Developmental Psychology 1993, Vol. 29, No. 3.498-510 Copyright 1993 by Ihe American Psychological Association, Inc. 0O12-I649/93/J3.OO Autistic Children's Difficulty With Mental Disengagement From an Object: Its Implications for Theories of Autism Claire Hughes and James Russell Experiment 1 demonstrated that autistic Ss continue to fail a task originally designed as one of strategic deception when there is no opponent present: They perseveratively indicate the target object. We argue that this behavior is better explained in terms of failing to disengage from an object than in terms of a theory-of-mind deficit. To ensure that their difficulties were not due to failure to construe the task in a competitive manner, we ran a 2nd study, on detour reaching. Compared with control Ss, the autistic Ss had great difficulty with the task. We discuss autistic children's difficulties with these 2 tasks in the light of recent evidence that autism is associated with failing executive tasks and argue that viewing the syndrome as an executive deficit has clear advantages. It has been proposed that childhood autism can best be characterized as a deviance or delay in the development of a theory of mind, which is the ability to represent mental representations. This has been dubbed a deficit in metarepresentation (Baron-Cohen, Leslie, & Frith, 1985; Leslie, 1987). In support of this claim, researchers have demonstrated that, in comparison with matched clinical controls, autistic children and adolescents find tasks that demand an appreciation of how false beliefs determine action and judgment difficult to complete (e.g., Baron-Cohen, 1989b; Baron-Cohen et al., 1985; U. Frith, 1989; Perner, Frith, Leslie, & Leekam, 1989). An understanding of false belief is crucial to a mature conception of mentality, because beliefs possess the hallmark of all thinking, namely, that of being "in the running for truth," capable of being either true or false. Entirely consistent with the metarepresentational deficit view is the emerging evidence that autistic children find strategic deception difficult (Russell, Mauthner, Sharpe, & Tidswell, 1991; Sodian & Frith, 1992). If deception means attempting to implant a false belief into the mind of another person, then it must be the case that anybody who cannot understand what it is to have a false belief will be incapable of deception. The primary motivation of our first study was to question whether such demonstrations of failures to deceive really provide evidence for the metarepresentational deficit view. In brief, it is possible that, whatever difficulties autistic children may or may not have with understanding false beliefs, they could be failing deception tasks because of an inability to perform the behavioral strategy necessary for deception. This strategy involves disengaging attention from a focal object (normally a desired object in a box) and behavioral reference (normally pointing) to a place where there is no object—an analogue of Woodruff and Premack's (1979) demonstration of deceptive behavior in the chimpanzee. This skeptical point will be made in the context of the Russell et al. (1991) study of deceptive behavior in autistic, mentally handicapped, and normal preschool subjects. Russell et al. used a procedure called the windows task. In the initial phase of the task, two opaque boxes were placed between the subject and an opponent, with the experimenter sitting beside the subject. The "players" closed their eyes as the experimenter placed some chocolate inside one of the boxes. The subject's task was to tell the opponent, by pointing, which of the two boxes he or she had to open in order to find the chocolate. Each time the opponent went to the baited box, he or she retained the chocolate, and each time the opponent went to the empty box, the subject was given the chocolate. In this manner, subjects inevitably discovered that it was in their interest for the opponent to be led to look in the empty box, and thus in their interest to point to the empty box. But because the boxes were opaque, the subjects did not, of course, know which one was the empty box before they pointed. Claire Hughes (now at Groupe de Recherches de Genetique Epidemiologique, Paris, France) and James Russell, Department of Experimental Psychology, Cambridge University, Cambridge, United Kingdom. The experiments reported here were conducted by Claire Hughes in partial fulfillment of the requirements for a doctoral degree in Cambridge University, supervised by James Russell. We are very grateful to the staff and pupils of the following U.K. schools for autistic children for their assistance: Broom Hayes, Devon; Doucecroft, Essex; Hope Lodge, Southampton; Linden Bridge, Surrey; Peterhouse, Southport; Portfield, Christchurch; Radlett Lodge, Hertfordshire; Stormhouse, South Yorkshire; Sybil Elgar, Ealing; and Wargrave House, Merseyside. We are also grateful to the staff and pupils of the following special schools: Downsview, London; Green Hedges, Cambridge; Beltwaite, Peterborough; Horizons, London; Highfield, Ely; Ickburgh, London; Lady Adrian, Cambridge; Meadowgate, Wisbech; Pepys Road, Cambridge; and Rees Thomas, Cambridge. Correspondence concerning this article should be addressed to James Russell, Department of Experimental Psychology, Cambridge University, Downing Street, Cambridge CB2 3EB, United Kingdom. After 15 trials, the boxes were changed. This time, they both had "windows" that faced away from the opponent and toward the subject. Where would the subjects now point? If they understood that it was necessary to deceive the opponent to win the chocolate, then they should point to the box that was now visibly empty. This was what the 4-year-old normal children and 498 499 MENTAL DISENGAGEMENT the nonautistic, mentally handicapped children tended to do both on the first trial and on all of the subsequent 20 trials. By contrast, the 3-year-old normal children and the autistic children typically pointed to the box containing the chocolate on the first trial. They failed to deceive the opponent when an opportunity to do so presented itself, a finding that is consistent with the metarepresentational deficit theory. Moreover, success on the windows task correlated quite well with success on a false-belief task. However, two considerations stand in the way of explaining the failures as being due to a deficit in mental knowledge. The first of these is empirical. The autistic subjects (and also the 3-year-old normal subjects) typically continued to indicate the baited box on all of the subsequent 20 trials, despite the fact that pointing to the baited box meant that the chocolate was lost to the opponent. It is not at all clear how the metarepresentational deficit hypothesis is supposed to explain the fact that autistic children are so prodigiously unresponsive to negative feedback. That is to say, why should a subject who has no conception of what it means to implant a false belief into the mind of another also be unable to learn the conditional rule, "Point to the empty box to get the chocolate"? Second, even if such strong perseveration with the wrong response were not strongly associated with failure, there would still be a questionmark over why the autistic subjects pointed to the baited box on the first trial. To refer to the empty box, a subject must not only "decide to deceive": He or she must also disengage attention from a desired object and point to a place where the object is not. It is one thing to know what it means to deceive somebody to gain a desired object, but quite another to be able to draw oneself away from that object and refer to the place where the object is absent. Perhaps autistic subjects, for whatever reason, find such disengagement plus reference extremely difficult, compared with matched clinical controls. At this point, it must be said that when we place the results of the Russell et al. (1991) study beside those of the Sodian and Frith (1992) study, it becomes apparent that the autistic subjects' difficulty is specifically with behavioral reference to the empty box, not with performing any action at an empty location. Sodian and Frith showed that autistic subjects are no less capable than are mentally handicapped subjects of locking an empty box in order that a puppet that they wish to help will fail to open that box and succeed in opening the baited box. This also shows that autistic subjects are capable of some degree of disengagement from a baited box in circumstances like this. We return to the Sodian and Frith study when the results of our two experiments have been reported. Our first experiment was designed to pit a prediction derived from the metarepresentational deficit hypothesis against a prediction derived from the hypothesis that the autistic subjects' difficulty is with disengagement from a focal object and subsequent behavioral reference toward an empty location. We refer to these as the metarepresentation and the disengagement hypotheses. Essentially, if the metarepresentation hypothesis is correct, autistic subjects should perform more successfully on the windows task when the deceptive element is removed, whereas the disengagement hypothesis predicts that they should find the task equally as difficult when there is no requirement to deceive. We removed the deceptive element from the task by removing the opponent. Subjects had simply to learn that to obtain a piece of candy, they had to point to the empty box. They were not in competition with the experimenter, who could see the location of the chocolate as well as they could and whose role was to dispense the chocolates