PPE FHS REVISION – 103 ETHICS CONSEQUENTIALISM WHAT IS CONSEQUENTIALISM? Central claim of consequentialism: The rightness or wrongness of an action is determined only by its consequences. A criterion of rightness – answer to the question what makes an act right. Question thus is – can judging an act by its consequences be a way of determining its rightness? → Can be combined with various theories of the good (theories of what makes one’s life go well). These include hedonism, desire theory, and objective list theory. It does not presuppose any of these. Motivating utilitarianism: (1) Claim that (act) consequentialism embodies the “compelling idea” that it’s irrational to choose to bring about a worse rather than a better outcome (SCHEFFLER) → PORTMORE 2009: What you morally ought to do is determined by what you have most reason to do. What you have most reason to do is determined by the reasons there are for preferring one outcome rather than another. (2) Social morality needs to be justified, and the best way to do that is by appealing to the good that it does. (3) Appeal to the moral importance of well-being and impartial concern for others → consequentialism best able to account for this → This motivates utilitarianism in particular – claims (1) and (2) motivate general forms of consequentialism! Utilitarianism is consequentialism + hedonism → Rightness of an act is judged by its consequences, and wellbeing consists in pleasure. Thus, according to utilitarianism, an act is right IFF (and because) of the actions available, it produces the most pleasure. FORMS OF CONSEQUENTIALISM ACT CONSEQUENTIALISM An act is right if and only if, among the alternatives, it has the best consequences. Arguments for act consequentialism: Rule consequentialism, properly applied, would collapse into act consequentialism. → Always instances where not following a rule has significantly better consequences than following it → Including all these cases in rules (“do not steal unless … or … or …”) will ultimately lead to act consequentialism Arguments against act consequentialism: No room for social institutions (e.g. promises) → If both parties know that promise will only be kept if doing so leads to best outcome it loses its value as that is dependent on the assurance that it will be kept These arguments are only specific arguments against act consequentialism. Objections to consequentialism overall will be looked at in the next part. RULE CONSEQUENTIALIS M An act is right if and only if it follows a rule such that, if everyone were to accept and follow this rule, it would lead to the best consequences. Refers to universal compliance. 1 PPE FHS REVISION – 103 ETHICS Arguments for rule consequentialism: Has room for social institutions (e.g. promises) Less demanding than act consequentialism (see demandingness objection) Arguments against rule consequentialism: Collapses into act consequentialism if properly applied (see discussion above) → Response: We also need to consider the implications of a rule such as “do not steal unless … or … or …” on compliance with the moral code. Bringing about widespread acceptance of a simpler code (“do not steal”) is likely to have the better consequences in total over time because people will be more likely to actually adhere to the code as it can more easily be used as an action guiding force Following rules can sometimes lead to a result that is not the best one → E.g. – should I keep a promise made on a desert island to someone who subsequently died? → Solution can be inclusion of a prevent disaster rule: Stick to rule unless breaking it prevents a significantly large disaster THEORIES OF THE GOOD What makes a life good? (I.e.: what should be maximized?) Hedonism: maximize pleasure and minimize pain Obj.: pleasure and pain are distinct from each other – people sometimes feel neither pleasure nor pain, and sometimes they feel both at once. Obj.: higher/lower pleasures (cf. Haydn and the Oyster: prefer very long Oyster live with small pleasures over shorter life of Haydn with higher pleasures?)? → Mill’s qualitative hedonism he suggested as solution is problematic, how to decide between different combinations of higher/lower pleasures? Obj.: not all pleasures are valuable (e.g. pleasure a sadist gets from whipping a victim) Obj.: some things are valuable independently of whether they lead to pleasure or avoid pain (e.g. love for one’s partner doesn’t become less valuable when one can get less pleasure from their partner because the partner has contracted some horrible disease) Pluralist theory of value: deny that all values can be reduced to any single ground (such as pleasure or desire satisfaction) – aim to maximize various values E.g. MOORE 1903 – ideal utilitarianism: takes into account the values of beauty and truth/knowledge in addition to pleasure Has many advantages – can e.g. maintain that social institutions such as promisekeeping are valuable because the values of truthfulness are important Utilitarianism of rights: an act is right if it maximizes respect for (or minimizes violations of) certain specified moral rights DEMANDINGNESS OBJECTION Consequentialism is implausibly demanding. Two forms: (1) Epistemic demandingness objection: under consequentialism, it’s very difficult to work out what the right thing to do in a given situation would be. (2) Deontic demandingness objection: consequentialism makes everything that is morally suboptimal morally impermissible and requires us to do acts that are or should be moral options. 