See discussions, stats, and author profiles for this publication at: https://www.researchgate.net/publication/229940901 Cognitive‐Behavioural Theory: An Alternative Conception Article in Australian Psychologist · February 2011 DOI: 10.1080/00050069308258894 CITATIONS READS 4 7,980 1 author: Jack James Reykjavik University 173 PUBLICATIONS 4,028 CITATIONS SEE PROFILE Some of the authors of this publication are also working on these related projects: Individual differences in cardiovascular stress reactivity and adaptation View project Caffeine View project All content following this page was uploaded by Jack James on 21 October 2014. The user has requested enhancement of the downloaded file. 151 Cognitive-Behavioural Theory: An Alternative Conception Jack E. James La Trobe UniversiU The present paper aims to show that mainstream cognitive and cognitive-behavioural theories are funda- mentally flawed, and should be discarded in favour of a behavioural explanation of the relationship behveen cognition and behaviour. The essence of this behavioural explanation of cognitive control is the distinction between contingency-shaped and rule-govemed behaviour. The former occurs when consequences are experienced directly, whereas the latter influences perceived consequences. Cognitive events, including thoughts, expectations, beliefs, and images, function as rules that encode relevant contingencies of reinforcement. In turn, rules serve as potent cognitive discriminative stimuli that profoundly influence cunent and future behaviour. The concerted effort to develop "cognitive" aliernatives to pre- Specifically, the present aim is to show that cognitive- viously established "behavioural" principles and practice has undoubtedly been the most striking feature of psychotherapy behavioural explanations of the relationship befween subjective experience and overt behaviour are fundamentally flawed, and should be discarded in favour of extant behavioural theory which holds that cognitive events function as discriminative stimuli. research over the past 2 decades. Evidence of these endeavours is readily apparent in mainstream clinical journals such as Behavior Therapy, Behaviour Research and Therapy, and the Journal of Consulting and Clinical Psychology, where it can be seen that "cognitive-behaviourai" has replaced "behavioural" as the favoured treatment modality among psychotherapy investigators. The ascendancy of cognitive-behaviour therapy is also evident in the establishment of new institutjons (e.g., the journal Cognitive Therapy and Research), and in changes to the formal structures of existing institutions capable of influencing the future direction of psychotherapy research. For example, on advice from the COGNITION A]\'D HUIVIAN BEHAVIOUR As the name implies, cognitive-behavioural theories have attempted to extend the explanatory power of the behavioural theory that preceded them. These attempts have found a responsive audience. Psychotherapists and consumers of psychotherapy Iiterature seem to have embraced each new cognitive reformula- tion of behavioural principles with unbridled enthusiasm. Publications Committee, Behavior Therapy, which formerly published original research on "behavior therapy or behavior modifi- According to one commentary, there now exist at least 20 distinct varieties of cognitive therapy (Mahoney & Lyddon, 1988), and the "cognitive revolution" in psychotherapy continues unabated. While there are undoubtedly many reasons why a particular cation", is now "devoted to the application of behavioral and approach to therapy wins favour over competitors.(e.g., cognitive sciences to clinical problems" (Craighead, 1990, p. i). Proponents of cognitive-behavjour therapy assert that the underlying theory has provided new insights into fundamental relationships between mental processes and behaviour. If this were true, we *'ould exp€ct, by now, to have witnessed new and original therapies based on the puqported advances in understanding. However, early scepticism (e.g., kdwidge, i978; Miller & Berman, 1983; Shapiro & Shapiro, 1982) as to whether the cognitive-behavioural approach has indeed produced original interventions, or even succeeded in enhancing the efficacy of existing behavioural interventions, has persisted (e.g., Berman, Miller, & Massman, 1985; Biglan, 1987; Eysenck, 1988; Rachlin, 1988). This is not to question the efficacy of cognitive-behaviour thera- l,edwidge, 1978), the success of the cognitive-behavioural movement is attributable in part to two popular misconceptions. The first of these concerns the supposed limitations of behavioural theory in explaining the role of cognitive events, while the second concerns the presumed adequacy of cognitive-behavioural theory in explaining the role of cognitive processes in human Association for the Advancement of Behavior Therapy py per se. There is widespread agreement that cognitivebehaviour therapy is comparatively effective in the treatment of a number of