Nietzsche's Use of Amor Fati in Ecce Homo Author(s): Brian Domino Source: Journal of Nietzsche Studies, Vol. 43, No. 2 (Autumn 2012), pp. 283-303 Published by: Penn State University Press Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/10.5325/jnietstud.43.2.0283 Accessed: 18-02-2016 14:47 UTC REFERENCES Linked references are available on JSTOR for this article: http://www.jstor.org/stable/10.5325/jnietstud.43.2.0283?seq=1&cid=pdf-reference# references_tab_contents You may need to log in to JSTOR to access the linked references. Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/ info/about/policies/terms.jsp JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org. Penn State University Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Journal of Nietzsche Studies. http://www.jstor.org This content downloaded from 165.190.89.176 on Thu, 18 Feb 2016 14:47:48 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions Nietzsche’s Use of Amor Fati in Ecce Homo Brian Domino Abstract: In Ecce Homo, Nietzsche flaunts his credentials to convince his readers to take him seriously. At the same time, he needs to counteract the human herd instinct. In the works of 1888, Nietzsche diagnoses humanity as approaching the enervated state of the last men. Nietzsche knows that he is similarly afflicted, so he must do what he can to avoid spreading an infected teaching while trying to improve his readers’ health. At the end of “Why I Am So Clever,” he mentions amor fati. By the time his readers reach this section, Nietzsche has made it clear that he has failed to live up to the ideal of amor fati. This failure forces them to question whether he has failed because it’s a poor teaching or whether the teaching is a healthy one despite his failings. In either case, Nietzsche succeeds in getting his readers to focus on the teaching, not the teacher. E cce Homo aims to prepare its readers for the coming reevaluation of all values to be inaugurated by The Antichrist(ian). Nietzsche explicitly tells his friends and publisher this, and he is relatively clear about it in Ecce Homo itself.1 From the opening line “Seeing that before long I must confront humanity with the most difficult demand ever made of it,” the reader knows Ecce Homo is a propaedeutic. Again in letters and in Ecce Homo itself, Nietzsche describes the preparation as consisting of an explanation of who exactly he is.2 The opening line continues: “[I]t seems indispensable to me to say who I am.”3 If humanity is going to abandon its values for a set of new tablets, we need to know who this bifurcator of history is and why we ought to believe him. So Nietzsche flaunts his credentials to convince his readers to take him seriously. In the four sections of Ecce Homo, Nietzsche demonstrates that he is so wise and clever, that he writes such good books, and—in case he hasn’t convinced the reader so far—that he is a destiny. After reading Nietzsche’s apology, readers should be able to decide whether to continue following “the crucified” (EH “Destiny” 9) or to jump ship and side with Nietzsche. This judicial relationship between author and reader is problematized by Nietzsche’s discovery of the disease of decadence.4 This disease, which seemingly afflicts all late moderns (TI “Skirmishes” 39), including Nietzsche himself, inverts the afflicted’s sense of the salubrious and the toxic. This i­ nversion Journal of Nietzsche Studies, Vol. 43, No. 2, 2012. Copyright © 2012 The Pennsylvania State University, University Park, PA. 283 This content downloaded from 165.190.89.176 on Thu, 18 Feb 2016 14:47:48 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 284 Brian Domino s­ymptomatically resembles the reversal that occurs in addiction, where the addict wrongly believes that the addictive substance or behavior greatly improves her life. Nietzsche tries to assuage his readers about his status, n­ oting that he has experienced both enervating decadence and supreme health (EH “Wise” 2). Unfortunately, merely having experienced both does not entail that Nietzsche can correctly distinguish the two. Usually experiencing both sickness and health puts you in a position to know when you’re sick and when you’re not. As a decadent, Nietzsche resembles an addict who declares that she feels healthy (EH P:3). We cannot reliably infer anything about her or Nietzsche’s health merely on the basis of their self-appraisals. That he undergoes a peak philosophical experience during “an uninterrupted three-day migraine, accompanied by laborious vomiting of phlegm” (EH “Wise” 1) is reason enough to question his ability to discern healthy states from sick ones. Nietzsche himself seems a bit confused on this score. He first praises the “dialectician's clarity” (“DialektikerKlarheit”) occasioned by his physical sickness but then asks his readers to remember that he understands “dialect as a symptom of decadence” (“Dialektik als Décadence-Symptom”) (EH “Wise” 1). Thus, if Nietzsche were to instruct his readers, he could never be certain whether the advice came from Nietzsche the hale philosopher or Nietzsche the weak decadent. Of equal concern to Nietzsche is his readers’ health. They are unlikely to be strong enough for the revaluation for which he wishes to enlist them. If his readers are decadents, which they almost assuredly are, they will continue to think Christianity healthier than Nietzsche’s alternative, thereby stymieing the revaluation. If his readers are healthy, they will adopt his teachings provided that Nietzsche is also healthy (or at least wrote only when healthy). If he is sick, he will infect a healthy population much as Socrates unknowingly did (EH “BT” 1; TI “Socrates” 11). In an effort to avoid repeating this world historic catastrophe, Nietzsche claims that he’s not a prophet, the founder of a religion, or more generally the sort of person anyone ought to follow (EH P:2, EH “Destiny” 1). Thus while writing Ecce Homo, Nietzsche needs to hope for the best situation (i.e., that he is healthy but his readers are decadent) while working to prevent the epidemiological nightmare that would ensue if the worst were true (i.e., Nietzsche is decadent; his readers weren’t until he infected them). Given Nietzsche’s self-assessment as the authority on decadence and as a psychologist of unparalleled acumen, it would be surprising if he did not take steps to prevent himself from contributing to the spread of decadence if he could.5 Given more time, I would argue that he employs various strategies in Ecce Homo to guide the reader safely through his approach to convalescence.6 Here I focus on one particular strategy, which Nietzsche uses in connection with amor fati. I begin by distinguishing amor fati from eternal recurrence This content downloaded from 165.190.89.176 on Thu, 18 Feb 2016 14:47:48 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions Nietzsche’s Use of Amor Fati in Ecce Homo 285 because interpreters often conflate these two teachings. I argue that Nietzsche’s chronic failure to love his own fate in Ecce Homo is strategic. Specifically, his self-reported inability to love his own fate forces readers to determine whether amor fati is an idea worth adopting on its own terms rather than on the basis of its pedigree.7 This helps to quarantine Nietzsche from his readers so that he does not inadvertently worsen them, as Socrates did his auditors and, via Christianity, most Europeans. Disentangling Amor Fati from Eternal Recurrence Nietzsche’s signature teachings include eternal recurrence (or the eternal return of the same) and amor fati. Nietzsche says little about either in his own voice in works he intended for publication. Indeed, I have already written amor fati more times than Nietzsche did in those works. While he may have written “eternal recurrence” more times than I have so far, he does not tell us much about it. Among the few helpful passages is one from Ecce Homo where he glosses “eternal recurrence” as “the unconditional and infinitely repeated circular course of all things” (EH “BT” 3). Given such meager assistance, scholars have been forced to fill the doctrinal lacunae themselves. And fill they have; few aspects of Nietzsche’s thought have been so thoroughly commented on as eternal recurrence. As I have nothing to add to that literature, I focus on the much less studied teaching of amor fati.8 Many discussions of eternal recurrence and amor fati focus on Thus Spoke Zarathustra. Eternal recurrence is Zarathustra’s signature teaching (EH “Z” 1), so it is not surprising that scholars concentrate on the eponymous book. Nonetheless, Thus Spoke Zarathustra sheds no light on amor fati because that phrase never occurs there. Thus Spoke