2 PPE FHS REVISION – 103 ETHICS EPISTEMIC DEMANDINGNESS OBJECTION It’s impossible that agents calculate all consequences of each act for every person for all time – but this is what consequentialism seems to require. Res. – misinterpretation: This is based on the assumption that the principle of utility is supposed to be used as a decision procedure/guide – but most classic and contemporary utilitarians and consequentialists don’t propose their principles as decision procedures! SIDGWICK 1907: “it is not necessary that the end which gives the criterion of rightness should always be the end at which we consciously aim” Overall utility is the criterion of what is morally right, not intended to provide a decision procedure → Cf. the laws of physics govern golf ball flight, but golfers don’t need to calculate physical forces while planning shots. → Overall utility can determine which decisions are morally right even if agents don’t need to calculate utilities while making decisions. Cf. RAILTON 1984 – we should be sophisticated consequentialists, i.e. follow the course of action that leads to the best consequences even if that course of action requires us not to adopt a consequentialist perspective in practical deliberation. More extensive discussion on this below in section on Alienation Objection Additional point: most people in most circumstances, on a consequentialist account, ought not to calculate utilities because they’re too likely to make serious miscalculations, leading to actions that will actually reduce utility HARE 1981: most agents usually ought to follow their moral intuitions, because these intuitions evolved to lead us to perform acts that maximize utility, at least in likely circumstances This doesn’t make consequentialism self-refuting – there’s nothing incoherent about having a decision procedure that is separate from one’s criterion of the right! DEONTIC DEMANDINGNESS OBJECTION Consequentialism makes everything that’s morally suboptimal morally impermissible – it requires us to do acts that are/should be moral options. Strange that (a) everything that’s not morally ideal is wrong; (b) there can be no actions that are morally excellent (i.e. better than what’s morally good) Ex.: when I choose to study philosophy rather than working for a charity my choice probably fails to maximize overall utility. But implausible to claim that studying philosophy is wrong. Why is this a problem? → Moral theories should be action-guiding and attainable, this just sets an unachievable ideal. → Also problematic that it strongly interferes with individual freedom and agency? Especially problematic with act consequentialism: Donating almost all my income to charity would lead to best consequences. Because of impartiality – does not matter who is affected by the consequences. Argument: Consequentialism conflicts with conventional morality (and is more demanding than it) and thus cannot be the right moral theory. Obj. – SINGER 1972: Conventional morality is also problematic and has inherent tensions. In structurally similar cases which appeal to the same principle, conventional morality gives us conflicting advice, and is thus a bad guide. Therefore, deference to conventional morality may mean deferring to biases and prejudices which cannot be rationally supported. Argument: 3 PPE FHS REVISION – 103 ETHICS → (1) I should save a child drowning in a pond if I can do so at insignificant costs to me, e.g. just my clothes getting muddy. → (2) This supports the principle “if it’s in our power to prevent something bad from happening, without thereby sacrificing anything of comparable moral importance, we ought, morally, to do it”. → (3) By virtue of this principle, I should e.g. also donate money to charity rather than buying luxury goods, because that allows me to prevent harm at relatively little costs. This is against our understanding of conventional morality but based on the same principle that supported our conventional understanding (1), so conventional morality is flawed. Objection less problematic for rule consequentialism that assumes full compliance: consider