common psychological disorders (e.g., depression, panic disorder). Thus, while issues such as innovation in therapy and the relative efficacy of alternative therapies are important, they are not the subject of the present paper. Virtually all psychotherapies possess a theoretical foundation upon which the defining charac- teristics of the approach are said to be based. Cognitive- behavioural theory attempts to explain the relationship between subjective experience (including cognition and affect) and overt behaviour (whether disordered or "normal"). The present paper questions mainstreamtognitive-behavioural theory, rather than the practices that characterise cognitive-behaviour therapy. behaviour, B e havioural T he o ry : Radical B e haviouris m Regarding the supposed limitations of behavioural theory, cog- nitive-behaviourists erroneously believe that',traditionai'i behavioural theory (especially radical behaviourism) either denies the existence of cognition, or is incapable of accommodating it within an overall explanation of human action. In part, these misconceptions may be due to confusion between the behavioural principles espoused by J.B. Watson and those of B.F. Skinner (Zettle & Hayes, 1982). In contrast to Watson and a number of other prominent exponents of behaviourism, Skinner was insistent about the necessity to explain the role of cognitive processes in human behaviour. He wrote extensively on the subject. However, as he himself acknowledged (e .g., Skinner, 1972), much of what he wrote about cognitive proc€sses appears not to have been read, much less understood. For example, about half of the text of Skinner's (1969) book, Contingencies of reinforcement: A theoretical analysis, was concerned with subjective experience, and he lamented the fact that this aspect of human behaviour has not received sufficient atten- The present article is based on a paper delivered as part of the Division of Scientific Affairs Symposium, Burhus Frederic Skrnner, 1904-1990: Sone reflections on his contribution to the disciptine of psychology (Convener; Professor Boris Crassini), Australian Psychological Society's Twenty.Sixth Annual Conference, Adelaide, 29 Seotember - 4 October 1991. Thanks to Drifa Hardardottir, Elizabeth Gregg, and Jay Birnbrauer for their helpful comments on earlier drafts of this paper. Requests for reprints should be sent to Professor Jack E. James, Department of Behavioural Health Sciences, La Trobe University, Bundoora ViC 3083 Australia. Australian Psychologist Vol. 28, No. 3, 1993 pp. l5l-155 152 Jack E. James tion from other behaviourists. He argued that whenever behaviourists of essentially unreplicated laboratory findings. Certainly, Bandura's (7969, 1977a) treatment of observational learning is excluded sensations, images, thought processes, and so on, from Iargely speculative. their deliberations ... the charge isjustified that they have neglected the facts of consciousness. The strategy is, however, quite unwise. It is particularly important that a science of behaviour face the prob-' lem of privacy. (Skinner, 1969, pp.227-228) Despite a dearth of relevant empirical evidence, Bandura's (7969, 1977a) claims for the extent and potency of observational leaming appear to have been widely accepted. In the absence of empirical evidence, Bandura (1917a) has cited examples of complex, integrated human skills, including playing golf, writing prose, and driving a car as illustrations of the potency of symbolic processes in general and observational learning in particular. Yet these same examples can be used to demonstrate the exact opposite the limited potency of observational leaming. - that is, Of these various examples, driving a car provides a good illustrative case in point. Bandura (1977a) has asserted explicitly that By privacy, Skinner meant subjective experience in general, including cognition and affect. While Skinner (1969) acknowledged the role of physiology when he wrote that an "adequate science of behaviour must consider events taking place within the skin of the organism" (p. 228), he gave particular attention to subjective human experiences such as thoughts, sensations, and images. Furthermore, Skinner (1969) criticised what became the popu- lar doctrine of so-called methodological behaviourism which argued for the exclusion of private events from scientific psychology because such events cannot be observed directly. Skinner argued that distinctions involving internal-external and public-private dimensions are arbitrary and artificial. His position was that, nofwithstanding the.ir private nature, cognitive processes are an essential aspect of human behaviour, and must therefore be accommodated within scientific psychology. The question, then, is not whether, but how subjective experience is accommodated within the framework of operant psychology. Before considering this question, we should first examine the second misconception alluded to above, rvhich concerns the supposed adequacy with *'hich subjective experience is explained by cognitive-behavioural theory. Role of Cognition: Social Learning Theory Although the following remarks deal specifically with social leaming theory (Bandura, 1969, 1977a), the same general arguments can be applied to cognitive and cognitive-behavioural theories broadly (e.g., Beck, Rush, Shaw, & Emery, i979; Ellis & Harper, 1975; Meichenbaum, 1977). Special attention is given to social leaming theory, because it has been particularly influential in determining the nature and development of cognitivebehavioural psychotherapy. According to one account of the his- tory of cognitive therapy, social learning theory "offered a revolutionary conception of human change processes [suggesting] that learning can occur entirely as a function of cognitive control" (Mahoney & Lyddon, 1988, p. 196, italics in original). Moreover, social learning theory is, according to Bandura (1,977a), "a unified theoretical framework for analyzing human thought and behaviour" (p. vi). The pivotal concept in social learning theory is "vicarious" learning, variously labelled symbolic learning, modelling, or obsertational learning. Empirical studies of observational learning during the 1960s (Bandura, Blanchard, & Ritter, 1969; Bandura, Grusec, & Menlove, 1967; Bandura, Ross, & Ross, 1963) provided a major empirical impe- tus to the development of social learning theory, to which Bandura (1969,1977a) has continued to be the major contributor. However, Bandura's representation of observalional learning is fundamentally flawed. Consequently, his account of cognitive processes is untenable. Observational learning. Central to understanding the deficiencies in Bandura's (1969, 1,977a) theoretical account of observational learning is his insistence that it is the most potent form of human learning. He has claimed that "most human behaviour is learned observationally through modeling" (Bandura, 1.977a, p. 22), and that "modeling serves as the principal mode of transmitting new forms of behaviour" (Bandu ra, 1977a, p, 54), Moreover, according to Baniura (1977a), "the capacity to iearn by observa- tion enables people to acquire large, integrated patterns of behaviour without having to form them gradually by tedious triai and error" (p. 12).Unfortunately, these claims lack supportive empirical evidence. Although observational learning has been demonstrated empirically, studies have been few in number and have mostly involved circumscribed events in the laboratory. To the extent that social learning theorists have drawn on empirical evidence, they have done so by way of elaborate generalisations Australian Psychologist Vol. 28, No. 3, 1993 pp. 151-155 skilled driving is primarily acquired through observation. However, while observation is surely involved in the process of learning to drive, it can be shown that observation is not the key element in the acquisition process. Prior to actually learning to drive, virtually everyone will have experienced many hundreds (possibly many thousands) of hours observing other people drive. Why is it that when we sit behind the wheel for the first time, we are far from capable of executing a smooth take-off involving change of gears, accurate steering, coordinated use of the foot pedals, to name just a few of the tasks that constitute driving a car? The fact is that contrary to Bandura's (1969, 1977a) assertion, the acquisition of driving skills is very much dependent on direct rather than vicarious experience. Observation actually plays a minor (often trivial) role in the acquisition of skills. The first time any of us sat behind the rvheel of a car, no doubt we were capable of orienting ourselves in a manner that was essentially accurate. That is, we probably sat facing towards the bonnet of the car, w.ith hands on the wheel, feet near the foot pedals, and so on. If we had never seen anyone drive a car before, it is unlikely that we would have known to do this at the outset. So, observation has contributed somethins. However, it is obvious that these initial orienting behaviours aie actually very minor variants of behaviours that were already part of our behavioural repertoire. That is, by the time most people come to learn to drive a car, they have already learned how to sit, to orient themselves in a forward position, and to position their hands and feet. This example, then, illustrates a fundamental limitation of observational experience. Observing others encourages the application of skills already learned through direct experience, but to apply them in different circurnstances (e.g., sitting behind the wheel of a car as distinct from say sitting at a table). Contrary to Bandura's claims, observational processes contribute little to the acquisition of complex patterns of behaviour (where, by definition, complex means substantially beyond the person's current expertise). If a new behaviour is encouraged through observation, it typically involves a slight modification of preexisting