AND EXPERIMENTAL QUASI-EXPERIMENTAL DESIGNSFORGENERALIZED CAUSALINFERENCE ii:. William R. Shadish Trru UNIvERSITYop MEvPrrts .jr-*"'"+.'-, , iLli" fr ** Thomas D. Cook NonrrrwpsrERN UNrvPnslrY Donald T. Campbell HOUGHTONMIFFLINCOMPANY 2002 Boston New York and Experiments Causal Generalized lnference Ex.per'i'ment (ik-spEr'e-mant):[Middle English from Old French from Latin experimentum, from experiri, to try; seeper- in Indo-European Roots.] n. Abbr. exp., expt, 1. a. A test under controlled conditions that is made to demonstratea known truth, examine the validity of a hypothesis, or determine the efficacyof something previously untried' b. The processof conducting such a test; experimentation. 2' An innovative "Democracy is only an experiment in gouernment" act or procedure: (.V{illiam Ralph lnge). Cause (k6z): [Middle English from Old French from Latin causa' teason, purpose.] n. 1. a. The producer of an effect, result, or consequence. b. The one, such as a person, an event' or a condition, that is responsible for an action or a result. v. 1. To be the causeof or reason for; result in. 2. To bring about or compel by authority or force. o MANv historians and philosophers,the increasedemphasison experimentation in the 15th and L7th centuriesmarked the emergenceof modern science 1983). Drake (1981) cites from its roots in natural philosophy (Hacking, 'Water, '1.6'!.2 or Moue in It as usheringin treatrseBodies Tbat Stay Atop Galileo's modern experimental science,but earlier claims can be made favoring \Tilliam Gilbert's1,600study Onthe Loadstoneand MagneticBodies,Leonardoda Vinci's and perhapseventhe Sth-centuryB.C.philoso(1,452-1.51.9) many investigations, pher Empedocles,who used various empirical demonstrationsto argue against '1.969a, 1'969b).In the everyday senseof the term, humans Parmenides(Jones, have beenexperimentingwith different ways of doing things from the earliestmoments of their history. Suchexperimentingis as natural a part of our life as trying a new recipe or a different way of starting campfires. z | 1. EXeERTMENTs ANDGENERALTzED cAUsALINFERENcE I However, the scientific revolution of the 1.7thcentury departed in three ways from the common use of observation in natural philosophy atthat time. First, it increasingly used observation to correct errors in theory. Throughout historg natural philosophers often used observation in their theories, usually to win philosophical arguments by finding observations that supported their theories. However, they still subordinated the use of observation to the practice of deriving theories from "first principles," starting points that humans know to be true by our nature or by divine revelation (e.g., the assumedproperties of the four basic elements of fire, water, earth, and air in Aristotelian natural philosophy). According to some accounts,this subordination of evidenceto theory degeneratedin the 17th "The century: Aristotelian principle of appealing to experiencehad degenerated among philosophers into dependenceon reasoning supported by casual examples and the refutation of opponents by pointing to apparent exceptions not carefully '1,98"1., examined" (Drake, p. xxi).'Sfhen some 17th-century scholarsthen beganto use observation to correct apparent errors in theoretical and religious first principles, they came into conflict with religious or philosophical authorities, as in the case of the Inquisition's demands that Galileo recant his account of the earth revolving around the sun. Given such hazards,the fact that the new experimental science tipped the balance toward observation and ^way from dogma is remarkable. By the time Galileo died, the role of systematicobservation was firmly entrenched as a central feature of science,and it has remained so ever since (Harr6,1981). Second,before the 17th century, appeals to experiencewere usually basedon passive observation of ongoing systemsrather than on observation of what happens after a system is deliberately changed. After the scientific revolution in the L7th centurS the word experiment (terms in boldface in this book are defined in the Glossary) came to connote taking a deliberate action followed by systematic observationof what occurred afterward. As Hacking (1983) noted of FrancisBacon: "He taught that not only must we observenature in the raw, but that we must 'twist also the lion's tale', that is, manipulate our world in order to learn its secrets" (p. U9). Although passiveobservation revealsmuch about the world, active manipulation is required to discover some of the world's regularities and possibilities (Greenwood,, 1989). As a mundane example, stainless steel does not occur naturally; humans must manipulate it into existence.Experimental science came to be concerned with observing the effects of such manipulations. Third, early experimenters realized the desirability of controlling extraneous influences that might limit or bias observation. So telescopeswere carried to higher points at which the air was clearer, the glass for microscopeswas ground ever more accuratelg and scientistsconstructed laboratories in which it was possible to use walls to keep out potentially biasing ether waves and to use (eventually sterilized) test tubes to keep out dust or bacteria. At first, thesecontrols were developed for astronomg chemistrg and physics, the natural sciencesin which interest in sciencefirst bloomed. But when scientists started to use experiments in areas such as public health or education, in which extraneous influences are harder to control (e.g., Lind , 1,753lr,they found that the controls used in natural AND CAUSATTONI I EXPERTMENTS sciencein the laboratoryworked poorly in thesenew applications.So they developed new methodsof dealingwith extraneousinfluence,such as random assignment (Fisher,1,925)or addinga nonrandomizedcontrol group (Coover& Angell, 1.907).As theoreticaland observationalexperienceaccumulatedacrossthesesettings and topics,more sourcesof bias were identifiedand more methodswere developedto copewith them (Dehue,2000). TodaSthe key featurecommonto all experimentsis still to deliberatelyvary somethingso asto discoverwhat happensto somethingelselater-to discoverthe what effectsof presumedcauses.As laypersonswe do this, for example,to assess happensto our blood pressureif we exercisemore, to our weight if we diet less, or ro our behaviorif we read a self-helpbook. However,scientificexperimentation has developedincreasinglyspecializedsubstance,language,and tools, inthat is the pricluding the practiceof field experimentationin the socialsciences mary focus of this book. This chapter begins to explore these matters by (1) discussing the natureof causationthat experimentstest,(2) explainingthe spethat decializedterminology(e.g.,randomizedexperiments,quasi-experiments) generalize problem how to (3) of the scribessocial experiments, introducing causalconnectionsfrom individual experiments,and (4) briefly situatingthe experimentwithin a largerliteratureon the nature of science. AND CAUSATION EXPERIMENTS A sensiblediscussionof experimentsrequiresboth a vocabularyfor talking about causationand an understandingof key conceptsthat underliethat vocabulary. DefiningCause,Effect,and CausalRelationships Most peopleintuitively recognizecausalrelationshipsin their daily lives.For instance,you may say that another automobile'shitting yours was a causeof the damageto your car; that the number of hours you spentstudyingwas a causeof your testgrades;or that the amountof food a friend eatswas a causeof his weight. You may evenpoint to more complicatedcausalrelationships,noting that a low test gradewas demoralizing,which reducedsubsequentstudying,which caused evenlower grades.Here the samevariable(low grade)can be both a causeand an effect,and there can be a reciprocal relationship betweentwo variables (low gradesand not studying)that causeeachother. Despitethis intuitive familiarity with causalrelationsbips,a precisedefinition of causeand effecthaseludedphilosophersfor centuries.lIndeed,the definitions 1. Our analysisrefldctsthe useof the word causationin ordinary language,not the more detaileddiscussionsof causeby philosophers.Readersinterestedin suchdetail may consult a host of works that we referencein this chapter,includingCook and Campbell(1979). 4 AND GENERALTZED CAUSAL INFERENCE | 1. EXPERTMENTS of terms suchas cause and,effectdependpartly on eachother and on the causal relationshipin which both are embedded.So the 17th-centuryphilosopherJohn Locke said: "That which producesany simpleor complexidea,we denoteby the generalnamecaLtse, and that which is produced, effect" (1,97s, p. 32fl and also: " A cAtrseis that which makesany other thing, either simpleidea, substance, or mode,beginto be; and an effectis that, which had its beginningfrom someother thing" (p. 325).Sincethen,otherphilosophers and scientists havegivenus useful definitionsof the threekey ideas--cause,effect,and causalrelationship-that are more specificand that betterilluminatehow experimentswork. We would not defend any of theseas the true or correctdefinition,giventhat the latter haseluded philosophersfor millennia;but we do claignthat theseideashelp to clarify the scientific practiceof probing causes. Cause 'We Considerthe causeof a forest fire. know that fires start in differentways-a match tossedfrom a ca\ a lightning strike, or a smolderingcampfire,for example. None of thesecausesis necessarybecausea forest fire can start evenwhen, say'a match is not present.Also, none of them is sufficientto start the fire. After all, a match must stay "hot" long enoughto start combustion;it must contact combustiblematerial suchas dry leaves;theremust be oxygenfor combustionto occur; and the weather must be dry enoughso that the leavesare dry and the match is not dousedby rain. So the match is part of a constellationof conditions without which a fire will not result,althoughsomeof theseconditionscan be usually takenfor granted,suchasthe availabilityof oxygen.A lightedmatchis, rherefore, what Mackie (1,974)called an inus condition-"an insufficient but nonredundantpart of an unnecessary but sufficient condition" (p. 62; italicsin original). It is insufficientbecausea match cannot start a fire without the other conditions. It is nonredundant only if it adds something fire-promoting that is uniquelydifferent from what the other factors in the constellation(e.g.,oxygen, dry leaves)contributeto startinga fire; after all,it would beharderro saywhether the match causedthe fire if someoneelsesimultaneouslytried startingit with a cigarettelighter.It is part of a sufficientcondition to start a fire in combination with the full constellationof factors.But that condition is not necessary because thereare other setsof conditionsthat can also start fires. A researchexampleof an inus condition concernsa new potentialtreatment for cancer.In the late 1990s,a teamof researchers in Bostonheadedby Dr. Judah Folkman reportedthat a new drug calledEndostatinshrank tumors by limiting their blood supply (Folkman, 1996).Other respectedresearchers could not replicatethe effectevenwhen usingdrugsshippedto them from Folkman'slab. Scientists eventuallyreplicatedthe resultsafter they had traveledto Folkman'slab to learnhow to properlymanufacture,transport,store,and handlethe drug and how to inject it in the right location at the right depth and angle.One observerlabeled thesecontingenciesthe "in-our-hands" phenomenon,meaning "even we don't AND CAUSATIONI S EXPERIMENTS know which details are important, so it might take you some time to work it out" (Rowe, L999, p.732). Endostatin was an inus condition. It was insufficientcause by itself, and its effectivenessrequired it to be embedded in a larger set of conditions that were not even fully understood by the original investigators. Most causesare more accurately called inus conditions. Many factors are usually required for an effectto occur, but we rarely know all of them and how they relate to each other. This is one reason that the causal relationships we discussin this book are not deterministic but only increasethe probability that an effect will occur (Eells,1,991,;Holland, 1,994).It also explains why a given causalrelationship will occur under some conditions but not universally across time, space,hu-"r pop,rlations, or other kinds of treatments and outcomes that are more or less related io those studied. To different {egrees, all causal relationships are context dependent,so the generalizationof experimental effects is always at issue.That is *hy *. return to such generahzationsthroughout this book. Effect 'We that can better understand what an effect is through a counterfactual model'l'973' goes back at least to the 18th-century philosopher David Hume (Lewis, p. SSel. A counterfactual is something that is contrary to fact. In an experiment, ie obseruewhat did happez when people received a treatment. The counterfactual is knowledge of what would haue happened to those same people if they simultaneously had not receivedtreatment. An effect is the difference betweenwhat did happen and what would have happened. 'We cannot actually observe a counterfactual. Consider phenylketonuria metabolic diseasethat causesmental retardation unless (PKU), a genetically-based treated during the first few weeks of life. PKU is the absenceof an enzyme that would otherwise prevent a buildup of phenylalanine, a substance toxic to the nervous system. Vhen a restricted phenylalanine diet is begun early and maintained, reiardation is prevented. In this example, the causecould be thought of as the underlying genetic defect, as the enzymatic disorder, or as the diet. Each implies a difierenicounterfactual. For example, if we say that a restricted phenylalanine diet causeda decreasein PKU-basedmental retardation in infants who are at birth, the counterfactual is whatever would have happened phenylketonuric 'h"d t'h.r. sameinfants not receiveda restricted phenylalanine diet. The samelogic applies to the genetic or enzymatic version of the cause. But it is impossible for theseu.ry ,"-i infants simultaneously to both have and not have the diet, the genetic disorder, or the enzyme deficiency. So a central task for all cause-probing research is to create reasonable approximations to this physically impossible counterfactual. For instance, if it were ethical to do so, we might contrast phenylketonuric infants who were given the diet with other phenylketonuric infants who wer€ not given the diet but who were similar in many ways to those who were (e.g., similar face) gender,age, socioeconomic status, health status). Or we might (if it were ethical) contrast infants who I 6 I 1. EXPERIMENTS ANDGENERALIZED CAUSAL INFERENCE were not on the diet for the first 3 months of their lives with those same infants after they were put on the diet starting in the 4th month. Neither of these approximations is a true counterfactual. In the first case,the individual infants in the treatment condition are different from those in the comparison condition; in the second case, the identities are the same, but time has passedand many changes other than the treatment have occurred to the infants (including permanent damage done by phenylalanine during the first 3 months of life). So two central tasks in experimental design are creating a high-quality but necessarilyimperfect source of counterfactual inference and understanding how this source differs from the treatment condition. This counterfactual reasoning is fundarnentally qualitative becausecausal inference, even in experiments, is fundamentally qualitative (Campbell, 1975; Shadish, 1995a; Shadish 6c Cook, 1,999). However, some of these points have been formalized by statisticiansinto a specialcasethat is sometimescalled Rubin's "1.974,'1.977,1978,79861. CausalModel (Holland, 1,986;Rubin, This book is not about statistics, so we do not describethat model in detail ('West,Biesanz,& Pitts [2000] do so and relate it to the Campbell tradition). A primary emphasisof Rubin's model is the analysis of causein experiments, and its basic premisesare consistent with those of this book.2 Rubin's model has also been widely used to analyze causal inference in case-control studies in public health and medicine (Holland 6c Rubin, 1988), in path analysisin sociology (Holland,1986), and in a paradox that Lord (1967) introduced into psychology (Holland 6c Rubin, 1983); and it has generatedmany statistical innovations that we cover later in this book. It is new enough that critiques of it are just now beginning to appear (e.g., Dawid, 2000; Pearl, 2000). tUfhat is clear, however, is that Rubin's is a very general model with obvious and subtle implications. Both it and the critiques of it are required material for advanced students and scholars of cause-probingmethods. CausalRelationship How do we know if cause and effect are related? In a classic analysis formalized by the 19th-century philosopher John Stuart Mill, a causal relationship exists if (1) the causeprecededthe effect, (2) the causewas related to the effect,and (3) we can find no plausible alternative explanation for the effect other than the cause. These three characteristics mirror what happens in experiments in which (1) we manipulate the presumed cause and observe an outcome afterward; (2) we see whether variation in the cause is related to variation in the effect; and (3) we use various methods during the experiment to reduce the plausibility of other explanations for the effect, along with ancillary methods to explore the plausibility of those we cannot rule out (most of this book is about methods for doing this). 2. However, Rubin's model is not intended to say much about the matters of causal generalization that we address in this book. EXPERTMENTS AND CAUSATTON | 7 I Henceexperimentsare well-suitedto studyingcausalrelationships.No other sciof causalrelationshipssowell. entificmethodregularlymatchesthe characteristics methods. In many correlational Mill's analysisalsopointsto the weaknessof other studies,for example,it is impossibleto know which of two variablescamefirst, so defendinga causalrelationshipbetweenthem is precarious.Understandingthis logic of causalrelationshipsand how its key terms,suchas causeand effect,are to critique cause-probingstudies. definedhelpsresearchers and Confounds Correlation, Causation, A well-known maxim in research is: Correlation does not proue causation. This is so becausewe may not know which variable came first nor whether alternative explanations for the presumed effectexist. For example, supposeincome and education are correlated.Do you have to have a high income before you can aff.ordto pay for education,or do you first have to get a good education before you can get a better paying job? Each possibility may be true, and so both need investigation.But until those investigationsare completed and evaluatedby the scholarly communiry a simple correlation doesnot indicate which variable came first. Correlations also do little to rule out alternative explanations for a relationship between two variables such as education and income. That relationship may not be causal at all but rather due to a third variable (often called a confound), such as intelligence or family socioeconomicstatus,that causesboth high education and high income. For example, if high intelligencecausessuccessin education and on the job, then intelligent people would have correlatededucation and incomes,not becauseeducation causesincome (or vice versa) but becauseboth would be causedby intelligence.Thus a central task in the study of experiments is identifying the different kinds of confounds that can operate in a particular researcharea and understanding the strengthsand weaknessesassociatedwith various ways of dealing with them Causes and Nonmanipulable Manipulable In the intuitive understandingof experimentationthat most peoplehave,it makes senseto say,"Let's seewhat happensif we requirewelfarerecipientsto work"; but it makesno senseto say,"Let's seewhat happensif I changethis adult maleinto a Experimentsexplore girl." And so it is alsoin scientificexperiments. three-year-old of a medicine,the the dose the effectsof things that can be manipulated,such as amount of a welfarecheck,the kind or amount of psychotherapyor the number of childrenin a classroom.Nonmanipulableevents(e.g.,the explosionof a supernova) or attributes(e.g.,people'sages,their raw geneticmaterial,or their biologiwe cannotdeliberatelyvary them cal sex)cannotbe causesin experimentsbecause most scientistsand philosophersagree to seewhat then happens.Consequently, that it is much harderto discoverthe effectsof nonmanipulablecauses. I 8 | 1. EXeERTMENTS ANDGENERALTzED cAUsALTNFERENcE To be clear,we are not arguing that all causesmust be manipulable-only that experimental causesmust be so. Many variables that we correctly think of as causes are not directly manipulable. Thus it is well establishedthat a geneticdefect causes PKU even though that defect is not directly manipulable.'We can investigatesuch causesindirectly in nonexperimental studiesor even in experimentsby manipulating biological processesthat prevent the gene from exerting its influence, as through the use of diet to inhibit the gene'sbiological consequences.Both the nonmanipulable gene and the manipulable diet can be viewed as causes-both covary with PKU-basedretardation, both precedethe retardation, and it is possibleto explore other explanations for the gene'sand the diet's effectson cognitive functioning. However, investigating the manipulablc diet as a causehas two important advantages over considering the nonmanipulable genetic problem as a cause.First, only the diet provides a direct action to solve the problem; and second,we will see that studying manipulable agents allows a higher quality source of counterfactual inferencethrough such methods as random assignment.