the case of donations to charity – if everyone capable of doing so would donate a small amount to charity that would be sufficient. Therefore, a rule “donate a small share of your income to charity” would be sufficient, and not be too demanding. But: in real world, most people don’t follow the moral code (problem of partial compliance) → If we react to this by including a prevent disaster rule, then rule consequentialism could again become very demanding Is this a valid objection? Maybe the perceived demandingness of morality is a product of the fact that we inhabit a world that exhibits a great deal of inequality. Would we object these demands if they were voiced in a more equal world by arguing that, if the world would be more unequal, they would be very demanding? This is for judging the prescriptions of morality (forward-looking) – points made above are more specifically on the judgements of morality on what’s happened (backwardlooking) Res. – compliance. Make consequentialism sensitive to facts of human psychology: people need to have incentives for working, incl. being able to keep a fair degree of their money. A person who donates everything to charity would end up less incentivized and productive, thus producing less to give away to the needy – i.e. this wouldn’t be maximally good! General argument (HOOKER): a very demanding moral code might be impossible to demand universally. Given the natural limitations and biases of human beings, adopting a less demanding morality might have better consequences overall. Obj.: this assumes that moral psychology is fixed – but people can potentially be trained/made to want to be more sacrificing, to take up the welfare of others as a project that brings happiness to their lives Q: how to draw the line between what’s acceptably demanding and what isn’t? Risk of privileging our pre-existing intuitions about what’d be too demanding. Res. – satisficing consequentialism (SLOTE 1984): give up maximization requirement, instead hold that we morally ought to do what creates enough utility. It’s not morally wrong to fail to contribute to a charity if one contributes enough to other charities and if the money that one could contribute does create enough good, i.e. isn’t wasted. Allows for supererogatory actions (morally superior but yet optional actions) and also for importance of agent-relative values (e.g. caring more about family members) Res. – SOBEL 2007: the demandingness objection presupposes that there is a morally relevant distinction between causing harm and allowing harm to occur which consequentialism cannot accommodate. It’s this distinction that grounds the objection in this case, not the demandingness of consequentialism in terms of its absolute costs. 4 PPE FHS REVISION – 103 ETHICS The distinction is required as a premise to justify that the demandingness objection treats the sacrifices the agent is asked to make differently from the sacrifices e.g. patients are asked to make. → Ex.: suppose Joe has two healthy kidneys and can live a decent but reduced life with only one. Further suppose that Sally needs one of Joe’s kidneys to live. Demandingness objection would state that it’s too demanding to ask Joe to give up a kidney. But consider things from Sally’s point of view: she could complain about the excessive demands a different moral theory would impose on her by permitting others to allow her to die when they could aid her. → Thus, can only show that this is a demanding case by focusing particularly on Joe, but this limited focus needs to be justified! That’s why the premise is needed. Therefore, because it needs to presuppose the objection that consequentialism wrongly holds that there is no distinction between causing harm and allowing harm to occur, the demandingness objection isn’t argumentatively forceful on its own. INTEGRITY OBJECTION Consequentialism fails to take the personal characteristics and attributes of the agent into account. (i.e. things that matter to the agent besides the objective maximization of some goal as the consequence of his actions.) (WILLIAMS) Strong claim: the consequentialist procedure entirely looses sight of the fundamental importance of personhood! Arg.: there’s no such thing as impartial agency in the sense of impartiality that utilitarianism requires. Practical deliberation is always first-personal, and we’re thus not “agents of the universal satisfaction system”. No agent can be expected to be what a utilitarian agent has to be – i.e. someone who’s abandoned their own particular life and projects for the impartial point of view of morality. “utilitarianism leaves no room for integrity in the sense of the value to be found in a person’s sticking by what the person regards as ethically necessary or worthwhile”; utilitarianism doesn’t understand integrity because “it