patterns rather than the acquisition of "large, integrated" patterns, Thus, the unique aspects of driving are learned, not tfuough observation, but through direct experience. Crunching gears is aversive and gradually decreases in frequency, whereas smooth gear changes are reinforced. The same is true of the other examples cited by Bandura (1977a), such as playing golf and writing prose, as it is for skilled behaviour in general. In summary, skilled behaviour (and this includes most of the observable behaviour of normally functioning humans) develops primarily out of direct experience. It is "contingency-shaped',, whereby successively closer approximations are differentially reinforced. The contribution of observation (modelling, vicarious experience) to skill acquisition is that it may facilitate the performance of responses already acquired through direct experience. Notwithstanding the limited role of modelling in the acquisition of contingency-shaped behaviour, observational experience is a key factor in the development of "rule-governed" behaviour (described below). Moreover, acknowledgment of the facilitative role of observation raises a question as to how its influence (how- ever slight) should be e.xplained. For more than 20 years, Bandura (1969,1977a) has argued that observational learning is a ' Cognitions as Discriminative unique, all-embracing process. In fact, despite general acceptance of the term observalional learning, modelling is not a learning process per se. When present, observation functions as an adjunct to leaming, and is easily accommodated by behavioural theory without the embellishments invented by Bandura (1969, 1977a) and other cognitive-behavioural theorists. and its environment must always specify three things: (1) the occasion upon which a response occurs, (2) the response itselt and (3) the reinforcing consequences. The interrelationships among them are the 'contingencies of reinforcement'. (p. 7) Thus, contingencies of reinforcement incorporate discriminative stimuli, responses, and reinforcing consequences. This tripartite conceptualisation has given rise to the so-called "ABCs" of behaviour analysis to symbolise the component elements of antecedents, behaviour, and consequences. The component of the three-term contingency of particular interest in the present context is that rvhich refers to antecedent conditions. In Skinner's (1969) words, "Any stimulus present when an operant is reinforced acquires control in the sense that the rate will be higher when it is present" (p. 7). These predisposing aspects of the environment, these discriminative stimuli, are said to "set the occasion" for behaviour. The literature on operant conditioning has tended to emphasise the role of consequences, sometimes to the neglect of the role of discriminative stimuli. This is unfortunate. because it is often discriminative-stimulus control that best informs us about the more subtle aspects of human behaviour. The role of discriminative stimuli in the learning process allows for the establishment of much more complex relationships than would be possible if learning merely included responses and their consequences. In many (a) e d v ersus Rule - gov ern ed B e haviour Behaviour that results in directly experienced (or acua[) consequences is refened to as contingency-shaped behaviour. On the other hand, behaviour that is influenced throughperceived consequences, rathei than actual consequences, is said to be rule-governed (Sktnner, 1969). Some examples from everyday life should help to clarify the distinction. Airline passengers are inclined to keep their seat belts fastened during flight, in order to reduce the risk of being injured in the event of turbulence or some other in-flight mishap. Similarly, car drivers are careful to apply the brakes in response to the illuminated rear brake lights of other vehicles, in order to avoid collisions. In general, inhabitants of Australia are careful when using a naked flame outdoors during hot, dry weather, because of the risk of inadvertently causing a bush fire. These are just a few of countless possible examples of rules that govern our lives. An important feature of rules is that awareness of them often has profound effects on behaviour, even though the consequences alluded to in a particular rule may never actually occur. With reference to the previous examples, it is not necessary to experience an in-flight mishap, a traffic coilision, or a raging bush fire to be profoundly affected by "knowledge" (i.e., thoughts, beliefs, images, etc.) of these events. DIS CRII\IINATIVE STI}TULI AND RULE-GOVERNED BEIIAVIOUR Rules as Discriminative Stimuli The importance of rule-governed behaviour is that it represents a special case of behaviour that is under discriminative-stimulus control. However, in this case, the discriminative stimulus is a rule (i.e., involves cognition). Specifically, rules are cognitively encoded contingencies of reinforcement (see Figure 1). By informing us about prevailing contingencies, rules serve as cognitive discriminative stimuli that set the occasion for behavins in sf/s' 5D alient aspect of the nvironment. Serves as a discriminative stimulus (SD). 