Uploaded by Jahnavi Ramesh

BoE 02 (1)

advertisement
Basics of Ethics-1
Lecture 2
Course structure
Topics:
–
Ethics and critical reasoning, argument analysis
–
Moral skepticism
–
Goodness and Value
–
Consequentialism
–
Non-consequentialism
–
Virtue ethics
–
Engineering ethics, Moral responsibility
Add
●
Capuchin monkeys
●
Divine command theory
–
●
Socrates and Euthyphro
What makes a problem moral
Morality in Monkeys?
●
Capuchin Monkeys Reject Unequal Pay
–
https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=meiU6TxysCg
●
Wrongness vs. Consequences
●
Ponder then:
–
Is there a sense of the ‘moral’ in the monkeys?
–
What does ‘wrongness’ capture over and above its
consequences?
Some deflationary theories: The hard
porblem
●
●
How could we ever see an ethical fact? When I attribute
goodness to an action or state of affairs, is there any
sense in the idea that I might perceive this goodness, as
I perceive the color of an object or its shape?
Ethical properties are not ordinary “natural” properties
of things, that you can see and touch; so what are they?
Is it perhaps wrong to think of moral words as denoting
properties of things at all? Maybe they have another
function entirely; if so, what might it be?
Deflationary solutions: Emotivism
Emotivism supposes that moral words serve merely to express emotions, rather than to
describe external facts
●
like saying “Boo!” and “Hurrah!”
–
Thus when I describe an action as good or right I am not attributing any real property to it;
●
I am simply expressing my approval of it.
–
●
●
●
There are no “moral facts” that might make an object of genuine moral knowledge; there
are just moral feelings that we express in words.
According to a similar view, moral language serves to prescribe courses of action rather
than to describe facts: if I call something good I am simply saying that everyone ought to
act that way, not ascribing some peculiar imperceptible property to it.
Moral statements are no more true or false than “Hurrah!” or “Love thy neighbor!”; indeed,
they are not really genuine statements.
–
They express emotions or prescribe actions, rather than state facts
Opposing view: Moral Realism
●
ethics is best conceived as a branch of a priori
knowledge:
–
●
when I come to know that stealing is wrong my knowledge is
based on a kind of direct intuition into the moral facts—just
like my knowledge of mathematical and logical truth.
I know just from the concept of stealing that stealing is
wrong; and similarly for murder and rape. Like other
kinds of a priori knowledge, ethical knowledge is not
derived from experience—in the sense that my senses
can detect the ethical properties of things.
Realism vs. Relativism
Emotivism as relativism (non-cognitivism)
●
–
No moral facts, only emotion and its expression
–
Emotions may be subjective
–
No moral facts out there
Moral Realism (cognitivism)
●
–
Moral knowledge can be objective
Ethics is best conceived as a branch of a priori knowledge: when I come to know that
stealing is wrong my knowledge is based on a kind of direct intuition into the moral
facts—just like my knowledge of mathematical and logical truth.
●
–
I know just from the concept of stealing that stealing is wrong; and similarly for murder and rape.
–
Like other kinds of a priori knowledge, ethical knowledge is not derived from experience—in
the sense that my senses can detect the ethical properties of things.
●
Immanuel Kant’s “Starry heavens above and the moral law within”!
Problems
●
No room for deliberation on emotions and moral
tastes
●
No room for praise or blame
●
No scope for moral responsibility
●
No scope for reason to motivate actions
–
Hume: reason is a slave to passion!
Divine Command Theory
●
●
An act is morally required just because it is
commanded by God, and immoral just because God
forbids it.
God is the source of morality
–
The reason murder, lying, adultery, are all wrong
(immoral) is because God commands and thereby
decrees that it is wrong
Exposing the fallacy of the argument
●
Socrates does this 2500 years ago
–
●
●
In Plato’s dialogue, Euthyphro
The setting:
–
Euthyphro is prosecuting his own father for having killed one
of the family’s servants.
–
Socrates sees him and asks how come he is testifying against
his own father.
–
Euthyphro replies that he is being pious and obeying the Gods
Socrates then wants to know what ‘piety’ consists in
What is Piety?
●
●
●
●
But when Euthyphro gives his definition of piety, Socrates is disappointed.
“To do as I am doing,” Euthyphro says, “prosecuting the impious.”
Socrates points out that although prosecuting the impious is certainly an
example of a pious action, there are obviously other kinds of pious
actions. Socrates wants to know what all (and only) pious actions have in
common that makes them pious.
Euthyphro says, “There are things that all the gods agree on. That must be
what makes something pious: being loved by all the gods.” Certainly this
is something that all and only pious actions have in common, Socrates
points out, but is that what makes them pious?
In other words, the gods love pious actions because they are pious; those
actions are not pious because the gods love them.
Deflating the argument
●
●
God’s commanding something is not what makes it
moral; rather, God commands things because they
are moral—because he recognizes something about
them that makes them good
Some people think that morality can only be binding
if God is at the root of it; without God it is a moral
free-for-all. Thus the reason murder is wrong is
just that God has commanded us not to murder
—he decrees that it is wrong.
●
The trouble with this position, as was pointed out by Plato over two thousand
years ago, is that it gets things backwards:
it is not that murder is wrong because God commands us not to
murder; it is rather that God commands us not to murder because
murder is wrong.
– God cannot simply by decree make murder wrong, any more than he
can make it right; if he could morality would be arbitrary and pointless.
Murder is wrong because of what it is, not because God has decided to declare
it wrong. God is not the source of moral truth—though He may be
responsible for rewards and punishments for your actions. But then, if God
cannot be the logical basis of morality, there is no necessity for God to exist
in order that morality has force: murder is still wrong even if there is no
God.
–
●
Laundry list of conditions
●
those who seek divine guidance in trying to lead a moral life
may succeed. But several conditions must be met. It must be
the case that
–
(1) God exists, and that we can be justified in believing this.
–
(2) Theists must be justified in selecting a particular source of
religious and moral wisdom, such as the Koran, the Book of
Mormon, or the Christian scriptures.
–
Theists must also (3) defend specific interpretations of those sources.
–
Finally, when an interpretation conflicts with tradition, religious
believers must (4) successfully argue for the priority of one over the
other.
Watch/Listen
●
●
Watch
–
The Great Hack
–
Human Nature
–
We Need to Talk About AI
–
The Bleeding Edge
–
Coded Bias
Listen
–
Examining Ethics
–
Ethics of AI in Context
–
Land of the Giants
Read:
●
●
Russ Shafer-Landau, Living Ethics: An Introduction
with Readings (2018)
Dean A Kowalski, Moral theory at the movies: An
Introduction to Ethics (2012)
Download