rather than win them for herself. We had a secondary aim. Because the subjects in the original version of the windows task had been required to point to the box that the opponent was to open, it might have been the case that their difficulties with disengagement were purely at the motor level. If this were so, it would severely restrict the implications of their failure and would certainly make any parallels between failure on this task and failure on the false-belief tasks difficult to sustain. For this reason, we included an additional condition in which the response was verbal: The two boxes were of different colors and the subject had to say which of them should be opened. Subjects in the experiment were either autistic or nonautistic but mentally handicapped children and adolescents. Each subject received the windows task in one of four conditions: manual response with opponent present (as in Russell et al., 1991); manual response without opponent; verbal response with opponent; and verbal response without opponent. Experiment 1 Method Subjects. Sixty subjects who had been diagnosed as autistic according to the Diagnostic and statistical manual ofmental disorders (3rd ed., rev., or DSM-III-R; American Psychiatric Association, 1987) and 60 mentally handicapped subjects without autism took part in the study. The autistic children were attending National Autistic Society-funded U.K. schools in London, Cambridge, Southampton, Devon, Merseyside, and Yorkshire. They had a mean age of 13 years and 3 months (range = 6 years and 6 months to 18 years and 4 months). These children all had verbal mental ages (MAs) of at least 3 years and 6 months and had all been able to give three successive correct answers on the training phase of the windows task (see below). The mentally handicapped subjects were attending special schools in Cambridgeshire or London and had a mean age of 11 years and 5 months (range = 6 years and 1 month to 17 years and 4 months). These subjects had verbal MAs of at least 2 years and 10 months and had all been able to give three successive correct answers on the training phase of the windows task. The sex ratios (male: female) were 3.6:1 for the autistic group and 3:1 for the mentally handicapped group. Design. Within both the autistic and the nonautistic groups, 15 subjects were assigned to each of the four experimental conditions: no-opponent plus verbal response; opponent plus verbal response; noopponent plus nonverbal response; and opponent plus nonverbal response. Matching groups for mental age. The nonverbal mental ages (NVMA) of the subjects were compared on the Raven's Coloured Progressive Matrices (Raven, 1962). However, because two thirds of the mentally handicapped, nonautistic subjects failed to attain a basal score, we did not consider the NVMAs informative. The inclusion of these nonautistic subjects in the study can, however, be justified post hoc: The experimental task turned out to be well within their range of ability. Note that a conservative comparison, for our purposes, required us to have autistic subjects with a higher level of intelligence than the nonautistic subjects. A second conservative measure was to ensure that the autistic subjects' verbal mental ages (VMAs) were at 500 CLAIRE HUGHES AND JAMES RUSSELL least as high as those of the nonautistic subjects, given that the VMAs of autistic children are typically lower than their N VM As (Lockyer & Rutter, 1970). The VMAs of all the nonautistic, mentally handicapped subjects and 74% of the autistic subjects were assessed on both the Verbal Comprehension and Naming subtests of the British Abilities Scales (BAS; Elliot, Murray, & Pearson, 1983). Sixteen of the autistic subjects (26%) received only a single test: the British Picture Vocabulary Scale (BPVS). (Because the subjects had recently been given this test by other researchers, the staff of the school in question felt that further testing would overtax the children.) The mean VMA of the autistic group on the verbal comprehension subtest was 4.3 years (n = AA, SD = 6.5 months), and the mean VMA of the nonautistic group was 4.0 years (SD = 7.2 months). The mean VMA of the autistic group on the other verbal tests (either naming or BPVS) was 6.5 years (SD = 17.62 months), and the mean VMA of the nonautistic group (on naming only) was 5.75 years (SD = 18.6 months). In fact, the VMAs of the autistic group are probably an underestimate, given that many of them were at ceiling on the verbal comprehension subtest: 36% of the autistic subjects against 5% of the nonautistic subjects at ceiling. The modal VMA of the autistic subjects on the verbal comprehension subtest was greater than 4 years and 10 months (ceiling), and the modal VMA for the nonautistic subjects on the verbal comprehension subtest was 3 years and 10 months. Because the disengagement and metarepresentation hypotheses make different predictions about whether the no-opponent condition should be easier than the opponent condition for the autistic children, it was particularly important to ensure that the intellectual level of the 30 autistic subjects in the no-opponent groups should approximate that of the 30 autistic subjects in the opponent subgroups. Fifty-seven percent of the no-opponent autistic subjects were at ceiling on verbal comprehension compared with 40% of the opponent autistic subjects, and 33% of the no-opponent autistic subjects were at ceiling on naming compared with 27% of opponent autistic subjects. Of the remaining cases, the mean VMAs (in years) for verbal comprehension and naming, respectively (BAS only), were as follows: no-opponent subjects, 4 years and 1 month and 6 years and 7 months, and opponent subjects, 4 years and 0 month and 6 years and 5 months. Materials. One red and two blue opaque boxes 5.5 X 4 X 3.5 in. (14 X 10 X 9 cm) were used in the training phase of the experiment. In the verbal conditions, one of the boxes was red and the other blue; in the nonverbal condition, they were both blue. In the experimental phase, similar boxes were used that had one transparent side (a "window"). There was a supply of candy (usually "Smarties") or a healthsnack equivalent for children with dietary problems. Procedure. Subjects were tested individually in a quiet room in the school. In the opponent conditions, they were first introduced to the opponent, who was either a second experimenter or a member of the school staff. The opponent sat across from the subject, and the experimenter sat beside the subject. Subjects were told that they had to compete with the opponent for candy and that they had to tell the opponent which box to open. If the opponent found the candy, the opponent kept it, but if the opponent went to the empty box, the candy was given to the subject. On each trial, the experimenter asked both the opponent and the subject to cover his or her eyes while she (the experimenter) hid candy in a box. Half of the children were asked to tell the opponent which box to open by pointing, and half of them were told to tell the opponent the color of the box to be opened. (The experimenter had first ensured that all subjects could use the color terms.) The subjects then witnessed the consequences of indicating the baited and the empty boxes, with the outcomes of their choices being made clear to them on each trial. They were told that they could either eat the candy as soon as they won it or save it for later. The training phase continued for J 6 trials. The critical instructions were worded as follows: In a minute I'm going to ask you both to cover your eyes while I put a sweet in one of the boxes. Then I'll ask you to uncover them and tell [the opponent—either by pointing or by saying the color of the box] which box to open. If she/he finds a sweet in the box, she/he will keep it. But if the box is empty, then we'll look in the other box and you will win the sweet that's there. In the experimental phase, the boxes were swapped for ones with a single transparent side. This meant that the subject, but not the opponent, could see the candy inside. This feature was pointed out to the subjects immediately before the first experimental trial began: "With these boxes, you'll be able to see the sweet, so the game gets really easy." This phase consisted of 20 trials in which the subjects were given the opportunity of engaging in the deceptive strategy of luring the opponent to the empty box. Throughout the experimental phase, the subject was encouraged to win as many pieces of candy as possible and was congratulated for doing so. During the procedure, the opponent behaved in an appropriately pleased or disappointed manner. In the no-opponent conditions, the experimenter began by making a pile of candy. She introduced the training phase by telling the subject that he or she was going to play a game to win candy that involved closing his or her eyes while the experimenter hid a piece of candy in one of the two boxes. The subject was told that he or she had to tell the experimenter which of the boxes to open. This could be done either by saying the color of the box or by pointing. If the opened box contained a piece of candy, it was returned to the experimenter's pile, and if the opened box was empty, the subject was given the piece of candy from the unopened box. The subject could eat the candy or save it for later. The procedures for ensuring that subjects had understood the rule used in the training phase (see below) were the same as in the opponent condition. In this case, the wording of the critical instructions were as follows: "If Ifinda sweet in that box, I'll put it back in the pile. But if the