153 resp€cts, it is the actions of discriminative stimuli that give human behaviour the flexibility and complexity that *'e identify as human. This is perhaps best exemplified in the distinction that may be drawn between contingency-shaped and rule-govemed behaviour. C o ntin ge ncy - shap Contingencies of R e inforc e m e nt Refurning.to the question of how subjective experience, including vicarious, symbolic, and cognitive processes in general, is accommodated by operant theory, it is necessary to consider the principles that govem the operation of contingencies of reinforce' ment. The "thlee-term contingency" is the essence of all operant learning. On this subject, we can do no better than to quote Skinner (1969) himself: An adequate formulation of the interaction between an organism Stimuli Cognitive event (Ru ) which as a memory, thought, belief, etc., serves as a rule. Rules are cognitions that encode relevant continsencies of reinforcement Rule-governe! behaviour (R). Contingent consequences which either reinforce (S+) or punish (S-lenactment of behaviour a rule. (R) prompted by and po"ssess SD properties. ) Hot, dry weather. Lighting an open fire in hot Careful use of fire. ffi and others, maintenance weather may cause a bush fire. of property and forests. c) Shopping mall. "I will probably lose my way in the mall and be overcome with Avoid mall, house bound.) panic". d) In bed, unable to sleep. "Nothing I do is Diminished aversive feelings of panic. (Person becomes a success" Refuse to go to work Reduced instances of work- on following and subsequent days. of depression.) ace e) Social gathering with unfamiliar people. "I must be thoroughly approved of by everyone" Avoidance of social gatherings. disappointment. (Beginnings Alleviation of anticipatory anxiety. (Maintenance of social isolation.) Figure 1 (a) Schematic general representation of cognitive responses serving as rules (encoding relevant contingencies of reinforcement), and functioning as discriminative stimuli. Examples are given to illustrate the influence of cognitive discriminative stim uli {i.e., rules) in everyday life (b), and in the development of psychopathology such as.panic {c), avoidance/depression (d), and anxiety (e). Dotted linds indicate cognitive processes, whereas continuous lines refer to observable relationships. Australian Psychologist Vol. 28, No. 3, 1993 pp. i51-155 154 Jack E. James ways that tend to maximise reinforcement and minimise punish- immediate consequences would affect behaviour" (Skinner, ment..Figure 1(a) provid.es a schematic representation of the 1969, p.769). ope ration- of rules as cognitive discriminative stimuli. By way of trlojt people, for example, find it aversive to make regular payan, everyday illustration, Figure 1(b)_ shows the operation of what ments oi sutstantial sumi of money to a bank. Nevertheless, the might be called the "Fire-safety Rule". Specifically, hot.weather majority of income earners apparintly seek out such financiat oPerates as a discriminative stimulus that sets the occasion for a buiden!. The explanation f'oi this apparentty-seii-auusiue particular cognition (a memory, thought, belief, hr:nch, image, behaviour is to be found in the discriminaiiu.-rtiriuiu, properties etc')' The cognition (or,.more^strictly, set of cognitions) i1 this of-a particular set of rules. These rules say something to the case is the formulation identified here as the Fire-safety Rule, effecf that "pain" and disadvantage now in the form of mortgage which-enco-des knowledge and beliefs about relevant contingen- repayments will be offset by the-benefits of property ownerstrip cies of reinforcement concerning bush fires. in-the future, In turn, the Fire-Safety Rule serves as a discriminative stimulus which sets the occasion for a variety of behaviours subsumed by B e n eJiting from O th ers' E rp erie n c e the pfuase, "careful use of fire". This behaviour has myriad conseAngther major function of rules is that they help people to avoid -learning quences. For example, it contributes to the preservation of forests "the hard way". This is particulariy true of'behaviours (a possible reinforcing outcome for the indivjdual), and helps to that have aversive consequences, especially those that threaten life avoid a host of aversive outcomes (e.g., property damage to self and limb. By either hearing about, reading about, or seeing people and others, lives Iost, legal sanctions). The host of consequences behaving in ways that are variously advintageous or harmful-to that serve to reinforce observance of the Fire-Safety Rule conthemselves or to others, people become informed about important tribute to its salience, thereby enhancing its effectiveness as a disrelationships between different behaviours and attendant