\fhen individuals with the nonmanipulable genetic problem are compared with personswithout it, the latter are likely to be different from the former in many ways other than the genetic defect. So the counterfactual inference about what would have happened to those with the PKU genetic defect is much more difficult to make. Nonetheless,nonmanipulable causesshould be studied using whatever means are availableand seemuseful. This is true becausesuch causeseventuallyhelp us to find manipulable agents that can then be used to ameliorate the problem at hand. The PKU example illustrates this. Medical researchersdid not discover how to treat PKU effectively by first trying different diets with retarded children. They first discovered the nonmanipulable biological features of retarded children affected with PKU, finding abnormally high levels of phenylalanine and its associated metabolic and genetic problems in those children. Those findings pointed in certain ameliorative directions and away from others, leading scientiststo experiment with treatments they thought might be effective and practical. Thus the new diet resulted from a sequenceof studies with different immediate purposes, with different forms, and with varying degreesof uncertainty reduction. Somewere experimental, but others were not. Further, analogue experiments can sometimes be done on nonmanipulable causes,that is, experiments that manipulate an agent that is similar to the cause of interest. Thus we cannot change a person's race, but we can chemically induce skin pigmentation changes in volunteer individuals-though such analogues do not match the reality of being Black every day and everywhere for an entire life. Similarly past events,which are normally nonmanipulable, sometimesconstitute a natural experiment that may even have been randomized, as when the 1'970 Vietnam-era draft lottery was used to investigate a variety of outcomes (e.g., Angrist, Imbens, & Rubin, 1.996a;Notz, Staw, & Cook, l97l). Although experimenting on manipulable causesmakes the job of discovering their effectseasier,experiments are far from perfect means of investigating causes. I EXPERIMENTS AND CAUSATIONI 9 Sometimesexperiments modify the conditions in which testing occurs in a way that reducesthe fit between those conditions and the situation to which the results are to be generalized.Also, knowledge of the effects of manipulable causestells nothing about how and why those effectsoccur. Nor do experiments answer many example, which questions are other questions relevant to the real world-for worth asking, how strong the need for treatment is, how a cause is distributed through societg whether the treatment is implemented with theoretical fidelitS and what value should be attached to the experimental results. In additioq, in experiments,we first manipulate a treatment and only then observeits effects;but in some other studieswe first observean effect, such as AIDS, and then search for its cause, whether manipulable or not. Experiments cannot help us with that search. Scriven (1976) likens such searchesto detective work in which a crime has been committed (..d., " robbery), the detectivesobservea particular pattern of evidencesurrounding the crime (e.g.,the robber wore a baseball cap and a distinct jacket and used a certain kind of Bun), and then the detectives searchfor criminals whose known method of operating (their modus operandi or m.o.) includes this pattern. A criminal whose m.o. fits that pattern of evidence then becomesa suspect to be investigated further. Epidemiologists use a similar method, the case-control design (Ahlbom 6c Norell, 1,990),in which they observe a particular health outcome (e.g., an increasein brain tumors) that is not seen in another group and then attempt to identify associatedcauses(e.g., increasedcell phone use). Experiments do not aspire to answer all the kinds of questions, not even all the types of causal questions, that social scientistsask. and CausalExplanation CausalDescription attribThe uniquestrengthof experimentationis in describingthe consequences utableto deliberatelyvaryinga treatment.'Wecall this causaldescription.In contrast, experimentsdo lesswell in clarifying the mechanismsthrough which and the conditionsunder which that causalrelationshipholds-what we call causal explanation.For example,most childrenvery quickly learnthe descriptivecausal relationshipbetweenflicking a light switch and obtainingillumination in a room. However,few children (or evenadults)can fully explain why that light goeson. To do so, they would haveto decomposethe treatment(the act of flicking a light switch)into its causallyefficaciousfeatures(e.g.,closingan insulatedcircuit) and its nonessentialfeatures(e.g.,whetherthe switch is thrown by hand or a motion detector).They would haveto do the samefor the effect (eitherincandescentor fluorescentlight can be produced,but light will still be produced whether the light fixture is recessedor not). For full explanation,they would then have to show how the causallyefficaciousparts of the treatmentinfluencethe causally affectedparts of the outcomethrough identified mediating processes(e.g.,the I INFERENCE ANDGENERALIZED CAUSAL 1O I T. CXPTRIMENTS passageof electricity through the circuit, the excitation of photons).3 ClearlS the causeof the light going on is a complex cluster of many factors. For those philosophers who equate cause with identifying that constellation of variables that necessarily inevitably and infallibly results in the effect (Beauchamp,1.974),talk of cause is not warranted until everything of relevanceis known. For them, there is no causal description without causal explanation. Whatever the philosophic merits of their position, though, it is not practical to expect much current social science to achieve such complete explanation. The practical importance of causal explanation is brought home when the switch fails to make the light go on and when replacing the light bulb (another easily learned manipulation) fails to solva the problem. Explanatory knowledge then offers clues about how to fix the problem-for example, by detecting and repairing a short circuit. Or if we wanted to create illumination in a place without lights and we had explanatory knowledge, we would know exactly which features of the cause-and-effectrelationship are essentialto create light and which are irrelevant. Our explanation might tell us that there must be a source of electricity but that that source could take several different molar forms, such as abattery, a generator, a windmill, or a solar array. There must also be a switch mechanism to close a circuit, but this could also take many forms, including the touching of two bare wires or even a motion detector that trips the switch when someone enters the room. So causal explanation is an important route to the generalization of causal descriptions becauseit tells us which features of the causal relationship are essentialto transfer to other situations. This benefit of causal explanation helps elucidate its priority and prestige in all sciencesand helps explain why, once a novel and important causal relationship is discovered, the bulk of basic scientific effort turns toward explaining why and how it happens. Usuallg this involves decomposing the causeinto its causally effective parts, decomposing the effects into its causally affected parts, and identifying the processesthrough which the effective causal parts influence the causally affected outcome parts. These examplesalso show the close parallel between descriptive and explanatory causation and molar and molecular causation.aDescriptive causation usually concerns simple bivariate relationships between molar treatments and molar outcomes, molar here referring to a package that consistsof many different parts. For instance, we may find that psychotherapy decreasesdepression,a simple descriptive causal relationship benveen a molar treatment package and a molar outcome. However, psychotherapy consists of such parts as verbal interactions, placebo3. However, the full explanationa physicistwould offer might be quite different from this electrician's explanation,perhapsinvoking the behaviorof subparticles.This differenceindicatesiust how complicatedis the notion of explanationand how it can quickly becomequite complex once one shifts levelsof analysis. 4. By molar, we mean somethingtaken as a whole rather than in parts. An analogyis to physics,in which molar might refer to the propertiesor motions of masses,as distinguishedfrom those of moleculesor atomsthat make up thosemasses. EXPERIMENTS AND CAUSATIONI 11 I generating procedures, setting characteristics,time constraints, and payment for services.Similarly, many depression measuresconsist of items pertaining to the physiological,cognitive, and affectiveaspectsof depression.Explan atory causation breaks thesemolar causesand effectsinto their molecular parts so as to learn, say, that the verbal interactions and the placebo featuresof therapy both causechanges in the cognitive symptoms of depression,but that payment for servicesdoes not do so even though it is part of the molar treatment package. If experiments are less able to provide this highly-prized explanatory causal knowledge, why.are experimentsso central to science,especiallyto basic social science,in which theory and explanation are often the coin of the realm? The answer is that the dichotomy ber'*reendescriptive and explanatory causation is lessclear in scientific practice than in abstract discussionsabout causation.First, many causal explanatironsconsist of chains of descriptivi causal links in which one event causesthe next. Experiments help to test the links in each chain. Second,experiments help distinguish betweenthe validity of competing explanatory theories, for example, by testing competing mediating links proposed by those theories. Third, some experiments test whether a descriptive causal relationship varies in strength or direction under Condition A versus Condition B (then the condition is a moderator variable that explains the conditions under which the effect holds). Fourth, some experimentsadd quantitative or qualitative observations of the links in the explanatory chain (mediator variables) to generateand study explanations for the descriptive causal effect. Experiments are also prized in applied areas of social science,in which the identification of practical solutions to social problems has as great or even greater priority than explanations of those solutions. After all, explanation is not always required for identifying practical solutions. Lewontin (1997) makes this point about the Human Genome Project, a coordinated multibillion-dollar research program ro map the human genome that it is hoped eventually will clarify the genetic causesof diseases.Lewontin is skeptical about aspectsof this search: '!ilhat is involvedhereis the differencebetweenexplanationand intervention.Many disorderscan be explainedby the failureof the organismto makea normal protein,a of a genemutation.But interuentionrequiresthat the failurethat is the consequence normalproteinbe providedat the right placein the right cells,at the right time and in the right amount,or elsethat an alternativeway be found to providenormal cellular to keepthe abnormalproteinaway function.'Whatis worse,it might evenbenecessary from the cellsat criticalmoments.None of theseobjectivesis servedby knowing the "1,997, p.29) of the defectivegene.(Lewontin, DNA sequence Practical applications are not immediately revealedby theoretical advance.Instead, to reveal them may take decadesof follow-up work, including tests of simple descriptive causal relationships. The same point is illustrated by the cancer drug Endostatin, discussedearlier. Scientistsknew the action of the drug occurred through cutting off tumor blood supplies; but to successfullyuse the drug to treat cancersin mice required administering it at the right place, angle, and depth, and those details were not part of the usual scientific explanation of the drug's effects. 12 I 1. EXPERTMENTS AND GENERALTZED TNFERENCE CAUSAL I In the end,then,causaldescriptionsand causalexplanationsarein delicatebalancein experiments.'$7hat experimentsdo bestis to improvecausaldescriptions; they do lesswell at explainingcausalrelationships.But most experimentscan be designedto providebetterexplanationsthan is typicallythe casetoday.Further,in focusingon causaldescriptions,experimentsoften investigatemolar eventsthat may be less strongly related to outcomesthan are more molecularmediating processes, especiallythoseprocesses that are closerto the outcomein the explanatory chain. However,many causaldescriptionsare still dependableand strong enoughto be useful,to be worth making the building blocks around which important policiesand theoriesare created.Just considerthe dependabilityof such causalstatements asthat schooldesegregation causeswhite flight, or that outgroup threat causesingroup cohesion,or that psychotherapyimprovesmentalhealth,or that diet reducesthe retardationdueto PKU. Suchdependable causalrelationships are usefulto policymakers,practitioners,and scientistsalike. MODERNDESCRIPTIONS OF EXPERIMENTS Some of the terms used in describing modern experimentation (seeTable L.L) are unique, clearly defined, and consistently used; others are blurred and inconsistently used. The common attribute in all experiments is control of treatment (though control can take many different forms). So Mosteller (1990, p. 225) writes, "fn an experiment the investigator controls the application of the treatment"l and Yaremko, Harari, Harrison, and Lynn (1,986,p.72) write, "one or more independent variables are manipulated to observe their effects on one or more dependentvariables." However, over time many different experimental subtypes have developed in responseto the needs and histories of different sciences 'Winston ('Winston, 1990; 6c Blais, 1.996\. TABLE1.1TheVocabularyof Experiments Experiment: A studyin whichan intervention to observe itseffects. is deliberately introduced Randomized Experiment: to receive the treatmentor An experiment in whichunitsareassigned an alternative conditionby a randomprocess suchasthe tossof a coinor a tableof randomnumbers. randomly. An experiment in whichunitsarenot assigned to conditions Quasi-Experiment: NaturalExperiment: Not reallyan experiment because the causeusuallycannotbe manipulated; with a studythat contrasts eventsuchasan earthquake occurring a naturally a comoarison condition. Correlational or observational study;a study Study:Usuallysynonymous with nonexperimental thatsimplyobserves amongvariables. the sizeanddirection of a relationship I OF EXPERIMENTS MODERNDESCRIPTIONS I tr Experiment Randomized The most clearlydescribedvariant is the randomizedexperiment,widely credited to Sir RonaldFisher(1,925,1926).Itwas first usedin agriculturebut laterspread to other topic areasbecauseit promisedcontrol over extraneoussourcesof variation without requiringthe physicalisolationof the laboratory.Its distinguishing featureis clear and important-that the varioustreatmentsbeingcontrasted(includingno treatmentat all) are assignedto experimentalunits' by chance,for example,by cointossor useof a table of random numbers.If implementedcorrectlS ,"rdo- assignmentcreatestwo or more groupsof units that are probabilistically Hence,any outcomedifferencesthat are obsimilarto .".h other on the average.6 servedbetweenthosegroupsat the end,ofa study arelikely to be dueto treatment' not to differencesbetweenthe groupsthat alreadyexistedat the start of the study. Further,when certainassumptionsare met, the randomizedexperimentyieldsan estimateof the sizeof a treatmenteffectthat has desirablestatisticalproperties' along with estimatesof the probability that the true effectfalls within a defined confidenceinterval.Thesefeaturesof experimentsare so highly prized that in a researchareasuchas medicinethe randomizedexperimentis often referredto as the gold standardfor treatmentoutcomeresearch.' Closelyrelatedto the randomizedexperimentis a more ambiguousand inconsistentlyusedterm, true experiment.Someauthorsuseit synonymouslywith randomizedexperiment(Rosenthal& Rosnow,1991').Others useit more genermanipally to refer to any studyin which an independentvariableis deliberately 'We ulated (Yaremkoet al., 1,9861anda dependentvariableis assessed. shall not usethe term at all givenits ambiguity and given that the modifier true seemsto imply restrictedclaimsto a singlecorrectexperimentalmethod. Quasi-Experiment Much of this book focuseson a class of designsthat Campbell and Stanley sharewith all other (1,963)popularizedasquasi-experiments.s Quasi-experiments 5. Units can be people,animals,time periods,institutions,or almost anything else.Typically in field experimentationthey are peopleor someaggregateof people,such as classroomsor work sites.In addition, a little thought showsthat random assignmentof units to treatmentsis the sameas assignmentof treatmentsto units, so thesephrasesare frequendyusedinterchangeably' 6. The word probabilisticallyis crucial, as is explainedin more detail in Chapter 8. 7. Although the rerm randomized experiment is used this way consistently acrossmany fields and in this book, statisticianssometimesuse the closely related term random experiment in a different way to indicate experiments for which the outcomecannor be predictedwith certainry(e.g.,Hogg & Tanis, 1988). 8. Campbell (1957) first calledthesecompromisedesignsbut changedterminologyvery quickly; Rosenbaum (1995a\ and Cochran (1965\ referto theseas observationalstudies,a term we avoid becausemany peopleuseit to to refer to correlationalor nonexperimentalstudies,as well. Greenbergand Shroder(1997) usequdsi-etcperiment refer to studiesthat randomly assigngroups (e.g.,communities)to conditions,but we would considerthesegrouprandomizedexperiments(Murray' 1998). I 14 I 1. EXPERIMENTS AND GENERALIZED CAUSAL INFERENCE I experiments a similar purpose-to test descriptivecausal hypothesesabout manipulable causes-as well as many structural details, such as the frequent presenceof control groups and pretest measures,to support a counterfactual inference about what would have happened in the absenceof treatment. But, by definition, quasiexperiments lack random assignment. Assignment to conditions is by means of selfselection,by which units choosetreatment for themselves,or by meansof administrator selection,by which teachers,bureaucrats,legislators,therapists,physicians, or others decide which persons should get which treatment. Howeveq researchers who use quasi-experimentsmay still have considerablecontrol over selectingand schedulingmeasures,over how nonrandom assignmentis executed,over the kinds of comparison groups with which treatment,groups are compared, and over some aspectsof how treatment is scheduled.As Campbell and Stanleynote: There are many natural socialsettingsin which the researchpersoncan introduce somethinglike experimentaldesigninto his schedulingof data collectionprocedures (e.g.,the uhen and to whom of measurement), eventhough he lacksthe full control over the schedulingof experimentalstimuli (the when and to wltom of exposureand the ability to randomizeexposures)which makesa true experimentpossible.Collecdesigns.(Campbell& tively,such situationscan be regardedas quasi-experimental p. 34) StanleS1,963, In quasi-experiments,the causeis manipulable and occurs before the effect is measured. However, quasi-experimental design features usually create less compelling support for counterfactual inferences. For example, quasi-experimental control groups may differ from the treatment condition in many systematic(nonrandom) ways other than the presenceof the treatment Many of theseways could be alternative explanations for the observed effect, and so researchershave to worry about ruling them out in order to get a more valid estimate of the treatment effect. By contrast, with random assignmentthe researcherdoes not have to think as much about all these alternative explanations. If correctly done, random assignment makes most of the alternatives less likely as causes of the observed treatment effect at the start of the study. In quasi-experiments,the researcherhas to enumeratealternative explanations one by one, decide which are plausible, and then use logic, design, and measurement to assesswhether each one is operating in a way that might explain any observedeffect. The difficulties are that thesealternative explanations are never completely enumerable in advance, that some of them are particular to the context being studied, and that the methods neededto eliminate them from contention will vary from alternative to alternative and from study to study. For example, suppose two nonrandomly formed groups of children are studied, a volunteer treatment group that gets a new reading program and a control group of nonvolunteerswho do not get it. If the treatment group does better, is it becauseof treatment or becausethe cognitive development of the volunteerswas increasingmore rapidly even before treatment began? (In a randomized experiment, maturation rates would t rl OF EXPERIMENTS 1s MODERNDESCRIPTIONS | this alternative,the rehavebeenprobabilisticallyequalin both groups.)To assess searchermight add multiple preteststo revealmaturationaltrend beforethe treatment, and then comparethat trend with the trend after treatment. Another alternativeexplanationmight bethat the nonrandomcontrol group into booksin their homesor childrenwho had lessaccess cludedmoredisadvantaged who had parentswho read to them lessoften. (In a randomizedexperiment'both this altergroupswould havehad similar proportionsof suchchildren.)To assess nativi, the experimentermay measurethe number of books at home,parentaltime would spentreadingtochildren,and perhapstrips to libraries.Then the researcher seeif thesevariablesdiffered acrosstreatment and control groups in the hypothesizeddirection that could explain the observedtreatment effect. Obviously,as the number of plausiblealternativeexplapationsincreases,the designof the quasi. experimentbecomesmore intellectually demandingand complex---especiallybecausewe are nevercertainwe haveidentifiedall the alternativeexplanations.The efforts of the quasi-experimenterstart to look like affemptsto bandagea wound that would havebeenlesssevereif random assignmenthad beenusedinitially. The ruling out of alternativehypothesesis closelyrelatedto a falsificationist logic popularizedby Popper(1959).Poppernoted how hard it is to be sure that a g*.r"t conclusion(e.g.,,ll r*"ttr are white) is correct basedon a limited set of observations(e.g.,all the swansI've seenwere white). After all, future observations may change(e.g.,somedayI may seea black swan).So confirmation is logically difficult. By contrast,observinga disconfirminginstance(e.g.,a black swan) is sufficient,in Popper'sview, to falsify the generalconclusionthat all swansare white. Accordingly,nopper urged scientiststo try deliberatelyto falsify the conclusionsthey wiih to draw rather than only to seekinformation corroborating them. Conciusionsthat withstand falsificationare retainedin scientificbooks or journals and treated as plausible until better evidencecomes along. Quasiexperimentationis falsificationistin that it requiresexperimentersto identify a causalclaim and then to generateand examineplausiblealternativeexplanations that might falsify the claim. However,suchfalsificationcan neverbe as definitiveas Popperhoped.Kuhn (7962) pointed out that falsificationdependson two assumptionsthat can never be fully tested.The first is that the causalclaim is perfectlyspecified.But that is neverih. ."r.. So many featuresof both the claim and the test of the claim are debatable-for example,which outcome is of interest,how it is measured,the conditionsof treatment,who needstreatment,and all the many other decisions must make in testingcausalrelationships.As a result, disconfirthat researchers mation often leadstheoriststo respecifypart of their causaltheories.For example, they might now specifynovel conditionsthat must hold for their theory to be irue and that were derivedfrom the apparentlydisconfirmingobservations.Second, falsificationrequiresmeasuresthat are perfectlyvalid reflectionsof the theory being tested.However,most philosophersmaintain that all observationis theorv-laden.It is laden both with intellectualnuancesspecificto the partially INFERENCE AND GENERALIZED CAUSAL 16 I 1. EXPERIMENTS I of the theory held by the individual or group deuniquescientificunderstandings vising the test and also with the experimenters'extrascientificwishes,hopes, aspirations,and broadly shared cultural assumptionsand understandings.If measuresare not independentof theories,how can they provideindependenttheory tests,includingtestsof causaltheories?If the possibilityof theory-neutralobservationsis denied,with them disappearsthe possibilityof definitiveknowledge both of what seemsto confirm a causalclaim and of what seemsto disconfirmit. a fallibilist versionof falsificationis possible.It arguesthat studNonetheless, iesof causalhypothesescan still usefullyimproveunderstandingof generaltrends that might pertainto thosetrends.It ardespiteignoranceof all the contingencies guesthat causalstudiesare usefulevenif w0 haveto respecifythe initial hypothAfesisrepeatedlyto accommodatenew contingenciesand new understandings. ter all, those respecificationsare usually minor in scope;they rarely involve wholesaleoverthrowingof generaltrendsin favor of completelyoppositetrends. Fallibilist falsificationalso assumesthat theory-neutralobservationis impossible but that observationscan approacha more factlikestatuswhenthey havebeenrepeatedlymadeacrossdifferenttheoreticalconceptionsof a construct,acrossmulthat observaand at multiple times.It alsoassumes tiple kinds of measurements, that different and one, not tions are imbued with multiple theories, iust operationalproceduresdo not sharethe samemultiple theories.As a result,observationsthat repeatedlyoccur despitedifferent theoriesbeing built into them havea specialfactlike statusevenif they can neverbe fully justifiedascompletely theory-neutralfacts.In summary,then, fallible falsificationis more than just seeing whether observationsdisconfirm a prediction. It involvesdiscoveringand judging the worth of ancillary assumptionsabout the restrictedspecificityof the causalhypothesisunder test and also about the heterogeneityof theories,viewpoints, settings,and times built into the measuresof the causeand effectand of modifying their relationship. any contingencies It is neitherfeasiblenor desirableto rule out all possiblealternativeinterpretarionsof a causalrelationship.Instead,only plausiblealternativesconstitutethe major focus.This servespartly to keep matterstractablebecausethe number of possiblealternativesis endless.It also recognizesthat many alternativeshaveno seriousempiricalor experientialsupport and so do not warrant specialattention. However,the lack of supportcan sometimesbe deceiving.For example,the cause of stomachulcerswas long thought to be a combinationof lifestyle(e.g.,stress) and excessacid production. Few scientistsseriouslythought that ulcers were that an it was assumed causedby a pathogen(e.g.,virus,germ,bacteria)because However,in L982 Ausacid-filled stomachwould destroy all living organisms. 