Art and Science JOSEPH AGASSI Boston University and Td-Aviv University T" I THE DISTINCTION BETWEEN SET AND SCIENCE Much is said, and much interesting information is extant, regarding the cooperation between the arts and the sciences. One domain may borrow from another an achievement or a technique. There is the use of photography for artistic purposes, even the use of microphotography, and even the use of microphotographs. An there is the employment by science and technology of artistic achievements, not only of perspective and of psychological insights, but also of sensitivities discovered by artists to diverse phenomena. Moreover, art and science may inspire each other. Thus, an artist like Beardsley has inspired the development of new techniques of photography and developments such as those of acoustic science and technology suggested electronic music of all sorts. All this belongs to a rich field which I shall not discuss. Let me say, rather, that the very cooperation between the arts and sciences is so very thrilling because the two domains are taken to be so very distinct. We all enjoy the cooperation of poetry and music, of paintings and music, of the theatre and music, of the theatre and poetry. Somehow, we feel, the cooperation of art and science differs from the cooperation of art with art, however natural or problematic (it surely seems more natural to us to mix I poetry with. music than paintings with music). The reason is, I suppose, that we feel that art and science are so significantly different as to make their cooperation much more intellectually exciting and thought-pro voking than the cooperation of diverse arts. The distinction between art and science seems all too clear. .art is emotional, science factual; art is subjective, science objective; art is pleasant, science is useful. So goes the common distinction. This distinction implicitly merges scientific technology with science, as against art - as . if it were a matter- of course. Yet it is not clear to me why that it is so. ─ and I think. it may very well be thought that the opposite is tree, if not even obviously true. I do not see why installing an- air-conditioner is a matter of objective technology, yet using it is subjective. And if using it is admitted to be objective, then I do not see why using a record of Beetle's music is not. The answer to this objection is, of course, that the Beatles are not everybody's cup of tea. But then neither. is. air-conditioning; s More subtly, technology is divided into an art and a science- whatever requires a knack, and is a doubtful matter of trial and error, is called subjective and an art; whatever can be done by rote with assured success is called a science. Thus is understood, for example, the debate as to whether medicine is an. art or a science. Science is- allegedly sure and, this is all to the good; but what is sure is also dull; art is. allegedly doubtful, but thereby also thrilling. I find all this rather infantile. I cannot see the humdrum of the conveyor:. belt as a science; I find it terrible and barely excusable. And I cannot see in the bunglings of a medic or of an acoustic engineer an art - under standable though it surely is- I can, on the contrary, see much. more in common between the bunglings of a Befthoven and the bunglings of a Newton. I can compare their zeal; their sense of perfection; their e$ perimentation and search for something objective, overruling the merely subjective and the accidental as much as possible and even hoping against all common-sense to eliminate it altogether. '_ Yet I wish to endorse fully the view that science and art are inherently distinct and can never be united or merged except as a remote and unattainable ideal. In the present essay I shall take only one aspect of the distinction, and show how unbridgeable it is, by a repeated effort to bridge, or close the gap between, scientific research and artistic activity the aim of science is the attaining of the truth, whereas the aim of art is the attaining of beauty. And so, much as we may narrow the gap between the two, all efforts to close it must fail. II r~ IWABTy' AND TRUTH Perhaps the simplest way to close the gap is simply to allow either art or science to betray its aim. If both are to serve the state, for example, then they can merge. If science were to betray the end of truth and aspire to what Martin Heidegger called a poetic truth n and were to place - the value of poetic truth above that of scientific truth, then art and science could merge. If art will cease to search for beauty and aim at. amusing audiences or manipulating them by psychological means, then we could produce works of art and artistic performances on conveyor-belts. Heidegger's talk about truth is, of course, merely a veiled proposal to make science and art both betray their true ends and serve the state instead. Likewise those who view the value of both art and science as measurable by the yardstick of utility - private or social - may have sense of neither art nor science and can thus shortcut them and talk. of the utility of Newton or. of Beethoven.. Alternatively, these people may have an independent sense of art and of science which can. be discussed as their value without reference to their