conse_ criminative stimulus. It is important to recognise, however, that it quences. This information, in the form of rules, guides behaviour, is not essential to have acnally experienced the honors of a bush enabling us to benefit from the experience of others. It is curious ' fire to learn to be careful with fire. Knowing about the likely con- that these are the very r_easons Bandura (1969,1977a) cites in sup sequences, especially with regard to the aversive experiences of port of iis advocacy of social learning theory. However, contrary others who have behaved in particular ways (used fire) in specific to Bandura's (1977a) claims, behavioural theory does not suggejt circumstances (e.g., heat wave, dry "speli", strong winds), is suffithat we learn only by a process of ,,tedious trial and erior',. cient to profoundly influence the cunent and future behaviour of Survival depends on our benefiting from others' experience, and persons confronted with similar circumstances. frequently this occurs without any direct experienie of relevant Ubiquity of rule-governed behav,iour. It is also important to contingencies less repeated trial and error. If humans - much recognise that when conceptualised as cognitive discriminative leamed only through direct experience of the universe of coniin_ stimuli, rules can be seen lo refer to virtually any reliable relagencies that influence behaviour, most would not survive childtionship befween behaviour and irs consequ.n..r. In this sense, hood. The behavioura_l.concept of cognitions serving as rules include laws and maxims (i.e., relationships involving reladiscriminative stimuli, which is the foundaiion of rule_sove;led tively stable contingencies), commands (contingencies implying behav.iour, provides a powerful and parsimonious explaiation of a. compliance imperative) versus requests (absence of imperahow this essential learning occurs. tive), warnings (suggestive of aversive consequences) virsus advice and instructions (suggestive of reinforcing consequences), RULE. GO VER].{ED BEIHVIOUR A}.{D and statements of purpose (which typically allude to aniicipated COGNITIVE THERAPY consequences). Likewise, contracts, bribes, resolutions, and plans Unfortunately, much of what is claimed to be distinctively cog_ . all signify rules implying consequences of one kind or another, nitive-behavioural theory is little more than a poor representation and each influences behaviour more or less, depending in part on of rules as discriminative stimuli. This can be seen by examining the specific nature of the attendant consequences. the justif.ication given for various intervention strategies derivel As such, cognitive discriminative stimu'ii (i.e., rules) are ubiouifrom competing cognitive theories. The concepts of -,,self_effica_ tous in everyday life. Understanding the principles of rule-govemed .1" Q..rl!_r.9, 1:977b), "negarive', (Beck et al.',1979), and ,,irra_ behaviour helps to elucidate the subtleties and shades of bJhaviour. tional" (Ellis & Harper, 1975) thinking, and the intervention both normal and abnormal. In all instances, the extent to which strategies sug€ested by each, have been particularly jnfluential. rules influence current behaviour, depends on the extent to whjch Figure 1(c) shows how expectationi serve as cognitive dis_ past rule-following behaviour has been differentially reinforced. criminative stimuli which function as rures describirig individuThus, the discriminative-stimulus properties of ruies will vary als' beliefs about the relationships between aspec'is of their between rules and behveen individuals, it least in subtle wai-s. as a behaviour (in this instance, going to the mall) and anticipated function of the complex afiav of consequences that will have been consequences (becoming lost and overwhelmed with panic). As experienced on countless previous occasions when rules of one such, cognitions in the form of expectations can and Oo influence kind or another were or were not followed by each individual. behaviour because of their discriminative-stimulus properties, in the same way that environmental discriminative stimuli influence FUNCTIOT.iS OF RULES behaviour. Similarly,_Figures 1(d) and 1(e) illustrare how negaConsidering the ubiquitous influence of rules as cognitive distive (Beck et al., 1979) 'and irrational (Ellis & Harper, 7915) criminative stimuli, it is appropriate to describe some of the printhoughts, respectively, function as cognitive discriminitive stim'_ cipal ways in which rule-governed behaviour functions in uli which set the occasion for self-defeating behaviour. The con_ everyday life. tingencies of reinforcement that define ruG-governed behaviour also. explain how therapeutic change occurs }ollowing cognitive Delayed Reinforcement (and behavioural) intervention. An important function of rules is that they serve as coenitive Frequently, in cognitive-behaviour therapy, patients are mediators to help bridge the "gap" when reinforcem'ent is encouraged