Uploaded by Emmanuel Akingbemi

Justice Final Essay

advertisement
Emmanuel Akingbemi
Poli sci 179: (Justice)
June 11th, 2021
Final Essay (2000 words)
Over the past ten weeks in this course, we studied three principles of Justice:
utilitarianism, libertarianism, and the teleological principles of Justice. Each of these principles
has different main ideas that help arrive at their definition of a just act. On the issue of
reparations, it is essential to know what these principles think about the original sin of slavery to
understand what they will decide about reparations and what it would look like in our
contemporary times. According to a Utilitarian, the definition of Justice is the act that yields the
maximum happiness for society overall. Utilitarianism's main idea is that the highest principle of
morality, whether personal or political morality, is to maximize the general welfare or collective
happiness or the overall balance of pleasure over pain, in essence, to maximize utility (Sandel, p.
34). The utilitarian always looks to ensure that the maximum happiness is achieved for the
greatest number of people by using the cost-benefit analysis to arrive at a decision. "...the
utilitarian assumption that morality consists in weighing costs and benefits, and simply wants a
fuller reckoning of the social consequences" (Sandel, p.33). For the utilitarian to assert that
reparations are justified, a utilitarian must conduct a cost-benefit analysis on whether the
decision to support reparations will promote the greatest happiness. On the other hand, the moral
crux of libertarian philosophy is the idea of self-ownership, meaning that if one owns one's self,
then no one else has the right to one's labor and time (Sandel, p. 65). This very premise of the
libertarian principle of Justice is that of anti-coercion. Thus, a libertarian would see slavery as a
morally reprehensible act. Still, even though they think slavery is an unjust act, it does not mean
that a utilitarian would necessarily support reparations. Lastly, the teleological premise of Justice
is that Justice is teleological and honorific. As the father of teleological thought, Aristotle
believed that "justice means giving people what they deserve, giving each person his or her due"
(Sandel, p. 187). In reasoning about Justice and rights, we have unavoidably to reason about the
purpose or the end of the telos of social practices and institutions. Justice requires giving equal
things to equal persons—that is equal to the respect of rewarding the virtue of the talented in
regards to what is being distributed. Aristotle had the most extensive opinions on slavery which I
plan on delving into later. Applying Aristotle's logic to where he would arrive at regarding the
issue of reparations, we might assume that the biggest question for Aristotle is whether or not
descendants of the enslaved are virtuous enough to receive whatever might be distributed as a
result of reparations. To decide whether or not reparations are justified, the thought leaders of
these principles of Justice will firstly have to answer whether slavery was a just act. If they
believe that slavery was unjust, they might be more inclined to support reparations in some form.
A utilitarian is all about maximizing utility or achieving the greatest happiness for the
highest number of people. With this premise, a utilitarian might justify slavery as necessary for
the betterment of early American society because it led to the greatest happiness for the more
significant number of people. For example, the vast majority of white settlers during the years of
slavery were content with the fact that enslaved Africans had to do all the labor in the fields
without any compensation. Therefore, they justified slavery because it made lives easier for the
white settlers, who could attend to whatever else they preferred to do with their free time and
profits gained from the slaves' labor. As the father of Utilitarian thought, Jeremy Bentham
believed that "the highest principle of morality is to maximize happiness, the overall balance of
pleasure over pain." (Sandel, p. 34). This means that the right thing to do is whatever will
maximize utility. Now, regarding slavery, Bentham would say that if the majority decides slavery
to maximize happiness, then the minority has to be subjugated to be ruled and oppressed by the
majority to maximize utility. Thus, one of the most significant objections to utilitarianism is that
it violates individual freedom by imposing the majority's opinion upon the minority, as seen in
the utilitarian defense of slavery. Now on the question of reparations, a utilitarian would first
ponder what the cost-benefit of enacting a reparations law would mean for its citizenry. That is,
would a reparations law lead to maximum utility amongst my constituents? A utilitarian must
conduct a cost-benefit analysis to answer this question on the issue of reparations. A utilitarian
cost-benefit analysis on reparations might conclude that the vast majority of the population does
not consent to be charged for the sins of their forefathers. Although some might argue that
slavery benefitted every person living in civilized America, others might counter this point by
saying that since no one alive experienced slavery nor participated in it; they do not bear the
Fault or responsibility to repay the descendants of the enslaved. A utilitarian would argue that
reparations blame the majority for something that they did not participate in nor engaged in, so
they do not have the onus to repay the proverbial debt for the sins of their ancestors. Ultimately,
a law favoring reparations will be the citizenry's responsibility, especially in a monetary form. A
utilitarian would argue that placing the atonement for the sin of slavery solely on the citizenry
would not maximize happiness. Instead, it places guilt and the financial burden on people who
did not directly commit the evil act they are being charged to atone.
A libertarian believes that unlike the utilitarian, who is mainly concerned with the
majority's collective happiness, the libertarian is primarily concerned with individual rights.