box is empty, then we'll look in the other box and you will win the sweet that's there." In the training phases of both the opponent and the no-opponent conditions, the following questions were asked from the 1 lth to the 16th trials after the indicated box had been opened. If the opened box was empty, we asked the subject where the candy is and then we asked, "Who wins the sweet?" (for the opponent conditions) or "Where does the sweet go?" (for no-opponent conditions). If the baited box had been indicated, we asked the subject just one of the latter questions. If a subject failed to give three correct answers in a row (with one of the three being a case where the empty box had been indicated) within these six trials, the session was discontinued, the subject was congratulated for winning so much candy, and another subject was recruited (see Subjects section). Results On the first experimental (windows) trial, more autistic subjects than nonautistic, mentally handicapped subjects (70% vs. 37%) indicated the box containing the candy, x 2 0, N = 60) = 13.39, p < .001 (see Table 1). It can be seen from the table that exactly half of the autistic subjects in this category continued to do this for the subsequent 20 trials, whereas none of the nonautistic subjects did so. Perseveration was, therefore, a significant feature of the autistic subjects' behavior. (The raw data, including IQ scores, are available from the authors on request.) However, not all of the autistic children failed because of perseveration. Eleven of the autistic subjects (spread evenly throughout the four subgroups) responded randomly. This pattern was rarer in the nonautistic subjects: Two of them did so. Sometimes this was because the autistic subject was persevera- 501 MENTAL DISENGAGEMENT tively pointing to the same box. Some of the others either may have wanted to distribute the candy between themselves and the experimenter (for evidence that autistic children understand social reciprocity, see Baron-Cohen, 1991) or were simply indifferent to winning. However, perseverative pointing to the baited box was the predominant form of behavior in the autistic subjects. It would appear from Table 1 that testing condition (i.e., with/ without opponent and with/without verbalization) had no effect on performance of the autistic subgroups. To see whether this was the case, we adopted arbitrary criteria for "passing" and "failing" the windows task similar to those adopted by Russell et al. (1991). On the liberal criterion, the subject had to make no more than three errors from 20 trials (i.e., three verbal or nonverbal references to the baited box). On the conservative criterion, a subject had not only to make no more than three errors overall but had to be correct (i.e., indicate the empty box) on the first trial. As can be seen from Table 2, the percentages of autistic subjects passing within each condition are the same under the two criteria. This tells us that all the autistic subjects who succeeded did so from the very first trial. In the nonautistic group, by contrast, subjects frequently began with the wrong strategy and improved as the session continued. That is to say, the nonautistic subjects generally benefitted from negative feedback and the autistic subjects did not. When the frequencies of passing in the two groups were compared on the conservative criterion (the criterion on which the nonautistic children were less successful), the group difference was clearly significant, x 2 0, N = 60) = 26.2, p < .001. It is evident that the superior performance of the nonautistic group was present under all four testing conditions. Chi-square tests confirmed that the performance of the autistic subjects was not affected by the presence or absence of an opponent, nor by the response mode. By contrast, the presence of an opponent did significantly improve performance in the nonautistic group on both criteria: x2(l, N = 30) = 5.55, p < .025, on the conservative criterion; x 2 0, N= 30)= 9.31, p< .01, on the liberal criterion. Discussion Removing the opponent in the windows task did not make the task easier for autistic subjects. The predominant mode of Table 1 Number of Subjects (From 15) Who Indicated the Incorrect (Baited) Box on the First Experimental (Windows) Trial Under the Four Conditions Nonautistic Autistic Condition n Perseverating subjects" n Perseverating subjects* No opponent, verbal No opponent, nonverbal Opponent, verbal Opponent, nonverbal Total 10 13 9 10 42 6 8 3 4 21 7 7 4 4 22 0 0 0 0 0 a Number of subjects who perseverated for all 20 trials. Table 2 Percentage of Autistic and Nonautistic Subjects Who Passed the Windows Test on the Two Criteria Under Four Conditions Nonautistic Autistic Condition Conservative criterion No opponent, verbal No opponent, nonverbal Opponent, verbal Opponent, nonverbal 13.3 6.7 13.3 20.0 2 1 2 3 46.7 40.0 73.3 73.3 7 6 11 11 2 1 2 3 66.7 53.8 93.3 93.3 10 8 14 14 Liberal criterion No opponent, verbal No opponent, nonverbal Opponent, verbal Opponent, nonverbal 13.3 6.6 13.3 20.0 Note. The n equals the number of subjects from 15 who passed. responding in the autistic subjects was their reference to the baited box throughout the phase of the task in which the candy was visible to them. This is in sharp contrast to the behavior of the comparison group of mentally handicapped subjects. Although these subjects often referred to the baited box on the first (windows) trial, they inevitably learned the strategy for winning the candy (their reference to the empty box) in the course of the 20 experimental trials: Perseverative reference to the baited box throughout the 20 trials occurred in none of our 60 nonautistic subjects. We can provisionally conclude, therefore, that these data support the mental disengagement account of the autistic subjects' original failure (Russell et al., 1991) against the metarepresentation account. That is to say, if the autistic subjects are still failing when there is no "other mind" in which to implant a false belief, then it makes little sense to say that they perseveratively pointed to the baited box because they lacked the necessary theoretical grasp of mental concepts. This is not, of course, to deny that autistic individuals might indeed lack such concepts, but it is to deny that their performance on the windows task demonstrates such a lack (see General Discussion). What these children and adolescents seem to be failing to do is to disengage their attention, and thus their behavioral reference, from an object that is both desired by them and the focus of the task. However, an advocate of the metarepresentational account might wish to use these data as evidence that performance on this task is simply irrelevant to the psychology of deception. The argument would run that children who succeed on the task do not do so by virtue of deceiving the opponent—they simply point to the empty box without giving thought to the mental state of the opponent, without even regarding him or her as an opponent. But such a denial would be unwise for two reasons. First, this task strips down the act of deception to its bare minimum: luring an opponent to a place where something is not when we know where that something really is. Such behavior is surely not irrelevant to the psychology of deception: It is a primitive, necessary condition for the more richly mentalistic form of deception that people practice in their everyday lives. 502 CLAIRE HUGHES AND JAMES RUSSELL Second, the metarepresentational theory is an ambitious theory that is supposed to explain virtually all of those respects in which autistic people fail psychological tests in comparison with matched clinical controls within a single deficit—the inability to represent the relationship between the mind and reality. Proponents of the theory should, therefore, be able to explain why autistic subjects perseverate on this task when it is stripped of deceptive elements, and this explanation should be theoretically motivated. That is to say, it is no goodfieldingpost hoc explanations of the autistic subjects' difficulties, such as, "The absolute number of items won is not intrinsically rewarding for them," "They have a characteristic way of giving up when they don't understand something—they perseverate," or "Autistic subjects are more compliant, so they do as they were initially told to do and tell the other person which box to open every time." These kinds of explanations are not motivated by the metarepresentational theory itself. That said, there is an impediment to our conclusion in favor of the disengagement hypothesis. It is that the no-opponent condition might be said to have required, if not full-blown deception, then at least the act of literally misleading another person. Moreover, the experimenter in this condition could potentially be construed as a competitor for resources. That is to say, we may have failed to eradicate the element of competition from the task in the no-opponent condition. This objection has some force, especially in the light of a recent study by Baron-Cohen (in press). In this, autistic children were taught a simple coin-hiding game in which one person puts his/her hands behind his/her back, hides a coin in one of them, and then presents his/her closed fists to an opponent who then has to guess which hand contains the coin. Playing the role of guesser was not difficult for the autistic children, but they had severe problems being the hider. In the role of hider, they would often reveal the coin to the guesser: They would thrust the hand containing the coin toward the guesser or even tell him or her which hand had