Phan 1 Sam Phan Professor Tucker English 205 3 April 2023 The Cost of Freedom Freedom is a word that is often one of, if not, the first values associated with the great nation of the United States. This only makes sense when one considers that America was essentially founded upon the original colonies’ vehement yearning for freedom—for independence—from their British progenitors. However, multitudes of peaceful solutions passed to no avail; it appeared only one recourse remained for the American founding fathers. Thomas Jefferson’s Declaration of Independence is a letter not only against the stranglehold of the British Crown but against the oppression of freedom of all forms in which it may have manifested. More than just a simple letter, however, this document and the words laid on it heralded hostile actions that changed the course of history forever. America followed down the warring path and forsook any of peace, all seemingly to achieve a peace of their own. This ostensibly contradictory approach boils down to one controversial question: do the ends justify the means? Machiavelli, infamous for his cynical and mercenary perspective on matters of ruling and governance, believes they do: “for in order to maintain the state he (the prince) is often obliged to act against his promise, against charity, against humanity, and against religion” (Machiavelli par. 23). Examining the Declaration under a Machiavellian lens provides deeper insight into the minds of both Jefferson and Machiavelli, as well as creates an interesting discourse about the nature of freedom as it pertains to social order. To understand how the Declaration may invoke Machivelli’s ideas in its writing, one must begin to analyze the document’s argument. More specifically, how the Declaration asserts Phan 2 that the means of rebellion is absolutely redeemable to achieve the ends of independence. I believe this is laid out most transparently in the second paragraph: “That whenever any Form of Government becomes destructive of these ends, it is the Right of the People to alter or to abolish it, and to institute new Government,” (Jefferson). Although Jefferson does not make any mention of how the people ought to proceed with the alteration or abolishment of a defective government, he clearly promotes those outcomes and deems them desirable. Applying Machiavelli’s framework to this statement, one can interpret the lack of specific instructions to connote Jefferson’s full commitment toward independence, or in other words, his readiness to violate the virtue of peace for the sake of ideal independence. It is reasonable to assume that Jefferson and his fellow founding fathers were privy to the procedures and consequences of rebellion. Therefore, when rephrased from this standpoint, a Machiavellian aspect of the Declaration is revealed. While reading through the document finds no explicit intention of waging war per se, it is crucial to remember the document’s purpose and its contents, particularly the numerous causes listed throughout the lines. The Declaration of Independence is written, as suggested by its title and first paragraph, to explain to American citizens and the rest of the world why the colonies benefit from the rejection of the British Crown and its forces: “decent respect to the opinions of mankind requires that they should declare the causes which impel them to the separation” (Jefferson). The document’s length itself primarily comprises the enumeration of iniquities committed by British personnel unto the early citizens of the United States of America. From this, one can infer that the authoring nation seeks no absolution for its decision; it is unapologetic, opting for a subtly hostile, albeit elegant and classy tone. Jefferson and his brethren intend to wholly see their way toward the ultimate goal of independence, even if it means Phan 3 overcoming the pain and turbulence of rebellion, and their words in the Declaration reflect this ambition. Jefferson and his colleagues clearly advocated against the abuses of the British government, stating their clear desire for independence within the Declaration. As previously mentioned one can certainly ascertain a degree of acceptance of the likely horrific procedure and acts of rebellion from the author. However, it is still ambiguous as to whether or not Jefferson does wholeheartedly believe that the processes of rebellion, including war, civil disorder, and death, are justifiable via the end of independence. An inference can be derived by comparing the texts of the Declaration of Independence and Machiavelli’s The Qualities of the Prince, which theoretically reflect both of their authors’ characters. One notable difference is within how both texts view integrity and honesty. Jefferson introduces the Declaration with the intention of appealing to the natural goodness within humans and explains the reason for his writing’s existence (par. 1). Whereas Machiavelli quite explicitly advocates the opposite: “the princes who have accomplished great deeds are those who have cared little for keeping their promises and who have known to manipulate the minds of men by shrewdness,” (par. 19). There is a lucid disconnect behind the morality of both of these thinkers. One maintains it; the other forgoes it. Another point of difference falls upon the topic of religion. The Declaration invokes notions of faith, while The Qualities of the Prince remains relatively secular, even recommending the Prince consider sinful behavior. Still, it is not as if these two do not share any commonalities. One subtle common trait lies in how both authors define a government’s role to its people. In essence, both believe that a government serves to protect its people and their well-being. This is evident in the opening lines of the Declaration and the emphasis on military prowess in The Prince. One can summarize that both