Faculty of Humanities, Development and Social Sciences, University of KwaZulu-Natal, South Africa Berghahn Books The 'Disorders of Discourse' Author(s): Derek Hook Source: Theoria: A Journal of Social and Political Theory, No. 97, Globalisation and the Demise of the Nation-State (June 2001), pp. 41-68 Published by: Berghahn Books in association with the Faculty of Humanities, Development and Social Sciences, University of KwaZulu-Natal, South Africa Stable URL: https://www.jstor.org/stable/41802158 Accessed: 13-11-2018 19:30 UTC JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org. Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at https://about.jstor.org/terms Faculty of Humanities, Development and Social Sciences, University of KwaZulu-Natal, South Africa, Berghahn Books are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Theoria: A Journal of Social and Political Theory This content downloaded from 203.163.238.160 on Tue, 13 Nov 2018 19:30:37 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms The 'Disorders of Discourse' Derek Hook Introduction There can be little doubt that discourse analysis has come to represent something of a 'growth industry' in the critical social sciences. Indeed, there has been, together with a proliferation of the various models of the process of discourse analysis (cf. Bannister 1995; Fairclough 1995; Parker 1992; Potter & Wetherell 1987) a veritable explosion of discursive analytic work. This almost unfettered expansion of discursive analytic work has led almost inevitably to a variety of misapplications of the work of Michel Foucault, whose name is often attached, almost as matter of course, to varieties of discourse analysis. This paper will indirectly take issue with erroneous (misapplications of Foucault's concept of discourse by attempting to re-characterise a Foucauldian perspective on what discourse is, and on what a sound discursive analytic methodology should entail. These objectives will be achieved through a close reading of Foucault's inaugural lecture at the Collège de France: 'The Order of Discourse'. Furthermore, this discussion will, where appropriate, be illustrated (or contrasted) with reference to one of the most popular methods of discourse analysis, namely that of Ian Parker (1992). 1 It is worthwhile briefly locating 'The Order of Discourse' in the context of Foucault's corpus. In many ways this key methodological paper marks a watershed in Foucault's writing. It signals, with rare perspicacity and accuracy, the future genealogical research interests Foucault was to pursue whilst at the Collège de France (studies of the prison, delinquency and penality which would lead to Discipline and Punish [1979], studies of the discursive production of sexuality, of sexual thematics in nineteenth-century medicine and psychiatry, which would lead to the three volumes of The History of Sexuality [1980a, 1986, 1988]). By the same token, the paper represents the cutoff point between Foucault's archaeological and genealogical methods, and as such represents a transition point between the 'analysis of local discursivities and possibilities of knowledge' (archaeological method), and the subsequent political study of material arrangements Theoria, June 2001 This content downloaded from 203.163.238.160 on Tue, 13 Nov 2018 19:30:37 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 42 Derek of Hook power and mobilisation extent, is t o relian Whilst Foucaul doubt unfold a provide a wor from Potter & the following w Discourse and social analy bu tive truths exis entific methods is seen as consti of discourse em (Coyle Whilst life 1998: 24 Parker commentary, h also attend to matters' (1992 'which courses structur reprodu Processes of Formation and Constraint In a succinct introduction to Foucault's 'The Order of Discourse' paper Young (1981) notes that the central focus of the paper is on the rules, systems and procedures which constitute, and are constituted by, our 'will to knowledge'. These rules, systems and procedures comprise a discrete realm of discursive practices - the order of discourse - a conceptual terrain in which knowledge is formed and pro- duced. As Young specifies, what is analysed here is not simply that which was thought or said per se, 'but all the discursive rules and categories that were a priori, assumed as a constituent part of discourse and therefore of knowledge' (Young 1981: 48). In this way, the effects of discursive practices is to make it virtually impossible to think outside of them; to be outside of them is, by definition, to be mad, to be beyond comprehension and therefore reason. Discursive rules are hence strongly linked to the exercise of power: discourse itself is both constituted by, and ensures the reproduction of, the social system, This content downloaded from 203.163.238.160 on Tue, 13 Nov 2018 19:30:37 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms The 'Disorders of Discourse ' 43 through forms of selection, exclusio asserts near the beginning of the pape tion of discourse is at once controlled, tributed by a . . . number of procedur outset then Foucault is involved in materiality and power to what, in the remained the largely linguistic concep that he wants to centre the analysis o political action. These concerns with tioning of discourse lead also to his course is both that which constrains thinking. What he terms 'discursive p and productive ways, implying a play both exclusions and choices (Foucau then, sexist or racist discourse would ing or 'shutting down' the speaking marginalised, it will also work to m authoritative, the speaking opportu processes, of formation and constraint inseparable. More than