Zarathustra is, of course, highly impressionistic, and I doubt that I could demonstrate conclusively that amor fati does not appear there conceptually.9 Nonetheless, because one can find almost whatever one desires in Thus Spoke Zarathustra, I hew closely to the literal appearances of the term amor fati.10 At the level of the names of the teachings, the two are not obviously related. “Amor fati” denotes an emotion or at least a psychological response; whereas “eternal recurrence,” understood as a cosmological claim, does nothing of the sort. Conversely, the notion of circularity or repetition is not obvious in fati. In terms of these distinctions, the most widely accepted understanding of the relationship between eternal recurrence and amor fati is that amor fati names the correct attitude to have toward eternal recurrence. I discuss that interpretation shortly. First, I want to discuss perhaps the second most popular interpretation, namely that amor fati and eternal recurrence are at least roughly synonymous. I argue that both interpretations are incorrect. This content downloaded from 165.190.89.176 on Thu, 18 Feb 2016 14:47:48 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 286 Brian Domino Amor Fati as Eternal Recurrence Some commentators explicitly equate the two doctrines. For example, C. Heike Schotten speaks of “Nietzsche’s reformulation of eternal recurrence into amor fati.”11 Roberto Alejandro is equally explicit: “Eternal recurrence is, in Nietzsche’s well-known phrase, amor fati.”12 Bernd Magnus accepts both of the now dominant interpretations: “The expression ‘amor fati’. . . is, of course, a handy synonym for eternal recurrence and the attitude Nietzsche recommends.”13 Leslie Paul Thiele follows suit: “To embrace one’s fate, indeed, to desire its repetition eternally, is the greatest affirmation of life and love of self.”14 Only slightly less explicit is Françoise Lionnet. Commenting on the passage in Ecce Homo where Nietzsche defines his kind of redemption as converting “every ‘it was’ into a ‘thus I willed it’” (EH “Z” 8), Lionnet writes that “this form of redemption is the basic theme of amor fati, or eternal return.”15 Some scholars import amor fati into Thus Spoke Zarathustra. For example, Al Lingis refers to “Zarathustra’s teaching of amor fati.”16 Since amor fati is not present in Thus Spoke Zarathustra, presumably Lingis sees the teachings as interchangeable. Similarly, Rose Pfeffer brings up amor fati while discussing Zarathustra and has Zarathustra espouse amor fati, as does Hugh Silverman.17 Ultimately, though, the two are not identical: “Amor fati becomes the foundation of Nietzsche's new ethics and finds its fullest expression in the teaching of the eternal recurrence,” but how they differ is unclear.18 Some commentators hover around equating the two. Max R. Layton, for example, writes that “fundamentally, amor fati and the doctrine of eternal recurrence are attitudes towards existence” and “the concepts of amor fati, eternal recurrence, and tragedy define the word ‘Dionysus.’”19 Others seem unsure whether the two are the same. Nel Grillaert sometimes talks about amor fati and eternal recurrence as if they were the same, and sometimes he separates the two but gives no description of the difference.20 Commentators who equate the two teachings generally do not offer evidence in support of this equation. Layton and Ridley are the only two of whom I am aware who offer textual evidence to support equating amor fati with eternal recurrence. Layton offers two arguments for considering amor fati, eternal recurrence, and tragedy as “interlocking ideas.”21 The first is that “all except amor fati are defined on the same page.” Textual proximity would be hermeneutically relevant in the interpretation of most philosophers. In the case of Nietzsche with his infamous flitting from topic to topic, it is less than convincing to argue that three ideas are tightly connected because two are defined on the same page (specifically, EH “BT” 3). On that same page, Nietzsche defines the tragic philosopher and Dionysian philosophy, both of which seem more helpful in defining “Dionysus” than an absent phrase. Layton goes on to claim that “taken together, they are the first test of strength of the overman, or more precisely, This content downloaded from 165.190.89.176 on Thu, 18 Feb 2016 14:47:48 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions Nietzsche’s Use of Amor Fati in Ecce Homo 287 they are the foundation of the overman’s mental make-up.” I discuss a version of this hypothesis in the next section. For now, I note that if amor fati can be connected to the Übermensch, it is not because the Übermensch “conceives of reality as it is” (EH “Destiny” 5). Nietzsche never offers any proof that our lives are fated, at least not in connection with amor fati, so it is difficult to see how amor fati describes the world as it is. Ridley asserts that “in Ecce Homo Nietzsche hails himself as the thinker of eternal recurrence,” a claim that suggests he thinks that eternal recurrence and amor fati are identical in Nietzsche’s mind (Ridley himself thinks that eternal recurrence should be jettisoned because it “undermines and cheapens” amor fati).22 Yet, a careful reading of Ecce Homo shows that Nietzsche keeps eternal recurrence at arm’s length. It is attributed to Zarathustra (EH “Z” 6) and possibly to his forerunner, Heraclitus (EH “BT” 3). Even when on the verge of taking credit for eternal recurrence in the famous account of his hiking vision, Nietzsche uses the passive voice. The idea of eternal recurrence “came to” (“kam”) Nietzsche, “Zarathustra came into being [entstand],” and Zarathustra as a type “overtook” (“ü b e r f i e l”) Nietzsche (all in EH “Z” 1). He won’t even take amanuensical credit but says “it was penned” (“er ist . . . hingeworfen”). The closest Nietzsche comes to taking ownership of eternal recurrence is his bizarre account of the history of the idea in him that parallels stories of divine insemination (EH “Z” 1).23 Ridley then quotes the definition of amor fati in “Why I Am So Clever” in Ecce Homo and the same passage that Layton cites. We’ve already seen the problems with the latter piece of evidence, and I address the problems with using EH “Clever” 10 below. So much for my argument via negativa. I now want to turn to Nietzsche’s texts to show that amor fati is not just rebranded eternal recurrence.24 I note several differences between the two teachings. First, amor fati does not apply to everything but only to what is necessary. Then I note several differences between the two concerning love, memory, and the perspective implied by each teaching. Nietzsche uses the phrase amor fati in only four passages in books he intended to be published (i.e., excluding The Will to Power and other works in the Nachlass). To place all the evidence on the table, here are those four passages in chronological order: I want to learn to see more and more as beautiful what is necessary in things; then I shall be one of those who makes things beautiful. Amor fati: let that be my love henceforth! (GS 276) My formula for greatness in a human being is amor fati: that one wants nothing to be different, not forward, not backward, not in all eternity. Not merely bear what is necessary, still less conceal it—all idealism is mendaciousness in the face of what is necessary—but love it. (EH “Clever” 10) [W]hat is necessary does not hurt me; amor fati is my inmost nature. (EH CW 4) This content downloaded from 165.190.89.176 on Thu, 18 Feb 2016 14:47:48 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 288 Brian Domino As my inmost nature teaches me, whatever is necessary—as seen from the heights and in the sense of a great economy—is also the useful par excellence: one should not only bear it, one should also love it. Amor fati: that is my inmost nature. (NCW “Epilogue” 1) In each excerpt, Nietzsche limits the application of amor fati to the necessary. Each passage implies that not everything is necessary, but none do so unambiguously. Those who interpret the two teachings as (roughly) identical would note that each passage is logically compatible with everything being necessary, as would be the case if everything repeated eternally. Reading “what is necessary” as everything entails that these four passages enjoin us to see everything as beautiful (GS 276), to love everything (EH “Clever” 10 and NCW “Epilogue” 1), and to believe that nothing can hurt us (EH CW 4). These implications do not fit with Nietzsche’s oeuvre. Nonetheless, some scholars accept the erotic consequence. For example, Irving Singer glosses amor fati as “cosmic love.”25 Michel Haar similarly says