'Warren discoveredspiral-shaped tralian researchersBarry Marshall and Robin bacteria,later named Helicobacterpylori (H. pylori), in ulcerpatients'stomachs. rilfith this discovery,the previouslypossiblebut implausiblebecameplausible.By "1994, a U.S. National Institutesof Health ConsensusDevelopmentConference concluded that H. pylori was the major causeof most peptic ulcers. So labeling ri- I OFEXPERIMENTS MODERNDESCRTPTONS II tt val hypothesesas plausible dependsnot just on what is logically possible but on social consensus,shared experienceand, empirical data. Becausesuch factors are often context specific, different substantive areasdevelop their own lore about which alternatives are important enough to need to be controlled, even developing their own methods for doing so. In early psychologg for example, a control group with pretest observations was invented to control for the plausible alternative explanation that, by giving practice in answering test content, pretestswould produce gains in performance even in the absenceof a treatment effect (Coover 6c Angell, 1907). Thus the focus on plausibility is a two-edged sword: it reducesthe range of alternatives to be considered in quasi-experimental work, yet it also leavesthe resulting causal inference vulnerable to the discovery that an implausible-seemingalternative may later emerge as a likely causal agent. NaturalExperiment The term natural experiment describesa naturally-occurring contrast between a treatment and a comparisoncondition (Fagan, 1990; Meyer, 1995;Zeisel,1,973l. Often the treatments are not even potentially manipulable, as when researchers retrospectivelyexamined whether earthquakesin California causeddrops in property values (Brunette, 1.995; Murdoch, Singh, 6c Thayer, 1993). Yet plausible causal inferences about the effects of earthquakes are easy to construct and defend. After all, the earthquakesoccurred before the observations on property values,and it is easyto seewhether earthquakesare related to properfy values. A useful source of counterfactual inference can be constructed by examining property values in the same locale before the earthquake or by studying similar localesthat did not experience an earthquake during the bame time. If property values dropped right after the earthquake in the earthquake condition but not in the comparison condition, it is difficult to find an alternative explanation for that drop. Natural experiments have recently gained a high profile in economics. Before the 1990s economists had great faith in their ability to produce valid causal inferencesthrough statistical adjustments for initial nonequivalence between treatment and control groups. But two studies on the effects of job training programs showed that those adjustments produced estimates that were not close to those generated from a randomized experiment and were unstable across tests of the model's sensitivity (Fraker 6c Maynard, 1,987; Lalonde, 1986). Hence, in their searchfor alternative methods, many economistscame to do natural experiments, such as the economic study of the effects that occurred in the Miami job market when many prisoners were releasedfrom Cuban jails and allowed to come to the United States(Card, 1990). They assumethat the releaseof prisoners (or the timing of an earthquake) is independent of the ongoing processesthat usually affect unemployment rates (or housing values). Later we explore the validity of this assumption-of its desirability there can be little question. 18 I 1. EXPERIMENTS AND GENERALIZED INFERENCE CAUSAL Nonexperimental Designs The termscorrelationaldesign,passiveobservationaldesign,and nonexperimental designrefer to situationsin which a presumedcauseand effect are identified and measuredbut in which other structural featuresof experimentsare missing.Random assignmentis not part of the design,nor are suchdesignelementsas pretests and control groupsfrom which researchers might constructa usefulcounterfactual inference.Instead,relianceis placedon measuringalternativeexplanationsindividually and then statisticallycontrolling for them. In cross-sectional studiesin which all the data aregatheredon the respondentsat one time, the researchermay not even know if the causeprecedesthe dffect. When thesestudiesare used for causalpurposes,the missingdesignfeaturescan be problematicunlessmuch is already known about which alternativeinterpretationsare plausible,unlessthose that are plausiblecan be validly measured,and unlessthe substantivemodel used for statisticaladjustmentis well-specified. Theseare difficult conditionsto meetin the real world of researchpractice,and thereforemany commentatorsdoubt the potentialof suchdesignsto supportstrongcausalinferencesin most cases. EXPERIMENTS ANDTHEGENERALIZATION OF CAUSALCONNECTIONS The strength of experimentation is its ability to illuminate causal inference. The weaknessof experimentation is doubt about the extent to which that causal rela'We tionship generalizes. hope that an innovative feature of this book is its focus on generalization. Here we introduce the general issuesthat are expanded in later chapters. Most Experiments Are HighlyLocalBut Have GeneralAspirations Most experimentsare highly localizedand particularistic.They are almostalways conductedin a restrictedrange of settings,often just one, with a particular version of one type of treatmentrather than, say,a sampleof all possibleversions. Usually they have severalmeasures-eachwith theoreticalassumptionsthat are differentfrom thosepresentin other measures-but far from a completesetof all possiblemeasures.Each experimentnearly always usesa convenientsampleof people rather than one that reflectsa well-describedpopulation; and it will inevitably be conductedat a particular point in time that rapidly becomeshistory. Yet readersof experimentalresultsare rarelyconcernedwith what happened in that particular,past,local study.Rather,they usuallyaim to learn eitherabout theoreticalconstructsof interestor about alarger policy.Theoristsoften want to CONNECTIONS OFCAUSAL AND THEGENERALIZATION EXeERTMENTS I t' connect experimental results to theories with broad conceptual applicability, which ,.q,rir., generalization at the linguistic level of constructs rather than at the level of the operations used to represent these constructs in a given experiment. They nearly always want to generallzeto more people and settings than are representedin a single experiment. Indeed, the value assignedto a substantive theory usually dependson how broad a rangeof phenomena the theory covers. SimilarlS policymakers may be interested in whether a causal relationship would hold implemented as a iprobabilistically) across the many sites at which it would be experimental original the beyond policS an inferencethat requires generalization stody contexr. Indeed, all human beings probably value the perceptual and cognitive stability that is fostered by generalizations. Otherwise, the world might appear as a btulzzingcacophony of isolqted instances requiring constant cognitive processingthat would overwhelm our limited capacities. In defining generalizationas a problem, we do not assumethat more broadly applicable resulti are always more desirable(Greenwood, 1989). For example, physicists -ho use particle accelerators to discover new elements may not expect that it would be desiiable to introduce such elementsinto the world. Similarly, social scientists sometimes aim to demonstrate that an effect is possible and to understand its mechanismswithout expecting that the effect can be produced more generally. For "sleeper effect" occurs in an attitude change study involving perinstance, when a suasivecommunications, the implication is that change is manifest after a time delay but not immediately so. The circumstancesunder which this effect occurs turn out to be quite limited and unlikely to be of any general interest other than to show that the theory predicting it (and many other ancillary theories) may not be wrong (Cook, Gruder, Hennigan & Flay l979\.Experiments that demonstrate limited generalization may be just as valuable as those that demonstratebroad generalization. Nonetheless,a conflict seemsto exist berweenthe localized nature of the causal knowledge that individual experiments provide and the more generalizedcausal goals that researchaspiresto attain. Cronbach and his colleagues(Cronbach et al., f gSO;Cronbach, 19821havemade this argument most forcefully and their works have contributed much to our thinking about causal generalization. Cronbach noted that each experiment consistsof units that receivethe experiencesbeing contrasted, of the treaiments themselves, of obseruations made on the units, and of the settings in which the study is conducted. Taking the first letter from each of these "instances on which data four iords, he defined the acronym utos to refer to the "1.982,p. 78)-to the actual people,treatments' measures' are collected" (Cronb ach, and settingsthat were sampledin the experiment. He then defined two problems of "domain about which [the] question is asked" generalizition: (1) generaliiing to the "units, treatments,variables, (p.7g),which he called UTOS; and (2) generalizingto oUTOS.e "nd r.r,ings not directly observed" (p. 831,*hi.h he called S, 9. We oversimplify Cronbach'spresentationhere for pedagogicalreasons.For example,Cronbach only usedcapital not small s, so that his system,eferred only to ,tos, not utos. He offered diverseand not always consistentdefinitions do here. of UTOS and *UTOS, in particular. And he doesnot usethe word generalizationin the samebroad way we I INFERENCE 20 I 1. EXPERIMENTS AND GENERALIZED CAUSAL outlinedbelowand presentedin more deOur theoryof causalgeneralization, tail in ChaptersLL through 13, melds Cronbach'sthinking with our own ideas about generalizationfrom previousworks (Cook, 1990, t99t; Cook 6c Campbell,1979), creatinga theory that is differentin modestways from both of these predecessors. Our theory is influencedby Cronbach'swork in two ways.First, we follow him by describingexperimentsconsistentlythroughout this book as consistingof the elementsof units, treatments,observations,and settingsrlothough we frequentlysubstitutepersonsfor units giventhat most field experimentationis conductedwith humansas participants.:Wealsooften substituteoutcomef.orobseruationsgiven the centrality of observationsabout outcomewhen examining areofteninterested causalrelationships.Second,we acknowledgethat researchers in two kinds of.generalizationabout eachof thesefive elements,and that these that two typesareinspiredbg but not identicalto, the two kinds of generalization 'We Cronbach defined. call these construct validity generalizations(inferences about the constructsthat researchoperationsrepresent)and externalvalidity genabout whetherthe causalrelationshipholdsovervariation eralizations(inferences variables). in persons,settings,treatment,and measurement ConstructValidity:CausalGeneralization as Representation The first causal generalization problem concerns how to go from the particular units, treatments, observations, and settings on which data are collected to the higher order constructs these instancesrepresent.These constructs are almost always couched in terms that are more abstract than the particular instancessampled in an experiment. The labels may pertain to the individual elementsof the experiment (e.g., is the outcome measured by a given test best described as intelligence or as achievement?).Or the labels may pertain to the nature of relationships among elements, including causal relationships, as when cancer treatments are classified as cytotoxic or cytostatic depending on whether they kill tumor cells directly or delay tumor growth by modulating their environment. Consider a randomized experiment by Fortin and Kirouac (1.9761.The treatment was a brief educational course administered by severalnurses,who gave a tour of their hospital and covered some basic facts about surgery with individuals who were to have elective abdominal or thoracic surgery 1-5to 20 days later in a single Montreal hospital. Ten specific outcome measureswere used after the surgery, such as an activities of daily living scaleand a count of the analgesicsused to control pain. Now compare this study with its likely t^rget constructs-whether 10. \Weoccasionallyrefer to time as a separatefeatureof experiments,following Campbell (79571and Cook and Campbell (19791,becausetime can cut acrossthe other factorsindependently.Cronbachdid not includetime in his notational system,insteadincorporating time into treatment(e.g.,the schedulingof treatment),observations (e.g.,when measuresare administered),or setting (e.g.,the historicalcontext of the experiment). oF cAUsALcoNNEcrtoNS| ,, ANDTHEGENERALIZATIoN EXnERTMENTs I patient education (the target cause)promotes physical recovery (the targ€t effect) "*ong surgical patients (the target population of units) in hospitals (the target univeise ofiettings). Another example occurs in basic research,in which the question frequently aiises as to whether the actual manipulations and measuresused in an experiment really tap into the specific cause and effect constructs specified by the theory. One way to dismiss an empirical challenge to a theory is simply to make the casethat the data do not really represent the concepts as they are specified in the theory. Empirical resnlts often force researchersto change their initial understanding of whaithe domain under study is. Sometimesthe reconceptuahzation leads to a more restricted inference about what has been studied. Thus the planned causal agent in the Fortin and Kirouac (I976),study-patie,nt education-might need to b! respecified as informational patient education if the information component of the treatment proved to be causally related to recovery from surgery but the tour of the hospital did not. Conversely data can sometimes lead researchersto think in terms o?,"rg., constructs and categoriesthat are more general than those with which they began a researchprogram. Thus the creative analyst of patient education studies mlght surmise that the treatment is a subclass of interventions that "perceived control" or that recovery from surgery can be function by increasing ;'p.tronal coping." Subsequentreaders of the study can treated as a subclas of even add their own interpietations, perhaps claiming that perceived control is really just a special caseof the even more general self-efficacy construct. There is a sobtie interplay over time among the original categories the researcherintended to represeni, the study as it was actually conducted, the study results, and subseqrr..ri interpretations. This interplay can change the researcher'sthinking about what the siudy particulars actually achieved at a more conceptual level, as can feedback fromreaders. But whatever reconceptualizationsoccur' the first problem of causal generaltzationis always the same: How can we generalizefrom a sample of instancesand the data patterns associatedwith them to the particular target constructs they represent? as Extrapolation ExternalValidity:CausalGeneralization The secondproblem of generalizationis to infer whether a causalrelationship holdsovervariationsin p.rrorrt, settings,treatments,and outcomes.For example, someonereadingthe resultsof an experimenton the effectsof a kindergarten grammarschoolreadingtestscoresof poor Head Startprogiam on the subsequent African Americanchildrenin Memphis during the 1980smay want to know if a programwith partially overlappingcognitiveand socialdevelopmentgoals_would be aseffectivein improvingthi mathematicstest scoresof poor Hispanicchildren in Dallas if this programwere to be implementedtomorrow. This exampl. again reminds us that generahzationis not a synonym for broader applicatiorr.H.r., generahzationis from one city to another city and 1. EXPERIMENTS AND GENERALIZED INFERENCE CAUSAL from one kind of clienteleto anotherkind, but thereis no presumptionthat Dallas is somehow broader than Memphis or that Hispanic children constitute a broader population than African American children. Of course,some generalizations are from narrow to broad. For example,a researcherwho randomly samplesexperimentalparticipants from a national population may generalize (probabilistically)from the sampleto all the other unstudiedmembersof that samepopulation. Indeed,that is the rationale for choosingrandom selectionin the first place.Similarly when policymakersconsiderwhetherHead Start should be continuedon a national basis,they are not so interestedin what happenedin Memphis.They are more interestedin what would happenon the averageacross the United States,as its many local programsstill differ from eachother despite efforts in the 1990sto standardizemuch of what happensto Head Startchildren and parents.But generalizationcan also go from the broad to the narrow. Cronbetween bach(1982)givesthe exampleof an experimentthat studieddifferences the performancesof groups of studentsattendingprivate and public schools.In this case,the concernof individual parentsis to know which type of schoolis better for their particular child, not for the whole group. \Thether from narrow to broad, broad to narroq or acrossunits at about the samelevelof aggregation, all theseexamplesof externalvalidity questionssharethe sameneed-to infer the extent to which the effect holds over variationsin persons,settings,treatments, or outcomes. Approaches to MakingCausalGeneralizations \Thichever way the causal generalization issue is framed, experiments do not seem at first glance to be very useful. Almost invariablS a given experiment uses a limited set of operations to represent units, treatments, outcomes, and settings. This high degree of localization is not unique to the experiment; it also characterizes case studies, performance monitoring systems, and opportunisticallyadministered marketing questionnaires given to, say, a haphazard sample of respondents at local shopping centers (Shadish, 1995b). Even when questionnaires are administered to nationally representative samples, they are ideal for representing that particular population of persons but have little relevanceto citizens outside of that nation. Moreover, responsesmay also vary by the setting in which the interview took place (a doorstep, a living room, or a work site), by the time of day at which it was administered, by how each question was framed, or by the particular race, age,and gender combination of interviewers. But the fact that the experiment is not alone in its vulnerability to generalization issuesdoes not make it any less a problem. So what is it that justifies any belief that an experiment can achieve a better fit between the sampling particulars of a study and more general inferences to constructs or over variations in persons, settings, treatments, and outcomes? oF cAUsALcoNNEcrtoNs I tt ANDTHEGENERALtzATtoN EXeERTMENTs Samplingand CausalGeneralization The methodmost often recommendedfor achievingthis closefit is the useof formal probabiliry samplingof instancesof units, treatments,observations,or setthat we have clearly tings (Rossi,Vlright, & Anderson,L983). This presupposes deiineatedpopulationsof eachand that we can samplewith known probability from within eachof thesepopulations.In effect,this entailsthe random selection earof instances,to be carefullydistinguishedfrom random assignmentdiscussed repreto chance by lier in this chapter.Randomselectioninvolvesselectingcases sentthat popuiation,whereasrandom assignmentinvolvesassigningcasesto multiple conditions. In cause-probingresearchthat is not experimental,random samplesof indilongitudinalsurveyssuchasthe PanelStudyof viduals"r. oft.n nr.d. Large-scale IncomeDynamicsor the National Longitudinal Surveyare usedto representthe populationof the United States-or certainagebracketswithin it-and measures Lf pot.ntial causesand effectsare then relatedto each other using time lags in All this is donein ,nr^"r.rr.-ent and statisticalcontrolsfor group nonequivalence. hopesof approximatingwhat a randomizedexperimentachieves.However,cases of random ielection from a broad population followed by random assignment from within this population are much rarer (seeChapter 12 for examples).Also Such rare arestudiesoi t".rdotn selectionfollowed by a quality quasi-experiment. that control logistical experimentsrequirea high levelof resourcesand a degreeof prefer to rely on an implicit set of nonstais iarely feasible,so many researchers tistical heuristicsfor generalizationthat we hope to make more explicit and systematicin this book. Random selectionoccurseven more rarely with treatments'outcomes,and settingsthan with people.Considerthe outcomesobservedin an experiment.How ofterrlre they raniomly sampled?'Wegrant that the domain samplingmodel of classicaltestiheory (Nunnally 6c Bernstein,1994)assumesthat the itemsusedto measurea constructhavebeenrandomly sampledfrom a domain of all possible items. However,in actual experimentalpracticefew researchersever randomly sampleitemswhen constructingmeasures.Nor do they do so when choosingmanipulationsor settings.For instance,many settingswill not agreeto be sampled, "rid ,o1n. of the settingsthat agreeto be randomly sampledwill almostcertainly not agreeto be randomlyassignedto conditions.For treatments,no definitivelist of poisible treatmentsusuallyexists,as is most obvious in areasin which treatare being discoveredand developedrapidly, such as in AIDS research.In -*,, general,then, random samplingis alwaysdesirable,but it is only rarely and confeasible. tingently "However, formal samplingmethodsare not the only option. Two informal, purposive samplingmethodrare sometimesuseful-purposive sampling of heterogeneousinstancesand purposivesamplingof typical instances.In the former case'the aim is to includeinrLni.r chosendeliberatelyto reflect diversity on presumptively important dimensions,eventhough the sampleis not formally random. In the latter INFERENCE CAUSAL ANDGENERALIZED 24 I .l. TxpEnIMENTS case,the aim is to explicate the kinds of units, treatments, observations, and settings to which one most wants to generalize andthen to selectat least one instance of each class that is impressionistically similar to the class mode. Although these purposive sampling methods are more practical than formal probability sampling, they are not backed by a statistical logic that justifies formal generalizations.Nonetheless, they are probabty the most commonly used of all sampling methods for facilitating generalizations. A task we set ourselvesin this book is to explicate such methods and to describe how they can be used more often than is the casetoday. However, sampling methods of any kind are insufficient to solve either problem of generalization. Formal probability sampling requires specifying a target population from which sampling then takes place, but defining such populations is difficult for some targets of generalization such as treatments. Purposive sampling of heterogeneousinstancesis differentially feasible for different elementsin a study; it is often more feasible to make measuresdiverse than it is to obtain diverse settings, for example. Purposive sampling of typical instancesis often feasible when target modes, medians, or means are known, but it leaves questions about generalizationsto a wider range than is typical. Besides,as Cronbach points out, most challenges to the causal generalization of an experiment typically emerge after a study is done. In such cases,sampling is relevant only if the instancesin the original study were sampled diversely enough to promote responsible reanalysesof the data to seeif a treatment effect holds acrossmost or all of the targets about which generahzation has been challenged. But packing so many sourcesof variation into a single experimental study is rarely practical and will almost certainly conflict with other goals of the experiment. Formal sampling methods usually offer only a limited solution to causal generalizationproblems. A theory of generalizedcausal inference needsadditional tools. A GroundedTheoryof CausalGeneralization in their research,and Practicingscientistsroutinely make causal generalizations do. In this book, we they they almostneveruseformal probability samplingwhen that is groundedin the actualpracticeof presenta theory of causalgeneralization science(Matt, Cook, 6c Shadish,2000). Although this theory was originally developedfrom ideasthat were groundedin the constructand externalvalidiry lithavesincefound that theseideasarecommonin eratures(Cook, 1990,1991.),we (e.g.,Abelson,1995;Campbell a diverseliteratureabout scientificgeneralizations & Fiske, 1.959;Cronbach& Meehl, 1955; Davis, 1994; Locke, 1'986;Medin, Hayward,Tu1,991';'$7ilson, 1989;Messick,1ggg,1'995;Rubins,1.994;'Willner, grounded theory this about \7e providemore details nis, Bass,& Guyatt, 1,995];t. that scientistsmakecausalgenin Chapters1L through L3, but in brief it suggests eralizationsin their work by usingfive closelyrelatedprinciples: "L. the apparentsimilaritiesbetweenstudy operaSurfaceSimilarity.They assess of the target of generalization. tions and the prototypicalcharacteristics I OFCAUSALCONNECTIONS AND THEGENERALIZATION EXPERIMENTS II ZS 2. Ruling Out lrreleuancies.They identify those things that are irrelevant because they do not change a generalization. Discriminations. They clarify k.y discriminations that limit Making 3. generalization. 