this, they are b tutive of one another; discourse is f mutual constitution. Foucault resolves first to deal with the most overtly exclusionary mechanisms affecting discourse. External Systems of Exclusion There are, according to Foucault (1981), three central means of exclusion that are operated by successful or powerful discourses: those of prohibition, those that enforce the division between madness and reason, and perhaps the most important of all, those which divide the truthful from the untruthful. The critical analysis of discourse should be crucially aware of each such method of exclusion. The social procedures of prohibition are fairly straightforward; Foucault does not spend much time in elaborating them, noting merely that where the (intersecting) grid of prohibition is tightest is in the regions of politics and sexuality. A case in point here is the recent evidence offered up to the South African Truth and Reconciliation Commission by victim-survivors of apartheid atrocities. These 'tellings' were clearly prohibited in apartheid-era South Africa, by extreme and oppressive measures. This content downloaded from 203.163.238.160 on Tue, 13 Nov 2018 19:30:37 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 44 Derek More and Hook a divisi reason fun Although Fou speech of the sanctioned fo and qualificat 'elements of t cault ful 1981 : 53 discourses their lack of ' attempt to for era South Afr nent disqualif short, to speak course, was no moral adopt and oth an unr importance the or time. The exclusion posed 'untrut something 'lik institutionally to unseat an ah for whom tru which one sub men who spok 54). For a subs of truth, but, placed from towards tion to the its became t ut refe the qu deferred inste not however b ing mutations ern the terrai the 'will to tr according to th tions of mental the k invest This content downloaded from 203.163.238.160 on Tue, 13 Nov 2018 19:30:37 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms The 'Disorders of Discourse ' 45 The easiest way of assimilating Fouca that truth, like the search for knowle end-point for critical research, pre Grace (1997) put it, truth and knowled course in the first place. What comes just as what comes to count as practi cal system, is less about pure knowle universal sense, than about relations o In other words, what comes to coun variety of institutional supports and p tion of truth. A psychological disorder cault's perspective, is less a trans-histor people across cultures, and is more an of particular qualified, professiona knowledges and practices (of psychia These basic material conditions of p avoided, if we are properly to gain a straining systems governing discour structures and practices which limit an course, which both reinforce and rene their rightful places within a thoro power of discursive practices. The 'will to truth' (the way in which orised, distributed) makes for a part workings of a successful discourse, an ical analysis. The strongest discourses to ground themselves on the natural, short, on the level of the various corr able. This situation is aptly characteris the will to exercise . . . control in society way to clothe, disguise, rarefy and wrap guage of truth, discipline, rationality, u And this language in its naturalness, aut ness and antitheoretical directness is . It makes for interesting speculation h points of apartheid discourse; the polit politicians of the time was replete wit tice, orderliness, Godliness, the natura segregation and so on, striking evide attempts to 'wrap itself in the truthfu This content downloaded from 203.163.238.160 on Tue, 13 Nov 2018 19:30:37 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 46 Derek Hook The methodolog is an unrelentin and statements proximity to a replace these 't which is more c 'the truth' is a will-to-truth which tain will p b not o contingenc a vital means o power-knowled To be clear, wh of the 'truthfu function cisely It is of disc rather in this 'relative', ditions in are tha way the equa spective. Fouca secure, as situa historical and s are part of, the not to a 'baseles of conditions of ingful One and true. should rightly no explicit course analysis. enough energy on demonstrat benefit from t Parker seems entirely to discur mately does wan would be largel political/ethica enough attentio qualified know he does not prop reasonable know This content downloaded from 203.163.238.160 on Tue, 13 Nov 2018 19:30:37 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms The 'Disorders of Discourse ' 47 be made. Careful examination of this sor isability of discursive analytic work (and of texts) beyond the level of the targete which Parker's model cannot manage. Parker (1992) similarly fails to properl with the 'will to power'; what counts a systems through which knowledge is traced back far enough to the material co multiple institutional supports and vario tices underlying the production of truth sufficiently grasped in its relation to becomes more a project of reading the t the breadth of discursive practices beyo Importantly, whilst Parker's method d specifying that institutions reinforced/ discourse should be identified, this awar not properly integrated into his method ably achievable within the frame of t that these are goals better attained in a that does not prioritise textual forms, in a latitude of diverse data forms. Internal Systems of Exclusion There are also a number of exclusions which work internally to discourse - the predominant amongst these are the discipline, the author and the commentary. Each of these allows the generation of new discourses virtually ad infinitum - although within certain limits of con- straint. In terms of the