that “amor fati is nothing but the echo of the love—both jubilant and rational—that Being has for itself.”26 Others, like Magnus, balk at universal love since it would include loving the extermination camps.27 To the best of my knowledge, no one pursues the equation with unwavering consistency and attributes to Nietzsche the teachings of universal beauty and invincibility. This is understandable since one would be hard pressed to find a passage in his works that does not contradict at least one of these injunctions, much less to locate support for them. Barring an acceptable interpretative principle that would exclude the unwanted consequences while retaining the two ostensible injunctions to universal love, amor fati and eternal recurrence must differ nontrivially on this basis alone. Nonetheless, further distinctions can be made. Another difficulty with equating the two teachings is that eternal recurrence does not produce love. It is often noted that if everything repeats, including the inauspicious night when one first learned of eternal recurrence from the demon, the proper response is indifference. If you cannot remember previous iterations, then eternal recurrence changes nothing. For all we know, and for all it matters, our current lives are repetitions. Amor fati does not similarly rely on memory, nor does it require that we adopt a supra-self perspective.28 If we consider eternal recurrence as a psychological test, we must be thinking of the oft-quoted passage from The Gay Science. That passage does not suggest love as a possible response. The closest it comes is this portion of the section: “How well disposed would you have to become to yourself and to life to long for nothing more ardently than for this last eternal sanctioning and sealing?” Even if we extend the meaning of “love” to include “ardently” the objects of love differ dramatically. Amor fati enjoins us to love our fate, while our ardent longing aims not at our lives but at the teaching of eternal recurrence understood as a “sanctioning and sealing.” Lastly, as a psychological claim, it is false to say This content downloaded from 165.190.89.176 on Thu, 18 Feb 2016 14:47:48 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions Nietzsche’s Use of Amor Fati in Ecce Homo 289 the more one loves an event, the more one wishes it could be repeated. I do not claim that a crisp line can be drawn, but it seems unlikely that anyone would want even the best moments of her life repeated infinitely. Part of what makes the events valuable is their singularity or at least rareness. To have them occur more often would make them mundane. If we do not want our best experiences repeated infinitely, it seems that we would not want our entire lives to be so repeated. At best we might be indifferent to the repetition of the quotidian events and perhaps might want the bad events repeated until they had lost their sting, but that certainly is not what Nietzsche had in mind. Amor fati as the Best “Response” to Eternal Recurrence The most common way to connect the two teachings is to say that amor fati names the appropriate or lauded response to eternal recurrence. As Maudemarie Clark puts it, amor fati is “the attitude of one who affirms eternal recurrence.”29 I neither wish to nor need to be precise about the relationship between eternal recurrence and amor fati. It is perfectly acceptable to me that Julian Young describes amor fati as “willing” eternal recurrence, “desiring” eternal recurrence, “embracing” it, and “the faith that allows one to will the eternal recurrence.”30 On this view eternal recurrence explains the mechanism by which our lives are predetermined or fated. This is a helpful connection to make because amor fati does not explain why we ought to believe that our lives are fated or even in what sense they are fated. Different interpreters put slightly different spins on the exact connection between eternal recurrence and amor fati. Michael Casey, for example, says that eternal recurrence makes worldly becoming not only necessary but also meaningless. On his account amor fati means that “man love his fate even though it is meaningless.”31 André Van der Braak writes that “in order to realize such an attitude of amor fati, the will itself . . . must be liberated from revenge. It must be able to passionately embrace the horrifying thought of eternal recurrence.”32 Thiele asserts that “amor fati is the disposition of the overman.”33 Thiele is not alone in describing those who can withstand the thought of eternal recurrence and love their fates as Übermenschen, and it seems reasonable to think that if anyone can do this, the Übermenschen could. Yet, if amor fati describes the attitude of those who can withstand the thought of eternal recurrence, and if one kind of such people are Übermenschen, it is strange that Nietzsche does not use the term amor fati in Zarathustra. Both eternal recurrence and amor fati are introduced in book 4 of The Gay Science, which Nietzsche saw to the publisher only four months before beginning work on Zarathustra. So both were very much on his mind. Since both Nietzsche and Zarathustra mention the Übermensch, we would expect at least one of them to make the eternal recurrence-amor fati -Übermensch connection, but neither do. Moreover, there is a sharp bifurcation between Zarathustra and eternal This content downloaded from 165.190.89.176 on Thu, 18 Feb 2016 14:47:48 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 290 Brian Domino recurrence, on the one hand, and Nietzsche and amor fati, on the other. As I have noted, Nietzsche distances himself from eternal recurrence in The Gay Science and Ecce Homo, while he takes ownership of amor fati in both books, calling it his “inmost nature” (EH CW 4), his formula (EH “Clever” 10), and his love (GS 276). Thus, if amor fati does name an attitude toward eternal recurrence, it isn’t that of the Übermenschen. In what follows, I argue that amor fati does not name an attitude toward eternal recurrence. To say that amor fati names the proper or best response to eternal recurrence suggests that they ought to be separate kinds of things. Specifically, it implies that eternal recurrence should be a descriptive account of the world and amor fati should describe a psychological or ethical state. Although many commentators, and indeed Nietzsche himself, have tried to provide scientific evidence for the truth of eternal recurrence, no one has succeeded. This failure is conspicuous in his published works, where Nietzsche offers no evidence to support eternal recurrence.34 As we have seen, eternal recurrence as a cosmological claim is incompatible with amor fati, first, because eternal recurrence makes everything necessary, while the amor fati passages suggest that not everything is necessary, and, second, because amor fati requires memory (i.e., you can’t love what you’ve forgotten) while eternal recurrence requires a complete disjunction between iterations of the same life (i.e., there’s no déjà vu in eternal recurrence). Because of these and other problems, most scholars today agree that eternal recurrence is not a descriptive claim.35 Instead, eternal recurrence is a psychological or moral test or perhaps a quasi imperative.36 If it is a test, whether moral or diagnostic, it must include a means of evaluating the results. The best textual evidence for this view comes from The Gay Science: “‘Do you desire this once more and innumerable times more?’ would lie upon your actions as the greatest weight” (GS 341). In contrast, amor fati does not offer prescriptive ethical advice. If anything, amor fati would offer solace, not regret or fear of eternal repetition. The demon then describes outcomes to hearing this, both of which are psychological. There is no need for amor fati as the proper response to eternal recurrence because eternal recurrence already contains one. My argument has thus far been more conceptual than textual. This is partly because most commentators do not provide support for their assertion that amor fati names a particular attitude toward eternal recurrence. Among those who do offer textual evidence, a passage from Beyond Good and Evil and one from Ecce Homo are the most commonly cited. I discuss each in turn. Da Capo! Two recent commentaries on Beyond Good and Evil claim that section 56 links eternal recurrence and amor fati.37 In this passage, Nietzsche suggests that if one thinks through pessimism from a vantage point beyond good and evil, one might stumble across “the opposite ideal: the ideal of the most high-spirited, This content downloaded from 165.190.89.176 on Thu, 18 Feb 2016 14:47:48 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions Nietzsche’s Use of Amor Fati in Ecce Homo 291 alive, and world-affirming human being who has not only come to terms and learned to get along with whatever was and is, but who wants to have what was and is repeated into all eternity, shouting insatiably da capo—not only to himself but to the whole play and spectacle” (BGE 56). Nietzsche goes on to state that this individual makes this “whole play and spectacle” necessary. It is difficult to know how to separate the eternal recurrence portion from the amor fati portion, if indeed both are present. Perhaps eternal recurrence is the “da capo” while shouting it insatiably is amor fati. Yet this bifurcation shortchanges both eternal recurrence and amor fati. Eternal recurrence as a going back, as a cosmological repetition, is untenable, as already shown. As a test, “da capo” (without emotional inflection, as might be found in a score) is an eviscerated version of the demon’s greatest weight. Eternal recurrence is presented here as a psychological stance, not a test. The passage does not assert that events will reoccur, just that the sort of person Nietzsche describes would want them to. We have already seen that this view leaves amor fati without a role. Either way, the “fati” half of amor fati is lost in the purely psychological half of this interpretation. These problems aside, one curious feature of BGE 56 is its silence about the future. The individual adopting Nietzsche’s recommended perspective seems to be at the end of his life. The passage talks about this individual’s relationship to “whatever is and was” but not will be. The cry of “da capo”—even if Nietzsche did not mean da capo al fine—is a retrogressive movement. At most, this individual’s desire for the repetition of the past and present is future directed. In contrast, Nietzsche generally presents amor fati as future directed. Most obviously, his New Year’s resolution in The Gay Science is future directed. In Nietzsche contra Wagner it is also presented as a normative teaching to guide future behavior. In the passage in Ecce Homo to which we now turn, the future is explicitly mentioned in the “definition” of amor fati: “[O]ne wants nothing to be different, not forward [. . .]” (EH “Clever” 10). In sum, BGE 56 provides more textual evidence that Nietzsche means eternal recurrence psychologically and not cosmologically and yet still does not connect eternal recurrence with amor fati. Indeed, amor fati is inconsistent with this passage. Not in All Eternity Of the four amor fati passages, the one that comes closest to connecting amor fati with eternal recurrence is this oft-cited one from Ecce Homo: “[A]mor fati: that one wants nothing to be different, not forward, not backward, not in all eternity [in alle Ewigkeit nicht]” (EH “Clever” 10). This definition ostensibly connects amor fati and eternal recurrence in two ways. First, Nietzsche seems to understand fate in a more encompassing way than it is traditionally understood. When we say that Oedipus was fated, we don’t mean anything more than that no matter what he did, he would kill Laius and sleep with Jocasta. We do not mean that every feature of his life was destined to occur. This content downloaded from 165.190.89.176 on Thu, 18 Feb 2016 14:47:48 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 292 Brian Domino In contrast, Nietzsche here seems to be invoking the same sense of fate used by the demon in The Gay Science to describe eternal recurrence. Second, there is the use of “eternity,” which doubtless invokes “eternal” in Nietzsche’s readers’ minds. This similarity is more easily addressed than the first. Obviously, Nietzsche is not committed to understanding “eternity” as designating circular and endlessly repetitious. As in English, in German, “eternity” can be used hyperbolically to mean a long time. This understanding fits the text as well as the more loaded understanding of eternity. It is also supported in the very next sentence: “Not merely bear what is necessary, still less conceal it—all idealism is mendaciousness in the face of what is necessary—but love it” (EH “Clever” 10). If every aspect of one’s life were fated (as would be the case with eternal recurrence), then there would be no need for the qualification “what is.” Rather than assume that Nietzsche was as careful when dealing with modals as philosophers are today, I want to examine Clark’s reconstruction of this passage. Clark has one of the most sophisticated and nuanced interpretations of eternal recurrence with which I am familiar. She asserts that to interpret it as implying a universal sense of fate is incorrect because such an interpretation is “completely incompatible with Nietzsche’s emphasis on change and creation.”38 It’s unclear why living an entirely fated life would be bereft of change. To be entirely fated is not to be a still life. It is true that sub specie dei, there would not be any change, but that perspective is not one Nietzsche finds viable. What perhaps she means is that lacking free will, I cannot make changes to my life in the fullest sense. She undoubtedly means something similar by “creation” as well. Although interpretations along these lines doubtless led to the existential reading of Nietzsche, it is not one that I find true to the texts. In any event, as I am willing to accept that the straightforward reading of “fate” in this passage is incorrect, I move on to her conclusion: “It therefore seems reasonable to interpret amor fati as the attitude of one who affirms eternal recurrence.”39 Knowing that this is quite a leap, she explains that “not wanting anything different in the past means accepting the past in the sense of affirming its eternal recurrence.”40 Again, this need not follow. I might not want anything in my past changed because any such change would have unknown consequences. More simply, being content with the way in which my life has unfolded is not the same as wishing its infinite repetition. As is now clear, we need to examine what Nietzsche means by necessity in connection with amor fati. The Psychology of the Necessary Nietzsche presents amor fati as a practical teaching. In The Gay Science he reports that amor fati is his New Year’s resolution. In Ecce Homo, it is his means of coping with being ignored by his contemporaries (EH CW 4). Severing amor fati from This content downloaded from 165.190.89.176 on Thu, 18 Feb 2016 14:47:48 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions Nietzsche’s Use of Amor Fati in Ecce Homo 293 eternal recurrence brings with it a pragmatic difficulty. If we understand eternal recurrence as an ethical injunction, it is easy to apply to our lives because it applies to everything. In contrast, to apply amor fati requires a means of differentiating the necessary from the accidental.41 If we cannot figure this out, either amor fati is ultimately incoherent or it can’t be rendered from eternal recurrence. Nietzsche suggests that at a suitable height the necessary-accidental distinction will be clear (NCW “Epilogue” 1), but it’s difficult to see how this guidance is helpful. From a suprahuman distance, one can imagine understanding world events as both determined machinations and random eruptions. Take, for example, the genealogy of morality presented in the first essay of On the Genealogy of Morals. Nietzsche implicitly lauds his own ability to see across a vast temporal horizon (GM I:8), but he is not clear as to whether the emergence of the priests was necessary. He describes their development out of the nobles as “easily” done and “particularly likely” (GM I:7), descriptions that dance along the razor’s edge between necessity and contingency. Moreover, the continued wrangling over the question of free will indicates that humans are inept at making the distinction in a way that is widely accepted at any altitude.42 Couple this with Nietzsche’s general disdain for metaphysics, and it seems likely that in the four passages containing the term amor fati, he is not using the phrase “what is necessary” in the metaphysical sense. In Beyond Good and Evil, Nietzsche shifts the topos of the free will question from metaphysics to the psyche, asserting that “psychology is now again the path to the fundamental problems” (BGE 23). The question is no longer the perhaps unanswerable “Is this event necessary?” but rather “What beliefs do I hold that lead me to think of this event as necessary?” He diagnoses the desire for “freedom of the will” as a manifestation of the desire to “bear the entire and ultimate responsibility for one’s actions oneself” (BGE 21). Nietzsche then proceeds to discuss the other half of the problem: [T]he “unfreedom of the will” is regarded as a problem from two entirely opposite standpoints, but always in a profoundly personal manner: some will not give up their “responsibility,” their belief in themselves, the personal right to their merits at any price [. . .]