4. Interpolation and Extrapolation. They make interpolations to unsampled values within the range of the sampled instances and, much more difficult, they explore extrapolations beyond the sampled range. 5 . Causal Explanation. They develop and test explanatory theories about the pattern of effects,causes,and mediational processesthat are essentialto the transfer of a causalrelationship. In this book, we want to show how scientistscan and do use thesefive principles to draw generalizedconclusions dbout a causal connection. Sometimes the conclusion is about the higher order constructs to use in describing an obtained connection at the samplelevel. In this sense,thesefive principles have analoguesor parallels both in the construct validity literature (e.g.,with construct content, with loru.rg.nt and discriminant validity, and with the need for theoretical rationales for consrructs) and in the cognitive scienceand philosophy literatures that study how people decidewhether instancesfall into a category(e.g.,concerning the roles that protorypical characteristicsand surface versus deep similarity play in determining category membership). But at other times, the conclusion about generalization refers to whether a connection holds broadly or narrowly over variations in persons, settings,treatments, or outcomes. Here, too, the principles have analogues or parallels that we can recognizefrom scientific theory and practice, as in the study of dose-responserelationships (a form of interpolation-extrapolation) or the appeal to explanatory mechanismsin generalizing from animals to humans (a form of causal explanation). Scientistsuse rhese five principles almost constantly during all phases of research.For example, when they read a published study and wonder if some variathink about similarition on the study's particulars would work in their lab, they '$7hen they conceptualize ties of the published study to what they propose to do. plan will match the to study they instances the new study, they anticipate how the prototypical featuresof the constructs about which they are curious. They may deiign their study on the assumptionthat certain variations will be irrelevant to it but that others will point to key discriminations over which the causal relationship does not hold or the very character of the constructs changes.They may include measuresof key theoretical mechanisms to clarify how the intervention works. During data analysis, they test all these hypotheses and adjust their construct descriptions to match better what the data suggest happened in the study. The introduction section of their articles tries to convince the reader that the study bears on specific constructs, and the discussion sometimes speculatesabout how results -igttt extrapolate to different units, treatments, outcomes, and settings. Further, practicing scientistsdo all this not just with single studies that they read or conduct but also with multiple studies. They nearly always think about 26 | INFERENCE CAUSAL 1. EXPERTMENTS ANDGENERALIZED how their own studiesfit into a larger literature about both the constructsbeing measuredand the variablesthat may or may not bound or explain a causalconnection, often documentingthis fit in the introduction to their study.And they apply all five principleswhen they conduct reviewsof the literature,in which they make inthat a body of researchcan suppoft. ferencesabout the kinds of generalizations Throughoutthis book, and especiallyin Chapters11 to L3, we providemore detailsabout this groundedtheory of causal generalizationand about the scientific doesnot Adopting this groundedtheoryof generalization practicesthat it suggests. we recommendsuchsamimply a rejectionof formal probabilitysampling.Indeed, to purposive samplingschemes pling unambiguouslywhenit is feasible,alongwith when formal randomselectionmethodscannotbe implemented. aid generalization But we alsoshow that samplingis just one methodthat practicingscientistsuseto along with practicallogic, applicationof diversestamake causalgeneralizations, tistical methods,and useof featuresof designother than sampling. AND METASCIENCE EXPERIMENTS Extensivephilosophicaldebatesometimessurroundsexperimentation.Here we briefly summarizesomekey featuresof thesedebates,and then we discusssome implications of thesedebatesfor experimentation.However,there is a sensein which all this philosophicaldebateis incidentalto the practiceof experimentation. Experimentationis as old as humanity itself, so it precededhumanity'sphilosophicaleffortsto understandcausationand genenlizationby thousandsof years. Even over just the past 400 yearsof scientificexperimentation,we can seesome constancyof experimentalconcept and method, whereasdiversephilosophical "Exof the experimenthavecomeand gone.As Hacking(1983)said, conceptions most perimentationhas a life of its own" (p. 150). It has beenone of science's powerful methodsfor discoveringdescriptivecausalrelationships,and it hasdone so well in so many ways that its placein scienceis probably assuredforever.To justify its practicetodag a scientistneednot resortto sophisticatedphilosophical reasoningabout experimentation. Nonetheless,it doeshelp scientiststo understandthesephilosophicaldebates. For example,previousdistinctionsin this chapterbetweenmolar and molecular causation,descriptiveand explanatorycause,or probabilisticand deterministic causalinferencesall help both philosophersand scientiststo understandbetter both the purposeand the resultsof experiments(e.g.,Bunge,1959; Eells, 1991'; Hart & Honore, 1985;Humphreys,"t989;Mackie, 1'974;Salmon,7984,1989; Sobel,1993;P.A. \X/hite,1990).Here we focus on a differentand broadersetof critiquesof scienceitself,not only from philosophybut alsofrom the history,sociologS and psychologyof science(seeusefulgeneralreviewsby Bechtel,1988; H. I. Brown, 1977; Oldroyd, 19861.Someof theseworks have beenexplicitly about the nature of experimentation,seekingto createa justified role for it (e.g., I AND METASCIENCE EXPERIMENTS I 27 '1.990; S. Drake, l98l; Gergen, Bhaskar,L975;Campbell,1982,,1988;Danziger, Pinch,6cSchaffer, L989; Gooding, Houts, Neimeyer,6d 1,973;Gholson,Shadish, 'Woolgar, 1,989b;Greenwood, L989; Hacking, L983; Latour, 1'987;Latour 6c & Fuller,L994; 1988;Orne,1.962;R.RosenthaL,1.966;Shadish 1.979;Morawski, Thesecritiqueshelp scientiststo seesomelimits of experimentaShapin,1,9941. tion in both scienceand society. TheKuhnianCritique Kuhn (1962\ describedscientificrevolutionsas differentand partly incommensueachother in time and in which the gradrableparadigmsthat abruptly succeedgd of scientificknowledgewas a chimera.Hanson(1958),Polanyi ual accumulation Toulmin (1'961),Feyerabend(L975),and Quine (1'95t' (1958),Popper('J.959), 1,969)contributedto the critical momentum,in part by exposingthe grossmistakesin logicalpositivism'sattemptto build a philosophyof sciencebasedon reconstructinga successfulsciencesuch as physics.All thesecritiquesdeniedany firm foundationsfor scientificknowledge(so, by extension,experimentsdo not provide firm causalknowledge).The logicalpositivistshopedto achievefoundations on which to build knowledgeby tying all theory tightly to theory-freeobservationthrough predicatelogic. But this left out important scientificconcepts that could not be tied tightly to observation;and it failed to recognizethat all observationsare impregnatedwith substantiveand methodologicaltheory,making it impossibleto conducttheory-freetests.lt The impossibility of theory-neutral observation (often referred to as the Quine-Duhemthesis)impliesthat the resultsof any singletest (and so any single experiment)are inevitably ambiguous.They could be disputed,for example,on groundsthat the theoreticalassumptionsbuilt into the outcome measurewere wrong or that the study made a fatity assumptionabout how high a treatment dosewas requiredto be effective.Someof theseassumptionsare small,easilydetected,and correctable,suchaswhen a voltmetergivesthe wrong readingbecause the impedanceof the voltagesourcewas much higherthan that of the meter ('$filson, L952).But other assumptionsare more paradigmlike,impregnatinga theory so completelythat other parts of the theory makeno sensewithout them (e.g.,the assumptionthat the earthis the centerof the universein pre-Galileanastronomy). Becausethe number of assumptionsinvolved in any scientifictest is very large, researcherscan easily find some assumptionsto fault or can even posit new "Even the father 11. However, Holton (1986) reminds us nor to overstatethe relianceof positivistson empirical data: phenomena to some which to link of positivism,AugusteComte, had written . . . that without a theory of somesort by 'it we conclusions, draw any useful and isolated observations the principles would not only be impossibleto combine (p. 32). noticed by our eyes"' part, would not be the fact most for the them, and, remember would not evenbe able to Similarly, Uebel (1992) providesa more detailedhistorical analysisof the protocol sentencedebatein logical positivism, showing somesurprisinglynonstereorypicalpositions held by key playerssuch as Carnap. 28 | INFERENCE CAUSAL ANDGENERALIZED r. rxeenlMENTs assumptions(Mitroff & Fitzgerald,1.977).In this way, substantivetheoriesare lesstestablethan their authors originally conceived.How cana theory be tested if it is madeof clayrather than granite? For reasonswe clarify later,this critique is more true of singlestudiesand less true of programsof research.But evenin the latter case,undetectedconstantbiases ."tt t.r,tlt in flawed inferencesabout causeand its genenlization.As a result,no exalwayshave perimentis everfully certain,and extrascientificbeliefsand preferences belief. scientific ioo- to influencethe many discretionaryjudgmentsinvolved in all Critiques ModernSocialPsychological working within traditionsvariouslycalledsocialconstructivism,episSociologists temologicalrelativism,and the strongprogram(e.g.,Barnes,1974;Bloor,1976; 1'979)have Collins,l98l;Knorr-Cetina,L981-;Latour 6c'Woolgar,1.979;Mulkay, at work in science.Their empiricalstudies shown thoseextrascientificprocesses show that scientistsoften fail to adhereto norms commonlyproposedas part of good science(e.g.,objectivity neutrality,sharingof information).They havealso rho*n how that which comesto be reportedas scientificknowledgeis partly determinedby socialand psychologicalforcesand partly by issuesof economicand political power both within scienceand in the largersociety-issuesthat arerarely mention;d in publishedresearchreports.The most extremeamongthesesocioloclaiming gistsattributesall scientificknowledgeto suchextrascientificprocesses, "the natural world has a small or nonexistentrole in the constructionof sciihat "l'98I, p. 3). entificknowledge"(Collins, Collins doesnot denyontologicalrea.lism,that real entitiesexistin the world. Rather,he deniesepistemological(scientific)realism, that whateverexternal reality may existcanconstrainour scientifictheories.For example,if atomsreally exist, do they affectour scientifictheoriesat all? If our theory postulatesan atom, is relit describing a realentitythat existsroughly aswe describeit? Epistetnologi,cal atiuistssuch as Collins respondnegativelyto both questions,believingthat the most important influencesin scienceare social,psychological,economic,and political, "ttd th"t thesemight evenbe the only influenceson scientifictheories-This view is not widely endorsedoutsidea small group of sociologists,but it is a useful counterweightto naiveassumptionsthat scientificstudiessomehowdirectlyreveal natur. to r.r,(an assumptiorwe callnaiuerealism).The resultsof all studies, including experiments,are profoundly subjectto theseextrascientificinfluences, from their conceptionto reportsof their results. and Trust Science A standard image of the scientist is as a skeptic, a person who only trusts results that have been personally verified. Indeed, the scientific revolution of the'l'7th century I I AND METASCIENCE EXPERIMENTS I 29 I claimed that trust, particularly trust in authority and dogma, was antithetical to good science.Every authoritative assertion,every dogma, was to be open to question, and the job of sciencewas to do that questioning. That image is partly wrong. Any single scientific study is an exercisein trust (Pinch, 1986; Shapin, 1,994).Studies trust the vast majority of already developed methods, findings, and concepts that they use when they test a new hypothesis. For example, statistical theories and methods are usually taken on faith rather than personally verified, as are measurement instruments. The ratio of trust to skepticism in any given study is more llke 99% trust to 1% skepticism than the opposite. Even in lifelong programs of research, the single scientist trusts much -or. than he or she ever doubts. Indeed, thoroughgoing skepticism is probably impossible for the individual scientist, po iudge from what we know of the psychology of science(Gholson et al., L989; Shadish 6c Fuller, 1'9941.Finall5 skepticism is not even an accuratecharacterrzation of past scientific revolutions; Shapin "gentlemanly trust" in L7th-century England was (1,994) shows that the role of central to the establishment of experimental science.Trust pervades science,despite its rhetoric of skepticism. for Experiments lmplications The net result of thesecriticismsis a greaterappreciationfor the equivocalityof all scientificknowledge.The experimentis not a clearwindow that revealsnature directly to us.To the contrary,experimentsyield hypotheticaland fallible knowledgethat is often dependenton context and imbuedwith many unstatedtheoretical assumprions.Consequentlyexperimentalresultsare partly relativeto those assumptionsand contextsand might well changewith new assumptionsor conconstructivistsand relativists. texts.In this sense,all scientistsare epistemological The differenceis whether they are strong or weak relativists.Strong relativists share Collins'sposition that only extrascientificfactors influenceour theories. 'Weak relativistsbelievethat both the ontologicalworld and the worlds of ideolog5 interests,values,hopes,and wishesplay a role in the constructionof scientiiic knowledge.Most practicingscientists,including ourselves,would probably ", Lrrtologicalrealistsbut weak epistemologicalrelativists.l2 describethemselves To the extent that experimentsrevealnature to us, it is through a very clouded windowpane(Campbell,1988). to naiveviewsof experimentswere badly needed.As reSuchcounterweights centlyas 30 yearsago,the centralrole of the experimentin sciencewas probably 1.2. If spacepermitred,we could exrendthis discussionto a host of other philosophicalissuesthat have beenraised about the experiment, such as its role in discovery versusconfirmation, incorrect assertionsthat the experiment is tied to somespecificphilosophysuch as logical positivismor pragmatism,and the various mistakesthat are frequentlymadei., suchdiscussions(e.g.,Campbell, 1982,1988; Cook, 1991; Cook 6< Campbell, 1985; Shadish, 1.995a\. I INFERENCE AND GENERALTZED CAUSAL 30 | 1. EXPERTMENTS taken more for granted than is the case today. For example, Campbell and Stan- ley (1.9631 describedthemselvesas: committed to the experiment: as the only means for settling disputes regarding educational practice, as the only way of verifying educational improvements, and as the only way of establishing a cumulative tradition in which improvements can be introduced without the danger of a faddish discard of old wisdom in favor of inferior novelties. (p. 2) "'experimental method' usedto be Indeed,Hacking (1983) points out that iust an(p.149); was then a more experimentation and other name for scientific method" fertile ground for examples illustrating basic philosophical issuesthan it was a , source of contention itself. 'We now understand better that the experiment is a profoundly Not so today. human endeavor,affected by all the same human foibles as any other human endeavor, though with well-developed procedures for partial control of some of the limitations that have been identified to date. Some of these limitations are common to all science,of course. For example, scientiststend to notice evidencethat confirms their preferred hypothesesand to overlook contradictory evidence.They make routine cognitive errors of judgment and have limited capacity to process large amounts of information. They react to peer pressuresto agreewith accepted dogma and to social role pressuresin their relationships to students,participants, and other scientists.They are partly motivated by sociological and economic rewards for their work (sadl5 sometimesto the point of fraud), and they display alltoo-human psychological needs and irrationalities about their work. Other limitations have unique relevance to experimentation. For example, if causal results are ambiguous, as in many weaker quasi-experiments,experimentersmay attribute causation or causal generalization based on study features that have little to do with orthodox logic or method. They may fail to pursue all the alternative causal explanations becauseof a lack of energS a need to achieveclosure, or a bias toward accepting evidence that confirms their preferred hypothesis.Each experiment is also a social situation, full of social roles (e.g., participant, experimenter, assistant) and social expectations (e.g., that people should provide true information) but with a uniqueness (e.g., that the experimenter does not always tell the truth) that can lead to problems when social cues are misread or deliberately thwarted by either party. Fortunately these limits are not insurmountable, as formal training can help overcome some of them (Lehman, Lempert, & Nisbett, 1988). Still, the relationship between scientific results and the world that science studies is neither simple nor fully trustworthy. These social and psychological analyseshave taken some of the luster from the experiment as a centerpieceof science.The experiment may have a life of its own, but it is no longer life on a pedestal. Among scientists,belief in the experiment as the only meansto settle disputes about causation is gone, though it is still the preferred method in many circumstances. Gone, too, is the belief that the power experimental methods often displayed in the laboratory would transfer easily to applications in field settings. As a result of highly publicized science-related I OR CAUSES?I gT A WORLDWITHOUTEXPERIMENTS I eventssuchasthe tragicresultsof the Chernobylnucleardisaster,the disputesover certaintylevelsof DNA testingin the O.J. Simpsontrials, and the failure to find a cure for most cancersafter decadesof highly publicizedand funded effort, the generalpublic now betterunderstandsthe limits of science. Yet we should not take these critiques too far. Those who argue against theory-freetestsoften seemto suggestthat everyexperimentwill comeout just as the experimenterwishes.This expectationis totally contrary to the experienceof who find insteadthat experimentationis often frustratingand disapresearchers, pointing for the theoriesthey loved so much. Laboratory resultsmay not speak but they certainlydo not speakonly for one'shopesand wishes. for themselves, "stubborn facts" with We find much to valuein the laboratoryscientist'sbeliefin a life spanthat is greaterthan the fluctqatingtheorieswith which one tries to explain them.Thus many basicresultsabout gravityare the same,whetherthey are containedwithin a framework developedby Newton or by Einstein;and no successortheory to Einstein'swould be plausibleunlessit could accountfor most of the stubbornfactlike findingsabout falling bodies.There may not be pure facts, but someobservationsare clearlyworth treating as if they were facts. Some theorists of science-Hanson, Polanyi, Kuhn, and Feyerabend included-have so exaggeratedthe role of theory in scienceas to make experimental evidenceseemalmost irrelevant.But exploratory experimentsthat were tangentialto unguidedby formal theory and unexpectedexperimentaldiscoveries the initial researchmotivationshaverepeatedlybeenthe sourceof greatscientific advances.Experimentshaveprovidedmany stubborn,dependable,replicableresultsthat then becomethe subjectof theory.Experimentalphysicistsfeelthat their laboratorydata help keeptheir more speculativetheoreticalcounterpartshonest, giving experimentsan indispensablerole in science.Of course,thesestubborn facts often involve both commonsensepresumptionsand trust in many wellestablishedtheoriesthat make up the sharedcore of belief of the sciencein quesare tion. And of course,thesestubbornfactssometimesproveto beundependable, reinterpretedas experimentalartifacts,or are so ladenwith a dominantfocal theory that they disappearoncethat theory is replaced.But this is not the casewith the greatbulk of the factualbase,which remainsreasonablydependableover relativelylong periodsof time. ORCAUSES? A WORLDWITHOUTEXPERIMENTS To borrow a thought experimentfrom Maclntyre (1981),imaginethat the slates of scienceand philosophywerewiped cleanand that we had to constructour understandingof the world anew.As part of that reconstruction,would we reinvent the notion of a manipulablecause?\7e think so, largely becauseof the practical utility that dependablemanipulandahave for our ability to surviveand prosper. IUTouldwe reinvent the experimentas a method for investigatingsuch causes? I AND GENERALTZED 32 | 1. EXPERTMENTS CAUSAL TNFERENCE Again yes,becausehumanswill always be trying to betterknow how well these manipulablecauseswork. Over time, they will refinehow they conductthoseexperimentsand so will againbe drawn to problemsof counterfactualinference,of causeprecedingeffect,of alternativeexplanations,and of all of the other features of causationthat we havediscussedin this chapter.In the end, we would probably end up with the experimentor somethingvery much like it. This book is one more stepin that ongoingprocessof refining experiments.It is about improving the yield from experimentsthat take placein complexfield settings,both the quality of causalinferencesthey yield and our ability to generalizetheseinferencesto constructsand over variationsin persons,settings,treatments,and outcomes. A CriticalAssessment of Our Assumptions As.sump.tion(e-simp'shen):[Middle Englishassumpcion,from Latin assumpti, assumptin-adoption, from assumptus,past participle of assmere,te adopt; seeassume.]n. 1. The act of taking to or upon oneself: assumptionof an obligation. 2.The act of taking overiassumptionof command. 3. The act of taking for granted:assumptionof a false theory. 4. Somethingtaken for granted or acceptedas true without proof; a supposition:a ualid assumption. 5. Presumption;arrogance.5. Logic.A minor premise. fltHIS BooK covers five central topics across its 13 chapters. The first topic | (Chapter 1) deals with our general understanding of descriptive causation and I experimentation. The second (Chapters 2 and 3) deals with the types of validity and the specific validity threats associatedwith this understanding. The third (Chapters 4 through 7) deals with quasi-experimentsand illustrates how combining design features can facilitate better causal inference. The fourth (Chapters 8 through L0) concerns randomized experiments and stressesthe factors that impede and promote their implementation. The fifth (Chapters 11 through L3) deals with causal generalization, both theoretically and as concerns the conduct of individual studies and programs of research.The purpose of this last chapter is to critically assesssome of the assumptions that have gone into these five topics, especially the assumptions that critics have found obiectionable or that we antici'We pate they will find objectionable. organize the discussionaround each of the five topics and then briefly justify why we did not deal more extensivelywith nonexperimental methods for assessingcausation. I7e do not delude ourselvesthat we can be the best explicators of our own assumptions. Our critics can do that task better. But we want to be as comprehensrve and sive an(l as explicit explclt as we can. can. This I nrs is part because ls in rn part becausewe we are are convinced convrnced of ot the the adaclvantages of falsification as a major component of any epistemology for the social sciences,and forcing out one's assumptions and confronting them is one part of falsification. But it is also becausewe would like to stimulate critical debateabout theseassumptionsso that we can learn from those who would challengeour think456 rct AND EXPERIMENTATION CAUSATION | ing. If therewereto be a future book that carriedevenfurther forward the tradition emanatingfrom Campbelland Stanleyvia Cook and Campbellto this book, then that futuie book *o,rld probably be all the better for building upon all the justifiedcriticismscomingfrom thosewho do not agreewith us, eitheron particcau,rlu6 o, on the whole approachwe havetaken to the analysisof descriptive would like this chapternot only to model the atsationand its generayzition.'We but i.