utility measure - even if, for one reason or another utility happens to equal intrinsic value. In. the JOSEPH AGASSI 129 end, it seems, acknowledging the intrinsic value of art and the intrinsic value of science is a moral matter: a matter of a primary, honest; straightforward attitude. The word `straightforward' plays an important role in my opinion. With sophistication we can get anywhere. We may say, and I believe we may truly say, that the end of science, its final and ideal end, the Truth,. is identical with the final end of art, the Beautiful. It is- no accident that Plato's moat satisfactory exposition of his theory of ideas is to be found in his Symposium, that classic study of beauty. The ideas, the world of ideas, is True, Beautiful, and Good. But scientific research still is, in a straightforward way, the search for truth, not for beauty, and artistic creation aims at beauty, not at truth. Hence, though the final end, perfection itself, may be the same for art and for science (extentionally speaking), the immediate end (intentionally speaking) of artistic and of scientific activity are obviously different. III REAsorr AND FMoTTON It is an interesting historical fact that the giants of the high Renaissance were Platonists and tended to blur the distinction between art and science, truth and beauty, and in many ways which fill the literature of the history of Renaissance Art, science, ethos. The idea of the distinction between art and science comes from the idea of the purity of science, from the view that science is good as long as it is kept pure. This idea belongs to Sir Francis Bacon who blamed older philosophers for mixing science and religion, science and metaphysics, science and politics. Bacon himself did not speak of art or of aesthetics. Yet the division between the arts and the sciences was accepted by his disciples, Descartes and his followers, as well as the Royal Society of London, and it immediately raised the problem for them: what role do the arts play in the life of a culture Descartes hinted, and the English peot John Dryden, Fellow of the Royal Society of London, said explicitly: The duty of art is to serve science, to make science agreeable to the public - art is merely ancillary to science; it has no role of its own. It is thus no accident that the eighteenth century saw poetry whose content is scientific; that John Constable, the famous early nineteenth century English painter who was the forerunner of impressionism, viewed himself a naturalist as he painted from the hand of nature, i.e., as his saw with an untutored eye, or a naive eye, or an innocent eye - not as his theories would tell him to see. It is no accident either that the impressionist painters advocated painting things as seen by the untutored eye, by the naive observer who sees - as Bacon said -things as they really are, uncolored by prejudice. The ides of the untutored eye and the role it. has played in the works of Constable and his followers has been discussed at great lenght by E.. H. 130 SCIENTIA 1 Gombrich in his art and Illusion; the empirical evidence of the impossibllity of seeing with the naked eye, accumulated since Helmholtz, has been gathering in works of Gibson and Gregory. It seems to me to be an obvious fact that the fascination and drama of such books is derived from the fact that Bacon's influence is still tremendous, and that this influence is strong enough to make the empirical evidence cause great discomfort to the many believers in the theory of the untutored eye, which is the theory of the separateness of science and art. To put it as a personal experience in the Baconian style, I have observed diverse audiences, students, colleagues, and others, greatly disturbed by any speaker who, like myself, is liable to fuse, or confuse, art and science on occasion. The reason so many people are disturbed w)Ien art and science are not kept separate seems to be to be obvious and not without merit: nobody seriously wants wishful thinking, that is to say, emotion, standing in the way of reason in its attempt to comp to the truth. The popular prejudice expressing this reasonable sentiment is the view that reason dampens emotion and emotion dampens reason when the two comingle; that science is reason alone and art emotion alone; that qua scientist a scientist must have a heart made of stone, that he must feel with his brain - just as qua artist an artist must have a brain made of straw, that he must think with his heart. Thus, a very reasonable and commonsense view gets. its popular expression couched in a string of inane and confused and irrational suggestions. It may well be worth examining the hold these suggestions have on the popular imagination. . IV THE $EQTJI73LIKENT FOE A SHARP SEPARATION To repeat, people are disturbed when art and science are not kept separate in as strict a manner as possible. Now, any requirement for a strict separation is rooted in a fear that the slightest overlap may lead to harmful results; the harmful result is usually the outcome of a total confusion of the two. Somehow the feeling is that the moment art is allowed the slightest foothold in science, then science loses its claim to objectivity without any further ado; that likewise, the moment art is