. Others, on the contrary, do not wish to be answerable for anything, or blamed for anything, and owing to an inward self-contempt, seek to lay the blame for themselves somewhere else. (BGE 21) These two diagnoses can be applied to an individual’s response to the teaching of amor fati. Those who reject it might do so because it robs them of merit for what they believe to be their actions. Conversely, others wish to embrace amor fati precisely to avoid responsibility. Neither reaction manifests a love of fate. Amor fati, then, is not only a teaching to be followed but also a psychological test to be conducted. Each of us must ask ourselves “why do I not love my fate?” before launching headlong into a campaign to force ourselves to do so. Separating the necessary from the contingent is not a matter only of examining our ideals related to responsibility or metaphysical freedom but also to a host of This content downloaded from 165.190.89.176 on Thu, 18 Feb 2016 14:47:48 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 294 Brian Domino other issues—from the idolization and idealization of genius to ressentiment—that Nietzsche collects under the rubric of idealism in Ecce Homo.43 To love your fate involves examining those ideals you hold that suggest that your life could be better than it is. These are the ideals that prevent you from loving your actual life and that convince you to redirect your love to another, nonexistent life. To love your fate means, in part, to shut the door on possibility, to reject the imaginings of the toxic ideals as merely so much fantasy that could not come to pass and so should not be mourned or desired. Why Does Nietzsche Fail to Love His Fate in Ecce Homo? Given his exuberance toward amor fati, one would expect Ecce Homo to depict its application to Nietzsche’s own life along with the life-affirming consequences of so doing. Instead, Ecce Homo chronicles Nietzsche’s spectacular failure to love his fate.44 To catalogue some of those instances that occur before the first mention of amor fati and thus would be in the reader’s mind when she comes across the initial amor fati passage: Nietzsche laments that his contemporaries are too small to understand him (EH P:1); perhaps he is merely “externally sprinkled with what is German” and is instead descended from Polish noblemen (EH “Wise” 3); despite an obvious penchant for skewering his opponents, he claims he never attacks persons (EH “Wise” 7); although he has contemplated the origin of evil since he was thirteen (GM P:3), he never experienced any religious difficulties (EH “Clever” 1); and he is “envious of Stendhal” for stealing his comic material (EH “Clever” 3), even though Stendhal died two years before Nietzsche’s birth. The suppressed revision to section 3 of “Why I Am So Wise” contains this passionate embrace of genetic fate: “I confess that the gravest objection to the ‘eternal recurrence’ [. . .] is always my mother and sister.” To be fair, Nietzsche occasionally loves his fate. He happily recalls that because his birthday coincided with that of King Frederick William IV, it was a holiday throughout his childhood (EH “Wise” 3). More seriously, in the dedicatory or intercalated passage, he is thankful for his amazingly productive fourth quarter of 1888: On this perfect day, when everything is ripening and not only the grape turns brown, the eye of the sun just fell upon my life: I looked back, I looked forward, and never saw so many and such good things at once. It was not for nothing that I buried my forty-fourth year today; I had the right to bury it; whatever was life in it has been saved, is immortal. The first book of the Revaluation of All Values, the Songs of Zarathustra, the Twilight of the Idols, my attempt to philosophize with a hammer—all presents of this year, indeed of its last quarter! How could I fail to be grateful to my whole life?—and so I tell my life to myself. Undoubtedly, 1888 was a very good year for Nietzsche and he is genuinely grateful for it. But does he exhibit amor fati? He is “grateful” (“dankbar”) This content downloaded from 165.190.89.176 on Thu, 18 Feb 2016 14:47:48 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions Nietzsche’s Use of Amor Fati in Ecce Homo 295 to his entire life, which is in keeping with the holism of amor fati, but the required sense of necessity is missing. He offers no evidence that his life had to ripen in his forty-fourth year. It is tempting to attribute to Nietzsche foreknowledge of his collapse a few months later, but this would be to romanticize a coincidence rather than to make a factual claim. He describes the books he wrote in 1888 as “presents” (“G e s c h e n k e”). Perhaps the giver of the presents is fate. Less romantically, this passage might be best understood according to Leiter’s interpretation: Nietzsche writes as “the conscious ‘self ’ which views the life as though a (grateful) spectator upon it.”45 Any of these three interpretations would show Nietzsche’s literal and attenuated amor fati. The difficulty is that because Nietzsche does not allude to any necessity, this passage is also consistent with our everyday understanding of “having a good year,” which does not involve fate at all. If we connect this passage with what follows immediately—gratitude for his entire life—we might think that Nietzsche values those books more than the struggles he had in his life prior to 1888. The works of 1888 then redeem his life, and redemption is precisely what amor fati seeks to avoid.46 If Nietzsche is not here expressing love of fate, we ought to be able to offer a psychological explanation for that along the lines of BGE 21. The explanation must not only address why Nietzsche doesn’t express love of his fate here but also must cohere with what else we know about him, especially as presented in Ecce Homo. Recall that the first type of person who wants to cling to freedom of the will is the one who wants to take credit for her accomplishments. While the chapter titles of Ecce Homo suggest that Nietzsche is this type of person, their contents do not. For example, why is Nietzsche so wise? The first of the two reasons he gives is that it is because he has the sort of parents that he does. The second is his acute sense of smell. Neither of these are achievements, and Nietzsche does not present them as such. He continues, correlating the production of The Dawn with various ailments he endured. He stops short of attributing The Dawn to his sickness but also never takes credit for himself. The section ends with his assertion that his unparalleled view of humanity stems from his oscillating between sickness and health, between decadence and vitality. The rest of the book generally follows suit and describes what makes Nietzsche great as largely beyond his control. If Nietzsche is not rejecting fatalism out of pride, the other possibility presented in BGE 21 is a desire to blame others and generally avoid responsibility for one’s actions. Continuing with the same section from Ecce Homo, Nietzsche clearly isn’t seeking to blame others. In particular, the shift to discussing his sickness avoids the economy of blame. This medical move beyond good and evil isn’t limited to Nietzsche’s life. Even though he traces the origin of decadence to Socrates, he never blames Socrates for his own decadence or even for its spread (TI “Socrates” 11, EH “BT” 1). This content downloaded from 165.190.89.176 on Thu, 18 Feb 2016 14:47:48 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 296 Brian Domino Another route into the intercalated passage is to interpret Nietzsche’s ostensible rhetorical question (“How could I fail to be grateful to my whole life?”) as a question to be answered. One could fail to be grateful if one harbored resentment toward fate (or whatever one wishes to call the forces that ostensibly direct one’s life); if, in other words, one believed that one’s life could have been better. This of course is a version of the mendacious idealism against which Nietzsche rails in Ecce Homo. Here he seems consistent. He doesn’t pine for a life different than the one he has so far led. Again, though, believing that one’s life could not be better is not the same as believing it to be fated, to have unfolded according to necessity. As a final attempt to locate amor fati in the intercalated passage, let us pursue the possibility that what Nietzsche meant to gesture toward is the more general idea of being grateful for his sickness because it led to his philosophy. He explicitly connects these registers in Nietzsche contra Wagner, but not in Ecce Homo. Nonetheless, Nietzsche does put a positive spin on his illnesses in Ecce Homo. If we prioritize the text, if we say that Nietzsche’s writings are the manifestation of his philosophy, we run afoul of his proclamation that he is one thing and his writings another (EH “Books” 1). Even if we ignore this separation and accept the general tenor of these comments to mean that his philosophy is no small part of who he is, Ecce Homo fails to present him as conforming to his own teaching. The question is not why Nietzsche wasn’t perfect, but why he chose to record his repeated failures to embrace amor fati. Certainly not out of some naive fealty to historical accuracy. No one needs to be entirely honest in a biography: “What prudent man would write a single honest word about himself today?