the coin in it. In terms of the metarepresentational account, these children were failing to understand the process and point of withholding information from another person. This may or may not be so, but the data certainly reveal a failure to grasp the point of a competitive game. There is, of course, an important difference between the coin-hiding procedure and our no-opponent condition, in that in our case, the experimenter could see everything. But the worry remains that our autistic subjects were failing to misdirect the experimenter because they failed to grasp some competitive element in the procedure, whereas the comparison subjects did grasp this competitive element and thereby succeeded. The following piece of data is at least weakly consistent with the argument that success on the no-opponent condition may have been achieved through a form of deceptive behavior. Recall that the mentally handicapped subjects in this experiment performed significantly better (on both the conservative and the liberal criteria) in the opponent condition. Given that the opponent condition was the condition in which the need for deceptive behavior was the more patent, we can explain nonautistic subjects' relative difficulty with the no-opponent condition by the fact that here it was less patent—implying that a competitive "set" may have underlain what success they did. achieve, compared with the autistic subjects in the no-opponent condition. Because of this problem of interpretation, we developed a new task on which to compare autistic subjects with control subjects. As will be seen, the new task still demanded mental disengagement from a desired object but did so in a situation in which the experimenter could not be construed as a competitor for resources. The subject's task was to obtain a marble that rested on a platform inside a box (see Figure 1). A direct reach toward the marble broke an infrared light beam, which caused a photoelectric cell inside the box to make the marble drop out of sight through a trap door in the platform. There were two ways in which the marble could be obtained. The subject could turn a knob on the right-hand side of the box to cause a paddle behind the marble to flip it down a chute and out of the box toward the subject—the "knob route." Alternatively, the subject could use a switch on the other (left) side of the box to extinguish the light beam and thus enable a reach—the "switch route." (Note that the switch route requires the subject to act on the side that is normally nondominant. However, left-handedness is about twice as common in children with autism and a variety of other mental handicaps than in the normal population [Fein, Waterhouse, Lucci, Snyder, & Humes, 1984]. In any event, there is no reason to believe that making an intentional movement to the left is especially difficult for autistic people.) If the autistic children have substantially greater difficulty with these detour tasks than the comparison groups, this will suggest that they have a specific problem with mental disengagement from an object. Such an outcome will not in itself explain why deception is difficult for such children, but it will reinforce the disengagement account of their performance on the windows task against the metarepresentational account. There are two additional reasons why this detour-reaching Figure 1. The box used in the detour-reaching task in Experiment 2. MENTAL DISENGAGEMENT 503 forward movement. Throwing this bolt triggered a green light on the left of the front face of the box and caused the yellow light to be extinguished. The green light signaled to the subject that the switch route was now required rather than the knob route. To use the switch route, the subject had to operate a small, toggle switch on the left side of the box. This switch was inoperative when the knob route was available and the yellow light was on. The left side of the box also contained a small door (15 x 20 cm), by means of which the experimenter could manipulate the bolt and reposition the marble at the end of each trial. Procedure. Subjects were tested individually in a quiet room in the school. A pilot study had established that retrieving the marble by means of the knob route was trivially easy for subjects in this ability range and that it was the switch-route task that caused difficulty. For this reason, the knob-route task was always given first, so as not to frustrate some subjects by presenting a difficult task first. The session began when the experimenter invited the subject to take the marble out of the box. After the subject had failed to do this twice because his or her reach triggered the trap-door mechanism, the experimenter demExperiment 2 onstrated that a direct route would invariably cause the marble to drop away. She then drew the subject's attention to the yellow light on the Method upper front face of the box and explained that whenever this light was Subjects. Forty children and adolescents with an established diagon, the only way to obtain the marble was by turning the knob on the nosis of autism as denned in DSM-III-R (American Psychiatric Assoright-hand side of the box. She demonstrated this two times and then ciation, 1987) and who are between 6 and 19 years made up the autistic invited the subject to do the same. Subjects were allowed to retrieve the group (mean age = 12 years and 8 months). They were attending many marble through the knob routefivetimes. All but 4 subjects performed of the same National Autistic Society-funded schools as those used in these five trials without error: Two of the autistic subjects made two thefirststudy, and many of the subjects had also participated in Expererrors, and 2 of the mentally handicapped subjects made two errors. iment 1. In the nonautistic, mentally handicapped group, there were After these five trials, the bolt was thrown to block the knob route, 25 subjects between 6 and 18 years (mean age = 10 years and 8 months). causing the yellow light to be extinguished and the green light to apThey were attending special schools in Cambridge or London. As in pear on the front of the box. The experimenter then showed the subject Experiment 1 these children had a variety of learning disorders and that when the green light was on, the knob did not work any more. She included only 1 child with Down's syndrome. Some of the children had then demonstrated the switch route and told the subject that it was now participated in the first experiment. The group of preschoolers comessential to flip the switch before reaching inside the box. She also prised twenty 3- to 4-year-old children (mean age = 3 years and 8 demonstrated again the consequences of a direct reach. The instrucmonths) attending nursery schools in Cambridge. tions for the switch route were as follows: "When the green light is on, Matching for mental age. Verbal mental age (VMA) was assessed this means that you can't use the knob any more. Instead the way to by the Test for the Reception of Grammar (TROG; Bishop, 1989).' The win the marble is by using this switch here; then you can reach in and mean VMA for the autistic group was 6.58 years (SD = 2.6; range = 4 get the marble. But you have to make sure that the switch is down first." years and 0 months to 13 years and 7 months), and the mean VMA for To maintain the subjects' interest in the task until the marble was the mentally handicapped group was 6.17 years (SD =1.38; range = 4 retrieved a criterial number of times, we used the following measure. years and 0 months to 10 years and 3 months). Nonverbal mental age Subjects were shown a plastic trumpet made up of 16 colored segments (NVMA) was assessed by the matrices subtest of the British Abilities and were allowed to blow into it, after which the trumpet was dismanScales (Elliot et al., 1983). The mean NVMA on this test for the autistic tled. Each time the marble was retrieved by the switch route, one seggroup was 6.76 years (SD = 2.9; range = 4 years and 0 months to 14 ment of the trumpet was reassembled, with the bell and mouthpiece years and 2 months), and the mean NVMA for the mentally handisegments kept back until the subject was about to attain criterion. capped group was 5.8 years (SD =1.5; range = 4 years and 0 months to 8 years and 2 months). Note that these mental ages are substantially higher than the chronological ages of the preschool children. 