allowed to be cerebral to any extent whatsoever; it loses its right to a claim on beauty: Thus, for example, when P. A. M. Dirac claimed that he used aesthetic arguments in order to retain his celebrated equation against empirical evidence which contradicted it, the impression was given that science lost all claim for its aspiration for truth. This, clearly, is an error. It is admittedly the case that Dirac used aesthetic arguments, yet only as encouragements, as giving him hope that his equation will prove defensible against known initial. criticism. Yet, it could happen that his hopes would not be fulfilled: his. -equation could. con.ceivably fare no better than other beautiful equations. Moreover,: though :i 1 i JOSEPH AGASSI 131 i ' the equation did withstand the initial objections and thus- attained its prominence, this is not. to say that it withstood all objections, and even Dirac himself does not now claim that he is, pleased with it, or in general with quantum theory as it now stands. Hence; clearly, though. aesthetic considerations did play a role, even a significant role; in; the history of science - of quantum theory in this case - the decisive considerations are not aesthetic but those which pertain to the truth. The same holds for scientific or cerebral considerations in art. It is wellknown that young artists often display aversion towards the acquisition of techniques which require cold calculations. Often a painter overcomes such, aversion by making a rather silly distinction between real or artistic painting and applied or commercial art, by allowing himself to acquire cerebral techniques for commercial art, and then unconsciously smug gling his knowledge (preferably transformed and altered to his taste) into his allegedly pure art. I have encountered many budding authors who struggle bitterly because they are steeped in the conviction that a. novel should grow organically, one page naturally following another. They regard with disdain the very thought of planning a novel by cerebral ana lytic means. To write a synopsis of a novel, a table of contents, an es timated length of each chapter - this seems so easy and so pointless, not to say `commercial', that they refuse to try it. And so they may be hopelessly frustrated. Only such people, and the popularity of the pre judices which frustrate them, can make the public gasp at the publication of Dostoevsky's notebooks. These notebooks, as one should expect, are highly analytic, and entirely cerebral; they record plans, experiments, suggestions; they do not appeal to their author's own emotions, but to his reason. Yet this very characteristic which should be expected a priori, is what did cause a stir. It is thus very clear that our popular views on art and on science are miles away from sheer commonsense. - . V ' r x R THE ERRORS BEHIND THE SETAEP SEPARATION The sharp separation is an error which is deeply reflected in our present way of life, and will not be eradicated by the mere indication that art has a cognitive side and science an aesthetic side. Consider old works of art and original versions of scientific theories. Both require a tra dition, a training, a. definite approach. We do have a tradition of the one and not of the other: we learn to appreciate the arts historically, but not the sciences. Admittedly we do learn certain ancient doctrines,. some clas sical scientific views such as Newton's and Lavoisier's. This is so by some sort of default: we do not know how to avoid teaching them, and we teach them in some highly modified versions, akin to Lamb's Stories of Shake speare and Hamilton Harty's version of Mindel's Royal Watermusic, t. r'~ AIL i !I 132 SCIENTIA not to mention some cinematic vulgarizations of ancient lore. These do, of course; serve a' purpose, they are substitutes for, and perhaps intro ductions to, the real things; but for the science connoisseur, nnlike the art connoisseur, the real thing, i.e. the originals of past scientific creative genius, is out of reach. Similarly, the cognitive side of art is more accessible to scientists- than the aesthetic side of science is accessible to artists. This point was first made in Lord Snow's enormously successful The Two Cultures and the Scientific Revolution. In this talk, as well as in its follow up, Snow found it necessary to blame artists for their insensitivity, through willful igno rance, he suggested, to the aesthetic side -of science; he only grudgingly acknowledged that scientists are often ignorant of art, and only in a hint he admitted their ignorance of any history whatever, of art or of science. His reason was his view that the scientific temperament is pro gressive, and thus, in the ethics of politics on the right side (which is left), whereas artists are natural Luddites. This, need I say, is just a degeneration of Dryden's view of art as a handmaid of science: art should serve both science and progressive politics, but, alas, it tends to go its own devious way. Both traditional defects come from the inability to take seriously the aesthetic side of science which, in turn, comes from the view of science as purely objective, as purely impersonal, as utterly devoid of all con nection with other aspects of the culture except through the economic