-p, to be cr"iti.alabout the assumprionsall scholarsmust inevitablymake be might they how and alsoto encourageothersto think about theseassumptions in fuiure empiricalor theoreticalwork' addressed ENTATION AND EXPERIM CAUSATION CausalArrows and Pretzels descriptive Experiments test the influence of one or at most a small subset of very few causes.If statistical interactions are involved, they tend to be among variables' moderator of treatments or between a single treatment and a limited set typical Many researchersbelieve that the causal knowledge that results from this structure fails to map the many causal forces that simultaneously af.*p.ii-..rtal (e.g., Cronbach et al', fe.t "ny given outcome in compiex and nonlinear ways prioritize on ar19g0; Magnusson,2000). These critics assertthat experiments an explanatory ,o*, .onrr-.cting A to B when they should instead seekto describe most causal pretzel or set of intersectingpretzels,as it were. They also believethat whether ielationships vary across ,rttitt, settings, and times, and so they doubt Snow, 6c (e.g., Cronbach there ".. "ny constant bivariate causal relationships reflect sta1977).Those that do appearto be dependablein the data may simply reveal the to tistically underpow.r.i irr,, of modeiators or mediators that failed sizesmight true underlying complex causal relationships. True-variation in effect or the also be obrc.rr"d b.c"rrs. the relevant substantive theory is underspecified, or attenuated, is outcome measuresare partially invalid, or the treatment contrast (McClelland causally implicated variables afe truncated in how they are sampled 6c Judd, 1993). As valid as theseobiectionsare, they do not invalidatethe casefor experiments.The purposeof experimentsis not to completelyexplain-some.phenomemakes non; it is to ldentify whethera particularvariableor small setof variables affecta margirraldifferencein someoutcomeover and above all the other forces not ing that outcome.Moreover,ontologicaldoubts such as the precedinghave many though as stJppedbelieversin more complex iausal theoriesfrom acting or as .r,rol relationshipscan be usefullycharacterizedas dependablemain effects In this very simpl. nonlin."rities that are also dependableenoughto be_u_seful. where connection,considersomeexamplesfrom educationin the United States, 4s8 I | 14.A CRTTTCAL ASSESSMENT OFOURASSUMPTTONS objections to experimentation are probably the most prevalent and virulent. Few educational researchersseemto object to the following substantiveconclusions of the form that A dependably causesB: small schools are better than large ones; time-on-task raises achievement; summer school raises test scores;school desegregation hardly affects achievement but does increaseWhite flight; and assigning and grading homework raises achievement.The critics also do not seemto object to other conclusions involving very simple causal contingencies: reducing class "sizable" size increasesachievement,but only if the amount of change is and to a level under 20; or Catholic schools are superior to public ones, but only in the inner city and not in the suburbs and then most noticeably in graduation rates rather , than in achievementtest scores. The primary iustification for such oversimplifications-and for the use of the experiments that test them-is that some moderators of effects are of minor relevance to policy and theory even if they marginally improve explanation. The most important contingencies are usually those that modify the sign of a causal relationship rather than its magnitude. Sign changesimply that a treatment is beneficial in some circumstancesbut might be harmful in others. This is quite different from identifying circumstancesthat influence just how positive an effect might be. Policy-makers are often willing to advocate an overall change,even if they suspect it has different-sizedpositive effects for different groups, as long as the effects are rarely negative. But if some groups will be positively affected and others negatively political actors are loath to prescribe different treatments for different groups becauserivalries and jealousies often ensue. Theoreticians also probably pay more attention to causal relationships that differ in causal sign becausethis result implies that one can identify the boundary conditions that impel such a disparate data pattern. Of course, we do not advocate ignoring all causal contingencies.For example, physicians routinely prescribe one of severalpossibleinterventions for a given diagnosis.The exact choice may depend on the diagnosis,test results,patient preferences, insurance resources, and the availability of treatments in the patient's area. However, the costs of such a contingent system are high. In part to limit the number of relevant contingencies,physicians specialize,andwithin their own specialty they undergo extensivetraining to enable them to make thesecontingent decisions. Even then, substantial judgment is still required to cover the many situations in which causal contingencies are ambiguous or in dispute. In many other policy domains it would also be costly to implement the financial, management, and cultural changesthat a truly contingent system would require even if the requisite knowledge were available. Taking such a contingent approach to its logical extremes would entail in education, for example, that individual tutoring become matched the order of the day. dav.Studentsand instructorswould haveto be carefullymatched for overlap in teachingand learning skills and in the curriculum supportsthey would need. tilTithinlimits, some moderators can be studied experimentallSeither by measuringthe moderator so it can be testedduring analysisor by deliberately AND EXPERIMENTATION CAU5ATION I Ot' experivarying it in the next study in a program of research'In conductingsuch takments,onemovesawayfrom thethik-bo" experimentsof yesteryeartoward by, them study!1g more seriouslyand toward routinely ing causalcontingencies the treatmentto examineits causallyeffectivecomfoi .""-ple, disaggregating ponents,iir"ggt.glting the effect,toexamineits causallyimpactedcomponents, variables,and .ondrr.ting ,n"ty*r ofi.-ographic and psychologicalmoderator affects exploringlhe causalpathwa-ysihtooghwhjch (parts.of) the treatment possiis not in a singleexperiment lparts of) the outcomJ.To do all of this well tl.. brrtto do someof it well is possibleand desirable. of E4periments Criticisms Epistemological we have In highlightingstatisticalconclusionvalidity and in-selectingexamples, testing' often linked causaldescriptionto quantitativemethodsand hypothesis positivism' Many criticswill (wrongly)r.. this asimplying a discreditedtheory of positivismreAs a philosophyof scieniefirst outlined in the early L9th century' about unobservables,and equated 1.ct.d' metaphysicalspeculations,especially school of lrro*t.ag. *lih descriptionsof e*periencedphenomena-A narrower realism logical pisitivism .*.rg.d in the eatly 20th century that also rejected form logic *til. "lro .-phasizing Ih. ,rr. of data-theoryconnectionsin predicate Both thesere""J " fr.f.r.r.. for p"redictingphenomenaover explainingthem' *.r. lonf ago discredited,especiallyas explanationsof how lated epistemologies this basis'Howscienceop.r"trr.*so few criticsseriouslycritici'e experimentson to attack ever,many critics use the term positiuismwith lesshistorical fidelity 1985)' quantitativesocialsciencemethodsin genera-l(e'g', Lincoln & Guba, quantification of use liuilding on the rejectionof logicalpositivism,they reiectthe measurement,and hypothesistesting.Because and forLal logic in observatiron, of positheselast featuresare part of experiments,to reiectthis looseconception are nutivism entailsrejectingexperiments.However,the errorsin suchcriticisms (like the idea that merous.For example,to ,eject a specificfeatureof positivism only permissiblelinks betweendata and f,r"rrtifi.rtion and p redicatelogicare the imlly reiectingall relatedand more generalpropositiheory;doesnot nJcessarily testing tions jsuch asthe notion that somekinds of quantificationand hypothesis ersuch more outlined may be usefulfor knowledgegrowth).Ife and othershave (Phillips,1990;Shadish,I995al' rors elsewhere criticismsof experimentationcitethe work of historians other epistemological and'woolof sciencesuchasKuh"n(1,g62),ofsociologistsof sciencesuchasLatour tend gar ltiZll "rrd of fhiloroph.ir of scienceiuchas Harr6'(1931).Thesecritics that notion of theories,the to focuson threethings.orre.i, the incommensurability specifiedand so can alwaysbe reinterpreted.As a retheoriesare neverper"fectly be reiected'its sult, when disconfirmingdata seemto imply that a theory should poriolut., can insteadbI reworkedin order to make the theory and observations to the consistentwith eachother.This is usuallydoneby addingnew contingencies 460 | 14.A CRIT|CAL ASSESSMENT OF OURASSUMPTTONS I theory that limit the conditions under which it is thought to hold. A second critique is of the assumption that experimental observations can be used as truth 'We tests. would like observations to be objective assessmentsthat can adjudicate between different theoretical explanations of a phenomenon. But in practice, observationsare not theory neutral; they are open to multiple interpretations that include such irrelevanciesas the researcher'shopes, dreams, and predilections. The consequenceis that observations rarely result in definitive hypothesistests.The final criticism follows from the many behavioral and cognitive inconsistenciesbetween what scientists do in practice and what scientific norms prescribe they should do. Descriptions of scientists' behavior in laboratories reveal them as choosing to do particular experiments becausethey have an intuition about a relationship, or they are simply curious to seewhat happens, or they want to play with a new piece of equipment they happen to find lying around. Their impetus, therefore, is not a hypothesis carefully deduced from a theory that they then test by means of careful observation. Although these critiques have some credibilitg they are overgeneralized.Few experimentersbelievethat their work yields definitive results even after it has been subjected to professional review. Further, though these philosophical, historical, and social critiques complicate what a "fact" means for any scientific method, nonethelessmany relationships have stubbornly recurred despite changesassociated with the substantive theories, methods, and researcherbiasesthat first generated them. Observations may never achieve the status of "facts," but many of them are so stubbornly replicable that they may be consideredas though they were facts. For experimenters, the trick is to make sure that observations are not impregnated with just one theory, and this is done by building multiple theories into observationsand by valuing independent replications, especiallythose of substantive critics-what we have elsewherecalled critical multiplism (Cook, 1985; Shadish,'1.989, 1994). Although causal claims can never be definitively tested and proven, individual experiments still manage to probe such claims. For example, if a study produces negative results, it is often the casethat program developersand other advocates then bring up methodological and substantive contingenciesthat might have changedthe result. For instance, they might contend that a different outcome measure or population would have led to a different conclusion. Subsequentstudies then probe these alternatives and, if they again prove negative, lead to yet another round of probes of whatever new explanatory possibilities have emerged. After a time, this process runs out of steam, so particularistic are the contingencies that remain to be examined. It is as though a consensusemerges:"The causal relationship was not obtained under many conditions. The conditions that remain to be examined are so circumscribed that the intervention will not be worth much 'W'e even if it is effectiveunder these conditions. " agreethat this processis as much or more social than logical. But the reality of elastic theory does not mean that decisions about causal hypotheses are only social and devoid of all empirical and logical content. I I I t I J AND EXPERIMENTATION CAUSATION | +er The criticismsnoted are especiallyusefulin highlightingthe limited value of individual studiesrelativeto reviewsof researchprograms.Suchreviewsare better becausethe greaterdiversityof study featuresmakesit lesslikely that the same theoreticalbiasesthat inevitablyimpregnateany one studywill reappearacrossall the studiesunderreview.Still, a dialecticprocessof point, response,and counterpoint is neededevenwith reviews,againimplying that no singlereview is definiiirr.. Fo, example,in responseto Smith and Glass's(1'977)meta-analyticclaim ck (L977)and Presby(1'977)pointedout *", .ff..tive, Eysen that psychotheiapy methojological and substantivecontingenciesthat challengedthe original rethat a differentanswerwould havebeenachieved viewers'reJults.They suggested if Smith and Glassitrd ""t combinedrandomizedand nonrandomizedexperimentsor if they had usednarrower calegoriesin which to classifytypesof therapy. Subsequentstudiesprobed thesechallengesto Smith and Glassor brought foith nouef or,., 1e.g.,\il'eiszet al., 1,992).This processof challengingcausal claimswith specificalternativeshas now slowedin reviewsof psychotherapyas have beenexplored.The that might limit effectiveness many major contingencies fiom reviewsof many experimentsin many kinds of settingsis currenrconsensus that psychotherapyis effective;it is not iust the product of a regressionprocess in needseekprofeslrporrt"nrors remission)wherebythosewho are temporarily ,ii""t help and get better,as they would haveevenwithout the therapy' NeglectedAncillarYQuestions Our focus on causalquestionswithin an experimentalframework neglectsmany other questionsthat arerelevantto causation.Theseincludequestionsabout how to decideon the importanceor leverageof any singlecausalquestion.This could entail exploringwhethera causalquestionis evenwarranted,as it often is not at the early sa"g.-ofdevelopmentof an issue.Or it could entail exploringwhat type of c".rsalquestionis moie important-one that fills an identifiedhole in someliterature,o, orr. that setsout to identify specificboundary conditionslimiting a causalconnection,or one that probesthe validity of a centralassumptionheld by within a field, or one that reducesuncertainty all the theoristsand researchers about an important decisionwhen formerly uncertaintywas high. Our approach alsoneglectsthe realitythat how oneformulatesa descriptivecausalquestionusuaily enLils meetingsomestakeholders'interestsin the socialresearchmore than those of others.TLus to ask about the effectsof a national program meetsthe staffs,the media,and policy wonks to learnaboutwhether needsof Congressional the program"*orks. But it can fail to meet the needsof local practitionerswho of microelementswithin the pro,rro"lly"*"nt to know about the effectiveness gram ,o thut they can usethis knowledgeto improve their daily practice.-Inmore Ih.or.ti."l work, to ask how some interventionaffectspersonalself-efficacyis likely to promote individuals'autonomyneeds,whereasto ask about the effects of a'persoasivecommunicationdesignedto changeattitudescould well cater to 462 t | 14.A CR|T|CAL ASSESSMENT OFOURASSUMPT|ONS the needs of those who would limit or manipulate such autonomy. Our narrow technical approach to causation also neglectedissuesrelated to how such causal knowledge might be used and misused. It gave short shrift to a systematic analysis of the kinds of causal questions that can and cannot be answered through experiments. \7hat about the effects of abortion, divorce, stable cohabitation, birth out of wedlock, and other possibly harmful events that we cannot ethically manipulate? What about the effects of class,race, and gender that are not amenable 'What to experimentation? about the effects of historical occurrencesthat can be studied only by using time-seriesmethods on whatever variables might or might not be in the archives?Of what use, one might ask, is a method that cannot get at some of the most important phenomena that shape our social world, often over generations,as in the caseof race, class,and gender? Many statisticians now consider questions about things that cannot be manipulated as being beyond causal analysis,so closely do they link manipulation to causation. To them, the cause must be at least potentially manipulable, even if it is not actually manipulated in a given observational study. Thus they would not consider race ^ cause, though they would speak of the causal analysis of race in studies in which Black and White couples are, say, randomly assignedto visiting rental units in order to seeif the refusal rates vary, or that entail chemically changing skin color to seehow individuals are responded to differently as a function of pigmentation, or that systematicallyvaried the racial mix of studentsin schools or classrooms in order to study teacher responsesand student performance. Many critics do not like so tight a coupling of manipulation and causation. For example, those who do status attainment researchconsider it obvious that race causally influences how teachers treat individual minority students and thus affects how well these children do in school and therefore what jobs they get and what prospects their own children will subsequentlyhave. So this coupling of causeto manipulation is a real limit of an experimental approach to causation. Although we like the coupling of causation and manipulation for purposes of defining experiments, we do not seeit as necessaryto all useful forms of cause. VALIDITY Objectionsto InternalValidity There are severalcriticismsof Campbell's(1957) validity typology and its extensions(Gadenne,1976;Kruglanski& Kroy, 1.976;Hultsch 6cHickey,1978;Cron'We bach, 1982; Cronbachet al., 1980). start first with two criticismsof internal validity raisedby Cronbach(1982)and to a lbsserextentby Kruglanskiand Kroy (1'976):(1) an atheoreticallydefinedinternal validity (A causesB) is trivial without referenceto constructs;and (2) causationin singleinstancesis impossible,includingin singleexperiments. vALtDtrY nol I lnternal Validity ls Trivial Cronbach(L982)writes: I consider it pointless to speak of causeswhen all that can be validly meant by refermaenceto a causein a particular instanceis that, on one trial of a partially specified phenamed, not conditions other nipulation under.orrditior6 A, B, and c, along with nomenon p was observed.To introduce the word cause seemspointless. Campbell's writings make internal validity a property of trivial, past-tense'and local statements' (p .t3 7 ) Hence,.,causallanguageis superfluous"(p. 140).Cronbachdoesnot retaina specific role fo, .",rr"Iinferenceln his validity typology at all. Kruglanski and Kroy (1976)criticizeinternalvalidity similanlSsaying: are The concrete events which constitute the treatment within a specific research is simply it Thus, ' ' ' category' meaningful only as members of a general conceptual are impossibleto draw strictly specificconclusionsfrom an experiment: our concepts g.rr.r"l and each pr.r,rppor"s an implicit general theory about resemblanceberween different concretecases.(p. 1'57) All theseauthors suggestcollapsinginternal with constructvalidity in different ways. and discusstreatmentsand conceptualize Of course,we agreethat researchers outcomesin concepfualterms.As we saidin Chapter3, constructsare so basicto l"rrgo"g. and thought that it is impossibleto conceptualizescientificwork without"thJm. Indeed,ir, *"ny important respects,the constructswe use constrain what we experience,a point agreedto by theoristsranging from Quine (L951' L96g)to th; postmodernists(Conner,1989;Testeq1993). So when we say that internalvalidity concernsan atheoreticallocal molar causalinference,we do not mean that the researchershould conceptualizeexperimentsor report a causal claim as "somethingmadea differencer"to useCronbach's(1982,p' 130) exaggeratedcharacterization. Still, it is both sensibleand usefulto differentiateinternal from constructvalidity. The task of sortingout constructsis demandingenoughto warrant separate attention from the task of sorting out causes.After all, operationsare concept to know fully what thoseconceptsare.In laden,and it is very rare for researchers fu.t, th, ,erearchrialmostcertainlycannotknow them fully becauseparadigmatic .orr..p,, areso implicitly and universallyimbuedthat thoseconceptsand their asby researchcommunitiesfor sumptions "r. ,oi,'.,imes entirely unrecognized_ y."ri. Indeed,the history of scienceis repletewith examplesof famousseriesof ."p.rim.nts in which a causalrelationshipwas demonstratedearlS but it took y."r, for the cause(or effect)to be consensuallyand stablynamed.For instance, in psychologyand linguisticsmany causalrelationshipsoriginally emanatedfrom a behavioriit paradigl but were later relabeledin cognitive terms; in the early Hawthorne st;dy, illumination effectswere later relabeledas effectsof obtrusive observers;and some cognitive dissonanceeffects have been reinterpretedas 464 I 14.A CRITICAL ASSESSMENT OF OURASSUMPTIONS attribution effects.In the history of a discipline,relationshipsthat are correctly identified as causalcan be important evenwhen the causeand effectconstructs are incorrectlylabeled.Suchexamplesexist becausethe reasoningusedto draw causalinferences(e.g.,requiring evidencethat treatmentprecededoutcome)differs from the reasoningusedto generalize(e.g.,matchingoperationsto prototypical characteristicsof constructs).