—he would have to be a member of the Order of Holy Foolhardiness to do so. We are promised an autobiography of Richard Wagner: who doubts that it will be a prudent autobiography?” (GM III:19). That Nietzsche nonetheless presents both amor fati and his failures to enact it—without providing one success story of even minor importance—suggests that a more complex picture lies underneath. One need not have gone through the detailed textual analysis we just completed to see this. For example, in Ecce Homo, Nietzsche seems to have conflicting desires. His avowed purpose in publishing the book is “to say: Hear me! For I am such and such a person. Above all, do not mistake me for someone else” (EH P:1). His desire for his readers to get these things right seems problematic given that he also asserts “I am one thing, my writings are another matter” (EH “Books” 1) and “I want no ‘believers’” (EH “Destiny” 1). This insistence on the separation of the author from his texts does not stem from some prescient notion of privacy. After all, he tells us where his apartment is (EH “TI” 3). Instead the problem is that, according to his own diagnosis, the world (or at least Western Europe) has inherited toxic values that have enfeebled everyone, including Nietzsche himself. This un-Nietzschean separation of author and texts draws the reader’s attention to the need to both study Nietzsche’s ideas and to protect herself from This content downloaded from 165.190.89.176 on Thu, 18 Feb 2016 14:47:48 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions Nietzsche’s Use of Amor Fati in Ecce Homo 297 them because of the problem that Nietzsche cannot be certain that he is writing in a state of health (and thus presumably forwarding healthy teachings) and not one of decadence. To insure that his readers notice his hypocrisy, Nietzsche declares that “[m]y formula for greatness in a human being is amor fati” (EH “Clever” 10). The immediate inference is that Nietzsche is not a great person by his own definition. His failures force his readers to ask themselves whether Nietzsche failed because it’s a poor teaching in some relevant sense or whether the teaching is still a healthy one despite his failings. In either case, Nietzsche has succeeded in having the reader focus on the teaching rather than the teacher. Nietzsche advertises his health so well that it is difficult to remember that he still suffers from decadence, much less to remember that he is concerned with infecting his readers. But he does provide evidence of this, as I hope to show now. Clearly the target of Ecce Homo is what Nietzsche calls “ideals.” Half of the sections of “Why I Am a Destiny” attack mendacious ideals and foists Nietzsche up as the first one to notice the problem and then to rise in opposition to it. His book-by-book chronology identifies ideals attacked in each book (HH 1 being the most obvious instance), as if to remind the reader that he has consistently attacked a wide range of values that deprecate life and sicken us. The range of ideals he tilts at is extensive, as are the ills they produce. What is unclear is what we can do about them. We do learn what Nietzsche does to combat ideals: he coolly puts them on ice and allows them to freeze to death (HH 1). Presumably this means to place the ideals in contact with Nietzsche’s philosophy, and “[p]hilosophy,” he explains, “as I have so far understood and lived it, means living voluntarily among ice and high mountains.” “The ice is near” around his writings, and indeed “there is no small danger that one may catch cold in it” (EH P:3). Even Nietzsche must be careful in his own rimy philosophy: “I do not refute ideals, I merely put on gloves before them” (“Ich widerlege die Ideale nicht, ich ziehe bloss Handschuhe vor ihnen an”) (EH P:3). Duncan Large helpfully expands on Kaufmann’s translation with “I just put on gloves to protect myself against them.”47 Today we might immediately think of surgical gloves. I do not want to put too fine a point on this, but the gloves are not to protect Nietzsche from the ideals he freezes but from the bitter cold of his philosophy. I suggest this both because it makes more sense (i.e., nowhere does Nietzsche suggest he needs protection from ideals) and is historically accurate. It was only during Nietzsche’s lifetime that the germ theory of disease was gaining currency. The most important proponents of germ theory (e.g., Robert Koch, Pasteur, Lister, and John Snow) were all Nietzsche’s contemporaries. It was not until 1890 that germ theory had attained a significant enough following that surgical gloves were invented. Nietzsche’s lauding of his olfactory abilities may stem from then-dominant miasma theory. On this theory, foul-smelling water or air was a source of disease. In any event, the gloves Nietzsche dons are to This content downloaded from 165.190.89.176 on Thu, 18 Feb 2016 14:47:48 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 298 Brian Domino protect his hands from his icy philosophy, a lesson Zarathustra apparently failed to learn: “Alas, ice is all around me, my hand is burned by the ice” (EH “Z” 7). If Nietzsche risks frostbite from his own philosophy, surely his readers would risk hypothermia. Knowing this, he devises amor fati as a means helping them overcome idealism in a less risky manner. If you think of yourself as largely fated, quite a number of Nietzsche’s most reviled ideals fall away. Morality requires freedom; without it, one cannot do evil. If one cannot do evil, the world is not in need of redemption and hence also not in need of a redeemer. At the same time, that one need love one’s fate prevents a collapse into nihilism. Without the injunction to love one’s fate, one might reason that one will do whatever one is fated to do, and so on. If we must love our fate, our attitude toward it will be radically different. To love something is to value it. The Intended Audience of Ecce Homo My interpretation relies on certain assumptions about the kind of readers Nietzsche wanted to attract with Ecce Homo. I conclude by discussing the topic of his auditors, especially given the disparity between the audience Nietzsche expected to get almost immediately and the audience he did get decades later. It isn’t obvious from the book itself, but Nietzsche wanted Ecce Homo to be a best seller. In early December of 1888, Nietzsche finished revising the manuscript of Ecce Homo and shared his plans for the book with the Swedish writer August Strindberg. He wanted it “appear simultaneously in German, French, and English.” He thought about the publisher and the selling price: “I suppose it would be, in the French edition (perhaps with Lemerre, Paul Bourget’s publisher!) priced at about three francs fifty. Since it says unheard of things and sometimes, in all innocence, speaks the language of the rulers of the world, the number of editions will surpass even Nana.”48 Those of us unfamiliar with the history of marketing might wonder about Nietzsche’s sales projections. According to one source, “The first printing [of Nana] was fifty-five thousand copies, and on the day of publication ten thousand more were ordered, figures hitherto unprecedented in French fiction.”49 While salacious scandal helped boost sales of Nana, its success was also very much the product of extensive marketing: In September, 1879, when Zola had written about half of Nana, he arranged with M. Laffitte, editor of Le Voltaire, which was then publishing his articles on “scientific fiction,” to produce the story in that newspaper; and M. Laffitte at once advertised it in a fashion worthy of Barnum himself. Huge posters appeared on all the wall of Paris, “displayed” announcements invaded the newspapers, sandwich men patrolled