side of things. Even the life of Madame Curie by her daughter shows no significant link between the character of that remarkable woman and her remarkable research. Even Helmholtz's researches- - which so ob viously reflect his personality, his conservatism, his philosophic taste, his taste for music - are presented not as personal but as a part of the vast impersonal tapestry that is science. That the alleged utter aesthetic neutrality of science is linked with its -, . ' - claim for utter objectivity, for absolute truth, can best be revealed in the works of authors about science who deny that utter aesthetic neutral ity. The philosophers of the conventionalist school, Poincare and Duhem in particular, insist on the aesthetic quality of science while denying all claim for scientific objectivity, while denying that scientific theories in any way reflect the structure of the universe, the nature of things. The way in which the cognitive side of art and the aesthetic side of science come to the fore, is first and foremost through the more modern philosophy of science, which Popper calls c< the third view)), and which may be called gradualism. Gradualism is the theory which, first and foremost, does not in the least deny the existence of a personal, of a subjective, element in science, but which declares, none the less, the aim of science, to be the objebtive and impersonal. Science, according to gradualism, gradually undergoes the process of objectivization. Products of science, say the gradualist, are likely to be rejected, in whole or in part, to be sifted,.to be viewed as approximations to the truth, indeed as different approzi- . x t: 0 . r JOSEPH AGASSI 133 . mationa when viewed from different angles and at different times. In the same way, precisely, the history of the cognitive side of the arts will be viewed as part and parcel of the history of science and technology proper. Indeed, at times this is all too obvious already, as when the artists' tools are reinforced concrete as used by architects or subtle psychological ob servations in the novels of the early Freudian period and slightly earlier. All this, much as it brings art and science closer to each other, recognizes the distinctness of their distinct ends. a OBJECTIVIZATION IN ART AND IN SC>.ENCE Distinct as art and science remain, they may have more in common than hitherto indicated, and significantly so, quite apart from the interactions between the arts and the sciences, and quite apart from the fact that the arts have a cognitive aspect and the sciences an aesthetic aspect. These are, as I shall venture to explain, the processes of objectivization. Let us begin with the processes themselves: with the scientific process, scientific research, and the artistic process, the act of creation. We can contrast the art with the product, the process with the achievement it leads us to. Somehow, we are able to belittle the achievement as compared with the straggle. We are in possession of the achievements of the past, and we do not think too highly of ourselves or of our possessions. But we do greatly appreciate the straggle of those who brought what we possess into our possession. This is why it takes training to learn to appreciate works of art of old masters: we have to learn to appreciate their straggle, to see the process which led to the product when we contemplate the product. This last point is a cornerstone of the philosophy of art of the celebrated E. H. Gombrich who is, not insignificantly, a disciple of the philosopher of science, Sir Karl Popper, the chief exponent of gradualism. Much as I endorse this point of Gombrich, however, I cannot endorse the detail of it. Seeing only troth but not beauty, as an ideal towards which to progress, he sees no point in the objectivization of the artistic part of art, only of the cognitive part of art. Hence he views the straggle of the artist as purely cognitive: though he sees the cognitive achievement of an old master as much inferior to what cognitive tools a mediocre artist has today, he declares the very straggle for that achievement essential to the old master's greatness. (I cannot offer an exact quote from Gombrich to substantiate my reading of him, but I think this is a failing of his style. If I have misread him I have to declare him elusive: I have tried to read him sympathetically and carefully, and I have compared notes with others, etc.). The reason why I disagree with this view of Gombrich's is that I find that there are many artists who have made important artistic innovations which they themselves put to use not i f . f34 j j • i i i SCIENTIA very, forcefully, but -which their less inventive contemporaries who were of greater artistic power exploited very effectively. Gombrich. himself notices that some great masters of the, past were arch-conservative and some of the greatest innovators were poor artists. Gomb=ich- explains well why people who break from old techniques need not be good artists, since they may have nothing interesting to replace them with; but he does not explain, and cannot explain, the fact that. innovation and great art, much as they go hand in hand, do not always go quite together. The question then forcefully arises, what is the struggle of