to employ adaptive self-statements-and-internal dia_ delayed. It is characteristic for humans to expend effo( to effect logues (e.g., Beck er a1.,7979; Ellis & Harper, 1975). The primaimportant consequences in the future. people are less likely to be ry effect of these cognitive processes is to increase the lalience of distracted by immediate, Iesser consequences, if they undirstand relevant rules. lVhe.n a person engages in an internal dialogue, the relationship befrveen current behaviour and likely future conthey increase the discriminative-stimulus properties of rutel in sequ€nc€s (Rachlin, 1974). This knowledge is part of a cognitive wa.ys that may be either adaptive or not. Accordingly, when ther_ mediation process in which rules have a central function. these, apists challenge the self-defeating thoughts of pltients, they in turn, function as discriminative stimuli that set the occasion for encourage the replacement of unhelpful rules with more realistii behaving in ways that produce delayed benefits despite possible and adaptive ones. in other words, therapists' efforts help to short-term costs. Skinner (1969) wrote, ,,Withouf rules, only decrease the salience (i.e., discriminative-stirnulus potency) of Australian Psychologist Vot. 28, No. 3, I 993 pp. I 5l-l 55 Cognitions as Discriminative Stimuli 155 and other cognitive events acquire discriminative-stimulus prop- maladaptive cognitions while increasing the salience of adaptive thoughts and beliefs. Typically, patients are encouraged (usually by way of explicit home assignments) to practice adaptive thoughts and behaviours. Practice provides conditioning opportunities, and these further strengthen the discriminative-stimulus properties of relevant cognitions (i.e., thoughts beliefs, self-statements, etc.) initiated and socially reinforced by the therapist. In tum, there is a good chance that the discriminative-stimulus potency of newly acquired adap tive self-statements and internal dialogues will be strengthened over time, as adaptive behaviours are reinforced by enhanced success in the natural environment. As such, most of what passes for cognitive theory and practice can be more clearly explained in terms of the principles that describe the role and functions of rulegoverned behaviour. Moreover, this analysis is consistent with a large volume of empirical data on the successful treatment of anxiety disorders, which suggests that processes involved in anxiety reduction are essentially both cognitive and enactive (i.e., involve symbolic and direct experience) (James, 1985, 1986). Bandura, A. (1969). Principles of behavior modification. New York: Holt, RineharL & Winston. Bandura, A. (1977a). Social learning rheory. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: PrenticeHall. Bandura, A (1977b). Self-efficacy: Toward a unifying theory of behavioral change. Psychological Review, 84, 191-2L5. Bandura, A. (i986). Socia!foundations of thought and action: A social cognitive theory. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall. CONCLUSION Bandura, A., Blanchard, E.G., & Ritter, B. (1969). The relative efficacy of desensitization and modeling approaches for inducing behavioural, affec- Behavioural theory is acknowledged as having its roots firmly grounded in experimental psychology. This may be contrasted with the embellishments that distinguish cognitive-behavioural theory, which have occurred independently of developments in experimental cognitive psychology (Kendall & Bacon, 1988). It is interesting to note that social learning theory has for many years derived much scientific prestige by claiming direct linage with empirically derived leaming theory. While such claims have probably been exaggerated, even this route to scientific respectability appears now to have been abandoned. In his most recent major work, Bandura (1986) has deleted the term "learning" from "social learning theory", preferring instead to refer to his model as "social cognitive theory" (Bandura, 1986). Since the "cognitive" elements of social cognitive theory have little in common with experimental cognitive psychology, social cognitive theory has become little more than a speculative edifice devoid of empirical foundation. Notwithstanding the enthusiasm that cognitive-behavioural speculation continues to enjoy, theory devoid of empirical foundation cannot survive as serious science. On the other hand, it may be possible to develop a genuine cognitive-behavioural science by treating cognitive events as discriminative stimuli within a framework of principles that define rule-governed behaviour. Zettle and Hayes (1982), for example, have used Skinner's (1957) analysis of verbal behaviour to outline a model of psychopathology and behaviourally oriented therapy in which rules function as cognitive discriminative stimuli. Such developments would seem to suggest a crucial role for experimental cognitive psychology in helping to elucidate the mechanisms underlying the formation and acquisition of rules, and the processes by which rules function to influence behaviour. It should be evident from the above that the present paper is wholly accepting of the notion that cognitions may mediate behaviour. Specifically, it has been argued throughout that cognitions exercise a mediating influence on behaviour by way of their function as discriminative stimuli. In this sense, the principles espoused in the present paper are explicitly cognitive-behavioural in nature while being very different fiom extant theories generally characterised as "cognitive-behavioural". Unfortunately, the cognitive and cognitive-behavioural theories currently in vogue have failed to advance scientific understandins of the relationship between cognition and human behaviour. T'he combination of elaborate speculation and disregard for empirical evidence that characterises mainstream cognitive theories, such as that proffered by Bandura (1977a, i986), obfuscate rather than clarify the role and function of cognition. Classical behavioural theory, such as that espoused by Skinner (e.g., 1969), holds that cognition is a key aspect of human behaviour. Nofrvithstanding the important role of cognitions, they are not exclusive causal agents. Thoughts, expectations, beliefs, images, erties against a background of environment-behaviour interac- tion, eventually serving as rules that encode contingencies of reinforcement. In this way, "internal" events (thoughts, beliefs, emotions, perceived physiological activity, images, and cognitive representations of all kinds) function in a dynamic process of reciprocal influence, action, and interaction with the environment and behaviour. There remains much work to be done within the combined fields of experimental cognitive psychology and behaviour analysis to elucidate these interactive processes. REFERENCES tive, and attitudinal changes. Journal of Personality and SociaI Prychology, 13,171199. Bandura, A., Grusec, J.8., & Menlove, F.L. (1967). Vicarious extinction of avoidance behavior. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 5' l D-l J, Bandura, A, Ross, D., & Ross, S.A (1963). Imitation of film-mediated aggressive models. Jou rnal of Abnormal and Social Psychobgy, 66, 3-71. Beck, AT., Rush, AJ., Shaw, B.F., & Emery, G. (1979). Cognitive therapy of depression. New York: Guildford Press. & Massman, P.J. (1985). Cognitive therapy versus systematic desensitization: Is one treatment superior? Psychological Berman, J.S., Miller, R.C., Bulletin, 97, 451461. Biglan, A. (1987). A behavior-anal;'tic critique of Bandura's self-efficacy rheory. The Behavior Analyst, 10, ]_15. Craigbead, W.E. (1990). Tbe cbanging narure of behaviour the:.py. Behavior Therapy,2l, l-2. Ellis, A., & Harper, R.A. (1975). A new guide Io rational /iving. New York: Prentice-Hall. Eysenck, H.J. (1988). Psychotherapy to behavior therapy: A paradigm shift. In D.B. Fishman, F. Rotgers, & C.M. Franks ff.ds.), Paradigms of behovior therapy: Present and prombe (op. a5-76). New York: Springer. James, J.E. (1985). Desensitization treatment of agoraphobia. British Journal ol C linical P :ycholost-, 24, 133-131. Janres, J.E. (1986). Review of the relative efficacy of imaginal and in vivo flooding in the treatment of clinical feat. Behavioural Psychotherapy, 14, 183_191. & Bacon, S.F. (1988). Cognitive behavior therapy. In D.B. Fishman, F. Rotgen, & C.M. Franks (EAs.), Paradigms of behavior therapy: Present and prombe (pp. 1a1-167). New York: Springer. Kendall, P.C., l-edwidge, B. (19i8). Cognitive behavior modification: A step in the wrong direction? Psycl ological Bulletin, 85, 353-375. Mahoney, M.J., & Lyddon, W.J. (1988). Recent developmenls in cognitive approaches to counseling and psychotherapy, The Counseling 1 6, 19U231. Meichenbaum, D.H. (197i). Cognitive-behavior modifcation: An integrative approach. New York: Plenum. Mi.ller, R.C., & Berman, J.S. (1983). The efficacy of cognitive behavior therapies: A quantitative review of thc research evidence. Psychological P sy cholo g is t, Bulletin, 9l, 39-53. Rachlin, H. (1974). Self-control. Beh aviorist4 2, 94-107 . Rachlin, H. (1988). Molar behaviorism. In D.B. Fishman, F. Rotgers, & C.M. Frank (Eds.), Paradigms ol behavior therapy: Present and pronbe Qry. 77-105). New York: Springer. Shapiro, D.A., & Shapiro, D. (1982). Meta-analysis of comparative therapy outcomc studies: A replication and refinement. Psychological BuIIeti4 92,581404. Skinner, B.F. (1957). Verbal behavior. New York: Applelon-Century-Crofu. Skinncr, B.F. (1969). Contingencies of reinforcement: A theoretical analysb. New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts. Skinner, B.F. (1972). Bqond freedom and dignity. London: Jonathan Capc. Zettle, R.D., & Haycs, S.C. (1982). Rule-governed behavior: A potential thcoretical framcwork for cognitivc-bchavioral therapy. Advances in Cognitive-Behavioral Research and Therapy, I,'13-118. Australian Psychologist Yol. 28, No. 3, I 993 pp. I View publication stats 5 1-l 55