Jefferson and Machiavelli share in what a government’s Phan 4 purpose is, but differ in how it ought to achieve said purpose. After examination, it is logical to conclude that had Jefferson been offered Machiavelli’s advice, as written in The Prince, Jefferson would have certainly disregarded a decent chunk of his guidance on grounds of moral infringement. It is also crucial to weigh evils in one’s justification. One can reasonably surmise that although Jefferson does not condone the means of rebellion, he justifies them as a lesser of two evils; the other being a concession of independence. Jefferson was a right-minded man, but drastic times call for drastic measures. Rebellion is not so much a cause as it is a symptom of hard times, and hard times they were for the young colonies which Jefferson called home. Briefly, I preface that I make no claim that rebellion was the definitively correct or incorrect choice available in this context; my argument solely pertains to the definition of morality within this specific context. Rebellion is seldom a peaceful process, more often associated with violent excursions and a certain French historical movement as opposed to any peaceful imagery. Rebellion bears such a violent connotation that non-violent acts aiming to achieve the same effects are categorized with entirely different terms, such as civil disobedience. It can be reasonably said that rebellion is by no means a moral or virtuous course of action. However, an argument arises surrounding a rebellion's long-term impacts: is it not morally acceptable, or even good, for rebellion to improve the state and the lives of its people? This question is difficult because of the nature of morality as a concept; I believe that moral values vary from person to person, meaning that morality becomes subjective. With this in mind, I pose a new question, a rephrased derivative of the aforementioned argument: would it be moral to dismiss the option of rebellion and concede to British oppression a people’s happiness and posterity? Worded as such, I assert that it would be immoral for Jefferson, and the other figureheads of the original colonies, to have remained expendable subjects in the eyes of the Phan 5 British government, and that the ends justify the means. Consider the Declaration’s implications on the function of government: Governments are instituted among Men, deriving their just powers from the consent of the governed… it is the Right of the People to alter or to abolish it, and to institute new Government, laying its foundation on such principles and organizing its powers in such form, as to them shall seem most likely to effect their Safety and Happiness. (Jefferson par. 2) There are two key takeaways in this statement: (1) governments rely on the consent of the subjects over which they rule and (2) governments serve to maintain and preserve the people’s security and well-being, among a host of other values such as freedom. What the British government was historically doing unto the colonies violates these two ideas, and as such, incited actions against the injustices which Jefferson and his fellow colleagues perceived. I believe it would have been unjustifiable, or immoral, had they remained complicit. One may argue that the death and bloodshed involved with rebellion are counterintuitive to these very values and that there are fewer macabre tragedies without rebellion. However, complicity does not compel change, and eternity under such circumstances only leads to more injustice and mistreatment. Rebellion, while grim up front, is an out to this endless suffering. I believe that life comprises the experiences and choices any individual undertakes and makes, which relates to the concept of freedom in a sense. Given that a rebellion does provide freedom in a society that locks it away, I stand that the means of rebellion, in all of its horrific potential, can be justified by the ends of independence, for a life without control—without independence—is not a life at all. Lastly, on a quick note, this discussion on independence as a justification for certain actions raises an interesting point. Independence and freedom are seemingly contradictory to Phan 6 social order. Every rule or law is one more chain against a people, and one action made in the name of freedom may cause chaos. Note that these facets are not binary but rather exist on a spectrum. Successful governments do not opt for one over the other but tread fine lines to balance them out. It is then beautifully apt that the path of rebellion, a considerably chaotic approach, is taken to reforge and reform an institution to arbitrate and legislate. In conclusion, Jefferson’s Declaration of Independence marks a shift in early American history—a moment when independence was forever engraved into this country’s values and foundation. Independence, however, comes at a cost. A cost of partial humanity expended for the sake of preserving what little remained of it and the dignity that remained of the young colonies. Left with few options, the choice became clear and Jefferson birthed a document that has since been echoed against tyranny for its elegance and eloquence. Unlike Machiavelli, Jefferson placed faith in the people to better the government and that is what makes this document and discussion special. Actions that invite inhumane consequences do not pardon nor permiss inhumanity. That is to say that it is important to try to remain virtuous and good in the face of perils that endanger and exploit such virtues. With the right combination of intent and circumstance, one can most certainly admit that the ends do justify the means. The young colonies of America knew this, and it is an important lesson that the people of today know when or when not to employ the same. Phan 7 Works Cited Machiavelli, Niccolò. The Prince. Translated by George Bull, Penguin Classics, 2003.