the artist who is a great artist yet not a great innovator of techniques? What else does a great artist innovate other than techniques, other than the cognitive or cerebral part of art? I shall return to this question soon. The analogue of this discussion as far as the history of science is concerned is also rather new but much less problematic. Viewing science as chiefly cognitive - i.e. as productive of ideas which are true or false - we may well imagine the scientist struggling with cognitive problems: is this or that idea true? What explains this or that, etc. Now the history of science as the history of a struggle, any struggle, is a new field; the stress on the personal, on the moral, on the aesthetic side of the struggle - the stress on the non-cognitive side of the struggle - is even newer. It is quite an intriguing fact that attempts to comprehend the non-cognitive side of the struggle is essential for the comprehension of the struggle, yet the achievement is certainly measured as cognitive, not as personal or aes thetic or moral. The process of science is the process of scientific objec tivization, where objectivization is the increased approximation to the truth, and is thus essentially cognitive though also essentially containing non-cognitive aspects. If we wish to retain the parallel, we would perhaps try to say in complete parallel to the above: the process of art is the process of artistic objec tivization, where objectivization is the increased approximation to beauty, and is thus essentially aesthetic though also essentially containing non aesthetic aspects. Clearly this is Platonic, assuming the existence of both the ideal truth and the ideal beauty. And this is the fundamental bias of the present essay. Some may find it problematic; I do not. Clearly one might ask, are the True and the Beautiful, or Truth and Beauty, not identical'? And if it is, does it not collapse the arts and the sciences into a unity? The, answer is clearly, no. Our stress is on the struggle, on the process, and the processes of art and of science differ even if they turn out to be workjng towards the same in the end. This, however, does not remove the central problem which the present essay raises: what is objectivization in the arts other than the progress of their cognitive aspects What is aes thetic objectivization? What exactly is the approach to the beautiful? How can we reconcile viewing beauty as the value of a- classical work of art as manifest in its process and the same as manifest in its end? After all, the beauty achieved and the beauty aimed at are different. - JOSEPH AGASSI 135 VII e ' FORK AND CONTENT It is my inclination to view the history of art, like the history of science, as a process of objectivization. And I owe this attitude to Robert Cogan, the contemporary avantgardist composer of New England Conservatory. It seems to me that there are the two sets of traditions,-that in each tra dition there is the personal imprint of its giants, that partly this personal imprint gets objectivized, partly it gets ironed out, or eliminated in the process of restatement, that later leaders contribute to the objectivization of earlier parts and replace them with newer material, in part subjective in part exploratory,. towards newer levels of higher objectivity. The question still is, since art does not pertain to truth, what in it can be objectivized and howl I find this question hard to handle for want of tools due to the following fact. It is customary, in the tradition of modern aesthetics in the meat, to identify the form of art with the objective and the content of art with the subjective. This need not square with what has been said thus far about the cognitive and the aesthetic, though all too often one tends -to identify the two distinctions as a matter of course. For, the aesthetic aspect of a painting by Bosch or Breugel, or of a novel by Dostoevaky or Zola, cannot possibly be the content which is intentionally anaesthetic. Therefore, those who identify the aesthetic with content will have to declare them ugly and prefer to them the pre-Raphaelites and Peter Pan, Little Lord Fazsntleroy and The Heart and all other pretty-pretty, works one could mention off-hand. If one protests that the pretty-pretty is not beautiful either, then one will none the less be bound to prefer Renoir to Gauguin or Van Gogh as a matter of course - which to me seems ob viously questionable. That form has to do with beauty is, indeed, acknowledged even by those who assume that art is subjective, is emotional, is content. To clarify this, one has to present the dispute between the defenders of the view of art as content and those who oppose them. Both parties agree that there is no content without form except unexpressed and inarticulate feelings; both parties likewise agree that there is no form without content except perhaps in the world of ideas which is also incommunicable. Every communicable item of art, then, has both form and content. The defender of the form theory, for example Arnold Schoenberg, will say, pay attention to form, and content will take care of itself; pay attention to form, and choose content as you wish. There is here an asymmetry between this -view and its opposition. The defender