Libertarian rejection of utilitarian logic says that the fundamental individual right is the right to
liberty precisely because we are separate individual beings (Sandel, p. 59). We are not available
to any use that society might desire or devise. While a utilitarian might justify slavery, the
libertarian recognizes that slavery is unjust under every circumstance because the individual did
not choose to be a slave without coercion. On the question of whether a form of repetitive and
dangerous job is, for the libertarian, "...the answer would depend on whether the workers had
freely exchanged their labor for a wage; if they did, the work is just" (Sandel, p. 203). Based on
this answer, a libertarian would vehemently reject the justification for slavery because it
infringed on individual rights and the principle of self-possession. The libertarian, having
conceded that slavery was an unjust act, the libertarian will be hesitant to support reparations
fully. The topic of reparations will look different for the libertarian because he believes there
must be no redistribution of wealth or income. "The libertarian theory of rights rules out any law
that requires some people to help others, including taxation for redistribution of wealth" (Sandel,
p. 60). Reparations can be seen as a redistributive effort to lessen the generational gap of wealth
amongst racial minorities and descendants of the enslaved. As previously stated that libertarians
recognize that reparations as a form of an apology to atone for the sins of the past are justified so
far as it is not for the sake of bringing about greater equality for its own sake. A famous
libertarian, Robert Nozick, argued that "...distributive justice depends on two
requirements—justice in initial holdings and justice in transfer" (Sandel, p. 63). The critical thing
that libertarians specify is Justice in the acquisition of wealth. A crucial question the libertarian
asks to decide if there was Justice in the acquisition is, "did people get the things they use to
make their money fairly?" A libertarian might argue that if the state could trace back the family
history of slave ownership, then that family is responsible for reparations to the descendants of
the slaves that the family owned in the past. The libertarian is against taxing the entire population
to atone for the sin of slavery because not everyone in the nation benefited from the institution of
slavery. It makes more sense to the libertarian that only the families who have benefitted from
owning slaves in the past are responsible for atoning for the sin of slavery.
The teleological principle of Justice dictates that Justice is about giving people what they
deserve. The teleological approach to Justice laid out the most extensive thought about the
morality of slavery. Aristotle stated in the justification of slavery that "justice is a matter of
fit...and to fit persons to the roles that suit them...giving persons their due means giving them the
offices and honors they deserve and the social roles that accord with their nature" (Sandel, p.
200). Slavery, according to Aristotle, was a necessary natural occurrence because certain people
are built to be slaves, and the society to function adequately needed slaves. "Slavery is necessary,
Aristotle argues, because someone must look after the household chores if citizens are to spend
time in the assembly deliberating about the common good" (Sandel, p. 201). Now, Aristotle
makes the distinction by asserting that slaves must fit their role, meaning that if someone were
made a slave and were not the right fit for that role, that act would be considered unjust.
Critiques of this view on social role and fit say that allocating rights based on fit is not a just act;
however, letting people choose their societal role is the ultimate peak of allocating rights.
Allocating right based on fit is unjust, and Aristotle does see that his defense of slavery can be
struck under certain conditions. He reasons that for slavery to be a just act, some people need to
be suited to the role of slaves by nature, and if they somehow were not suited by nature to be
slaves, then it is unjust. It is easy to wonder then how one can tell if someone is suited to be a
slave by nature; Aristotle answers this by saying you would have to see who flourishes in their
roles as slaves, and as long as they are not forced to do it then it is a just act. On the topic of
reparations, Aristotle would ask if the slaves were forced into their roles as slaves; if the answer
is yes, the teleological principle necessitates a law for reparations. "For Aristotle, coercion is a
sign of injustice, not because consent legitimates all roles, but because the need for force
suggests an unnatural fit" (Sandel, p. 202). If a nation needs to force a people to be under
servitude for generations, then people did not willingly choose to be slaves, which makes it an
injustice. Injustices need to be atoned. The teleological mode of thought would argue that
because not all slaves were fit to be slaves, especially because many slaves were captured as
prisoners of war, they were not fit to be slaves, and the fact that they were slaves was a great
injustice.
The three principles of Justice: utilitarianism, libertarianism, and teleological principle,
have varying views on slavery and reparations. It is clear to see that their opinion on reparations
is contingent on their view of slavery. The libertarian approach on reparations of putting the onus
on families with a history of slave-ownership seems to be the most feasible and the most
persuasive because it is natural for the vast majority of the population to reject the responsibility
of slavery. However, it is difficult for a family with a history of slave-ownership to outrightly
reject responsibility because it can be argued that their family history of slave-ownership led to
their present-day wealth and atone for their family's sin. However, the teleological approach to
reparations is also compelling considering that it is an argument that an entire citizenry can
understand. The injustice of slavery will fall solely on society because some will say slavery was
necessary but still an unjust act.
Download