cannot coherently describe the relations between a man’s projects and his actions” Doctrine of negative responsibility: we’re as responsible for things that we allow/fail to prevent than we are for things that we actively bring about (has to be endorsed by consequentialists as, in terms of consequences, agency doesn’t matter). This is what WILLIAMS is especially concerned with: utilitarianism cannot make sense of the distinction that exists between my agency and that of other people! Why is agency/integrity important? → Because any world-view which loses sight of the nature of agency doesn’t make sense because it involves deserting one’s individual position to “the point of view of the universe” (SIDGWICK 1981). WILLIAMS: “there is simply no conceivable exercise that consists in stepping completely outside myself and from that point of view evaluating in toto the dispositions, projects, and affections that constitute the substance of my own life” → I.e. we cannot understand the world except through the perspectives of individual agents, and these will always be connected to their agency → Worry isn’t that impartiality as an ethical consideration is not conceivable (it is) but that we cannot reach a point of view of absolute impartiality (the “point of view of the universe”) 5 PPE FHS REVISION – 103 ETHICS Examples: George and the Warfare Laboratory: George is offered a job in a chemical warfare laboratory, something he is strongly opposed to. If he declines the job, someone else will take it and continue the research more intensely than George would have. Should George take the job? Jim and the Indians: Jim comes into a village where a general is planning to kill twenty innocent Indians. The General makes Jim an offer – either he kills one of the Indians and the other 19 will be left alive, or all 20 are killed by the military. Should Jim kill one Indian, despite his strong opposition to killing someone? Problematic that all that matters for assessing what George/Jim should do are the consequences of their actions, without considering the consequences of the actions on them at all, and the importance of them acting. The consequentialist prescriptions (take the job, kill the Indian) are conflicting with the common idea that agents have a special responsibility for what they do. → E.g. Jim might argue that morality requires him not to kill. This is the core of the objection – it’s not about utilitarianism being counterintuitive! (WILLIAMS even states that the utilitarian is right in holding that Jim should kill the one Indian.) Squeamishness objection: people not acting if their action could prevent some harm are just squeamish. E.g. if I’m conducting scientific research on a beach, and see a child drowning in the sea, I should give up the research to save the child. Res.: this isn’t analogous to integrity objection cases which argue that people shouldn’t be morally required to do things that are normally very bad in order to save others Obj.: we do intuitively accept that doing bad things to avoid greater harm is the right course of action. E.g. telling someone who’s trying to murder my friend a lie about my friend’s whereabouts. → I’d just be squeamish if I wouldn’t do that due to my objection to lying! Difference integrity/demandingness objection: issue here isn’t that act of e.g. killing is too demanding, but that morally requiring it would fail to take the personal characteristics and attributes of the agent into account ALIENATION OBJECTION Following a consequentialist morality can alienate the agent from their personal commitments, feelings, from other people, or even from morality itself. (RAILTON) Ex. (STOCKER): person visits friend in hospital, friend is grateful to the visitor. But the visitor points out that he’s only visiting because he knows that doing so will have the best consequences. → Problem: personal character of the relationship is diminished and replaced by an objective requirement. Focus here on consequences of acting rather than failure to respect the inherent importance of integrity/autonomy? Is this what distinguishes it from other objections, e.g. integrity objection? NEAREST AND DEAREST OBJECTION Suppose I have $100 and can either give them to my child or to a stranger who will derive slightly more utility from it. Our intuition would be that I wouldn’t be wrong to give it to my child – but consequentialism would claim that I ought to give it to the stranger. Arg.: this shows that consequentialism is in conflict with what makes a life worth living because it would render the morally good life not worth living. The morally good life for 6 PPE FHS REVISION – 103 ETHICS consequentialism with an agent-neutral theory of value would be the one in which we constantly strive to maximize neutral value. But our personal relationships and life projects are the things that give meaning and value to our lives, and that make them worth living. (JACKSON 1991) PARFIT 1984: such consequentialism is indirectly collectively self-defeating: if several people would try to achieve their aims as given by it, the aims would be worse achieved. → If we all consistently try and succeed in maximizing neutral value, this requires that our strongest desire is that for maximizing neutral value. But if this was our strongest desire, our lives would end up being worse (→ worse consequences!), because it makes our lives go better if we at least sometimes have the desire that benefits are allocated to our nearest and dearest. Response – Agent-relative consequentialism (JACKSON 1991): the right action is determined by (a) its consequences and (b) the probability that an agent can bring about that outcome. It’s more likely that agents can produce a good outcome when they’re able to act according to their inner motivations and pay special attention to their nearest and dearest, thus, the right action to take does depend on individual characteristics of the agent and can include special attention being paid to the agent’s nearest and dearest. Crowd Control Example: a policy inspector using his squad to control a large crowd at a football match will achieve the better results by allocating a specific sector to every member of the squad for which they’ll be responsible compared to telling every squad member that they’re responsible for the entire crowd. → It’s thus better to have policemen specialize – for various reasons, including that this improves coordination, assigns feelings of special responsibility, allows the emergence of personal relations, etc. → All of these increase the probability that the best possible outcome will be brought about. → Same is true in our lives – better to have everyone specialize and assign special value to their own personal relations and projects than try to have everyone care about all problems at the same time. Can be response to other objections (e.g. integrity) too! But: fact that we arrive at this conclusion because it’s the best way of maximizing neutral value is insufficient because it doesn’t mean that the theory now accounts for the importance of close personal relationships; or the inherent importance of autonomy… Obj. (SMITH 2009) – this argument is based entirely on the empirical claims that there are certain relevant limits to our knowledge and self-control. But we can imagine situations in which agents are not so limited. → Suppose a community made up of individuals willing and able to act in ways that increase expected neutral value for a group that they’re not close to, even if that comes at a cost to them. Agent-relative consequentialism would demand from them that they don’t pay special attention to their nearest and dearest, and they’d act wrongly if they’d do so. Underlines point above that just because outcomes align in certain cases this theory can’t account for the inherent importance of close relationships, integrity, … RAILTON’S SOLUTION – OBJECTIVE VS SUBJECT IVE HEDONISM RAILTON – the paradox of hedonism: Adopting as one’s exclusive ultimate end in life the pursuit of maximum happiness may well prevent one from having certain experiences or engaging in certain sorts of relationships or commitments that are among the greatest sources of happiness 7 PPE FHS REVISION – 103 ETHICS Proposed solution by RAILTON 1984: distinguish between criterion of the right and decisionmaking procedure. Consequentialists don’t need to endorse consequentialist attitudes and deliberative strategies which are the key source of the alienation problem. Distinguish between objective and subjective consequentialism: According to subjective consequentialism, one should adopt the hedonistic point of view as a guide to action: Whenever one deliberates on what to do, one should do whatever seems to contribute to one’s happiness According to objective consequentialism, one, should follow the course of action that would contribute the most to one’s happiness – even if that course of action would require one not to adopt a hedonistic perspective in practical deliberation A sophisticated consequentialist will adopt objective consequentialism and not be committed to subjective consequentialism (“is prepared to eschew the hedonistic point of view whenever taking this point of view conflicts with following an objectively hedonistic course of action”) → Compare a chess player who realizes that not playing with the sole objective to win but rather out of an enjoyment of the game increases his chances of winning → Note that RAILTON talks of hedonism, but can apply the same distinction to consequentialism. Arg.: To avoid the alienation problem, we should become sophisticated consequentialists, endorsing objective consequentialism and recognizing that sometimes we will be required to therefore reject a characteristically consequentialist mode of deliberation → E.g. if there is a gas leak it’s better to react immediately rather than first calculate which reaction would have the best consequences – until it is too late, which would mean that overall, the possibly worst consequences were caused But: Ultimately, the same problem remains: What is the ultimate root reason for you visiting the friend in hospital? It might be that you’re their friend (not that you’re adopting a hedonistic perspective in practical deliberation), but if the root reason for you being their friend is that it has the best consequences, then the problem isn’t avoided. Obj. – STOCKER 1976: Sophisticated consequentialism is psychologically incoherent. Arg.: assume that there’s a division between what makes an act right and what motivates an agent to act (sophisticated consequentialism). If the agent would completely ignore what’s right in deciding his actions, the decision procedure would never change to maximize good consequences. Thus, the agent would be forced to constantly decide between doing what they’re motivated to do (as endorsed by the theory) and doing what the theory directly says is the right thing to do (something they need to be sensitive too to some extent). 8 PPE FHS REVISION – 103 ETHICS EXAM STRATEGY / QUESTION ANALYSIS A lot of ‘moving parts’ here – arguments and solutions (e.g. agent-relative consequentialism, sophisticated consequentialism) can be used in response to various arguments/objections! If question gives an argument to discuss, make sure to identify and discuss all the premises! E.g. “Consequentialism is impossibly demanding. So, it cannot be correct.” (2014) – two premises here: (1) Consequentialism is impossibly demanding. (2) A moral theory that is impossibly demanding cannot be correct. (suppressed premise) → Need to talk about both! If just (1) would have been relevant, the question would just have stated “Consequentalism is impossibly demanding, discuss”. There are many different forms of consequentialism with distinct motivations → due to these distinct motivations be cautious about trying to present one theory as the solution to problems with another: good solutions to problems for a theory address the problems without sacrificing what makes the theory attractive in the first place PAST QUESTIONS DEMANDINGNESS OBJECTION − − − − Do demandingness objections to consequentialism illicitly assume that a moral requirement to X implies an all-things-considered requirement to X? (2018) Is satisficing consequentialism an adequate response to the worry that maximizing consequentialism is too demanding? (2017a) “Consequentialism is impossibly demanding. So it cannot be correct.” Discuss. (2014a) “Unless we are to be allowed to rewrite our moral duties to suit our convenience, there can be no truth in the claim that consequentialism is too demanding.” Discuss. (2010b) INTEGRITY OBJECTION − (a) Can a consequentialist make sense of the idea that I should be more concerned with my wrongdoings than with yours? Does she need to? OR (b) Suppose that Charity A and Charity B avert the same number of deaths per unit of money donated, but that Charity A works by campaigning for peace while Charity B works by immunising against life-threatening diseases. If killing were worse than letting die, would this ground any case for donating to Charity A rather than Charity B? (2016) ALIENATION OBJECTION − − Must consequentialism misunderstand the value of close personal relations? (2012a) Can a utilitarian be a good friend? Does it matter whether or not she can? (2011b) 9 PPE FHS REVISION – 103 ETHICS VARIOUS − − − − − − − How much of a problem is it that we can’t foresee all the consequences of our actions? (2017b) Does act-consequentialism better approximate the demands of beneficence than commonsense morality? (2016) “Since a deontologist can always hold that rule-breakings are intrinsically bad, there is no serious question over whether consequentialism is true – the question is only which consequences are important.” Is that so? (2014b) (a) “Consequentialism is not a complete moral theory since it only talks about right action and not about our duties to other people.” Discuss. OR (b) “Consequentialism is false, since the consequences of teaching it would be bad.” Discuss. (2013) “Consequentialism can make no sense of excusable wrongs, so consequentialism is false.” Discuss. (2012b) Can it ever be morally right to bring about a worse rather than a better state of affairs? (2011a) “Consequentialism is a good theory for bureaucratic planners, but unless every aspect of life should be bureaucratically planned, it cannot be a good ethical theory.” Discuss. (2010a) 10