1 In this test, subjects are presented with a series of four colored Materials. The box (see Figure 1) was made of aluminum and meapictures and have to indicate the one to which a sentence applies. For sured 30 x 30 X 30 cm. In its front face was a centrally located, circular example, presented with (a) a boy and a girl jumping over some opening, 15 cm in diameter, cut in a perspex square. Mounted inside flowers, (b) a boy and a girl jumping over a wall, (c) a boy and a girl the box was a pyramid-shaped platform with a narrow, flat top on behind a wall, and (d) a boy jumping over a wall, they have to indicate which a large marble rested. On either side of the opening in the front the picture of which "They are jumping over the wall" is true. This face of the box were photoelectric cells by means of which an infrared item probes subjects' understanding of the distinction between singubeam was directed toward the top of the platform. When the beam was lar/plural personal pronouns. Overall, the grammatical structures broken, a trapdoor at the top of the platform was automatically actitested range from noun and verb up to "neither X nor Y" and the vated. Immediately behind the marble's resting position was a small embedded sentence. Our autistic subjects did remarkably well on this metal paddle that could beflippedforward by turning a round knob in test—indeed, their verbal M As were comparable with their nonverbal the right, external side of the box. By this means, the marble could be M As. This may be because the TROG is a relatively pure test of recepprojected forward and down a small chute running between the plattive syntax. It has no planning components that the difficult items in form and a catch tray at the front of the box. A yellow light mounted at the BAS verbal comprehension test have (e.g., "Before you give me the the right-hand top of the front face of the box remained lit when the van, give me the little house"), and it has no items that probe underknob route was available. The knob route could be blocked by throwstanding of social and emotional facts, as do the standard naming tests. ing a small bolt located in front of the paddle, thus obstructing its task may clear up interpretational problems remaining from Experiment 1. First, despite the efforts made to match groups for verbal intelligence, it is possible that the autistic subjects were understanding the procedure less well and that their failure to understand manifested itself in stereotyped responding. The detour-reaching task is far easier to understand than the windows task. Second, as we argued in the introduction with reference to Sodian and Frith's (1992) data, autistic subject's difficulty appears to be with their reference away from an object rather than with performing an action at a place where the object is absent. In the detour-reaching task, no reference is required, which enables us to determine the role of the referential act per se in autistic subjects' problem with disengagement from an object. 504 CLAIRE HUGHES AND JAMES RUSSELL Thus, by the end of the experiment, subjects had assembled trumpets whose sizes varied in proportion to the number of trials they had taken to attain a criterial run. Immediately after we showed subjects the trumpet, the trials with the switch route commenced. Each time a subject failed to retrieve the marble (either by a direct reach or by turning the knob), he or she was reminded of the switch-route procedure. If a subject did nothing either at the beginning of a trial or after having used the switch, he or she was given a verbal reminder of what to do. This is referred to as a prompt. Scoring of the switch route. In coding responses, we discriminated between those uses of the switch and subsequent reaches that were the result of prompting by the experimenter (i.e., to switch, to reach, or to do both) and those responses that were not. If a subject made a direct reach, thus causing the marble to drop through the trap door, this was coded as a failure. Trials on which the subject touched the knob were also coded separately. Only coordinated switch-and-reach sequences were scored as correct. If the sequence involved prompting from the experimenter, touching the knob, glances to the experimenter, or pauses of over 7 s, this was not recorded as a correct trial. Criterion was a run of three coordinated switch-and-reach sequences within 15 trials. Results The autistic subjects were significantly less likely to attain the criterial number of retrievals on the switch-route task than were the other two groups: Only 55% of the autistic children and adolescents attained criterion as compared with 92% of the mentally handicapped children and 95% of the preschoolers. Comparison of the performance of the two clinical groups produced the followingchi-square value: x2(l. N= 65)= 15.51, /?< .001. The data are illustrated in Figure 2 in terms of the percentages of the three groups attaining criterial runs within sets of three trials. (The coded raw data and details of IQ matching are available from the authors on request.) In Figure 3 we illustrate the relationship among the attainment of criterion and chronological age (CA), VMA, and NVMA in the autistic subjects. In each case, the subjects are split into four groups of 10 subjects each in terms of these three measures. On the ordinate is shown the average performance for each subgroup, which could range from 1 (i.e., every subject reached criterion) to — 1 (i.e., every subject failed to reach criterion). Thus, if the histogram is below zero, it means that more subjects failed to reach criterion in that particular subgroup than succeeded in doing so. It can be seen that there is an apparent disjunction between the lowest quartile of subjects and the other three: On all three measures (CA, VMA, and NVMA), more subjects in the lowest quartile failed to reach criterion than attained it. Indeed, none of the subjects in the lowest NVMA quartile attained criterion. The figure also shows the mean ages (CA or MA) in each quartile. Two things are apparent from these data. First, success on this task begins to emerge in autistic subjects with MAs of around the late 4 years, whereas failure to attain criterion is not uncommon with a mean MA of just under 7 years. Recall that the task is trivially easy for normal children who are approaching 4 years of age or who have recently turned 4. Second, it would appear that MA is a better predictor of success than CA. To check this last conclusion, we computed the correlation between number of trials to criterion (or to end of the session for subjects not reaching criterion) and VMA (age partialled) and NVMA (age partialled) and with CA. The results were as follows: The correlation of trials-to-criterion with VMA (age partialled) was r= -.60 (p < .01); with NVMA (age partialled), r = -.65, p < .01; and with age (VMA partialled), r = .035, ns. Figure 4 presents the data for the mentally handicapped children in the same way as does Figure 3 for the autistic children. Because there were 25 subjects in this group, the divisions were into groups of 5 this time. When analyses were run for these subjects that were similar to those run for the autistic subjects, none of the correlations were found to be significant. We now turn to qualitative differences in performance between the two clinical groups. Was perseveration more common in the autistic subjects? The first kind of perseveration considered was direct-route perseveration in which the subject Group performances on the box task Pass in 3 Pass in 6 Pass in 9 Pass in 12 Pass in 15 FAIL Success level Figure 2. The percentages of subjects from the autistic, mentally handicapped (MLD), and normal groups who attained criterion on the box task in Experiment 2 within sequences of three trials. 505 MENTAL DISENGAGEMENT Autistic performance related to subject age 8 . 23 0.0- •0.5- 17. 23 11 .66 0.5- • • j 14 .85 Mm reaches except for a fully prompted switch-and-reach sequence on Trial 5. We can conclude, therefore, that although perseveration with a direct route to the goal was not the virtual prerogative of the autistic subjects that it had been in the first experiment, this kind of perseveration was clearly more common in autistic subjects than in the clinical comparison group. It is also possible to regard touching the knob as a form of WILD performance related to subject age 1 c o I 2 3 Aga Ranking 4 Autistic performance related to subject NVMA c 'E 0.0 -1.0 ic 2 •5 2 3 NVMA Ranking I i 3 4 5 Age Ranking c o 'C © MLD performance related to subject NVMA O) Autistic performance related to subject VMA 1 I •0.501 c c is •1.0 2 3 NVMA 2 3 VMA Ranking Figure 3. The proportion of autistic subjects (10 per subgroup) ranked by chronological age, nonverbal mental age (NVMA), and verbal mental age (VMA) who reached criterion on the box task. (For example, 1.0 means all 10 subjects passed; -1.0 means all 10 failed.) reaches directly for the marble and causes it to drop out of sight. This is strongly analogous to the form of perseveration seen in Experiment 1. We only coded a repetition of a direct reach as perseverative. In the autistic group, 65% of the subjects made at least two such consecutive direct reaches, compared with 32% of the mentally handicapped subjects, x 2 0, N= 65) = 6.75, p < .01. Moreover, 3 of the autistic subjects produced nothing but direct reaches throughout the 15 trials, although there were a number of other autistic subjects whose responses were nearly all direct reaches. For example, 1 subject began with a switchknob-reach sequence and produced direct reaches on all the other 14 trials, whereas another subject performed all direct £ c a> 2 © 3 4 Ranking MLD performance related to subject VMA 1.0 0.5- 0.0 -0.5- -1.0 2 3 VMA 4 Ranking Figure 4. The proportion of mentally handicapped (MLD) children (5 per subgroup) ranked by chronological age, nonverbal mental age (NVMA), and verbal mental age (VMA) who reached criterion on the box task. (For example, 1.0 means all 5 subjects passed; -1.0 means all 5 failed.) 