commentary, Foucault (1981) is speaking of the discourses based upon the major foundational narratives of a soci- ety, and the interchange between these primary (foundational religious, juridical or scientific texts) and secondary cultural texts (commentaries). It is due to the 'top-heaviness' of primary texts that they will remain permanent, yet ever capable of being brought up to date, revisited for hidden or multiple meanings (Foucault 1981). Each form of commentary obeys the simple directive of recitation; each gives us the opportunity to say something other than the text itself, but on condition that it is the text itself which is uttered (Foucault 1981 : 58). The centrality of the bible as a primary text which both disallows certain forms of discourse, but that simultaneously makes possible an This content downloaded from 203.163.238.160 on Tue, 13 Nov 2018 19:30:37 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 48 Derek Hook infinite the numbe production The more over-play course gene the when i in repetition, dis Fouc within which w our presumed a what is said, b discourse', before above (Fouca every opp ising collectiv A complemen author. ing of Foucault discours Whereas identity comm of rep element throug Although the p each instance of ity of certain s of a propositio Foucault has se modernity in su who is asked to versing The the tex discipline tion. A valid d conditions, Fou of objects, theo niques and inst discipline need of simple truth errors and trut of 'complex an atology of kno that one ority' may h (Foucaul Kuhn's (1970) n thinker might This content downloaded from 203.163.238.160 on Tue, 13 Nov 2018 19:30:37 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms The ' Disorders of Discourse ' 49 truthful assertions, which whilst import of a viable and future sub-discipline, wou fied on the basis of their lack of corre current theorisations. In violating the integrity of the principl cipline, and in demonstrating how comm which re-circulates given understandings we have dangerously overestimated the c ities of discourse. It will be impossible, h positive and multiplicatory role of these take into consideration their restrictive a (Foucault 1981: 61). Discourse analysis s merely with the search for a plenitude o search for the scarcity of meaning, wi what is impossible or unreasonable within Parker's (1992) model of discourse an well in reference to Foucault's commenta of author and discipline. Parker is empha individual, and that one should look be when attempting to grasp meanings wi gests 'that there need not be an author b the animating impetus of Parker's work imperative to critique and question the and practices of established, mainstream sense Discourse Dynamics , like a variet 1989, 1999; Parker et al. 1995) certainly of the inhibiting discursive powers of th to disrupt and destabilise these bounda although the extent to which this awaren cally) implemented within his analytic m Philosophical Themes of Limitati Having uncovered the predominant m upon discourse Foucault is now concern relating philosophical themes that rei question, in essence, is how modern west cessful in eliding the presence and acti he identifies collude: they all propose a course, they all adopt an immanent ra This content downloaded from 203.163.238.160 on Tue, 13 Nov 2018 19:30:37 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 50 Derek Hook their behaviour, edge 'which prom (Foucault course thought ply 1981 and spe thought The : should first m means Heideggerian ide empty forms of founding subjec does not need to manifest them' meaning is (1 grasp ences and deduct 1981). In other w prior A to languag second theme position cations, around that at things a us and recognition' o (Fou is occupied by ' language has on has always the alread skeleton', world' (1981 pre-existing order to understa Universal tion of a : 65 me media omni concepts and al the whole ratio the reification gleaming of a tr 'things an themselv discourse 1981: 66). as the The co concepts we ha somehow pre-p It is through t themes, the fo This content downloaded from 203.163.238.160 on Tue, 13 Nov 2018 19:30:37 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms The 'Disorders of Discourse ' 5 1 mediation that discourse is reduced to lit ing, in the case of the first, of reading in in the third (Foucault 1981). These admit only the most superficial qualities (mark ing, reading and exchange never puts any discourse is hence annulled in its reality signifier. Here then is perhaps Foucault ' analysis of discourse should not defer sim ity, to a study of powerful signification a refusal of analyses couched in terms of th of signifying structures, and a recourse to a ogy of relations of force, strategic developm which determines us has the form of a war relations of power, not relations of meanin This commentary asserts a formidable p course analysis, indeed for many critic within the context of their analyses, foc the text alone. Foucault's claim here is attribute undue power to the internal pro against a pan-textualism which might clai sibly be analysed as a text, as a language, power in language links to, and stems tactical forms of power. Power, in no unc or apprehended in the meanings and sign be grasped and traced through the ana relations of force. If one is thus attempting to engage c Foucault understands it, then those fo 'turn to text', that define discourse as construct ... an object' (Parker 1992: 5), tion . . . and written texts' (Potter & Wet course to refer to a set of meanings, rep and statements (Burr 1995), will rema attempts to apprehend discourse in the f approaches come dangerously close to tives, to forms of representation, to la (1992), although perhaps to a lesser ex despite the fact that he does emphasise, discourse may also take material forms, kinds of practice. The problem here is th This content downloaded from 203.163.238.160 on Tue, 13 Nov 2018 19:30:37 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 52 Derek nal Hook his course, awaren rem to involve the forms of powe The he Princip Foucault's first means reversal (Young origin. 