of content, say Richard Wagner, will not declare form insignificant or capable of taking care of itself; he will merely declare form ancillary, and strictly so. Thus if the recipient is aware more of the form than of the content then the item of art traps muted is cerebral. and thus inferior. Superior art, along these lines, re quires botli significant emotional content and the proper form to transmit or convey it: ideally art should be the immediate transmission of strong - 136 j . - $CIENTIA feelings from artist to public, and the artist should strive to come as close to that ideal as possible, though it is unattainable. Now to apply this to our problem. From the viewpoint asserting that form is cognitive and content is artistic, clearly there can be only one way to objectify beauty - to objectify content. The way to doing this, then, is to develop our emotional capacities. I think this is in part true but not sufficient. It is clear that to objectify must mean here also to make more formal, more cerebral, and that also will not do. Yet is is possible to say that there is room for widening the range of feelings a culture offers its individual members, and this partly has to do with the role of art. The psychological novel is but an obvious example; the garden scene in Mozart's Don Giovanni is but a subtler example. The formalist, of course, must deny the identity of art with content and thus will be able to look for both aesthetic and cognitive aspects of art capable of development and objectification. But it is still not clear how. VIII HOW CAN WE OBJECTivrzE EMOTIONS ! Let us explore the possibility that emotional content can be objectivized in the sense that a culture offers, objectively, a range of emotions through its artistic achievements. These emotions may be studied, then, by studying the culture's arts, and so evaluated. It is doubtless, for example, that Beethoven has indeed expressed anger in music, thereby giving both anger and music newer and wider scope. Similarly, Wagner gave in music the expression of collectivism, of the individual's helpless delicious dependence on the tribe, on the emotional line which made him what he is. I am speaking here of emotional content, not of psychology. For, the content of psychology is statements which are true or false, whereas emotional contents are just there, in fact. There is then a possibility to accept them or reject them, there is even an intellectual possibility of weighing arguments in favour or against submitting to the emotions offered by Wagner, to the emotional bathos which are his operas. Every patient of psychotherapy knows that he has such options as to wish or not to wish to like someone or some feeling, and perhaps do something about it. We may appreciate a person or an attitude and wish to endorse it - or not. Therefore, it seems at first, the content of the art of Wagner, or of Delacroiz, or of Baudelaire, or of Rilke, is not as unimportant as Schoenberg said, but is of great value, though a negative one and an objectionable one at that. Even the art of Hermann Hesse, or Rachma ninoff, or gate gollwitz, being an expression of bovine self-pity, seems to be of a rather significant negative value, though less that that of Wagner. ' . r But no. Much as I agree with the assessment of the examples just men tiongd, I object both to the tone and to the generalization of the previous paragraph. 9s to the tone, it is functionalist. I have in mind in particular; Tolstoy's functionalist theory of art which is a generalization of Dryden's H JOSEPH AGASSI 137 theory. According to Dryden art derives its value from its function as an ancillary to science. According to Tolstoy it matters little to what art is ancillary, and he approved in particular of folk-art which is always. he said - integrated in folk-life and thus - he said - accentuates aspects of it, like the song and dance at a wedding feast or the wail of the mourners at a. funeral. This view, whether in Dryden's or Tolstoy's formulation; of art as ancillary, of art as at its beat when it is frankly applied art; comes chiefly to deny the contemplative view of art, the view of art as an object of contemplation, as Collingwood has put it. Since I endorse the autonomy of art, I cannot possibly endorse functionalism. And indeed, the problem I am dealing with - in what sense can art. be objectivizedmakes no sense unless we endorse the autonomy of the arts.. We may try to turn the tables and see if we do not get better results. Whereas functionalism in art makes aesthetics a part of ethics, aes theticism in morality makes ethics a part of aesthetics. Without any debate I shall assume here both the autonomy of ethics and the autonomy of aesthetics; yet I shall try to take a hint from aestheticism. Let us say, though magnanimity is not required by our moral code, surely magnanimity is very beautiful as Victor Hugo showed in Les Xiserables; and though self-pity is not forbidden, surely it is ugly and was justly ridiculed by Harpo in .I Day at the Races when he plays Rachmaninoff's C-sharp minor dtude on a piano which literally goes to piece. But no. This will not do either. The sentiment the previous paragraph expresses is wrong again, and the generalization it offers is the same as before and still false. The sentiment of aestheticism is somewhat decadent and objectionable both morally and aesthetically. The generalization can be refuted by many counter-examples. The misanthropic novels of Dosto evaky, the vulgar and reactionary movie Gongs-Din which excited even Bertholt Brecht, Degas's portrait of his parents and Grant Wood's justly celebrated American Gothic, both of which excel in malice and pettiness, are pieces of commendable art - and as such examples all too obvious and all too obviously devastating. Even tribalism can become something out of this world in Charles Ives' music, and self-pity an object of aes thetic contemplation in the world of Marcel Proust. And so, clearly, within the compass of classical aesthetics, on its division between form and content, our study must remain frustrated. We have a clear impression of progress in aesthetics through objectivization, yet we can barely say what objectivization is in any reasonably feasible manner. Someone may object to the claim that objectivization in the art is abvious or that we even know what. it is. That we do not know what it is is the major frustration expressed here. But it is obvious all the same: anger in music as opposed to Beethoven's anger, neurotic helplessness as opposed to Dostoevaky's heroes or Chekov's heroes. A sense of worth as opposed to Goethe's Faust, etc. Likewise, perspective as opposed to that of Brunelleschi or Alberti or Leonardo. Tonality, atonality - not necessa rily Schoenberg's, catharsis, not necessarily of this or that dramatist, etc. - 138 I~ SCIENTIA 33ETWEKN CONTENT AND FORM t The classical aesthetic approach divides content from form and asks, does the beauty of a work of art lie in its content or in its form? This approach has a long history and for many historical reasons - good, bad, and indifferent. Yet, I think, many discussions for a long time past, couched in terms of that approach, actually made that approach burst at its seams. The idea that certain contents fit certain forms and not others is repeatedly expressed by the use of the hackneyed metaphor of the Next Testament regarding old wine and new bottles. I do not know how convincing is Albert Schweitzer when he correlates the religious content of Bach's preludes and fugues with their form; but I dare say the general idea was hackneyed already then. The sensitivity of the artist, yesterday and today, is -expressed not only in his sensitivity to content, but in his feel for the need of art for a new form, a new medium, a new technique of expression in word, in sound, in color. I do not wish to say that the cognitive aspect of art is purely formal. Beethoven's ability to express anger is no doubt a matter of innovation, a cognitive process, and a matter of content, anger. His creation of new kinds of sound, new textures, created new problems for the art forms he used, the piano sonata or the orchestral symphony; and he solved his problems by creating a new form, or by modifying an existing form. The same goes for a religious sentiment. It may be easy enough to emulate Bach, or Bruckner, and express even today religious sentiments in modern compositions the like of which we often hear in Hollywood movies. When Arnold Schoenberg wished to express it, say, in -the last, the choral part, of his Survivor from Warsaw, he could use neither tonal music nor his usual serial music; he created a new type of melody which is neither, though, admittedly akin to the one used in Sessions Violin sonata for totally different purposes to totally different effects. Here I would be bold and say, perhaps again in agreement with- Schoenberg's recommendation to~take care of the form and not of content: the artist straggles to solve new problems because he has new contents, new experiences, which plainly do not fit old forms. He invents, then, new solutions which are new forms capable of adequately .expressing new _ feelings. I do not quite feel at ease with this: I feel that the artist may widen his range of feelings while exploring as an artist; art need not be only -the expression of already given new feelings, it may be the creation of new feelings as well. But I am not clear as to whether there is a clear disagreement here. In the classical theory all was clear enough, where content was emotional and subjective, form cerebral and objective, and beauty residing in one; or the other -possibly both, but separately nonetheless. It is no longer clear what is feeling, what is form. As the composer Roger Sessions and the philosopher Milic Capek both stress, we have a prevalent prejudice that the cerebral part of art can be articulated in words no less than in JOSEPH AGASSI 139 painting, music, poetry. But this .is not true. Certainly certain ideas, certain images, can be better conveyed in a picture than in a thousand words, as old Confucius said.,~ There is an ancedote, certainly spurious, of the reply Beethoven gave to the question what did a sonata mean which he had just finished playing: he played it all over again. Doubtlessly, this ancedote is romantic, sub jectivist; art is content and content is best conveyed by the form chosen for it by the artist or else the artist is inferior. Once we accept the formal approach we can answer the question, what does a work of art mean by formal analysis, by viewing a picture as a canvas divided into parts, by revealing the form of a symphony. But all this is very limited. It is quite possible that an idea can be better articulated by art, such as an answer to the question, what do you think is the character of . a friend, or what is New York like. If Capek is right on this, then it is hard to say any longer where content ends and form begins, .and certainly it is impossible to locate the aesthetic in either exclusively. It may very well be that the aesthetic is what widens our range of feelings, that the aesthetic is the fit of form and content, that we thus have layers of feelings, aesthetics and other, building up alternately. X CULTURE AS AN ART In his book on Movies and Society, Ian Jarvie speaks of anything well designed as a work of art, concluding that a man may - but need not -live his life as a work of art. Literature is full of such people, of those who tried to live their lives as works of art to varying degrees of success depending on all sorts of factors. I wish here to go further and see whether it is possible to objectify this point: these all sorts of factors may be well designed not only in one man but even in one culture. (gad passing a character to the culture is what, I have suggested, objectivization amounts to.) This is not new. Indeed it is hackneyed to the extent that it raises suspicion -.and rightly so. We are over need today to correlate the diverse arts and sciences and philosophies of a given period, and it is now fashionable to call baroque and rococo not only all the art styles current in these periods, but even their sciences and philosophies. Of course, this can be merely a matter of coy expression: we may call `baroque' anything that happened daring a certain span of time in the world, or in Western Europe. Of course, the history of such expressions goes to Hegel's theory i of the spirit of the age which is reflected in everything current in that age and more so in the better things current in that age. In that case, calling both painting and philosophy-of a given time `baroque' will not suffice: we should be able to show the same spirit of the same age reflected .in both. This should enrich our feel for, and experience of, the diverse aci' tivities of the age. An here readers are suspicions that authors promise l C 140 $CIBIVTIAa the harder thing, the sense of unity of any given age,, and when they fail they -supply a mere empty label instead. It seems to me clear that, in a non-trivial sense, there is some truth in Hegel's idea of the spirit of an age. However remote two activities of an age are, given enough perspective and enough contrast with other ages, some interesting connections can be found. The very absense of motorvehicles in past ages is already a terribly interesting integrating factor. But Hegel's philosophy is disastrous in its excesses. We must all agree that there are diverse degrees of integration, that by some lucky or unlucky accident one culture may be more integrated than another; one tradition, artistic, scientific, political, whatever, may be better or worse integrated in the culture than another tradition. This final point is so trite that I wonder how come I have to make it. Arthur goestler in his famous The Sleep-walkers has declared that the Pythagoreans represented an integrated -culture where art and science were united, and that mankind hardly ever saw such balanced integration. Brace Mazlish and Jacob Bronowsky saw the Renaissance as such a period. Clearly it is an ideal, and one we all see reflected, better or worse, in better or worse periods in the history of culture. Yet Plato's theory of Ideas, in its very ahistorical declaration of Truth, Beauty and Goodness being united, spoke against approaching such a unity. Hegel has claimed that his relativism introduces a historical dimension into philosophy. Every achievement, he says, is not better or worse, but always the best; nevertheless, the best can develop, nevertheless it can grow. What a terrible illogicality, what a terrible license for making all post hoc into propter hoc, for allowing everything subjective to be declared objective or objectified by the mere say so of the philosopher, for letting anything go. The strength of Hegel was in his seeing much of the limitstions of traditional philosophy and in his allowing us to transcend these. His weakness is the confusion he caused by adding the new without ousting the old. Even here the radicalist effort to eradicate all the old and stick only to the newest was criticized by him and he simply topped the new on the old. We need not accept all this confusion; we are, indeed, long past it. We can see the limitations of the achievements of the old, we can appreciate their struggle, we need not confuse them with us, or their views with ours: we have since learned to keep apart yet sympathize, to sympathize and criticize. We °can critically assess different- degrees of integration of different cultures. J. A. An earlier version of this paper was read at a symposium on aesthetics that took place- in Tel-Aviv University on 26 March 197'2. Dr. James Hu7let has corrected the final version and :has my gratitude.