506 CLAIRE HUGHES AND JAMES RUSSELL perseveration. Although this is not perseverative behavior directed at the goal, it is perseveration with a response that was successful in the previous phase of the experiment. Of the autistic subjects, 22.5% touched the knob at least once, compared with 4% of the mentally handicapped subjects, x2(l, N= 65) = 4.19, p< .05. It turned out that, in general, if an autistic subject touched the knob once, he or she probably touched it at least a second time, whereas there was only one case of touching the knob in the mentally handicapped children—on the first trial and not repeated. Thus, perseveration in the sense of repeating a previously successful strategy, despite demonstrations of its inefficacy, was also more likely to feature among the responses of the autistic group. There was, however, a third distinctive way of failing to attain a criterial run that cannot be regarded as perseverative. This occurred when a subject produced a coordinated switchand-reach sequence but failed to follow this up with another one. This never occurred in the preschool children and occurred only twice (8%) in the mentally handicapped subjects. It occurred, however, in 42.5% of the autistic subjects. When we compare the two clinical groups, we find a chi-square value of X2(l, N= 65) = 8.82, p < .001. Indeed, 5 of the autistic adolescents produced a switch-and-reach response on the first trial and then followed it up with a direct reach. This might be regarded as a failure to monitor a correct response that one has produced as being a correct response. Alternatively, this behavior might be seen as being due to the performance of a reach triggering another reach without a prior switch—a failure to inhibit rather than monitor behavior. In light of this uncertainty, we refer to this form of error as "failing to capitalize" on a correct response. We have identified, therefore, three kinds of error. All of them were more prevalent in the autistic children. Discussion Autistic subjects continue to have difficulties disengaging from a salient, desired object when all vestiges of interpersonal competition are removed from the task. Specifically, the autistic subjects found it much more difficult than did mentally handicapped children to throw a switch in order to perform an object retrieval. This would appear to be something that is difficult to account for on the metarepresentation hypothesis. A result that requires immediate comment is that the knob route to retrieval was trivially easy for the autistic subjects. On the disengagement hypothesis, this must be explained by saying that the demands for "mental disengagement" from the marble were much higher in the switch route than in the knob route. This may be so, but there are two, rather clearer, differences between the routes: (a) The switch route required two distinct acts that had to be performed in the correct order, whereas the knob route required a single act; and (b) the causal relation between the act and the retrieval was direct and clear in the knob route but, in the switch route, was sufficiently indirect and obscure (to a subject who knows nothing about how breaking invisible light beams can trip mechanisms) as to seem arbitrary Both of these considerations limit somewhat the explanatory force of the disengagement hypothesis. The first suggests that the autistic subjects may be finding the switch route difficult because it requires a minimal degree of planning in addition to mental disengagement. The second suggests that it not so much the planning requirements of the switch-and-reach sequence that are causing difficulty as it is the fact that thefirstof the two acts bears an arbitrary relation to the second. This seeming arbitrariness of the means-end relation may have some bearing on the contrast, noted in the introduction, between the difficulties that autistic subjects have with the windows task and the relative ease with which, on the data of Sodian and Frith (1992), they are able to lock an empty box so that an ally will go instead to the baited one. We claimed that the first causes difficulty because it requires reference (an act of pointing) and the second does not because it requires action at an empty location. An essential feature of referring is that the relation between the sign and the referent be arbitrary or "nonnatural" (Grice, 1957). The relation between locking a box and another agent failing to gain entry to it is, in contrast, a "natural" one. It may, then, have been the seeming arbitrariness of the switch-and-reach relation that caused the difficulty—a hypothesis that could easily be tested by keeping the means-end demands constant in detour reaching but rendering obvious the causal relation between the acts. It is significant, in this context, that autistic children are relatively unimpaired on search tasks, tool use, and categorization by color, form, and function (Morgan, Cutrer, Coplin, & Rodrigue, 1989; Sigman & Ungerer, 1984). These are means-end tasks in which the relation between means and ends is nonarbitrary. Analysis of the different kinds of errors that the autistic subjects made was revealing. One message is that the autistic subjects were not simply victims of what Sandson and Albert (1984) call, in their analysis of perseveration, "stuck-in-set" perseveration. That is to say, it was by no means the general rule that these subjects would make a direct reach, witness its consequences, and then fail to change their behavior. Some of the less-able autistic subjects produced a pattern like this, but they were not in the majority. This is noteworthy, because it is possible to describe the form of perseveration shown in the windows task as stuck-in-set perseveration. The other two forms of error involved use of the knob and failure to capitalize on a successful switch-and-reach sequence. The first of these might be regarded as a case of what Sandson and Albert (1984) call recurrent perseveration—"an abnormal post-facilitation of memory traces" (p. 715). In other words, the task triggered memories of an action that had been successful on previous trials. The second of these, in which subjects perform a successful response and then lapse back into error, is still further from stuck-in-set perseveration. In this case, as we have argued, subjects are either failing to monitor their behavior as correct or are failing to suppress a direct reach once they have made one after a switch-and-reach sequence. This analysis of errors provides further reason for denying that the autistic subjects' difficulty was caused simply by their inability to disengage their attention from the focal object. Perseveration with the direct reach certainly comes under this heading, as does failure to capitalize on a correct response, if we assume that the latter is due to the failure to suppress a repetition of the direct reach. However, use of the knob route when the switch route is required is better regarded as failure to MENTAL DISENGAGEMENT disengage from a previous strategy. Indeed, the fact that the knob route was very easy for the autistic subjects suggests that they are certainly able to disengage from the object sufficiently well to retrieve it by action at another place. Despite the questions that these data raise about the disengagement hypothesis, the difference between the two clinical groups was very clear and does not yield to an explanation in terms of theory-of-mind deficits. In general, the autistic subjects exhibited a lower level of executive ability, a fact whose general significance is now discussed. General Discussion Our first experiment suggested that autistic subjects fail a test of strategic deception because they have difficulty with mentally disengaging from a focal object, not because they are unable to implant a false belief into the mind of a competitor: They found the task equally difficult when there was no competitor to deceive. Our second experiment revealed similar difficulties with the simpler task of throwing a switch before reaching for a marble. On the face of this at least, these data are not explicable in terms of the metarepresentation hypothesis. However, insofar as the disengagement hypothesis locates the autistic person's executive difficulties squarely with disengaging attention from a focal object, it is probably too simple. The executive demands for successful deception require the subject not only to disengage from the object but also to establish a three-stage plan (i.e., refer to empty location, lure opponent there, and obtain goal at another location). Moreover, the disengagement hypothesis implies that the problems with reference to an empty location arise out of a primary failure of disengagement, whereas reference—as an arbitrary means— sets a mental challenge of its own. These shortcomings were highlighted in Experiment 2, in which we showed that disengagement from a focal object was trivially easy when there was a direct causal link between an act that was distinct from the object and the attainment of it (i.e., the knob route). However, when the subject was required, on the switch route, to perform a separate and—for the subject—arbitrary means to enable direct action on the object, a variety of perseverative behaviors ensued. We must conclude, therefore, that these two experiments provide evidence for a general executive impairment in autism rather than for a specific impairment in mental disengagement. Provisional disengagement from a goal in order to perform the arbitrary means to attain it is just one component of a constellation of mental operations referred to as the executive functions. These are taken to encompass all those mental operations that are separately necessary and jointly sufficient for volitional, goal-directed behavior: inhibition of perceptually triggered or inappropriate responses; planning and embedding of behavioral and cognitive sequences; maintaining an appropriate set and disengaging from an inappropriate one; and monitoring the success and failure of current strategies. These are the functions normally assumed to be carried out by the prefrontal cortex (Luria, 1973; Shallice, 1988). On the level of behavior, the executive functions provide an agent with a flexible and autonomous relationship to the environment. On the level of thought, they provide the individual with what Piaget called autoregulation—the capacity to avoid "centration" (Pia- 507 get, 1950) on