1981), Those t positive role in the demonstrat discourse typically (Fou dera way, the indivi expertise from The methodol way of enforci event which he ation (1981). T the alibis of c origins of disc sion and 're-so tion of the m indeed, the m operations of come, and, as a our analyses w seen as a way accounts of discourse. Said (1983) similarly emphasises the importance of re-relating dis- course to a greater network of power-relations when he notes that Foucault's method of critically engaging discourse is to strip it of its esoteric or hermetic elements and to do this by making [it] assume its affiliations with institutions, agencies, classes, academies, corporations, groups, ideologically defined parties and professions . . . [These critical engagements] . . . forcibly redefine and re-identify the particular interests that all [discourses] serve. (Said 1983: 212) This content downloaded from 203.163.238.160 on Tue, 13 Nov 2018 19:30:37 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms The ' Disorders of Discourse ' 53 Re-emphasising the importance of this that '[e]ach discourse ... is to some de control and a set of institutions within the culture over what it consti- tutes as its special domain' (Said 1983: 219). Here it should again be noted that Parker's (1992) method does make allowance for the identification of institutions; similarly, it makes mention of the fact that discourses reproduce power-relations. However, in both of the above cases, Parker fails to properly explain how the identification of institutions, like the identification of those who will/will not benefit from the mobilisation of the discourse, may be properly accommodated within a methodology that treats discourse chiefly as a form of language. Again one feels that a broader definition of discourse, and a broader analytic scope than one limited basically to the analysis of texts will be necessary if this method is to comply with Foucault's demands. Similarly, Parker is anxious about how one might imply the omnipresence of power by emphasising the inextricability of power and discourse, and thereby lose sight of the prospects of resistance. This is clearly antithetical to Foucault's approach, which seeks precisely to emphasise how enmeshed power is within discourse. (Importantly here, an emphasis of the intimacy and interconnectedness of power and discourse need not, for Foucault, mitigate against the possibilities for resistance, particularly given that, in his conceptualisation, resistance is a feature of every power relationship; there can be no relation of power without resis- tance [Foucault 1982].) A perhaps even more direct way of tying discourse to the power- interests it serves is by isolating the material implications of discourse. Here another pragmatic upshot of prioritising discourse as event becomes clear: that one should approach discourse not so much as a language, or as textuality, but as an active 'occurring', as something that implements power and action, and that also is power and action. Rather than a mere vocabulary or language, a set of instruments that we animate, discourse is the thing that is done, 'the violence', as he puts it, 'which we do things' (Foucault 1981: 67). In a similar vein Said adds that the predominant goal of discourse is 'to maintain itself and, more important, to manufacture its material continually' (Said 1983: 216). Many of Foucault's later works take this material level of discourse as their prime focus. Discipline and Punish (1979) is a case in point where Foucault maps, in rigorous detail, power's various and developing investments in the body. Here, each facet of discursive commentary is led and substantiated by the minu- This content downloaded from 203.163.238.160 on Tue, 13 Nov 2018 19:30:37 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 54 Derek tiae Hook of various impact, would Again here systems of against at the The the Par con nec same tim Principl Foucault's Perhaps trust it (1970) work, secon the mo display had alr linear c evolution are analysis. The n re concept stems explanation, it its analytical comment risk of ac that project analysis will u The importan past' and 'a his tially a work political o realm pened in a prev it risks reprod context as it 1998). Rather standings and d t a prefers to inte and understand bilising In content to critica equivalent of te disc decentre authority, such an and 'truthful makes for This content downloaded from 203.163.238.160 on Tue, 13 Nov 2018 19:30:37 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms a no The 'Disorders of Discourse ' 55 was previously considered immobile . . . unified . . . [and] shows the heterogeneit consistent' (Foucault 1977: 147). In th course become that much more discern appeared as a 'transparent medium of able, just as some of our most fundamen psyche, sexuality and society become entities. Hence one starts to see the ab that any critical, or politically efficacio sis will have upon effective forms of hi portant font of critical 'counter-kno well-suited to destabilising current hier tance and struggle. Indeed, without this be limited to 'scratching the surface remain loaded with contemporary values porary discourse than a critical analysis Parker's (1992) method does suggest t located', in conjunction with the war should be wary of disconnecting themse Whilst these stipulations are commendab history can only possess a limited, per ity if not centralised as a prime method appeal to history has an 'after the fac poses, it loses much of its destabilisin mately, this reference to history lack contrary counter-knowledges may be pu discursive knowledges. The methodological opposition Foucau way of enforcing the importance of the that of series versus unity. Rather than or suppose that each component of th type, the discourse analyst must be p functions across a variety of differen material reality, institutions, subjectivit lowing linear successions of developmen ses), the discourse analyst must trace a l regularity (horizontal, 'sideways' pattern ority given to textual forms of disco problematic; without the realisation tha sation-point' of discourse, without the b consider a variety of diverse forms, the This content downloaded from 203.163.238.160 on Tue, 13 Nov 2018 19:30:37 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 56 Derek Hook be able to capacities mou of d Foucault's alerting notio to t contradictory w to us gauge it in notion that can ponents, despit 'flexible positi authority chara mentary, 'un-u work together that 'discursive series which, h (1981:69). Parker of He of (1992) the flexibili speaks of ho extending it However these extra-textual forms of discourse. Given then that discourse is able to work in discontinuous ways, that discursive practices are able to cross and juxtapose one another with 'mutual unawareness' (Foucault 1981), then we cannot simply speak against discourse, or attempt to liberate a network of repressed discourse lying beneath it. To attempt to 'give voice' to a great unspoken risks simply reproducing the criticised discourse in another way. Indeed: the fact that there are systems of rarefaction does not mean that beneath them . . . there reigns a vast unlimited discourse . . . which is . . . repressed by them, and which we have the task of raising up by restoring the power of speech to it. (Foucault 1981: 67) It is not the case that there is a great 'unsaid' or great 'unthought' which runs throughout the world 'and intertwines with all its forms and all its events' (Foucault 1981: 67). Foucault is pointing out that the model of repression will be inappropriate here in describing the functioning of discourse - because, it is quite simply not the case that the attempt to utter those meanings excluded, marginalised or 'repressed' by discourse will bring us to truth. There is not a vast and unlimited, continuous and silent discourse 'quelled and repressed by This content downloaded from 203.163.238.160 on Tue, 13 Nov 2018 19:30:37 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms The 'Disorders of Discourse ' 51 various practices', and subsequently, i 'raise up the restored power of speech This is a difficult point in the sense th be Foucault's task to do just this, to giv sources so thoroughly disqualified fro Foucault 1980b). Whilst this may no bearing in mind that this kind of genea voices does not occur under the ausp untruthfulness with the force of an ind under the auspices of tracing discursive trol, by assembling a strategically or knowledges which will be capable of against the coercion of presiding dis more of a question of increasing the com subversive forms of knowledge than of their 'truth-value'; more a tactic of s straightforward head-to-head measurin 'truer' counter-example. The analyst of discourse is predomin exploiting the gaps or shortcomings o tematically demonstrating its contradic are the seams to be pulled, the joints an stressed. In this connection, Parker's m such an emphasis of the internal cont that he suggests to analysts that one 'se one another' (1992: 14). Exposing these p nitely preferable to the attempt to unr because the latter risks simply repro arresting its activity. The Principle of Specificity; Regu In speaking of specificity Foucault is eralising forms of analysis which would lar discursive forms into 'a play of pre- The activity of a 'general reading' of because such an activity makes the assum towards us a legible face which we w (Foucault 1981: 67). In strong oppositi cault warns that 'the world is not the This content downloaded from 203.163.238.160 on Tue, 13 Nov 2018 19:30:37 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 58 Derek Hook there is no pre favour' (1981 : in things, true and or to that intrins distingu important wor that 'there is thing within knowledge of capacity (the sc by certain dis there is nothin the world is reducible to certain textual markers. In contrast to suggestions that discursive practices can be largely reduced to textuality (as implicit in the approaches of Parker [1992]), Foucault's warning is that we must resolve to 'throw off the sovereignty of the signifier' and look further afield to identify a wider array of discursive effects (Foucault 1981 : 66). Similarly, he demands that one does not reduce the analysis of discourse merely to the 'markings of a textuality', but that one fixes it also in the physicality of its effects, in the materiality of its practices (1981: 66). As such, critical readings, like interpretative exercises, will be insufficient, they will allow one to deny the materiality of discourse, to elide much of its force, and will hence result in the crippling of the political impact of our analyses. The opposition Foucault draws on here is that between regularity and originality. His point here is to impress upon us the fact that similar discursive acts can occur in a multitude of different ways, in var- ious different forms which