the streets, ticket-advertisements were even affixed to the gutta-percha tubes of the pipe-lights in the tobacconists’ shops; and, indeed, upon every side one found the imperious injunction: Read Nana! Nana! Nana!!50 This content downloaded from 165.190.89.176 on Thu, 18 Feb 2016 14:47:48 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions Nietzsche’s Use of Amor Fati in Ecce Homo 299 Nietzsche may have been oblivious to this Parisian marketing, but I suspect he knew of it, if only secondhand. Nietzsche considered himself a “good European” (EH “Wise” 3) rather than a German or citizen of any country in particular (GS 377, HH 475). His frequent travels and stays in hotels and boarding houses put him in contact with people from all over the Continent. If he had a remotely accurate idea about the sales of Nana, then he wanted Ecce Homo to reach a very broad audience. Of course, Nietzsche had no guarantee that his correspondence would be collected and disseminated, and it is certainly a speculation that Nietzsche had some inkling about the hypermarketing of Nana. I therefore want to look at what Ecce Homo tells us about the readership Nietzsche hopes to cultivate without relying on material he could not assume we would have. Who are the readers Nietzsche expects? Nietzsche liked to point out the difficulties intellectuals had with his work (EH “Books” 1, HH 6, CW 4). While the obvious implication is that no one is smart enough to understand him, Ecce Homo differs from Nietzsche’s other books in terms of the intended audience. Nietzsche did not expect philosophy professors to read Ecce Homo. Indeed, that he lumps them with “other hollow pots, [and] cabbage heads” (EH “Books” 5) suggests he doesn’t want professors reading him. In an oft-quoted passage from the same section, Nietzsche describes the kind of readers he merits: “That a psychologist without equal speaks from my writings, is perhaps the first insight reached by a good reader—a reader as I deserve him, who reads me the way good old philologists read their Horace” (EH “Books” 5). Since Nietzsche must supply the inference that a good reader would reach, we can infer that in Ecce Homo he does not expect to have the readership he deserves.51 Since he nonetheless wishes to convey something to his readers, he might need to be a bit obvious, if only by the standards of Nietzsche scholarship today. Thus, he not only presents multiple instances demonstrating his failure to love his fate but also repeatedly boasts of his psychological prowess. The latter portion of this deserved reader quotation is well known, but I’m unaware of anyone explaining its meaning. It ostensibly means “read me carefully,” but that seems circumlocutory for Nietzsche. After all, Nietzsche could’ve written “read me as a philologist would” if he meant to convey only the idea of reading him carefully. Moreover, since Nietzsche just implied that he does not expect such readers, it is all the more unlikely that those he does get would have detailed knowledge of how “old philologists read their Horace.” Nietzsche’s remark won’t make the reader suddenly train a sharper set of exegetical tools onto Ecce Homo. And why Horace? Why not Ovid or Virgil? Or why not more simply “the way old philologists read ancient texts”? The sort of reader that Nietzsche expects to have in Ecce Homo would probably not know how “old philologists read their Horace” beyond “carefully.”52 She may, however, know Horace as the author of many famous quips, including the now clichéd “carpe diem.” The full passage from which that expression This content downloaded from 165.190.89.176 on Thu, 18 Feb 2016 14:47:48 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 300 Brian Domino comes reads “as we speak cruel time is fleeing. Seize the day, believing as little as possible in the morrow.”53 Horace enjoins his reader to “seize the day,” but the old philologists do this by reading Horace, not by acting on his advice. That they are “old” suggests that they’ve done this for decades. In reviewing his writings in “Why I Write Such Good Books,” perhaps Nietzsche believes that he deserves this kind of reader because of the complexity of his thought and its aphoristic expression. So he deserves readers who will devote their lives to studying the intricacies of his works but never follow them. With Ecce Homo, he wants to change that because the future of humanity is at stake. Recall his earlier description of his imaginary “perfect reader” as “a monster of courage and curiosity; moreover, supple, cunning, cautious; a born adventurer and discoverer” (EH “Books” 3). In short: not an old philologist. Thus the readers “he deserves” is not a laudatory phrase but a sarcastic jab at his fate. The kinds of readers he wants for Ecce Homo are those who will experiment with the strategies and techniques for flourishing presented in Ecce Homo but who will do so as scientists and not believers. Conclusion I have made two points. First, we should not understand amor fati as a repackaged version of eternal recurrence or the appropriate attitude to have toward eternal recurrence—or even as the specific teaching that we ought to love our fates simpliciter. Rather, the expression amor fati is a convenient way of referring to Nietzsche’s teachings about what is necessary and our reactions to them as a whole. I did not exhaustively list those teachings in order to pursue my second thesis, namely that Nietzsche’s ironic use of amor fati in Ecce Homo is strategic. Specifically that his self-reported failures to love his own fate together with his description of amor fati as his formula for greatness in a human being should make his readers all the less likely to follow him blindly and instead focus critically on what they might learn from him. Nietzsche pursues this strategy to help minimize the chances that he will infect his readers à la Socrates. If I am right about this, Ecce Homo needs to be interpreted from a different standpoint from that of Nietzsche’s other works and from which it has so far been read by many. Miami University dominob@muohio.edu Notes An earlier version of part of this essay was presented at the 2011 meeting of the North Carolina Philosophical Society. I would like to thank the audience members for their questions and suggestions, especially John Whitmire and Christopher Hoyt. I would also like to thank the two JNS reviewers for their helpful comments and criticisms. Paul Loeb offered some sound advice on This content downloaded from 165.190.89.176 on Thu, 18 Feb 2016 14:47:48 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions Nietzsche’s Use of Amor Fati in Ecce Homo 301 a number of issues, and I am always grateful for his thoughtful and rapid assistance. Lastly, I must thank Anthony K. Jensen for his patience while I battled my own case of décadence. 1. See his letters to Constantin-Georg Naumann, November 19, 1888, Peter Gast, October 30, 1888, and Georg Brandes, November 20, 1888. 2. See his letters to Meta von Salis, November 14, 1888, Franz Overbeck, November 13, 1888, and Gast on October 30, 1888. 3. I generally rely on Walter Kaufmann’s translations. Quotations in German are from KGW. 4. Readers familiar with Daniel Conway’s work, especially Nietzsche’s Dangerous Game (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997), will no doubt think of his interpretation. I have a more optimistic view of what Nietzsche’s goals and methods in Ecce Homo, which I hope to articulate in subsequent publications. 5. EH “Wise” 1; EH “Books” 5; see also his letter to Malwida von Meysenbug, dated October 18, 1888, in which he declares that “in questions of decadence, I am the highest authority on Earth.” Preventing the spread of decadence isn’t the same as eliminating it, something Nietzsche had already argued in Twilight of the Idols cannot be done (TI “Socrates” 11; TI “Skirmishes” 43). 6. I give one such strategy in “The Casuistry of the Little Things,” Journal of Nietzsche Studies 23 (2002): 51–62. 7. The problem is stated clearly by Locke, who in his discussion of what has come to be known as the fallacy of appeal to authority notes that once someone “has gained a name” and is held as some kind of authority, “it is thought a breach of modesty for others to derogate any way from it, . . . and it is looked upon as insolence, for a man to set up and adhere to his own opinion” (An Essay Concerning Human Understanding 4.17.19). 8. Béatrice Han-Pile, “Nietzsche and Amor fati,” European Journal of Philosophy 19.2 (2009): 224–61. 