local saliences and, through this, the achievement of the kind of balance between competing representations that is necessary for adequate judgment. Our data fit alongside other recent evidence that autistic subjects perform poorly on the standard tests of executive functioning (Ozonoff, Pennington, & Rogers, 1991; Ozonoff, Rogers, & Pennington, 1991; Prior & Hoffman, 1990; Rumsey, 1985; Rumsey & Hamburger, 1988, 1990; Steel, Gorman, & Flexman, 1984). Ozonoff, Pennington, and Rogers (1991), for example, reported a comparison between a group of high-functioning autistic children and control children with a variety of mild mental disorders by using a number of measures, including theory-of-mind tasks, executive function tasks, emotion perception tasks, memory tasks, and spatial tasks. The two deficits that were the most widespread in the autistic sample were those of executive function (i.e., Tower of Hanoi and the Wisconsin Card Sorting Test) and of second-order theory of mind (i.e., questions about one person's thoughts about another person's thoughts). Only some of the autistic children had difficulties with the standard false-belief task (presumably because these subjects were high-functioning). In general, executive function performance was the best discriminator between the two groups. We now consider two ways in which one might view the relationship between executive dysfunctions in autism and theoryof-mind difficulties, which are also a feature of the syndrome. The first concerns assessment and the second concerns etiology. In the first place, given the executive difficulties that autistic persons experience, the tests that have traditionally been used to assess their theory of mind would seem to be inappropriate. For example, the usual procedure for assessing a subject's understanding of false belief is one in which the subject's own knowledge of the object's location is in competition with whatever grasp he or she may have of the protagonist's mental state (Wimmer & Perner, 1983). Clearly, this means setting the subject an executive problem. Were autistic individuals to be given deception and false-belief tasks in which their knowledge of the current state of physical reality was not in competition with their representation of another person's mental state, they would, on this argument, find the tasks much easier. In this context, it is significant that Ozonoff, Pennington, and Rogers (1991) found that it was second-order belief that was the more widespread deficit in the autistic children, because, in addition to requiring some degree of mental knowledge, second-order belief tasks also require the subject to perform a complex series of planful computations not dissimilar from those required by a task such as the Tower of Hanoi. Most normal adults would fail a third- or fourth-order belief task; this would not be because their grasp of mentality is impoverished but because the demands placed on the capacity for sequential embedding are so great. However, there is a piece of evidence that would seem to contradict our claim that autistic subjects fail tasks of the falsebelief kind because they are mentally drawn to the focal object. Autistic subjects perform well on the so-called false-photograph task (Leekam & Perner, in press). This is a task designed by Zaitchik (1990) that is structurally similar to the false-belief task but in which a camera rather than a mind represents the 508 CLAIRE HUGHES AND JAMES RUSSELL initial situation. One answer might be that it is only when autistic subjects' knowledge of another's mental state is in competition with their knowledge about an object that the latter wins out. In the false-photograph task, there is competition between two physical objects for mental salience—the object initially photographed and the photograph. We turn now from questions of assessment to questions of etiology. The previous discussion left open the possibility that, were the executive demands of theory-of-mind tasks stripped away, autistic persons would be shown to have a more or less normal conception of mental life. This is highly implausible. We suggest, instead, that (a) autistic persons' difficulties with mentalizing are real and profound, and (b) that these may be a developmental consequence of early executive dysfunction. It is certainly possible to take the symmetrically opposing view to this and regard executive deficits as a product of an innate lack of a theory of mind (Baron-Cohen, 1989a), and it is certainly possible to regard mentalizing and executive deficits as being causally unrelated. However, the present conjecture is that executive deficits, if they are present very early in life, may handicap the child in the acquisition of mental concepts. Consider, in illustration, the Norman and Shallice (1986) model of the executive system. This contains a "supervisory attentional system" that has it effects by modulating the action of lower, more automatic systems and that comes into play when the individual is required to deal with novelty and to make decisions. Because dealing with novelty and making decisions are two prerequisites for successful social interaction, a child who was congenitally handicapped in this regard would fail to develop normal social relations. Moreover, such a child would fail to develop a sense of himself or herself as a more or less autonomous ego, framing and executing intentions. The developmental outcome would indeed be "lack of a theory of mind." Strong support for the view that autism is rooted in a disorder of the executive functions would be provided by evidence that early frontal impairment results in later autism. However, the evidence is somewhat contradictory (Price, Daffner, Stowe, & Mesulam, 1990; Welsh, Pennington, Ozonoff, Rouse, & McCabe, 1991) and difficult to interpret (Bishop, in press). Until this question is resolved, there are two good reasons for considering the possibility that autism may be rooted in early executive dysfunction. The first of these concerns the neurophysiology of the disorder: We at least know a little about the physiological underpinnings of the executive functions and have some ideas about how malfunctioning of these might result in mental illness. The second reason is that regarding autism as a disorder of the executive functions enables us to explain a wider range of component symptoms. We deal with each of these in turn. In thefirstplace, the commonalities between frontal patients and autistic people have been well documented (Damasio & Maurer, 1978; Fein, Pennington, Markowitz, Braverman, & Waterhouse, 1986; Rumsey, 1985). However, the claim that the underlying deficit in autism involves the prefrontal cortex also suggests a commonality with schizophrenia, a disorder that is often regarded as a "frontal disorder" (C. D. Frith, 1987; Robbins, 1990; Weinberger, 1988). The problem is that although autism and schizophrenia share some features, they are manifestly different syndromes. However, as C. D. Frith and Frith (1991) have argued, this paradox can be resolved by attending to the fact that autism is invariably acquired early in life, whereas schizophrenia is typically acquired later. It is possible to claim that both syndromes are caused by a dysfunction of the frontal-limbic system—early dysfunction in autism and later dysfunction in schizophrenia. The argument is based on C. D. Frith's (1987) account of schizophrenia. The theory runs that in acute schizophrenia there is disruption of the route between the formation of goals and plans and their execution as willed actions: the monitoring of launched intentions has broken down. Such a disruption can explain many of the common acute symptoms, such as patients hearing their own thoughts relayed to them as if broadcast by others, having the delusion that their actions are not under their own control, and misattributing intentions and beliefs to others. The predominantly negative symptoms found in chronic schizophrenia are a developmental outcome of such a chaotic and unpredictable mental life. At this stage, patients now have a deficit not in monitoring goals and plans but in generating them. Note that it is in chronic schizophrenia that we find a high level of stereotypical behavior (C. D. Frith & Done, 1983), similar though not identical to that found in autism (Prior & Macmillan, 1973). To return to the C. D. Frith and Frith (1991) hypothesis in light of this, if a frontal-limbic dysfunction occurs after the period when the basic mental concepts develop in normal children, we would expect a disorder to emerge in which patients know what thinking and intending consist of but in which they cannot control the attribution of these processes—schizophrenia. If, on the other hand, the frontal-limbic dysfunction occurs very early in life, if, that is, there is a disorder of volition while mental concepts are still developing, a disorder will result in which the patient lacks a basic conception of the mental domain—autism. One clear impediment to this hypothesis is the lack of evidence for a specific frontal-limbic dysfunction in autism. In fact, there is a bewildering proliferation of neurological theories of autism, and many of these isolate subcortical rather than frontal impairments (Coleman & Gillberg, 1985; Courchesne, 1989; Prior, 1987; Reichler& Lee, 1987). However, if we assume, along with Luria (1973; and see Prior, 1987), that adequate development of the higher mental functions in the cortex depends on a prior adequate development of intact "lower" processes, then there is no contradiction in isolating an early subcortical dysfunction as the primary cause of autism while also regarding the disorder as a disorder of the executive functions. We turn finally to the second reason for considering autism as a disorder of the executive functions: It explains more symptoms. The stereotypies, excessive desireforsameness,and repetitive interests in very narrow topics that are central features of autism (Kanner, 1943; Prior & Macmillan, 1973) are all easy to regard as manifestations of a deep volitional disorder. They also involve, in various ways, perseveration. Our experiments have highlighted perseveration in autism, and perseveration is strongly associated both with frontal damage and with schizophrenia (Freeman & Gathercole, 1966; C. D. Frith & Done, 1983; Sandson & Albert, 1984). Moreover, the dramatic volitional impairments found in obsessive-compulsive disorder are MENTAL DISENGAGEMENT associated with poor performance on executive function tasks such as the Wisconsin Card Sorting Test (Head, Bolton, & Hymas, 1989). In conclusion, we have argued that an adequate grasp of mental concepts may well depend on the adequate functioning of the executive system, and so, to that extent, there is no unresolvable conflict between approaches to autism that stress executive dysfunctions and those that stress metarepresentational ones. The real theoretical dispute is about which dysfunction is developmentally primary. References American Psychiatric Association. (1987). Diagnostic and statistical manual of mental disorders (3rd ed., rev). Washington, DC: Author. Baron-Cohen, S. (1989a). Do autistic children have obsessions and compulsions? British Journal of Clinical Psychology, 28,193-200. Baron-Cohen, S. (1989b). The autistic child's theory of mind: A case of specific developmental delay. Journal of Child Psychology and Psychiatry, 30, 285-298. Baron-Cohen, S. (1991). The theory of mind in autism: How specific is it? British Journal of Developmental Psychology, 9, 301-314. Baron-Cohen, S. (in press). Out of sight or out of mind?: A naturalistic study of deception in autism. Journal of Child Psychology and Psychiatry. Baron-Cohen, S., Leslie, A. M., & Frith, U (1985). Does the autistic child have a "theory of mind"? Cognition, 21, 37-46. Bishop, D. V M. (1989). T.ROG.—Tesl for the Reception of Grammar. (Available from D. V M. Bishop, Department of Psychology, Manchester University, Manchester Ml 3 9PL, United Kingdom). Bishop, D. V M. (in press). Autism and frontal-limbic functions. Journal ofChild Psychology and Psychiatry. Coleman, M., & Gillberg, C. (1985). The biology of the autistic syndromes. New York: Praeger. Courchesne, E. (1989). Neuroanatomical systems involved in infantile autism: The implications of cerebellar abnormalities. In G. Dawson (Ed.), Autism: Nature, diagnosis, and treatment (pp. 119-143). New York: Guilford Press. Damasio, A. R., & Maurer, R. G. (1978). A neurological model for childhood autism. Archives of Neurology, 35, 777-786. Elliot, C. D, Murray, D. J., & Pearson, L. S. (1983). British Abilities Scales. Windsor, England: NFER-Nelson. Fein, D, Pennington, B., Markowitz, P., Braverman, M., & Waterhouse, L. (1986). Towards a neuropsychological model of infantile autism: Are social deficits primary? Journal of American Academic Childhood Psychiatry, 25, 198-212. Fein, D., Waterhouse, L., Lucci, D, Snyder, D., & Humes, M. (1984, January). Cognitive functions in left- and right-handed autistic children. Paper presented at the annual meeting of the International Neurological Society, Houston, TX. Freeman, T, & Gathercole, C. E. (1966). Perseveration—the clinical symptoms—in chronic schizophrenia and organic dementia. British Journal of Psychiatry, 112, 27-32. Frith, C. D. (1987). The positive and negative symptoms of schizophrenia reflect impairments in the perception and initiation of action. Psychological Medicine, 17, 631-648. Frith, C. D, & Done, D. J. (1983). Stereotyped responding by schizophrenic patients on a two-choice guessing task. Psychological Medicine, 13, 779-786. Frith, C. D., & Frith, U. (1991). Elective affinities between schizophrenia and childhood autism. In P. Bebbington (Ed.), Social psychiatry: Theory, methodology, and practice (pp. 72-111). New Brunswick, NJ: Transactions Press. 509 Frith, U. (1989). Autism: Explaining the enigma. Oxford, England: Basil Blackwell. Grice, H. P. (1957). Meaning. Philosophical Review, 66, 377-388. Head, D, Bolton, D, & Hymas, N. (1989). Deficit in cognitive shifting ability in patients with obsessive-compulsive disorder. Biological Psychiatry, 25, 929-937. Kanner, L. (1943). Autistic disturbances of affective contact. Nervous Children, 2.217-250. Leekam, S. R., & Perner, J. (in press). Does the autistic child have a metarepresentational deficit? Cognition. Leslie, A. M. (1987). Pretense and representation: The origins of "theory of mind." Psychological Review, 94, 412-426. Lockyer, L., & Rutter, M. (1970). Afivetofifteenyear follow-up study of infantile psychosis: IV Patterns of cognitive ability. British Journal of Social and Clinical Psychology, 9,152-163. Luria, A. R. (1973). The working brain. Harmondsworth, Middlesex, England: Penguin Press. Morgan, S. B., Cutrer, P. S., Coplin, J. W, & Rodrique, J. R. (1989). Do autistic children differ from retarded and normal children in Piagetian sensorimotor functioning? Journal ofChild Psychology and Psychiatry, 27, 857-864. Norman, D. A., & Shallice, T. (1986). Attention to action: Willed and automatic control of behavior. In R. J. Stevenson & D. Shapiro (Eds.), Consciousness and self-regulation (Vol. 4, pp. 1 -18). New York: Plenum Press. Ozonoff, S., Pennington, B. F., & Rogers, S. J. (1991). Executive function deficits in high-functioning autistic individuals: Relationship to theory of mind. Journal of Child Psychology and Psychiatry, 32, 1081-1105. Ozonoff, S., Rogers, S. J., & Pennington, B. F. (1991). Asperger's syndrome: Evidence of an empirical distinction from high-functioning autism. Journal of Child Psychology and Psychiatry, 32,1107-1122. Perner, J., Frith, U, Lesfie, A. M., & Leekam, S. R. (1989). Exploration of the autistic child's theory of mind: Knowledge, belief and communication. Child Development, 60, 689-700. Piaget, J. (1950). The psychology ofintelligence. London: Routledge& Kegan Paul. Price, B. H., Daffner, K. R., Stowe, R. M., & Mesulam, M. M. (1990). The comportmental learning disabilities of early frontal damage. Brain, 113, 1388-1393. Prior, M. R. (1987). Biological and neurological approaches to childhood autism. British Journal of Psychiatry, 150, 8-17. Prior, M. R., & Hoffman, W (1990). Brief report: Neuropsychological testing of autistic children through an exploration of frontal lobe tests. Journal of Autism and Developmental Disorders, 20, 581-590. Prior, M. R., & Macmillan, M. B. (1973). Maintenance of sameness in children with Kanner's syndrome. Journal ofAutism and Childhood Schizophrenia, 3, 154-167. Raven, J. (1962). Coloured progressive matrices. London: H. K. Lewis. Reichler, R. J., & Lee, E. M. C. (1987). Overview of biomedical issues in autism. In E. Schopler&G. B. Mesbov (Eds.), Neurobiologicalissues in autism (pp. 142-168). New York: Plenum Press. Robbins, T. W (1990). The case for frontostriatal dysfunction in schizophrenia. Schizophrenia Bulletin, 16, 391 -401. Rumsey, J. M. (1985). Conceptual problem-solving ability in highly verbal, nonretarded autistic men. Journal of Autism and Developmental Disorders, 15, 23-36. Rumsey, J. M., & Hamburger, S. D. (1988). Neuropsychological findings in high-functioning men with infantile autism, residual state. Journal ofClinical and Experimental Neuropsychology, 10, 201 -221. Rumsey, J. M., & Hamburger, S. D. (1990). Neuropsychological divergence of high-level autism and severe dyslexia. Journal ofAutism and Developmental Disorders, 20, 155-168. Russell, J., Mauthner, JN., Sharpe, S., & Tidswell, T. (1991). The 'windows task' as a measure of strategic deception in preschoolers and in 510 CLAIRE HUGHES AND JAMES RUSSELL autistic subjects. British Journal of Developmental Psychology, 9, 331-349. Sandson, J., & Albert, M. L. (1984). Varieties of perseveration. Neuropsychologia. 22, 715-732. Shallice, T. (1988). From neuropsychology to mental structure. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press. Sigman, M., & Ungerer, J. A. (1984). Cognitive and language skills in autistic, mentally retarded, and normal children. Developmental Psychology, 20, 293-302. Sodian, B., & Frith, U. (1992). Deception and sabotage in autistic, retarded and normal children. Journal ofChild Psychology and Psychiatry, 33, 1-15. Steel, J. G., Gorman, R., & Flexman, J. E. (1984). Neuropsychiatric testing in an autistic mathematical idiot-savant: Evidence for nonverbal abstract capacity. Journal of the American Academy of Child Psychiatry, 23, 704-707. Weinberger, D. R. (1988). Schizophrenia and the frontal lobe. Trends in Neurosciences, 11, 367-370. Welsh, M. C, Pennington, B. E, Ozonoff, S., Rouse, B., & McCabe, E. R. B. (1991). Neuropsychology of early-treated phenylketonuria: Specific executive function deficits. Child Development, 61, 1697— 1713. Wimmer, H., & Perner, J. (1983). Beliefs about beliefs: Representation and constraining function of wrong beliefs in young children's understanding of deception. Cognition, 13, 103-128. Woodruff, G, & Premack, D. (1979). Intentional communication in the chimpanzee: The development of deception. Cognition, 7, 333363. Zaitchik, D. (1990). When representations conflict with reality: The preschooler's problem with false beliefs and "false" photographs. Cognition, 35, 41-68. Received November 12,1990 Revision received June 23,1992 Accepted July 10,1992 •