stretch from what has typically been considered 'discursive', that is, the textual, to the 'extra-discursive', the material level of discursive practices. Foucault's use of the term 'discursive practices' here is noteworthy; not only does it suggest a diverse plurality that nonetheless maintains a unified function, it also makes it difficult to separate the material and the textual, to grant either a separate (and mutually-exclusive) integrity beyond the other. The collapse of this textual/material, 'discursive'/'extra-discursive' division seems strategic on Foucault's part; his agenda, it seems, is precisely to complicate and problematise the division. Indeed, once we consider the discursive utterance (the diagnosis of someone as a 'pervert', say for example) as an action, as a practice or an event, then this utterance seems to start verging on the territory of materiality, This content downloaded from 203.163.238.160 on Tue, 13 Nov 2018 19:30:37 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms The 'Disorders of Discourse ' 59 and becomes more easily linked to th through which such a diagnosis may be other hand, more obviously material pr reason of sado-masochistic sexual beha be of a different ontological nature, abl discourse, without being exhausted by i The collapse of such a division also b it - most obviously an over-emphasis of are to be found here. The first resides 'discursive', nothing beyond the text, se a form of dialogue. The second reside empowered status to language alone. the deployment of political correctness the world in isolation from certain fundamental material conditions. These errors signal a myopia of the text, an over-valuation of the lin- guistic and representational powers of language in isolation of the material arrangements of power in which they are enmeshed, and which they in turn extend. The breadth of a focus on 'discursive practices' (so conspicuously absent in Parker's [1992] method) mitigates against exactly such a myopia. Indeed, as problematic as it is to threaten the collapse of this distinction on an ontological level, there is nonetheless a critical methodological efficacy in a cautious, pre-cursory exploration of the blurring between the textual and material, the 'discursive' and the 'extra-discursive'. Indeed, as will become increasingly clear, this whole distinction, which to a large extent still retains its integrity, can be a dangerous one in the sense that it aids and abets the contempo- rary effacement and denial of the potency of discourse's material effects. Being able to cautiously blur these lines will keep the analyst from under-estimating the discursive effects of the material, and the material effects of the discursive. It seems that by being able to work in two analytic domains, to substantiate critical textual assertions on the basis of materially-focused analyses, and vice versa, Foucault gains a unique epistemological strength in his work, a strength lacking in Parker's (1992) model. There can be little doubt that Foucault's priority is not that of 'reading', textuality or signification, but rather that of materiality, conditions of possibility, historical circumstance. Hence one might contend that Foucault's analysis of discourse occurs fundamentally through the extra-discursive ; a fact which brings his approach to discourse into strong conflict with that of Parker. This content downloaded from 203.163.238.160 on Tue, 13 Nov 2018 19:30:37 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 60 Derek Hook The Princip Conditions of Rather than 'hidden should those mov nucleus move for elements ditions of w possib injunction here i prove inadequate is insufficient, b This is the ported well as probl textual i any othe significance beyo This problem o political sis utility (Burman aware. makes As it others. 'truth' i 199 Burr ( difficul Because lying wit findings as open absence of notion of reference in ent discourses Burman (1990) explicit ments d or li politica that it th it is possible to rather than anot It is clear in thi to certain stable those of truth a efforts of the d then these analy ferent epistemol that one needs possible, to a dou textual dimensio architecture, or This content downloaded from 203.163.238.160 on Tue, 13 Nov 2018 19:30:37 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms The 'Disorders of Discourse ' 61 There is a second reason why merely prove inadequate. If we produce texts as that is to say, if we attempt to gener basis of effective opposition, we may ve oblique support or adjunct to the crit much on the textual level of discours attentions (and discourse itself) to this t our critical readings and writings open facets of the opposing discourse. Wh here is the distinction between discourse as power itself. My concern is that in en textual level one is predominantly dealin power , and is, in relative terms, neglect instrument of power. Foucault makes a that discourse should be viewed as n instrument of power: 'discourse is not struggles or systems of domination, but which there is struggle' (Foucault 198 In emphasising that discourse is both hoped-for effects), and its means (its warning us that we are making a mistak function of discourse to any one comfor of power. Indeed, one needs only briefly the mutually-beneficial and interdepend rial and the discursive in the operation course often appears as both instrumen its antecedent and its offshoot. (Discour emergence of certain relations of mater these effects after the fact. Similarly, m enable certain speaking rights and privi ial substantiation to what is spoken in mutual reliance of this relationship can such, the attempt to isolate either aspect analysis of discourse risks severely und analysis, and colluding in the ongoing p Remaining within the text, and maint the contents of the text only, means th not be able to properly engage with d power precisely because they will no macro perspective where different and power are intimately connected to it This content downloaded from 203.163.238.160 on Tue, 13 Nov 2018 19:30:37 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 62 Derek Hook lacking this networks of m po the possibility instruments o counter-discour in an oblique w those forms of place. The lack analysis withou the same cised), be a disco leaves part mantle. it instru Fouca useful here in tent and overt means ious The of in d which instrumen conceptua exteriority sibility (1981) tions alone, F overlapping for and in the absence of which certain discursive statements could not have been made. Analytic attentions hence need to defer to a variety of circumstantial variables, stretching across the material, institutional and historical circumstances that make certain acts, statements and subjects possible at certain specific locations. Rather than just locating discourse within a web of discursive effects then, one might also unearth certain of its various potential instruments. Having already favoured lateral as opposed to vertical lines of analysis, Foucault (1981) now uses the notion of exteriority to eschew depth in favour of breadth as the primary focus of analytic work. He notes: Whereas the interpreter is obliged to go to the depth of things, like an excavator, the moment of . . . [genealogy] is like an overview, from higher and higher up, which allows the depth to be laid out in front of him in a more and more profound visibility; depth is re-situated as an absolutely superficial secret. (Cited in Dreyfus & Rabinow 1982: 106-107) To this he adds the observation that the deepest truth that the geneal- ogist has to reveal 'is the secret that [things] have no essence ... or that their essence was fabricated in a piecemeal fashion from alien This content downloaded from 203.163.238.160 on Tue, 13 Nov 2018 19:30:37 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms The 'Disorders of Discourse ' 63 forms' (cited in Dreyfus & Rabinow 19 interpretation is an unending task, it is ing to interpret. There is nothing abs because, when all is said and done, un already interpretation' (cited in Dreyf Perhaps the most important point of t discussion, is that it plays up the extent course analysis inevitably defer to a kin which, in a sense, recuperates the princi interpretative researcher. (It should be Hogg [1990] have criticised Parker's crite discourses, arguing that his stress on th realised in texts' obscures the role of th preter. Similarly, Marks [1993] claims th ivity in discourse analysis procedure 'reading' carries the most weight (rela jects), a fact that is also conceded by Lacking the breadth or latitude of approach to critical investigation, discou tinues to follow 'a vertical line of inv approach' to the text. Hence, as Potte 1995), one's own less than explicitly co comes to assume the anchoring-position sion of the notion of 'truth'. Basicall model provided by Parker (1992) cann that it functions as an interpretative ac recuperates the author-principle (in the f restores a central anchoring point, not th but in the authoritative interpretation, same function. Given that there is no 'p activity which is interpretative in some uncover discursive effects. To critical does not need implicitly interpretative a trast, to map discourse, to trace its outl across a variety of discursive forms and Conclusion: The Shortcomings of Returning to Coyle's (1998) understand opened this paper, we can certainly see This content downloaded from 203.163.238.160 on Tue, 13 Nov 2018 19:30:37 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 64 Derek Hook (1981) conceptio of discourse an course; (2) tions as a to de by-pr ways in which Likewise, havi why 'has for to Parker be locate transform though, it model at the has least, translate all o model of analy Indeed, in line this paper, course ent: can the be tha analysis. variou better work than (depending a th on broader analysi and the underly as reasonable kn can be drawn f ception of disco riality and pow this paper that analysis that so tory power an approaches like It is and with as a refe way of foregoing meth ments may be course indispen discourse analy a 'history of s exclude the di course is to risk ical discursive c reproducing This content downloaded from 203.163.238.160 on Tue, 13 Nov 2018 19:30:37 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms pr The 'Disorders of Discourse ' 65 rogate. In this connection, Parker (1992) forms of analysis in only a peripheral a Secondly, for Foucault, a study of disc a focus on discourse-as-knowledge - th matter of the social, historical and po statements come to count as true or f Without reference to the underwriting c the frame of what constitutes reasonabl lytic procedures such as Parker's (1992) w lated comments, with a generalisability to the reference point of the analysed te Thirdly, without reference to material method of Parker) discourse analysis r 'the markings of a textuality', a play of set of hermeneutic interpretations that More than this, by fixing on textual eff at the cost of an awareness of discourse as also the instrument of power), discourse analysis aids and abets in the contemporary effacement and denial of its material effects and appears to risk a dangerous reductionism in thinking power. As a way of uniting the above three conditions of discourse in one overriding methodological imperative, one could suggest that the analysis of