9. Paul Loeb’s recent study of Thus Spoke Zarathustra (The Death of Nietzsche’s Zarathustra [Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2010]) mentions amor fati only once, and then only in a quotation from another scholar. Similarly, in Nietzsche’s Teaching: An Interpretation of “Thus Spoke Zarathustra” (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1987), Laurence Lampert relegates discussion of amor fati to footnotes, where it is connected to The Gay Science (334 n. 95 and 350 n. 14) or other scholars (335 n. 102). 10. Should one need evidence, see the many interpretations of Zarathustra discussed in Steven E. Aschheim’s The Nietzsche Legacy in Germany, 1890–1990 (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1992). 11. C. Heike Schotten, Nietzsche’s Revolution: Décadence, Politics, and Sexuality (New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2009), 196. 12. Roberto Alejandro, Nietzsche and the Drama of Historiobiography (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 2011), 188. 13. Bernd Magnus, Nietzsche’s Existential Imperative (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1978), 216 n. 2. 14. Leslie Paul Thiele, Friedrich Nietzsche and the Politics of the Soul: A Study of Heroic Individualism (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1990), 197. 15. Françoise Lionnet, Autobiographical Voices: Race, Gender, Self-Portraiture (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1989), 88. 16. Alphonse Lingis, “The Will to Power,” in The New Nietzsche, ed. David B. Allison (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1985), 39. 17. Rose Pfeffer, “Eternal Recurrence in Nietzsche’s Philosophy,” Review of Metaphysics 19.2 (1965): 294–98; Hugh J. Silverman, “The Autobiographical Textuality of Nietzsche’s Ecce Homo,” boundary 2 9.3 (1981): 145. 18. Pfeffer, “Eternal Recurrence in Nietzsche's Philosophy,” 294. This content downloaded from 165.190.89.176 on Thu, 18 Feb 2016 14:47:48 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 302 Brian Domino 19. Max R. Layton, “In Defence of Ecce Homo,” Gnosis: A Journal of Philosophic Interest 1.1 (1973): 86. 20. Nel Grillaert “Determining One’s Fate: A Delineation of Nietzsche’s Conception of Free Will,” Journal of Nietzsche Studies 31 (2006): 54–55. 21. Layton, “In Defence of Ecce Homo,” 86. 22. Aaron Ridley, “Nietzsche’s Greatest Weight,” Journal of Nietzsche Studies 14 (1997): 23. 23. Nietzsche does take ownership of eternal recurrence once, namely in Twilight of the Idols (TI “Ancients” 5). 24. In a forthcoming careful and thought-provoking study that I became aware of as this article was going to press, Paul Loeb (“Ecce Superhomo: How Zarathustra Became What Nietzsche Was Not,” in Nietzsche’s “Ecce Homo,” ed. Duncan Large and Nicholas Martin [Berlin: de Gruyter, forthcoming]) also challenges the equation of amor fati and eternal recurrence, albeit for different reasons concerning his interpretation of eternal recurrence as allowing the possibility of déjà vu and transinstantiational memory. 25. Irving Singer, The Creation of Value: Meaning in Life, vol. 1 (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2010), xxi. Daniel Chapelle offers a less compact but essentially identical formulation: “the love of what was and is and will be, for no other sake than its own” (Nietzsche and Psychoanalysis [Albany: State University of New York Press, 1993], 80). 26. Michel Harr, Nietzsche and Metaphysics (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1996), 128. 27. Bernd Magnus, “Self-Consuming Concepts,” International Studies in Philosophy 21.2 (1989): 69. 28. David Parker makes an even stronger claim: amor fati requires “the strength to forget all that negates” an abundant life (“Nietzsche’s Ethics and Literary Studies: A Reading of Ecce Homo,” Cambridge Quarterly 33.4 [2004]: 309–10). 29. Maudemarie Clark, Nietzsche on Truth and Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990), 282. 30. Julian Young, Friedrich Nietzsche: A Philosophical Biography (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2010), 18, 501 (“willing), 337, 351 (“desiring”) 531 (“embracing”), 501. Philip Kain also describes Nietzsche as “embracing” eternal recurrence (“Eternal Recurrence and the Categorical Imperative,” Southern Journal of Philosophy 45.1 [2007]: 110), a description John Nolt uses in the title of his essay (“Why Nietzsche Embraced Eternal Recurrence,” History of European Ideas 34.2 [2008]: 310–23). 31. Michael Casey, Meaninglessness: The Solutions of Nietzsche, Freud, and Rorty (Lanham, MD: Lexington Books, 2002), 34. 32. André Van der Braak, Nietzsche and Zen: Self-Overcoming Without a Self (Lanham, MD: Lexington Books, 2011), 115. 33. Thiele, Friedrich Nietzsche and the Politics of the Soul, 200. 34. The argument for eternal recurrence in Z:III “Vision and Riddle” 2 supplies no empirical evidence. 35. For example, Clark, Nietzsche on Truth and Philosophy, 245–86, Paul Loeb, “Identity and Eternal Recurrence,” in A Companion to Nietzsche, ed. Keith Ansell-Pearson (Malden, MA: Blackwell, 2006), 171–88, Alexander Nehamas, Nietzsche, Life as Literature (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1985), 148ff., and Ivan Soll “Reflections on Recurrence,” in Nietzsche: A Collection of Critical Essays, ed. Robert Solomon (Garden City, NY: Doubleday 973), 323. See Robert Wicks, “Nietzsche's ‘Yes’ to Life and the Apollonian Neutrality of Existence,” Nietzsche-Studien 34 (2005): 118, for an interesting twist on the cosmological vs. ethical interpretations. 36. Cf. Kain, “Eternal Recurrence and the Categorical Imperative.” This content downloaded from 165.190.89.176 on Thu, 18 Feb 2016 14:47:48 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions Nietzsche’s Use of Amor Fati in Ecce Homo 303 37. Christa Davis Acampora and Keith Ansell-Pearson, Nietzsche’s “Beyond Good and Evil”: A Reader’s Guide (New York: Continuum, 2011); Gareth Southwell, A Beginner's Guide to Nietzsche's “Beyond Good and Evil” (Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell, 2009). 38. Clark, Nietzsche on Truth and Philosophy, 282. 39. Clark, Nietzsche on Truth and Philosophy, 282. 40. Clark, Nietzsche on Truth and Philosophy, 282. 41. Michael Ryan doesn’t see the problem in the same way: “Furthermore, Dionysus, the Dionysian considered as amor fati, that which castration threatens, might also, by converting accidents into necessities, work to neutralize castration” (“The Act,” Glyph 2 [1977]: 67). 42. Aaron Ridley sees this as “a job for the intellectual conscience,” a claim in need of substantial unpacking (introduction, The Anti-Christ, Ecce Homo, Twilight of the Idols, and Other Writings [Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 2005], xiii). 43. EH P:2 and 3; EH “Clever” 1, 2, 10; EH “Books” 1, 4, 5; EH “Destiny” 3. Relevant here are his accounts of mendaciousness: EH P:2; EH “Books” 3; EH “Destiny” 1, 4, 5, and 7. 44. Others have noticed this failure. See Julian Young, Nietzsche's Philosophy of Art (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1992), 151–52, and Parker, “Nietzsche’s Ethics and Literary Studies,” 310. Robert Solomon reads it as “Nietzsche’s ultimate self-irony” (Living with Nietzsche: What the Great “Immoralist” Has to Teach Us [Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2003], 35). In contrast, Kaufmann finds the picture Nietzsche paints of his own life to be “imbued with gratitude and love—with amor fati” (editor’s introduction, On The Genealogy of Morals and Ecce Homo [New York: Vintage, 1969], 206) as does Michael Platt (“Behold Nietzsche,” in Nietzsche: Critical Assessments, ed. Daniel W. Conway and Peter S. Groff [London: Routledge, 1998], 235, 243). 45. Brian Leiter, Routledge Philosophy Guidebook to Nietzsche on Morality (London: Routledge, 2002), 85. 46. Cf. Babette Babich, “Nietzsche’s Imperative as a Friend’s Encomium: On Becoming the One You Are, Ethics, and Blessing,” Nietzsche-Studien 32 (2003): 30. 47. Ecce Homo: How to Become What You Are, trans. Duncan Large (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007). 48. Letter to August Strindberg, December 7, 1888. 49. Ernest Boyd, introduction, Nana (New York: Modern Library, 1928), vi. 50. Ernes A. Vizetelly, Émile Zola, Novelist and Reformer: An Account of His Life and Work (New York: John Lane, 1904), 187. 51. Nietzsche is well known for lamenting the state of the reading public. See, e.g., GM P:8. 52. See section 5 of the preface Nietzsche added to Dawn in 1886 for a compact discussion of his “definition” of philology and the philologist. Note, too, that in the final sentence he distinguishes between “perfect readers” and “philologists.” 53. Horace, Odes 1.11.8. This content downloaded from 165.190.89.176 on Thu, 18 Feb 2016 14:47:48 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions