See discussions, stats, and author profiles for this publication at: https://www.researchgate.net/publication/329029399 The Tragedy of the Commons Chapter · May 2018 DOI: 10.4324/9781315640051-24 CITATIONS READS 0 4,594 1 author: Kevin Ells Texas A&M University - Texarkana 14 PUBLICATIONS 21 CITATIONS SEE PROFILE Some of the authors of this publication are also working on these related projects: Semiotic's Sense of Synecdoche View project All content following this page was uploaded by Kevin Ells on 18 November 2018. The user has requested enhancement of the downloaded file. First published 2018 by Routledge 2 Park Square, Milton Park, Abingdon, Oxon OX14 4RN and by Routledge 711 Third Avenue, New York, NY 10017 Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group, an informa business © 2018 selection and editorial matter, Noel Castree, Mike Hulme and James D. Proctor; individual chapters, the contributors The rights of Noel Castree, Mike Hulme and James D. Proctor to be identified as the authors of the editorial material, and of the authors for their individual chapters, has been asserted in accordance with sections 77 and 78 of the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988. All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reprinted or reproduced or utilised in any form or by any electronic, mechanical, or other means, now known or hereafter invented, including photocopying and recording, or in any information storage or retrieval system, without permission in writing from the publishers. Trademark notice: Product or corporate names may be trademarks or registered trademarks, and are used only for identification and explanation without intent to infringe. British Library Cataloguing-in-Publication Data A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data A catalog record for this book has been requested ISBN: 978-1-138-19219-5 (hbk) ISBN: 978-1-138-19220-1 (pbk) ISBN: 978-1-315-64005-1 (ebk) Typeset in Stone Serif and Rockwell by Apex CoVantage, LLC Contents List of contributors Preface Introduction: environmental studies past, present and future Noel Castree, Mike Hulme and James D. Proctor Part 1 Classic concepts Editorial introduction 1.1 Adaptation Marcus Taylor 1.2 Bioregionalism Richard Evanoff 1.3 Conservation Chris Sandbrook 1.4 Desertification Diana K. Davis 1.5 Environment Sverker Sörlin 1.6 Ecosystems Erle C. Ellis 1.7 Environmental catastrophe Giovanni Bettini 1.8 Ecological footprint William Rees 1.9 The environmental Kuznets curve David I. Stern 1.10 Gaia Karen Litfin 1.11 The Jevons Paradox John M. Polimeni and Raluca I. Iorgulescu 1.12 Nature R. Bruce Hull 1.13 One world Volker M. Welter 1.14 Overpopulation Eric D. Carter 1.15 Precaution Tim O'Riordan and Rupert Read 1.16 Risk Susan L. Cutter 1.17 Resilience Jeremy Walker and Melinda Cooper 1.18 The resource curse Michael J. Watts 1.19 Scarcity and environmental limits Sara Nelson 1.20 Stewardship Willis Jenkins 1.21 Sustainable development Mark Whitehead 1.22 The tragedy of the commons Kevin Ells 1.23 Uncertainty Andy Stirling 1.22 The tragedy of the commons Kevin Ells The “tragedy of the commons” is the name the biologist Garrett Hardin gave to a thought experiment in a now famous 1968 Science article. It predicted global resource degradation and societal ruin from the net consequences of individuals acting in their short-term interests but at a long-term cost to the environment. This chapter will outline the history of the concept and, after presenting some compelling critiques of it, demonstrate its continuing utility in helping us understand environmental problems. History Hardin’s principal source was an 1832 Oxford lecture W. F. Lloyd published in rebuttal to Thomas Malthus’s influential analysis (in six editions from 1798 to 1830) of unsustainable countervailing growth trends in human population versus agricultural resources. Malthus predicted famine and accelerated death rates in England once geometric growth in human population outpaced linear arithmetic growth in the food supply. Lloyd argued rational self-interest would undermine Malthus’s appeal to “moral restraint” in procreation with reference to the degraded state of England’s common grazing areas. Herdsmen each add cattle to a common area because the long-term loss in food supply is shared by all herdsmen, with only a small net loss for each. By analogy, Malthus’s solutions to limit human population growth, voluntary delayed marriage and sexual abstinence, would fail, and the common labor market was doomed to overstocking to the point of saturation. Hardin reiterated Lloyd’s hypothetical example in a thought experiment intended to demonstrate that global overpopulation would lead to the collapse of Earth’s carrying capacity. Picture a pasture open to all. . . . Explicitly or implicitly, . . . [each herdsman] asks, “What is the utility to me of adding one more animal to my herd?” . . . Since [he] receives all the proceeds from the sale of the additional animal, the positive utility is nearly +1. . . . Since, however, the effects of overgrazing are shared by all. . ., the negative utility for any particular decision-making herdsman is only a fraction of 1. . . . [T]he only sensible course . . . is to add another animal to his herd. . . . Therein is the tragedy. Each man is locked into a system that compels him to increase his herd without limit—in a world that is limited. Ruin is the destination toward which all men rush, each pursuing his own best interest in a society that believes in the freedom of the commons. Freedom in a commons brings ruin to all. Hardin substituted Malthus’s voluntary moral restraint with mandatory restraint by the state, “mutual coercion, mutually agreed upon.” Malthus was of course wrong that the population of England would exhaust its food supply (as the global population has not worldwide), but reiterations of his thesis appeared in later social Darwinist writing, and persisted even after the Third Reich tamped down public support for eugenics. For example, American ornithologist William Vogt and sociologist (and eugenicist) Elmer Pendell warned in their 1948 books against incompatible trends in human fertility and environmental sustainability, publishing detailed updates in 1960. Hardin’s article appeared during a high watermark in public fear of overpopulation. During the late 1960s and early 1970s, biologist Paul Ehrlich’s The Population Bomb (also 1968) and The Limits to Growth (Meadows et al., 1972) sold millions of copies, and Soylent Green, a science fiction film depicting a diabolical solution to preventing famine in an overpopulated future society, was a box-office hit in 1973. Critique Criticism of Hardin’s thesis appeared as early as readers’ letters in a 1968 issue of Science. They offered alternative solutions (contraception, agronomics), or found Hardin’s appeal to the social good contradicted his assertion that people are motivated only by economic self-interest. David Harvey demonstrated that curbing population growth presumes our cultural perspectives on nature, social organization of scarcity, and attitude toward material goods are fixed and immutable (1974, pp. 272– 273). Thousands of people have since proven complex problems have multiple points of engagement by agreeing to buy environmentally neutral or beneficial products, organizing to manage commons areas, and so on. Certainly, if profits are distributed privately, but the costs of resource loss or toxic waste are disbursed among millions of taxpayers, corporate or state entities may find themselves caught up in a system wherein they must pollute. So the “tragedy of the commons” fable clarifies the need for legislative intervention to manage or preserve a wide range of areas or resources analogous to a public common. However, in a post-agrarian society, we cannot logically conflate this narrative with the decision of parents to bear children. The herdsman adds cattle to the commons as capital. Parents’ income from children, if any, does not recapitulate, let alone exceed, the costs incurred in raising them. Even considering the intangible rewards of childrearing, doubling household population does not double the love within it, nor do three children in addition to the first quadruple security in old age. Ironically, Hardin’s fable remains directly relevant to virtually every environmental issue except overpopulation. Hardin did concede thirty years after publishing “The tragedy of the commons” that he should have specified he was writing about “an unmanaged commons” (1998, p. 682), a crucial distinction, as it leaves open the political choice of management scheme (from enforced decree through free market incentives), as well as widely varying responses to local conditions. Elinor Ostrom and her colleagues refer instead to “the drama of the commons” (2002). Ostrom’s extensive research program has documented numerous case studies of local resource commons use ending not in tragedy (though some do) but in perpetual sustainability for the benefit of the communities that manage them. Utility Social commentator Friedrich Engels optimistically argued in 1844 that science would discover a solution to Malthus’s conundrum (the 1950s Green Revolution in high-yield agricultural productivity is the most prominent confirmation of this prediction). But Engels deemed Malthus’s work of great use in posing the problem so clearly. In a sense, the present chapter takes the same stance toward Hardin’s rhetorical argument. Multiple case studies in the half century since Hardin raised his alarm have disproven his claim that the fate of a resource commons is inexorably tragic. Some have suggested retiring the concept for good (“Malthusianism” and “The tragedy of the commons” appear in the anthology This Idea Must Die, 175 short essays answering the question “What scientific idea is ready for retirement?”). Yet the structure of Hardin’s argument retains its utility for environmental rhetoric and advocacy. It is a vicarious narrative in which readers can imagine themselves in the place of the fictional herdsman, subject to his economic temptation to overuse a community resource. Even those who hope they would find workable alternatives can easily infer that numerous neighbors might not. Hardin’s thought experiment proves an implied two-part deductive argument. First, 1. In reading about someone doing X, you can imagine yourself doing X 2. If you can imagine yourself doing X, you can imagine anyone doing X 3. You can therefore imagine everyone doing X. This X is an individual act, relatively harmless in itself to the system in which one is embedded, which would destroy the whole if everyone else did it, too. Here is the second part: 1. Everyone doing X will bring about Y 2. You can imagine everyone doing X (proven in part one) 3. Y will happen. Hardin’s vicarious narrative is not a story narrated in the second person, but a hypothetical example he invites the reader to interpret vicariously (“Picture a pasture open to all”). Rather than depicting a horrifying future that might occur “if this goes on,” Hardin makes a future that logically must occur a new aspect of the reader’s sense of the present. His rhetorical accomplishment is that an audience for his story believes its global implications must occur precisely because they attended to the story and understood it. Conclusion “The tragedy of the commons” remains a compelling rhetorical trope, since it applies with full logical force to multiple environmental issues such as overfishing, deforestation, watershed pollution, and soil erosion. Writers and advocates may still use the structure of Hardin’s argument to demonstrate the danger of relaxing regulations that manage any natural resource commons, or persuade people to see themselves as influential agents in systems in which they are embedded. This ready applicability could account for the persistent popularity of Hardin’s article even for readers opposed politically or ethically to Hardin’s prescriptions for curbing human population, or for whom global overpopulation has cooled as a front-burner environmental concern. When Erlich’s dire scenarios did not materialize, his bestseller passed into obscurity. Hardin remains relevant because the structure of his thought experiment still cogently expresses the potential intractability of many environmental problems. One may plausibly assert that Hardin takes a narrow view of human nature, or call his herdsman the product of a particular, perhaps peculiar, culture. But those engaged in environmental journalism or education may set aside Hardin the policy analyst while imitating Hardin the rhetorician, as have readers familiar only with excerpts of his article. One need not throw out the persuasive baby with the political bath water. Learning resources Here is a compelling and detailed interactive map of twenty-first-century population projections (net births, life expectancy, income, and more) by region: http://www.prb.org/Publications/Datasheets/2015/2015-world-population-datasheet/world-map.aspx#map/world/population/2015 A generally balanced 10-minute survey of population concerns and misconceptions, using the UK as a case study applicable in varying degrees to overcrowded or sparsely populated areas: https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=VUTP93qWV7I A study in contrasts – two thoroughly cited and richly-linked articles on opposite ends of the current spectrum of concern about human population growth: http://www.pewresearch.org/fact-tank/2015/06/08/scientists-more-worried-than-publicabout-worlds-growing-population/ http://www.slate.com/articles/technology/future_tense/2013/01/world_population_may_a ctually_start_declining_not_exploding.single.html Bibliography Brockman, J. (2015) This idea must die: Scientific theories that are blocking progress. New York: Harper Perennial. Dietz, T., Dolšak, N., Ostrom, E. & Stern, P. C. (2002) The drama of the commons. In Ostrom, E., Dietz, T., Dolšak, N., Stern, P.C., Stonich, S. and Weber, E.U. (Eds) The drama of the commons (pp. 3–36). Washington, D.C.: National Academy Press. Ehrlich, P. (1968) The population bomb. New York: Ballantine Books. Engels, F. (2010) Outlines of a critique of political economy. In Marx and Engels: Collected works, volume 3. London: Lawrence and Wishart. Hardin, G. (1968) The tragedy of the commons. Science, 162: 1243–1248. Hardin, G. (1998) Extensions of ‘The tragedy of the commons’. Science, 280, 682. Harvey, D. (1974) Population, resources, and the ideology of science. Economic Geography, 50(3), 256–277. Lloyd, W.F. (1980) W.F. Lloyd on the checks to population. Population and Development Review, 6: 473–496 . Meadows, D.H., Meadows, D.L., Randers, J. & Behrens III, W.W. (1972) The limits to growth: a report for the Club of Rome’s project on the predicament of mankind. New York: New American Library. Ostrom, E., Dietz, T., Dolšak, N., Stern, P.C., Stonich, S. and Weber, E.U. (Eds) (2002) The drama of the commons. Washington, D.C.: National Academy Press. View publication stats