discourse, according to a Foucauldian perspective, cannot remain simply within the text, but needs to move, in Said's (1983) formulation, both in and out of the text. If one is to ensure that one's ana- lytic efforts do not result in mere 'markings of textuality', with limited political relevance, restricted generalisability and stunted critical penetration, then it will be necessary to corroborate the findings of textual analyses with reference to certain extra-textual factors (history, materiality, conditions of possibility); to do exactly what Parker (1992) fails to do, to drive the analysis of the discursive through the extra-discursive. This content downloaded from 203.163.238.160 on Tue, 13 Nov 2018 19:30:37 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 66 Derek Hook NOTES 1. Parker's (1992) method of discourse analysis is here taken as an emblematic example of many popular applications of discourse analysis. The attempt here is not simply to criticise Parker's work in an isolated way, but to comment far more broadly on methodological problems of much discourse analysis as it is practised more generally. 2. By 'conditions of possibility' here Foucault (1981) is referring to materialist conditions that are historically specific and contingent in themselves, rather than in any way 'transcendental'. 3 . Note that whilst Said ( 1 983) suggests that such a 'regularising collectivity' migh be somehow overcome, Foucault (198 1) declines to endorse such a position, pre- ferring, by contrast, to emphasise the 'unthinkability' of that which lies beyond such systems of régularisation. 4. The strategic importance of history here, as a destabilising (yet realist) element through which contemporary discourse can be interrogated and critiqued, is, fo Foucault, unquestionable. The idea is that an historical dimension of analysis will be precisely that kernel of resistance and refutation needed to guard against the recuperative powers of current discourse. 5. This relationship between discursive and material relations of power appears be much like the relationship between power and knowledge for Foucault (1979). The power-knowledge complex points our attention to the endlessly circular rela tionship between relations of power and knowledge, relations which are mutually reinforcing and which substantiate and extend each other in highly complex ways. If we look beneath the surface of knowledge we will find power, and beneath power we find knowledge; both in fact are vital to the ongoing production and expansion of the other. 6. This is a distinction reinforced by McHoul and Grace's (1997) observation tha Foucault moves the concept of discourse away from a linguistic system or gram mar towards the understanding of a discipline - a discipline both in the scholarly sense (of science, medicine, psychiatry, sociology, etc.) and in the sense of the disciplinary institution (such as the prison, the school, the hospital, the confessional, etc.). REFERENCES Abrams, D. & M.A. Hogg. 1990. 'The Context of Discourse: Let's not Throw the Baby out with the Bathwater', Philosophical Psychology , pp.2 19-225. Bannister, P. 1995. Qualitative Methods in Psychology : a Research Gu Buckingham: Open University Press. This content downloaded from 203.163.238.160 on Tue, 13 Nov 2018 19:30:37 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms The 'Disorders of Discourse ' 67 Burman, E. 1990. 'Differing with Deconstr I. Parker & J. Shorter (eds), Deconstructin Routledge. pp. 325-342. Burr, V. 1995. An Introduction to Social Constructionism. London: Routledge. Butchart, A. 1998. The Anatomy of Power: European Constructions of the African Body. London & New York: Zed Books. Coyle, A. 1998. 'Discourse Analysis', in G.M. Breakwell, S. Hammond & C. Fife-Shaw (eds), Research Methods in Psychology. London: Sage, pp.243-258. Dreyfus, H.L. & P. Rabinow. 1982. Michel Foucault Beyond Structuralism and Hermeneutics. New York: Harvester Wheatsheaf. Fairclough, N. 1995. Critical Discourse Analysis: the Critical Study of Language. London & New York: Longman. Foucault, M. 1970. The Order of Things: an Archaeology of the Human Sciences. London: Tavistock. Language, Counter-memory ; Practice. New York: Press, pp. 199-204. Penguin. York: Vintage House. Selected Interviews and Other Writings by Mi New York: Pantheon Books, pp. 78-108. Text: a Post-structural Anthology. Boston: Rout pp.48-78. (eds), Michel Foucault Beyond Structuralism an York: Harvester Wheatsheaf, pp.208-226. New York: Vintage. New York: Vintage. Kuhn, T. S. 1970. The Structure of Scientific Revolu University Press. Marks, D. 1993. 'Case-conference Analysis and Ac Burman & I. Parker (eds), Discourse Analytic Res and Readings of Texts in Action. London: Routle McHoul, A. & W. Grace. 1997. The Foucault Primer University Press. This content downloaded from 203.163.238.160 on Tue, 13 Nov 2018 19:30:37 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 68 Derek Hook Parker, I. 1989. London & New Individual Psychology. London: Routledge. Parker, I. & E. Burman. 1993. 'Against Discursive Empiricism and Construction: Thirty-two proble Analysis', in E. Burman & I. Parker (eds), Discou Repertoires and Readings of Texts in Action. Lon Parker, I., E. Georgaca, D. Harper, T. McLaughlin 1995. Deconstructing Psy chopathology. London Potter, J. & M. Wetherell. 1987. Discourse and So Attitudes and Behaviour. London: Sage. Said, E. 1978. Orientalism. Pantheon Books: New Y University Press. Young, R. 1981. (ed.). Untying the Text : a Post-structu Boston: Routledge & Kegan Paul. This content downloaded from 203.163.238.160 on Tue, 13 Nov 2018 19:30:37 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms