
service employees are compelled to maintain a façade of cheerfulness, despite personal
discomfort or emotional distress. This not only abuses workers' right to emotional autonomy
but also imposes an expectation to constantly perform emotional labor as a part of a job
requirement. Such occurrence clearly shows external coercion where people are forced to
surpass or fabricate their emotions for monetary compensation. This may lead to an
emotional dissonance where a person experiences opposite emotions to the ones expressed,
leading to potential burnout and psychological problems in the long run. It is worth noting
that this kind of coercion is hidden under the unequal employer-employee power dynamics,
which is part of a larger issue. This leads to a question of whether such kind of coercion can
be perceived as directly resulting from the emotional labor commodification or from the
external power imbalance that would have existed without emotional labor. The origins of
coercion, however, do not change the fact that it exists in correlation with emotional labor.
The corruption argument refers to markets expanding into areas earlier ruled by non-market
norms. When goods that have unmeasurable, non-monetary value are given a tangible price
tag, their intrinsic value eventually becomes completely repressed (Sandel, 2012). In service
jobs, where employees are expected to show false emotions and suppress genuine ones, the
authenticity of human feelings is reduced. The commodification transforms genuine emotions
into tradable goods which are used to the benefit of companies using emotional labor. The
most important consequence of this is the change in workers’ perception of their own
emotions. When employees display emotions opposite to their true feelings, it can lead to a
Szymon Amałowicz
sense of separation from their own emotional experiences. The requirement to continuously
manage and manipulate emotions for commercial purposes can eventually lead to a severe
mental problem with expressing true emotions. The commodification of emotional labor can
also have a broader impact on the whole society. As the authenticity of human emotions is
questioned by an increasing number of people, this may affect how individuals relate to each
other in all social situations.
The moral evaluation of commodification can be challenging. One primary concern with
condemning it outright is that employees consent to perform these jobs, often having
specialized in this field previously, usually aware of the emotional labor involved. Even if their
consent is under some form of coercion, they typically know the job's requirements.
Employees have the option to choose employment in different environments that do not
demand emotional labor. If they are properly informed about the potential consequences to
their psychological well-being before engaging in such work, then, according to the Common
Law doctrine of 'Volenti non fit iniuria,' it should be permissible. The coercion argument is not
completely decisive, because the degree of coercion is moderate and comes from the external
dynamic of employer–employee relations. Another consideration is the extent of emotional
labor expected from employees relative to their salary. Fair compensation should be set by
the regulatory body, particularly when the job could risk an employee's psychological health.
In my opinion, if the governments were to mandate minimum bonus requirements for jobs
that include emotional labor, then the issue would be addressed fairly.
The argument for corruption, on the other hand, is more convincing. The degradation of the
value of emotions is a serious issue and should not be disregarded. If emotional labor is fully
permitted and not regulated, then the intrinsic value of human emotions may be replaced
with the monetary one. It shows the importance of protecting the intrinsic value of human
emotions and interactions. It risks creating a culture where emotions are seen primarily in
terms of their economic utility, rather than as fundamental aspects of human experience and
connection. Implementing regulations preventing employees from being expected too much
emotional labor and educating society about it and the intrinsic value of emotions can be seen
as the most appropriate solutions to this issue.
In summary, I believe that emotional labor should be permitted as it is not completely
destructive and immoral. However, it should be heavily regulated to compensate for the
coercion and health risks to employees performing it. Society should be educated about the
intrinsic value of human emotions in the early stages of education which will allow many
people to acknowledge it and not allow it to be traded for money in the future.
Szymon Amałowicz
Bibliography
Grandey, A. (2000). Emotion regulation in the workplace: A new way to conceptualize
emotional labor. Journal of Occupational Health Psychology, 5(1), 95-110.
Hochschild, A. R. (1983). The Managed Heart: Commercialization of Human Feeling. University
of California Press.
Sandel, M. J. (2012). What Money Can't Buy: The Moral Limits of Markets. Farrar, Straus and
Giroux.
Download