\Tithout understandingwhat is meant by descriptive causation, we have no means of telling whether a claim to have establishedsuchcausationis justified. Cronbach's(1982) prosemakesclear that he understandsthe importanceof causallogic; but in the end, his sporadicallyexpressedcraft knowledgedoesnot add up to a coherenttheory of judgingthe validity of descriptivecausalinferences. His equation of internal validity as part of reproducibility (under replication) missesthe point that one can replicateincorrectcausalconclusions.His solution to suchquestionsis simplythat "the forceof eachquestioncan bereducedby suitable controls" (1982,p. 233).This is inadequate, for a completeanalysisof the problem of descriptivecausalinferencerequiresconceptswe can useto recognize suitablecontrols.If a suitablecontrol is one that reducesthe plausibilityof, say historyor maturation,asCronbach(1982,p.233)suggests, thisis little morethan internalvalidity aswe haveformulatedit. If one needsthe conceptsenoughto use them, then they should be part of a validity typology for cause-probing methods. For completeness, we might add that a similar boundaryquestionarisesbetween constructvalidity and externalvalidity and betweenconstructvalidity and statisticalconclusionvalidity. In the former case,no scientistever framesan external validity questionwithout couchingthe questionin the languageof constructs.In the latter case,researchers neverconceptualizeor discusstheir results solelyin terms of statistics.Constructsare ubiquitousin the processof doing researchbecausethey are essentialfor conceptualizingand reporting operations. But again,the answerto this objectionis the same.The strategiesfor making inferencesabout a constructare not the sameas strategiesfor making inferences about whether a causal relationship holds over variation in persons,settings, treatments,and outcomesin externalvalidity or for drawing valid statisticalconclusionsin the caseof statisticalconclusionvalidity.Constructvalidity requiresa theoreticalargumentand an assessment betweensamples of the correspondence constructs. and Externalvalidity requiresanalyzingwhethercausalrelationships hold over variations in persons,settings,treatments,and outcomes.Statistical conclusionvalidity requirescloseexaminationof the statisticalproceduresand assumptionsused.And again,one can be wrong about constructlabelswhile being right about externalor statisticalconclusionvalidity. Objections to Causation in SingleExperiments A second criticism of internal validity deniesthe possibility of inferring causation in a single experiment. Cronbach (1982) says that the important feature of causation is the "progressivelocalizationof a cause" (Mackie, 1974, p.73) over mul- J vALrDrry otu | tiple experimentsin a program of researchin which the uncertainties about the essential i."t.rr.r of the cause are reduced to the point at which one can characterize exacflywhat the causeis and is not. Indeed, much philosophy of causation asserts that we only recognize causes through observing multiple instances of a putative causal relationship, although philosophers differ as to whether the mechanism for recognition involves logical laws or empirical regularities (Beauchamp, 1974;P. White, 1990). However, some philosophers do defend the position that causescan be inMadden & Humferred in singleinstances(e.g.,Davidson, 1,967;Ducasse'1,95L1' (e.g., Honore, 1985)' Hart & law in the ber, L97'1,).A good example is causation by which we judge whether or not one person, say, caused the death of another despitethe fact that the defendant may 4ever before have been on trial for a crime. The verdict requires a plausible casethat (among other things) the defendantb actions precededlhe death of the victim, that those actions were related to the death, that other potential causesof the death are implausible, and that the death would not have occurred had the defendant not taken those actions-the very logic of causal relationships and counterfactualsthat we outlined in Chapter 1. In fact, the defendant'scriminal history will often be specifically excluded from consideration in iudging guilt during the trial. The lessonis clear. Although we may learn more "bo,rt ."nsation from multiple than from single experiments, we can rnf.ercause in single experiments.Indeed, experimenterswill do so whether we tell them to or not. Providing them with conceptual help in doing so is a virtue, not a vice; failing to do so is a major flaw in a theory of cause-probing methods. Of course, individual experiments virtually always use prior concepts from other experiments.However, such prior conceptualizations are entirely consistent with the claim that internal validity is about causal claims in single experiments. If it were not (at least partly) about single experiments, there would be no point to doing the experiment, for the prior conceptualization would successfullypredict what will be observed.The possibility that the data will not support the prior conceptualization makes internal validity essential.Further, prior conceptualizations are not logically necessary;we can experiment to discover effects that we "The physicist George Darwin used have no prior conceptual structure to expect: to say tliat once in a while one should do a completely crazy experiment, like blowing the trumper to the tulips every morning for a month. Probably nothing wiil hafpen, but if something did happen, that would be a stupendousdiscovery" (Hacking, L983, p. 15a). But we would still need internal validity to guide us in judging if the trumpets had an effect. Objections to Descriptive Causation A few authorsobjectto the very notion of descriptivecausation.Typicall5 however,suchobjectionsaremadeabout a caricatureof descriptivecausationthat has not teen usedin philosophyor in sciencefor many years-for example,a billiard ball modelthat requiresa commitmentto deterministiccausationor that excludes 466 | ra.n cRrrcALAssEssMENT oFouRAssuMproNs reciprocalcausation.In contrast,mostwho write aboutexperimentationtoday espousetheoriesof probabilisticcausationin which the many difficultiesassociated Even with identifyingdependablecausalrelationshipsare humbly acknowledged. languagethemselves, more important, thesecriticsinevitablyusecausal-sounding "mutual "cause" simultaneousshaping" (Lincoln 6c for example,replacing with p. seem to us to avoidthe word but keep Guba, 1985, 151).Thesereplacements the concept,and for good reason.As we saidat the end of ChapterL, if we wiped the slatecleanand constructedour knowledgeof the world aneq we believewe would end up reinventingthe notion of descriptivecausationall over again, so greatlydoesknowledgeof causeshelp us to survivein the world. Between ObjectionsConcerning the Discrimination ConstructValidityand ExternalValidity Although we traced the history of the present validity system briefly in Chapter 2, readers may want additional historical perspectiveon why we made the changes we made in the present book regarding construct and external validity. Both Campbell (1957) and Campbell and Stanley(1963) only usedthe phraseexternal validitS which they defined as inferring to what populations, settings,treatment variables, and measurement variables an effect can be generalized.They did not rcfer at all to construct validity. However, from his subsequentwritings (Campbell, 1986), it is clear Campbell thought of construct validity as being part of external validity. In Campbell and Stanley therefore, external validity subsumed generalizing from researchoperations about persons, settings,causes,and effects for the purposes of labeling theseparticulars in more abstract terms, and also generalizing by identifying sourcesof variation in causal relationships that are attributable to person, setting, cause, and effect factors. All subsequentconceptualizations also share the same generic strategy based on sampling instancesof persons, settings, causes,and effects and then evaluating them for their presumed correspondenceto targets of inference. In Campbell and Stanley'sformulation, person, setting, cause,and effect categories share two basic similarities despite their surface differences-to wit, all of them have both ostensive qualities and construct representations.Populations of persons or settings are composed of units that are obviously individually ostensive. This capacity to point to individual persons and settings, especially when they are known to belong in a referent category permits them to be readily enumerated and selectedfor study in the formal ways that sampling statisticiansprefer. By contrast, although individual measures (e.g., the Beck Depression Inventory) and treatments (e.g., a syringe full of a vaccine) are also ostensive,efforts to enumerate all existing ways of measuring or manipulating such measuresand treatments are much more rare (e.g.,Bloom, L956; Ciarlo et al., 1986; Steiner& Gingrich, 2000). The reason is that researchersprefer to use substantivetheory to determine which attributes a treatment or outcome measureshould contain in any .J vALrDtrYI oe, given studS recognizing that scholars often disagreeabout the relevant attributes of th. higher order entity and of the supposed best operations to representthem. None of ihis negatesthe reality that populations of persons or settingsare also defined in part by the theoretical constructs used to refer to them, just like treatments and outiomes; they also have multiple attributes that can be legitimately con'!(hat, for instance, is the American population? \7hile a legal definition tested. surely exists,it is not inviolate. The German conception of nationality allows that the gieat grandchildren of a German are Germans even if their parents and grandp"r*t, have not claimed German nationality. This is not possible for Americans. And why privilege alegaldefinition? A cultural conception might admit as American all thor. illegal immigrants who have been in the United Statesfor decades and it might e*cl.rde those American adults with passports who have never lived in the United States. Given that person's,settings, treatments, and outcomes all have both construct and ostensive qualities, it is no surprise that Campbell and Stanley did not distinguish between construct and external validity. Cook and Camptell, however, did distinguish between the two. Their unstated rationale for the distinction was mostly pragmatic-to facilitate memory for the very long list of threats that, with the additions they made' would have had to fit under bampbell and Stanley'sumbrella conception of external validity. In their theoretical diicussion, Cook and Campbell associatedconstruct validity with generalizingto causesand effects, and external validity with generalizing to and across persons, settings, and times. Their choice of terms explicitly referencedCronbach and Meehl (1955) who used construct and construct validity in "about higher-order constructs from remeasurementtheory to justify inferences search operations'; lcook & Campbel| 1,979, p. 3S). Likewise, Cook and Campbeli associatedthe terms population and external ualidity with sampling theory and the formal and purposive ways in which researchersselect instances of persons and settings. But to complicate matters, Cook and Campbell also "all aspectsof the researchrequire naming samples in brlefly acknowledged that termi, including samplesof peoples and settings as well as samples gener-alizable of -r"r,rres or manipulations" (p. 59). And in listing their external validity threats as statistical inieractions between a treatment and population, they linked external validity more to generalizing across populations than to generalizing to them. Also, their construct validity threats were listed in ways that emphasized generalizing to cause and effect constructs. Generalizing across different causes ind effect, *", listed as external validity becausethis task does not involve attributing meaning to a particular measure or manipulation. To read the threats in Cook and Campbell, external validity is about generalizing acrosspopulations of persons and settings and across different cause and effect constructs, while construct validity is about generalizing to causesand effects.Where, then, is genera\zing from samples of persons or settings to their referent populations? The text disiussesthis as a matter of external validitg but this classification is not apparent in the list of validity threats. A system is neededthat can improve on Cook and Campbell's partial confounding between objects of generalization (causes 468 ASSESSMENT OF OURASSUMPTIONS 14.A CRITICAL and effects versus persons and settings) and functions of generalization (generalizing to higher-order constructs from researchoperations versus inferring the de- greeof replicationacrossdifferent constructsand populations). This book usessucha functional approachto differentiateconstructvalidity from externalvalidity. It equatesconstructvalidity with labelingresearchoperations, and externalvalidity with sourcesof variation in causalrelationships.This new formulation subsumesall of the old. Thus, Cook and Campbellt underto standingof constructvalidity asgeneralizingfrom manipulationsand measures causeand effectconstructsis retained.So is externalvalidity understoodas generalizingacrosssamplesof persons,settings,and times.And generalizingacross different causeor effectconstructsis now,evenmore clearlyclassifiedas part of exrernalvalidity.Also highlightedis the needto label samplesof personsand settings in abstractterms, iust as measuresand manipulationsneedto be labeled. Suchlabelingwould seemto be a matterof constructvalidity giventhat construct validity is functionallydefinedin termsof labeling.However,labelinghumansamples might have been read as being a matter of external validity in Cook and Campbell,given that their referentswere human populationsand their validity typeswereorganizedmore around referentsthan functions.So,althoughthe new we are formulation in this book is definitelymore systematicthan its predecessors, unsurewhetherthat systematizationwillultimately result in greaterterminological clarity or confusion.To keepthe latter to a minimum, the following discussion reflectsissuespertinentto the demarcationof constructand externalvalidity that have emergedeither in deliberationsbetweenthe first two authorsor in classes versionsof this book. that we havetaughtusingpre-publication ,i-{11 f i.. Is Construct Vatidity a Prerequisite for External Vatidity? In this book, we equateexternalvalidity with variation in causalrelationshipsand operations.Somereadersmight seethis constructvalidity with labeling.research of a causalrelationshiprequiresthe acassuggesting that successfulgeneralization curate labelingof eachpopulation of personsand eachtype of settingto which generalization is sought,eventhough we can neverbe certainthat anythingis labeledwith perfectaccuracy.The relevanttask is to achievethe most accurateasTechnically,we can.test genenlizasessmentavailableunder the circumstances. tion acrossentitiesthat are akeadyknown to be confoundedand thus not labeled well-e.g., when causaldata arebrokenout by genderbut the femalesin the sample are, on average,more intelligentthan the malesand thereforescorehigheron everythingelsecorrelatedwith intelligence.This exampleillustrateshow dangerous it is to rely on measuredsurfacesimilarity alone (i.e.,genderdifferences)for determininghow a sampleshouldbe labeledin populationterms.\7e might more accuratelylabel genderdifferencesif we had a random sampleof each gender taken from the samepopulation.But this is not often found in experimentalwork, and eventhis is not perfectbecausegenderis known to be confoundedwith other attributes(e.g.,income,work status)evenin the population,and thoseother at- t .,.J vALrDrrY I oo, tributes may be pertinent labels for some of the inferencesbeing made. Hence, we usually have to rely on the assumption that, becausegender samplescome from the same physical setting, they are comparable on all background characteristics that might be correlated with the outcome. Becausethis assumption cannot be fully testedand is ^nyw^y often false-as in the hypothetical example above-this means rhat we could and should measure all the potential confounds within the limits of our theoretical knowledge to suggestthem, and that we should also use these measuresin the analysis to reduce confounding. Even with acknowledged confounding, sample-specific differences in effect sizesmay still allow us to conclude that a causal relationship varies by something associatedwith gender.This is a useful conclusion for preventing premature overgeneralization.Iilith more breakdownq, confounded or not, one can even get a senseof the percentageof contrastsacrosswhich a causal relationship does and does not hold. But without further work, the populations across which the relationship varies are incompletely identified. The value of identifying them better is particularly salient when some effect sizescannot be distinguished from zero. Although this clearly identifies a nonuniversal causal relationship, it does not advance theory or practice by specifying the labeled boundary conditions over which a causal relationship fails to hold. Knowledge gains are also modest from generalization strategiesthat do not explicitly contrast effect sizes.Thus, when different populations are lumped together in a single hypothesis test, researcherscan learn how large a causal relationship is despite the many unexamined sources of variation built into the analysis. But they cannot accurately identify which constructs do and do not co-determine the relationship's size. Construct validity adds useful specificity to external validity concerns, but it is not a necessarycondition for external validity.'We can generalize across entities known to be confounded' albeit lessusefully than acrossaccurately labeled entities. This last point is similar to the one raised earlier to counter the assertion of Gadenne (L9761and Kruglanski and Kroy (1976) that internal validity requires the high consrruct validity of both causeand effect. They assertthat all scienceis "something causedsomeabout constructs, and so it has no value to conclude that thing sfss"-1hs result that would follow if we did a technically exemplary randomized experiment with correspondingly high internal validity but the causeand effect were not labeled. Nonetheless, a causal relationship is demonstrably en"something reliably causedsomething else" might lead tailed, and the finding that to further researchto refine whatever clues are available about the cause and effect constructs. A similar argument holds for the relationship of construct to external validity. Labels with high construct validity are not necessaryfor internal or for external validity, but they are useful for both. Researchersnecessarilyuse the language of constructs (including human and setting population ones) to frame their research questions and selecttheir representationsof constructsin the samplesand measureschosen.If they have designed their work well and have had some luck, the constructs they begin and end with will be the same,though critics can challengeany claims they make. However, the 470 OFOURASSUMPTIONS ASSESSMENT 14.A CRITICAL samplesand constructs might not match we[], and then the task is to examine the samples and ascertain what they might alternatively stand for. As critics like Gadenne,Kruglanski,and Kroy havepointedout, suchrelianceon the operational levelseemsto legitimizeoperationsashavinga life independentof constructs.This is not the case,though,for operationsare intimatelydependenton interpretations at all stagesof research.Still, every operation fits some interpretations, however tentative that referent may be due to poor researchplanning or to nature turning out to be more complex than the researcher'sinitial theory. How Does Variation AcrossDifferent Operational Representations of the SameIntendedCauseor EffectRelateto Constructand ExternalValidity? In Chapter 3 we emphasizedhow the valid labeling of a cause or effect benefits from multiple operational instances,and also that thesevarious instancescan be fruitfully analyzedto examine how a causal relationship varies with the definition used. If each operational instance is indeed of the sameunderlying construct, then the samecausalrelationshipshouldresult regardlessof how the causeor effectis operationally defined. Yet data analysis sometimes revealsthat a causal relationship varies by operational instance.This means that the operations are not in fact equivalent,so that theypresumablytap both into differentconstructsand into different causalrelationships.Either the samecausalconstructis differentlyrelated to what now must be seenas two distinct outcomes,or the sameeffectconstruct is differently related to two or more unique causal agents.So the intention to promote the construct validity of causesand effects by using multiple operations has now facilitated conclusions about the external validiry of causesor effects;that is, when the external validity of the causeand effect are in play, the data analysishas revealed that more than one causal relationship needsto be invoked. FortunatelS when we find that a causal relationship varies over different causes or different effects, the research and its context often provide clues as to how the causalelementsin eachrelationshipmight be (re)labeled.For example,the researcher will generally examine closely how the operations differ in their particulars, and will also study which unique meaningshave been attached to variants like thesein the ex- isting literature.While the meaningsthat are achievedmight be lesssuccessfulbecause they have been devised post hoc to fit novel findings, they may in some crcumstances still attain an acceptable level of accuracy and will certainly prompt continued discussion to account for the findings. Thus, we come full circle. I7e began with multiple operational representations of the same causeor effect when testing a single causal relationship; then the data forced us to invoke more than one relationship; and finally the pattern of the outcomes and their relationship to the existing literature can help improve the labeling of the new relationships achieved.A construct validity exercise begets an externat validity conclusion that prompts the need for relabeling constructs. Demonstrating effect size variation acrossoperations presumed to represent the same cause or effect can enhance external validity by vALlDlrY I ort are involved than was origishowingthat more constructsand causalrelationships validity by preand in that case,it can eventuallyincreaseconstruct nally envisaged; in the original choiceof measventingany mislabelingof the causeor effectinherent causalrelationshipsabout how the ures and by providffilues from detailsof the seehereanalytictasksthat flow elementsin each..f"io"ritp shouldbe labeled.'We concerns'involving each' smoothlybetween.onr,r.r.i and externalvalidity of Personsor settings should Generalizingfrom a single sample Be Classifiedas External or Construct Validity? or settings,this samplemust representa If a study hasa singlesampleof pers.ons is an issue'Given that construct population.How ,"nlrrr-pre should be labeled an issueof constructvalidity?Afvalidity is about rJ.iirrg, i, Itbeling the lample sincewith a singlesampleit is not ter all, externalvalidity hardly seemsrelevant in causalrelationshipswould immediatelyobvious*n", comparisonof variation of personsor settingsis treatedas a be involved.So if g.".t"iit-g fio* a sample from treatment and outmatter of constructvalidity analogousto generalizing highlightsa potential conflict in come operations,i*o probl.-, "r-ir.. Firstl this someparts of which saythat genusagein the generalsocialsciencecommunity' vaof peopleto its pofulation are a matter of external eralizationsfrom;;;i; ,"y ih", labefingpeopleis a matter of constructvalidity, evenwhen ;rh.;;;", in Cook and Campbellthat lidity. Second,trrir-J".r not fit'with the discussion personsand settingsas an external treatsgeneralizingrr.t" irrdiuidrr"lsamplesof threatsdoesnot explicitly deal validity matter,thoughtheir list of .*t.*"1 validity betweenthe treatmentand attributesof with this and only mentionsinteracti,ons the settingand Person. selectedfrom.the popThe issueis most acutewhen the samplewas randomly so keento promoterandom samulation. considerwhy samplingstatisticiansare Suchsamplingensuresthat the pling for represe";i"; " *.il-dJrignated universe. on all measuredand unmeasured sampleand populatiJndistributionsare identical Notice that this includesthe populavariableswithin the limits of samplingerror. also randomsamplingguarantees tion label(whethermoreor less"ccorit.;, which a well K.y tg tle or.i rl*r, of random samplingis having appliesto the ,";;[. in samplingtheory and boundedpop.rl"tiJ., from which to sample,a-requirement many well boundedpopulations somethingoften obviousin practice.Given that that a valid populationlaguarantees are alsowell tabeied,r""a.- samplingthen For instance'the population of bel can equallyvalidly be applied,o itt. saripl.. known and is obviouslycorrectly telephoneprefixesor.d i' tlie city of Chicagols digit dialing frol that list of labeled.Hence,i *""fa be difficuli. ,rrJt"ndom telephone sampleas representing Chicagopr.fi*., "nJ itt." mislabelthe resulting a clearly Given sJction-of Chicagoownersin Detroii o, orty in the Edgewater the samplelabel is the populationlaboundedpopulationand random saripling, that no methodis superiorto ranbel, which is why samplingstatisticiansbelieve populationlabelis known' dom selectio'f- iun.ii"g"tumpleswhen the ASSESSMENT OFOURASSUMPTIONS 472 I T+.N CRITICAL With purposive sample selection,this elegant rationale cannot be used, were selected whetheror not the population label is known. Thus, if respondents haphazardlyfrom shoppingmalls all over Chicago,many of the peoplestudied would belongin the likely populationof interest-residentsof Chicago.But many would not becausesomeChicagoresidentsdo not go to malls at the hours interviewing takes place, and becausemany personsin these malls are not from Chicago.Lacking random sampling,we could not evenconfidentlycall this sample "peoplewalking in Chicagomalls," for other constructssuchas volunteering with samplemembership.So, to be interviewedmay be systematicallyconfounded a popmeremembershipin the sampleis not sufficientfor accuratelyrepresenting ulation, and by the rationalein the previousparagraph,it is alsonot sufficientfor accuratelylabelingthe sample.All this leadsto two conclusionsworth elaborating: (1) that random sampling can sometimespromote constructvalidity, and (2) thatexternalvalidity is in play when inferring that a singlecausalrelationship from a samplewould hold in a population,whetherfrom a randomsampleor not. On the first point, the conditions under which random samplingcan sometimespromote the constructvalidity of singlesamplesare straightforward.Given a well boundeduniverse,samplingstatisticianshavejustifiedrandom samplingas away of clearlyrepresentingin the sampleall populationattributes.This must includethe populationlabel,and so random samplingresultsin labelingthe sample in the sameterms that apply to the population. Random samplingdoesnot, of course,tell us whetherthe population label is itself reasonablyaccurate;random samplingwill also replicatein the sampleany mistakesthat are madein labeling the population. However,given that many populationsare alreadyreasonably well-labeledbasedon past researchand theory and that suchsituationsare often experiencedin an area,random samplingcan, intuitively obviousfor researchers be countedon to promoteconstructvalidity.However, underthesecircumstances, when random selectionhas not occurredor when the populationlabel is itself in doubt, this book hasexplicatedother principlesand methodsthat can be usedfor labelingstudy operations,including labelingthe samplesof personsand settings in a study. On the secondpoint, when the questionconcernsthe validity of generalizing from a causalrelationshipin a singlesampleto its population,the readermay also wonder how externalvalidity can be in play at all. After all, we haveframedexternal validity as beingabout whetherthe causalrelationshipholds overuariation variables.If thereis only in persons,settings,treatmentvariables,and measurement over which to exvariation is the one random samplefrom a population,where aminethat causalrelationship?The answeris simple:the variationis betweensampled and unsampledpersonsin that population.As we saidin Chapter2 (and as was true in our predecessorbooks), external validity questionscan be about whether a causalrelationshipholds (a) over variationsin persons,settings,treatments,and outcomesthat were in the experiment,and (b) for persons,settings, treatments,and outcomesthat werenot in the experiment.Thosepersonsin a pop- vALlDlw | 473 ulation who were not randomly sampledfall into the latter category.Nothing requires about externalvalidity,eitherin the presentbook or in its predecessors, that all possibleuariuiion, of externalvalidity interestactuallybe observedin the study-indeed, it would beimpossibleto do so,and we providedseveralarguments in Cirapter2 aboutwhy it would not be wise to limit external validity questions only to variationsactuallyobservedin a study.Of course,in most casesexternal to things that were not studied are difficult, having to rely ualidiry generalizations on the .L.r..pt, and methodswe outlined in our grounded theory of generalized causalinferencein Chapters11 through 13. But it is the great beautyof random samplingthat it guaran;es that this generalizationwill hold over both sampledand ,rnr"-pl".d p.rr6nr. So it is indeedan externalvalidity questionwhah-e1acausal relationshipthat hasbeenobservedin a singlerandomsamplewould hold for those units that were in the populationbut not'in the random sample. Inthe end,this book treatsthe labelingof a singlesampleof personsor settings asa matterof constructvalidiry whetheror not random samplingis used.It alsi treatsthe generalizationof causalrelationshipsfrom a singlesampleto unobservedinstancesasa matterof externalvalidity-againrwhether or not random samplingwas used.The fact that random sampling(which is associatedwith ex,.rrr"l uiiairy in this book) sometimeshappensto facilitatethe constructlabeling of a sampleis incidentalto the fact that the population label is alreadyknown. Though many populationlabelsare indeedwell-known, many more are still mat,.r, of debate,as reflectedin the exampleswe gavein Chapter3 of whetherpersonsshouldbe labeledschizophrenicor settingslabeledas hostilework environments.In theselatter cases,random samplingmakesno contribution to resolving debatesabout the applicabilityof thoselabels.Instead,the principlesand methods we outlinedin Ci"pt.rs 11 through 13 will haveto be brought to bear.And when random samplinghasnot beenused,thoseprinciplesand methodswill also haveto be broughito b.". on the externalvalidity problemof generalizingcausal relationshipsfrom singlesamplesto unobservedinstances. of the Typology ObjectionsAbout the Completeness The first objectionof this kind is that our lists of particularthreatsto validity are incomplete.Bracht and Glass(1,968),for example,ad-dednew externalvalidity and threatsthat they thought were overlookedby Campbelland Stanley(1,96311' These more recentlyAiken ind West (1991) pointed to new reactivity threats._ "r. i*portant becausethe key to the most confidentcausalconclusions challenges in our ,f,.ory of validity is the ability to construct a persuasiveargumentthat every plausibleand identifiedthreat to validity has beenidentifiedand ruled out. Howiver, thereis no guaranteethat all relevantthreatsto validity havebeenidentified. Our lists are not divinely ordained,as can be observedfrom the changesin the threats from Campbel IUST) to Campbell and Stanley (1'963)to Cook and 14.A CRITICAL ASSESSMENT OF OURASSUMPTIONS Campbell(1979) to this book. Threatsare better identifiedfrom insiderknowledgethan from abstractand nonlocal lists of threats. A secondobjectionis that we may haveleft out particularvalidity fypesor organizedthem suboptimally.Perhapsthe bestillustration that this is true is Sackett's(1979) treatmentof bias in case-controlstudies.Case-controlstudiesdo not designs; commonly fall under the rubric of experimentalor quasi-experimental but they are cause-probingdesigns,and in that sensea generalinterestin generalized causalinferenceis at leastpartly shared.Yet Sackettcreateda different typology.He organizedhis list around sevenstagesof researchat which biascan oc(3) in and selection, cur: (1) in readingaboutthe field, (2) in samplespecification 'in measuringexposureand outcome, defining the experimentalexposure,(4) (5) in dataanalysis,(5) in interpretationof analyses, and (71inpublishingresults. Each of thesecould generatea validiry type, someof which would overlapconsiderablywith our validity types.For example,his conceptof biases"in executing the experimentalmanoeuvre" (p. 62) is quite similar to our internal validiry whereashis withdrawal biasmirrors our attrition. However,his list alsosuggests new validity types,such as biasesin readingthe literature,and biaseshe lists at each stageare partly orthogonal to our lists. For example,biasesin readinginclude biasesof rhetoric in which "any of severaltechniquesare usedto convince the readerwithout appealingto reason"(p. 60). In the end,then, our claim is only that the presenttypologyis reasonablywell informed by knowledgeof the nature of generalizedcausalinferenceand of some of the problemsthat are frequentlysalientabout thoseinferencesin field experimentation.It can and hopefullywill continueto be improvedboth by addition of threatsto existing validity types and by thoughtful exploration of new validity typesthat might pertainto the problem of generalizedcausalinferencethat is our main concern.t 1. We are acutelyaware of, and modestlydismayedat, the many differentusagesof thesevalidity labelsthat have developedover the years and of the risk that posesfor terminological confusion---eventhough we are responsible for rnany of thesevariations ourselves.After all, the understandingsof validiry in this book differ from those in Campbelland Stanley(1963),whoseonly distinctionwas betweeninternal and externalvalidity. They alsodiffer from Cook and Campbell (7979), in which externalvalidity was concernedwith generalizingto and across populations of personsand settings,whereasall issuesof generalizingfrom the causeand effect operations constitutedthe domain of constructvalidity. Further,Campbell(1985) himselfrelabeledinternalvalidiry and external validiry as local molar causalvalidity and the principle of proximal similarity, respectively.Steppingoutside Campbell'stradition, Cronbach(1982) usedtheselabelswith yet other meanings.He said internalvalidity is the problem of generalizingfrom samplesto the domain about which the questionis asked,which soundsmuch like our construct validity except that he specifically denied any distinction betweenconstruct validiry and external validiry, using the latter term to refer to generalizingresults to unstudied populations, an issueof extrapolation beyond the data at hand. Our understandingof external validity includessuch extrapolations as one case,but it is not limited to that becauseit also has to do with empirically identifying sourcesof variation in an effect sizewhen existing data allow doing so. Finally, many other authors have casually used all theselabels in completelydifferent ways (Goetz & LeCompte,1984; Kleinbaum,Kupper, & Morgenstern,1982;Menard, 1991).So in view of all thesevariations, we urge that theselabels be used only with descriptionsthat make their intended understandingsclear. ::j !t t VALIDTTY | 47s the Natureof Validity ObjectionsConcerning 'We it difdefined validity as the approximate truth of an inference. Others define ferently. Here are some alternatives and our reasonsfor not using them' Validity in the New TestTheory Tradition well bevalidity(e.g.,cronbach,1946;Guilford,1,946) discussed Testtheorists fore Campbell(L957) inventedhis typology.Sfecan only begin to touch on the many iss.re,pertinentto validity that aboundin that tradition. Here we outline a f.* i.y poinis that help differentiateour approachfrom that of test theory.The early emphasisin test theory was mostly on inferencesabout what a test measof constructvalidity. Cronbach or.j, with a pinnaclebeingieachedin the notion "proper breadth to the notion of ltltll creditsCook and -a-pbell for giving consffucts',(p. 152) in constructvalidity through their claim that constructvalidity is not j"tt li-it.d to inferencesabout outcomesbut also about causesand about orherfeaturesof experiments.In addition, early test theory tied validity to "The literatureon validationhasconcentratedon the the truth of suchinferences: truthfulnessof testinterpretation"(Cronbach,1988,p' 5)' However,the yearshave bro.tght changeto this early understanding'In one particularlyinfluentialdefinitionof validity in test theory Messick(1989)said' ;V"lidiry ii an integratedevaluativejudgmentof the degreeto which empiricalevof inrationalessupportthe adequacyand appropriateness idenceand theoreti"cal (p. L3); and actionsbasedon testscoresor other modesof assessment" ferences "Validiry is broadly definedas nothing lessthan an evaluaand later he saysthat tive summary'of both the ruid.tr.. for and the actual-as well as potentialour unconsequen..,of scoreinterpretationand use" (1995, p.74L)._Whereas. definithis d.rrtu.rdirrgof validity is that inferencesare the subjectof validation, tion suggeJt,th"t actionsare also subjectto validation and that validation is actually evaluation.Theseextentionsare far from our view. A little historywill help here.Testsare designedfor practicaluse.Commerhope to profit from salesto thosewho usetests;employers cial test developers hope to ,rr. t.rt, to seiectbetterpersonnel;and test takershope that testswill Thesepracticalapplicationsgentell them somethingusefulabout themsqlves. eratedconcerni., tf,e AmericanPsychologicalAssociation(APA) to identify the characteristicsof better and worse tests.APA appointeda committeechairedby Cronbachto addressthe problem.The committeeproducedthe first in a continuing seriesof teststandaris(APA,1,954);andthis wolk alsoled to Cronbachand Melhl', (1955)classicarticle on constructvalidity. The test standardshave been freq.rerrtiyrevised,most recentlycosponsoredby other professionalassociations (AmericanEducaiionalResearchAssociation,American PsychologicalAssociaRetion, and National Council on Measurementin Education,1985, 1999)' qoirl-.nts to adhereto rhe standardsbecamepart of professionalethical codes. Th" ,tandardswere also influential in legaland regulatoryproceedingsand have 14.A CRITICAL ASSESSMENT OF OURASSUMPTIONS beencited,for example,in U.S.SupremeCourt casesaboutallegedmisusesof testing practices (e.g., Albermarle Paper Co. v. MoodS 1975; Washington v. Davis, L976) and have influencedthe "Uniform Guidelines"for personnelselectionby the Equal EmploymentOpportunity Commission(EEOC)et al. (1978).Various validity standardswere particularly salientin theseuses. Becauseof this legal,professional,and regulatoryconcernwith the useof testing, the researchcommunity concerned with measurementvalidity began to use the i' ,;;:: "asonewaytojustifytheuseofatest" word ualiditymoreexpansivelyforexample, (Cronbach,1989,p. M9).It is only a short distancefrom validatinguseto validating action, becausemost of the relevantuseswere actionssuchas hiring or firing someoneor labelingsomeoneretarded.Actions,in turn, haveconsequences-some positive,suchas efficiencyin hiring and accuratediagnosisthat allows bettertailoring of treatment,and somenegative,suchas lossof incomeand stigmatization.So Messick(1989, 1995l proposedthat validationalsoevaluatethoseconsequences, especiallythe socialjusticeof consequences. of test Thus evaluatingthe consequences usebecamea key featureof validity in test theory.The net resultwas a blurring of the line betweenvalidity-as-truth and validity-as-evaluation,to the point where Cronbach(1988)said"Validationof a testor testuseis evaluation"(p.4). 'We strongly endorse the legitimacy of questions about the use of both tests and experiments. Although scientistshave frequently avoided value questions in the mistaken belief that they cannot be studied scientifically or that scienceis value free, we cannot avoid values even if we try. The conduct of experiments involves values at every step, from question selection through the interpretation and reporting of results. Concerns about the usesto which experiments and their results are put and the value of the consequencesof those usesare all important (e.g.,Shadishet al., 1991), as we illustrated in Chapter 9 in discussingethical concerns with experiments. However, if validity is to retain its primary association with the truth of knowledge claims, then it is fundamentally impossible to validate an action becauseactions are not knowledge claims. Actions are more properly evaluated, not validated. Supposean employer administers a test, intending to use it in hiring decisions. Suppose the action is that a person is hired. The action is not itself a knowledge claim and therefore cannot be either true or false. Supposethat person then physically assaultsa subordinate. That consequenceis also not a knowledge claim and so also cannot be true or false. The action and the consequencesmerely exist; they are ontological entities, not epistemological ones. Perhaps Messick (1989) really meant to ask whether inferencesabout actions and consequencesare true or false. If so, the inclusion of action in his (1,989)definition of validity is entirely superfluous, for validity-as-truth is already about evidencein support of inferences,including those about action or consequ.rr..s.' 2. Perhapspartly in recognitionof this, the most recentversionof the test standards(AmericanEducational ResearchAssociation,American PsychologicalAssociation,and National Council on Measurementin Education, 1999) helpsresolvesomeof the problemsoudined hereinby removingreferenceto validatingaction from the definition of validity: "Validity refersto the degreeto which evidenceand theory support the interpretationsof test scoresentailedby proposedusesof tests" (p. 9). i ,l ,I t VALIDITY I 477 Alternatively perhaps Messick ('1.989,L995) meant his definition to instruct "Validtest validators to eualuatethe action or its consequences,as intimated in: ity is broadly defined as nothing less than an evaluative summary of both the evidence for and the actual-as well as potential--consequences of score interpretation and use" (1,995, p. 742). Validity-as-truth certainly plays a role in evaluating testsand experiments.But we must be clear about what that role is and is not. Philosophers(e.g., Scriven, 1980; Rescher,1969) tell us that a judgment about the value of something requires that we (1) selectcriteria of merit on which the thing being evaluated would have to perform well, (2) set standards of performanci for how well the thing must do on each criterion to be judged positivel5 (3) gather pertinent data about the thing's performance on the criteria, and then Validity-as-truth i+j i"6gr4te the results into one or more evaluative conclusions. is one (but only one) criterion of merit in dvaluation; that is, it is good if inferences about a test are true, just as it is good for the causal inference made from an experiment to be true. However, validation is not isomorphic with evaluation. First, criteria of merit for tests (or experiments) are not limited to validity-as-truth- For example, a good test meetsother criteria, such as having a test manual that reports ,ror*^r, being affordable for the contexts of application, and protecting confidentialiry ", "ppropriate. Second,the theory of validity Jvlessickproposed gives no help in accomplishing some of the other steps in the four-step evaluation process outlined previously. To evaluate a test, we need to know something about how much ualidity the inference should have to be judged good; and we need to know how to integrate results from all the other criteria of merit along with validity into an overall waluation. It is not a flaw in validity theory that these other steps are not addressed,for they are the domain of evaluation theory. The latter tells us something about how to executethesesteps (e.g.,Scriven, 1980, 1'991)and also about other matters to be taken into account in the evaluation. Validation is not evaluation; truth is not value. Of course, the definition of terms is partly arbitrary. So one might respond that one should be able to conflate validity-as-truth and validity-as-evaluation if one so chooses.However: The very fact that termsmusrbesuppliedwith arbitrarymeaningsrequiresthat words This responsibilityis twofold: first, to esbe usedwith a greatsenseof responsibility. tablished,6"9"; second,to the limitationsthat the definitionsselectedimposeon the "l'982, user.(Goldschmidt, P. 642) 'We need the distinction between truth and value becausetrue inferencescan be about bad things (the fact that smoking causescancer does not make smoking or cancer good); "nd f"lr. inferencescan lead to good things (the astrologer'sadvice 'lavoid alienating your coworkers today" may have nothing to do with to Piscei to heavenly bodies, but may still be good advice). Conflating truth and value can be actively harmful. Messick (1995) makes clear that the social consequencesof test"bias, fairness, and distributive justice" (P. 745). ing are to be judged in terms of 'Wi agreewith this statement,but this is test evaluation, not test validity. Messick I 478 | ra. n cRrTrcAL ASSESSMENT OFOURASSUMPTTONS notes that his intention is not to open the door to the social policing of truth (i.e., a test is valid if its social consequencesare good), but ambiguity on this issuehas nonethelessopened this very door. For example, Kirkhart (1,995)cites Messick as justification for judging the validity of evaluations by their social consequences: "Consequential validity refers here to the soundnessof changeexerted on systems by evaluationand the extent to which thosechangesare just" (p.a).This notion is risky becausethe most powerful arbiter of the soundnessand iustice of social consequencesis the sociopolitical systemin which we live. Depending on the forces in power in that system at any given time, we may find that what counts as valid is effectively determined by the political preferencesof those with power. Validity in the Qualitative Traditions One of the most important developmentsin recent social researchis the expanded use of qualitative methods such as ethnography ethnology, participant observation, unstructured interviewing, and case study methodology (e.g., Denzin 6c Lincoln, 2000). These methods have unrivaled strengths for the elucidation of meanings, the in-depth description of cases,the discovery of new hypotheses,and the description of how treatment interventions are implemented or of possible causal explanations. Even for those purposes for which other methods are usually preferable,such as for making the kinds of descriptivecausalinferencesthat are the topic of this book, qualitative methods can often contribute helpful knowledge and 'S7henever reon rare occasionscan be sufficient (Campbell, 1975; Scriven, 1976ll. sources allow, field experiments will benefit from including qualitative methods both for the primary benefits they are capable of generatingand also for the assistance they provide to the descriptive causal task itself. For example, they can uncover important site-specificthreats to validiry and also contribute to explaining experimental results in general and perplexing outcome patterns in particular. However, the flowering of qualitative methods has often been accompanied by theoretical and philosophical controversy, often referred to as the qualitativequantitative debates. These debates concern not just methods but roles and rewards within science,ethics and morality and epistemologiesand ontologies. As part of the latter, the concept of validity has receivedconsiderableattention (e.g., Eisenhart & Howe, 1992; Goetz & LeCompte,1984; Kirk & Miller, 1'986;Kvale, 1.989;J. Maxwell, 1.992;J. Maxwell 6c Lincoln, 1.990;Mishler, 1,990;Phillips, 'Wolcott, 1,987; 1990). Notions of validity that are different from ours have occasionally resulted from qualitative work, and sometimesvalidity is rejectedentirely. However, before we review those differences we prefer to emphasize the commonalities that we think dominate on all sides of the debates. Comtnonalities. As we read it, the predominant view among qualitative theorists is that validity is a concept that is and should be applicable to their work..We start with examples of discussionsof validity by qualitative theorists that illustrate these similarities becausethey are surprisingly more common than someportrayals in the : I :l{ VALIDITYI O'' they demonstratean underlydebatessuggestand because qualitative-quantitative widely shared ing unity of interestin producingvalid knowledgethat we believeis "qualitative re(1990) says, by"*ori social scientiits.For example,Maxwell are just as concernedas quantitativeonesabout'getting it wrong,' and searchers validity broadlydefinedsimplyrefersto the possibleways one'saccountmight be 'validity threats' can be addressed"(p. 505). Even those *rorrg, and how these "go quafi[tive theoristswho saythey rejectthe word ualidity will admit that they painsnot to getit all wrong" (Wolcott,1990,p. L27).Kvale(1989) to considerable "conceptsof validity are rootedin more comtiesvalidity directlyto truth, saying assumptionsof the nature of true knowledge"(p. 1-1); epistemological prehensive l'refersto the truth and correctness of a statement"(p.731. and later that validity 'valid' is as a properly "the technicaluseof the term Kirk and Miller (1986) say 'true' " (p. L9). Maxwell (L9921says"Validiry in a hedgedweak synonymfor broad sense,pertainsto this relationshipbetweenan accountand somethingoutsidethat account" (p. 283). All theseseemquite compatiblewith our understanding of validity. Maxvreli's(7992\ accountpoints to other similarities.He claimsthat validity "the kinds of understandingsthat accountscan embody" is always relative to (p. 28il and that different communitiesof inquirers are interestedin different areinterestedin five He notesthat qualitativeresearchers kindsof understandings. kinds of understandingsabout: (1) the descriptionsof what was seenand heard, (2) the meaningof what was seenand heard, (3) theoreticalconstructionsthat characteriz.*h"t was seenand heardat higher levelsof abstraction,(4) generalizationof accountsto other persons,times,or settingsthan originallystudied,and (5) evaluationsof the objectsof study (Maxwell, 1'992;he saysthat the last two are of interestrelativelyrarely in qualitativework). He then prounderstandings one for eachof the typology for qualitativeresearchers, posesa five-p-artvalidity 'We ?ineorrd..standings. agreethat validity is relativeto understanding,thoughwe iather than understanding.And we agreethat different usuallyrefer to in-ference communitiesof inquirerstend to be interestedin different kinds of understandings,though common interestsare illustratedby the apparentlysharedconcerns have in how bestto characthlt both ixperimentersand qualitativeresearchers terizewhatwas seenand heardin a study (Maxwell'stheoreticalvalidity and our constructvalidity). Our extendeddiscussionof internal validity reflectsthe interest of the community of experimentersin understandingdescriptivecauses'proevenwhen their portionatelymore so than is relevantto qualitativeresearchers, repletewith the languageof causation.This observationis reportsare necessarily nor is it a criticism of experimentersas ,rot " criticismof qualitativeresearchers, in thick descriptionof an indibeing lessinterestedthan qualitativeresearchers vidualcase. On the other hand, we should not let differencesin prototypical tendencies acrossresearchcommunitiesblind us to the fact that when a particular understandingls of interest,the pertinentvalidity concernsarethe sameno matterwhat the metlodology usedto developthe knowledgeclaim. It would be wrong for a 14.A CRITICAL ASSESSMENT OF OURASSUMPTIONS qualitative researcherto claim that internal validity is irrelevantto qualitative methods.Validity is not a properry of methodsbut of inferencesand knowledge claims. On those infrequent occasionsin which a qualitative researcherhas a stronginterestin a local molar causalinference,the concernswe haveoutlinedunder internal validity pertain.This argumentcuts both ways,of course.An experimenterwho wonderswhat the experimentmeansto participantscould learna lot from the concernsthat Maxwell outlinesunder interpretivevalidity. Maxwell (1992) also points out that his validity typology suggeststhreats to validity about which qualitativeresearchers seek"evidencethat would allow them to be ruled-out. . . usinga logic similar to that of quasi-experimental researcherssuch as Cook and Campbell" (p. 296). He does not outline such threatshimself,but his descriptionallows one to guesswhat somemight look like. To judge from Maxwell's prose,threats to descriptivevalidity include errors of commission(describingsomethingthat did not occur),errorsof omission (failingto describesomethingthat did occur),errorsof frequency(misstating how often something occurred), and interrater disagreementabout description.Threatsto the validity of knowledgeclaimshavealsobeeninvoked by qualitative theorists other than Maxwell-for example,by Becker(1979), Denzin(1989'),and Goetzand LeCompte(1984).Our only significantdisagreement with Maxwell's discussionof threats is his claim that qualitative researchers are lessable to use "designfeatures"(p. 296) to deal with threatsto validity. For instance,his preferreduseof multiple observersis a qualitativedesignfeaturethat helpsto reduceerrorsof omission,commission,and frequency. The repertoireof designfeaturesthat qualitativeresearchers usewill usuallybe quite different from those used by researchersin other traditions, but they are designfeatures(methods)all the same. Dffirences. Theseagreementsnotwithstanding,many qualitativetheoristsapproach validity in ways that differ from our treatment.A few of thesedifferences are basedon argumentsthat are simplyerroneous(Heap,7995;Shadish,1995a). But many are thoughtful and deservemore attention than our spaceconstraints allow. Following is a sample. Somequalitativetheoristseither mix togetherevaluativeand socialtheories of truth (Eisner,\979,1983) or proposeto substitutethe socialfor theevaluative. SoJensen(1989)saysthat validiry refersto whethera knowledgeclaim is "meaningful and relevant" (p. 107) to a particular languagecommunity; andGuba and Lincoln (1,982)saythat truth can be reducedto whetheran accountis credibleto thosewho read it. Although we agreethat socialand evaluativetheoriescomplement eachother and are both helpful, replacingthe evaluativewith the socialis misguided. These social alternatives allow for devastatingcounterexamples (Phillips, 1987): the swindler'sstory is coherentbut fraudulent;cults convince membersof beliefsthat havelittle or no apparentbasisotherwise;and an account of an interactionbetweenteacherand studentmight be true evenif neitherfound it to be credible.Bunge(1992) showshow one cannotdefinethe basicideaof er- I I :J :iil 14.A CRITICAL ASSESSMENT OF OURASSUMPTIONS qualitative researcher to claim that internal validity is irrelevant to qualitative methods. Validity is not a properfy of methods but of inferencesand knowledge claims. On those infrequent occasions in which a qualitative researcher has a strong interest in a local molar causal inference,the concernswe have outlined under internal validity pertain. This argument cuts both ways, of course. An experimenter who wonders what the experiment meansto participants could learn a lot from the concerns that Maxwell outlines under interpretive validity. Maxwell (1,992) also points out that his validity typology suggeststhreats to validity about which qualitative researchersseek "evidencethat would allow them to be ruled-out . . . using a logic similar to that of quasi-experimentalresearcherssuch as Cook and Campbell" (p. 296). He does not outline such threats himself, but his description allows one to guess what some might look like. To judge from Maxwell's prose, threats to descriptive validity include errors of commission (describing something that did not occur), errors of omission (failing to describesomething that did occur), errors of frequency (misstatitg how often something occurred), and interrater disagreement about description. Threats to the validity of knowledge claims have also been invoked by qualitative theorists other than Maxwell-for example, by Becker (1,979), Denzin (1989), and Goetz and LeCompte (1984). Our only significant disagreement with Maxwell's discussion of threats is his claim that qualitative researchersare less able to use "design features" (p. 2961to deal with threats to validity. For instance, his preferred use of multiple observers ls a qualitative design feature that helps to reduce errors of omission, commission, and frequency. The repertoire of design featuresthat qualitative researchersuse will usually be quite different from those used by researchersin other traditions, but they are design features (methods) all the same. Differences. These agreementsnotwithstanding, many qualitative theorists approach validity in ways that differ from our treatment. A few of thesedifferences are basedon argumentsthat are simply erroneous(Heap, 1.995;Shadish,1995a). But many are thoughtful and deservemore attention than our spaceconstraints allow. Following is a sample. Some qualitative theorists either mix together evaluative and social theories "1.979,1983) of truth (Eisner, or propose to substitutethe socialfor the evaluative. So Jensen(1989) saysthat validiry refers to whether a knowledge claim is "meaningful and relevant" (p. L07l to a particular language community; and Guba and Lincoln (t9821say that truth can be reduced to whether an account is credible to those who read it. Although we agree that social and evaluative theories complement each other and are both helpful, replacing the evaluative with the social is misguided. These social alternatives allow for devastating counterexamples (Phillips, L987): the swindler's story is coherent but fraudulent; cults convince members of beliefs that have little or no apparent basis otherwise; and an account of an interaction between teacher and student might be true even if neither found it to be credible. Bunge (1992) shows how one cannot define the basic idea of er- .il j t I I 'iil VALIDITYI +ET ror usingsocialtheoriesof truth. Kirk and Miller (1986) capturethe needfor an evaluativetheory of truth in qualitativemethods: In responseto the propensity of so many nonqualitative researchtraditions to use such hidden positivist assumptions, some social scientists have tended to overreact by stressinj the possibility ;f alternative interpretations of everything to th€ exclusion of of oburry .ffor, to chooseamong them. This extreme relativism ignores the other side at all. It ignores the distinction between leciivity-that there is an external world lrro*l"dg. and opinion, and results in everyonehaving a separateinsight that cannot be reconciledwith anyone else's.(p. 15) A seconddifferencerefersto equatingthe validity of knowledgeclaimswith their earlierwith tqsttheory (e.g.,Eisenhart6CHowe, L992)' evaluation,aswe discussed that much of validityin qualiThis is mostexplicitin Salner(L989),whosuggested "that are useful for evaluatingcompeting tative methodoiogyconcernsthe criteria to exposethe moral andvalueimplications claims',(p. 51);"id rh. urgesresearchers is to testtheory.Our response (1.989)saidin reference of ,.r."rch, *.rch asMessick'We claims endorsethe need to evaluateknowledge the sameas for test theory. broadly includingtheir moial implications;but this is not the sameassayingthat the claim is-t.ue.Truih is just onecriterionof merit for a good knowledgeclaim. A third differencemakes validity a result of the processby which truth emerges.For instance,emphasizingthe dialecticprocessthat givesrise to truth' ,,ValidLnowledgeclaimsemerge. . . from the conflict and difSalnei(l9g9l says: ferencesbetweenthe contextsthemselvesas thesedifferencesare communicated and actions"(p. 61).Miles and amongpeoplewho sharedecisions and negotiated Huberman(1984)rpr"t of th. problemof validity in qualitativemethodsbeing 'Lnalysis proceduresfor qualitative data" (p. 230). Guba and an insufficiencyof Lincoln (1989) argue that tiustworthinessemergesfrom communicationwith The problemwith all thesepositionsis the erother colleaguesarid stakeholders. ror of thinklng that validity is a property of methods.Any procedurefor generatit is the knowledge ing knowledg! can g.n.r"i. invalid-knowledge,so in the end "The validity of an ac(1992) says, claim itself that muJt be judged.As Maxwell count is inherent,not in the proceduresusedto produceand validateit, but in its relationshipto thosethings it is intendedto be an accountof" (p' 281)' to validity must be A fourth differencesuggeststhat traditional approaches "historically arosein the reformulatedfor qualitativemethodsbecausevalidiry p' Othersre64\' 1992, context of experimentalresearch"(Eisenhart6CHowe, ject validity for similar reasonsexceptthat they saythat validity arosein test theo.y 1..g.,*lol.orr, 19gO).Both are incorrect,for validiry concernsprobably first "ror. Jrt.*"ti.ally in philosophyprecedingtesttheory and experimentalscience by hundredsor thour"ndr of years.Validity is pertinentto any discussionof the warrant for believingknowledgeand is not specificto particular.methods. A fifth differenie .on..rrri the claim that there is no ontological reality at all, so thereis no truth to correspondto it. The problemswith this perspective First, evenif it were true' it would apply only to "r. .rror1nous(Schmitt,1,995). -T 8z oF ouR AssuMploNs I r+.n cRtlcAL AssEssMENT correspondence theories of truth; coherence and pragmatist theories would be unaffected. Second, the claim contradicts our experience. As Kirk and Miller ( 1 9 8 6 1 p u ti t : Thereis a world of empiricalreality out there.The way we perceiveand understand that world is largelyup to us, but the world doesnot tolerateall understandings of it equally(sothat the individualwho believes he or shecanhalt a speeding train with his or her bare handsmay be punishedby the world for actingon that understanding). ( p .1 1 ) Third, the claim ignores evidenceabout the problems with people'sconstructions. Maxwell notes that "one of the fundamental insights of the social sciencesis that people's constructions are often systematic distortions of their actual situation" (p. 506). FinallS the claim is self-contradictory becauseit implies that the claim itself cannot be rrue. A sixth difference is the claim that it makes no senseto speak of truth because there are many different realities, with multiple truths to match each (Filstead, 1.979;Guba 6c Lincoln, L982; Lincoln 6c Guba, 1985). Lincoln (L990), for example, says that "a realist philosophical stance requires, indeed demands, a singular reality and thereforea singulartruth" (p. 502), which shejuxtaposesagainst her own assumption of multiple realities with multiple truths. Whatever the merits of the underlying ontological arguments, this is not an argument against validity. Ontological realism (a commitment that "something" does exist) does not require a singular reality but merely a commitment that there be at least one reality. To take just one example, physicists have speculated that there may be circumstancesunder which multiple physical realities could exist in parallel, as in the case of Schrodinger'scat (Davies,1984; Davies & Brown, 1986). Such circumstances would in no way constitute an objection to pursuing valid characterizationsof those multiple realities. Nor for that matter would the existenceof multiple realities require multiple truths; physicists use the same principles to account for the multiple realities that might be experiencedby Schrodinger'scat. Epistemological realism (a commitment that our knowledge reflects ontological reality) does not require only one true account of that world(s), but only that there not be two contradictory accounts that are both true of the same ontological referent.3 How many realities there might be, and how many truths it takes to account for them, should not be decided by fiat. A seventh difference objects to the belief in a monolithic or absolute Truth (with capital T). rUfolcott (1990) says, "'What I seek is something else, a quality that points more to identifying critical elements and wringing plausible interpretations from them, something one can pursue without becoming obsessedwith 3. The fact that different people might have different beliefs about the same referent is sometimes cited as violating this maxim, but it need not do so. For example, if the knowledge claim being validated is "John views the program as effective but Mary views it as ineffective," the claim can be true even though the views of John and Mary are contradictory. j j ii VALIDITY I 483 finding the right or ultimate answer'the correctversion,the Truth" (p' 146)' He quantities-orientedand qualidescribes"the critical point of departurebetween 'know'with the former'ssatisfyties-orientedresearch[as beingthat] we cannot ing levelsof certainty" (p. 1,47).Mishler (t990) objectsthat traditional ap"as universal,abstractguarantorsof truth" prl".h., to validationare portrayed "the realistpositiondemandsabsolutetruth" ip. +ZOl.Lincoln(1990)thinksthat or absolutetruth tp. SOZI.However,it is misguidedto attributebeliefsin certainty havemadeclear we hope tf appioachesto validity srrchas that in this book.'We by now that thereare no guarantorsof valid inferences.Indeed,the more experigain,the morethey appreciatethe ambiguityof their encethat mostexperimenters "An experimentis somethingeverybodybelieves results.Albert Einsteinoncesaid, exceptthe personwho madeit" (Holton, 1986, p. 13).Like \(olcott, most ex,..k only to wring plausibleinterpretationsfrom their work, believperiri-renter, irrg thut "prudencesat poisedbetweenskepticismand credulity" (Shapin,1994, p."xxix). rilfletteednor, shouldnot, and frequentlycannot decidethat one account i, ,broirrt.ly true ani the other completelyfalse.To the contrary' tolerancefor multiple knowledgeconstructionsis a virtual necessity(Lakatos, 1'978)because evidenceis frequeirtlyinadequateto distinguishbetweentwo well-supportedacaccountsthat appearto be uncounrs(islight " p"tti.l. or wave?),and sometimes for manyyearsturn out to betrue (do germscauseulcers?)by euiJence supported "An have eighih differenceclaims that traditional understandingsof validity "forces ismoral shoitcomings.The argumentsherearemany,for example,that it ethics to be submerged" sues of politics, ial,res (social and scientific), and "social science'experts' . (Lincoln, 1,990,p. 503) and implicitly empowers ensurestamale,and middle-class) (primarily'$7hite, whoseclasspreoccupations . . . thoseof women, personsof color, or tus for somevoiceswhile marginalizittg "1.990,p. may 502).Althoughthesearguments minoritygroupmembers"(Lincoln, b. ou"..tlted, they contain important cautions.Recallthe examplein Chapter3 in healthresearch.No doubt this biaswas that ,,Eventhe rats werewhite males" 'White malesin the designand executionof health partly due to the dominanceof '..r.ur.h. None of the methodsdiscussedin this book are intendedto redressthis problem or are capableof it. The purposeof experimentaldesignis to elucidate ca.rsalinferences-or. than morallnferences.'Whatis lessclearis that this problem requiresabandoningnotions of validity or truth. The claim that traditional ,pprou.h.s to truth forcibly submergepolitical and ethicalissuesis simplywrong. Tb-the extent that morality is reflectedin the questionsasked,the assumptions made,and the outcomesexamined,experimentefscan go a long way by ensuring of stakeholdervoicesin study design.Further,moral social a broad representation sciencereiuires commitment to truth. Moral righteousnesswithout truthful analysisis ihe stuff of totalitarianism.Moral diversityhelpspreventtotalitarianism, but without the discipline provided by truth-seeking,diversity offers no -."16 to identify thoseoptionsthat are good for the human condition,which is, of morality.In order to havea moral socialscience,we must after all,the essence haveboih the capacityto elucidatepersonalconstructionsand the capacityto see 484 | 14.A CR|T|CAL ASSESSMENT OF OURASSUMPTTONS how thoseconstructionsreflectand distort reality (Maxwell, 19921.'Weembrace the moral aspirationsof scholarssuchas Lincoln, but giving voiceto thoseaspirations simply doesnot requireus to abandonsuchnotions as validity and truth. Q UASI.EXPERIM ENTATION Criteriafor RulingOut Threats: The Centralityof FuzzyPlausibility In a randomized experiment in which all groups are treated in the sameway excepr for treatment assignment,very few assumptionsneed to be made about ro,rr.", of bias. And those that are made are clear and can be easily tested,particularly as concerns the fidelity of the original assignment process and its subsequentmaintenance. Not surprisinglS statisticiansprefer methods in which the assumptionsare few, transparent, and testable. Quasi-experiments, however, rely heavily on researcheriudgments about assumptions, especiallyon the fuzzy but indispensable concept of plausibility. Judgments about plausibility are neededfor deciding which of the many threats to validity are relevant in a given study for deciding whether a particular designelement is capable of ruling out a given threat, for estimating by how much the bias might have been reduced, and for assessingwhether multiple threats that might have been only partially adjusted for might add up to a total bias greater than the effect size the researcher is inclined to claim. Vith quasiexperiments, the relevant assumptions are numerous, their plausibility is less evident, and their single and joint effectsare lesseasily modeled. We acknowledgethe fuzzy way in which particular internal validity threats are often ruled out, and it is becauseof this that we too prefer randomized experiments (and regressiondiscontinuity designs)over most of their quasi-experimentalalternatives. But quasi-experiments vary among themselveswith respect to the number, transparencg and testability of assumptions. Indeed, we deliberately ordered the chapters on quasi-experiments to reflect the increase in inferential power that comes from moving from designs without a pretest or without a comparison group to those with both, to those based on an interrupted time series,and from there to regression discontinuity and random assignment.Within most of these chapters we also illustrated how inferencescan be improved by adding design elements-more pretest observation points, better stable matching, replication and systematic removal of the treatment, multiple control groups, and nonequivalent dependentvariables. In a sense,the plan of the four chapters on quasi-experiments reflects two purposes. One is to show how the number, transparency and testability of assumptions varies by type of quasi-experimental design so that, in the best of quasi-experiments,internal validity is not much worse than with the randomized experiment. The other is to get students of quasi-experimentsto be more sparing with the use of this overly general label, for it threatens to tar all quasi- t +SS QUASI-EXPERIMENTATION | to the experimentswith the samenegativebrush. As scholarswho have contributed institution alization of the t i^ quoti-experiment, we feel a lot of ambivalence the randomabout our role. Scholarsneed to itrint critically about alternatives to laized experiment, and from this need arisesthe need for the quasi-experimental under the bel. But all instancesof quasi-experimentaldesignshould not be brought do studies best the sameunduly broad quasi-experimentalumbrella if attributes of not closely match the weaker attributes of the field writ large. use of Statisticians seek to make their assumptions transparent through the stratthis resisted have formal models laid out as formulae. For the most part, we very conegy becauseit backfires with so many readers,alienating them from the inwords .!pt.r"t issuesthe formul ae aredesignedto make evident.'We have used cognoscenti' stead.There is a cost to this, and not jupt in the distaste of statistical The particularly those whose own research has emphasized statistical modelsformally to main cost is that our narrative approach makes it more difficult the alternative demonstrate how much fewer and more evident and more testable quasiinterpretations became as we moved from the weaker to the stronger acrossthe .*p.ri-.rrts, both within the relevant quasi-experimental chapters and 'We regret this, but do not apologize for the accessibility we tried to set of them. Fortucreate by minimirirrg the use of Greek symbols and Roman subscripts. to develop nately, this deficit is not absolute, as both we and others have worked in particmeth;ds that can be used to measurethe size of particular threats' both and 2000) Shadish, 1998; ular studies(e.g.,Gastwirth et al., L994;Shadishet al., Posavac,6c in sets of studiis (e.g.,Kazdin 6c Bass, 1989; Miller, Turner, Tindale, our Further, & Putnam,t982\. & Rubin,1,978;Willson Dugoni,1,991;Ror."nitt.t statistical narrative approach has a significant advantage over a more narrowly threats emphasisii allows us to addressa broad er array of qualitatively different therethat to validitS threats for which no statistical measure is yet available and quantification. fore mighi otherwise be overlooked with too strict an emphasison at all Better to h"u. imprecise attention to plausibility than to have no attention measured' paid to many imptrtant threats just becausethey cannot be well PatternMatchingas a ProblematicCriterion about the desirabilityof imbuing This book is more explicitthan its predecessors a causalhypothesiswith multiple tistable implicationsin the data, providedthat we they servett reducethe viability of alternativecausalexplanations.In a sense' assessment u-sual the for havesoughtto substitutea pattern-matchingme{rod-ology'We do this not because differ. reliably of wheth-era few means,oft.n only fwo, num.o-pl.*ity itself is a desideratumin science.To the contrary,simpliciry in the The simplicity be, of questionsaskedand methodsusedis highly prizedin science. well. of ,arrjomized experimentsfor descriptivecausalinferenceillustratesthis However,the samesimple circumstancedoes not hold with quasi-experiments. With them. we haveassirtedthat causalinferenceis improvedthe more specific, 488 | ro.o cRtlcALAssEssMENT oF ouRAssuMploNs generatingtheselists.The main concernwas to havea consensus of educationresearchersendorsingeachpractice;and he guessedthat the number of thesebest practicesthat dependedon randomizedexperimentswould be zero. Severalnationally known educationalresearcherswere present,agreedthat such assignment probably playedno role in generatingthe list, and felt no distressat this. So long as the belief is widespreadthat quasi-experiments constitutethe summit of what is neededto support causalconclusions,the support for experimentation that is currently found in health, agriculture,or health in schoolsis unlikely to occur.Yet randomizationis possiblein.manyeducationalcontextswithin schools if the will existsto carry it out (Cook et al., 1999;Cook et al., in press).An unfortunate and inadvertentside effect of seriousdiscussionof quasi-experiments may sometimesbe the practicalneglectof randomizedexperiments.That is a pity. RANDOMIZED EXPERIMENTS This sectionlistsobjectionsthat havebeenraisedto doingrandomizedexperiments, and our analysisof the more and lesslegitimateissuesthat theseobiectionsraise. Experiments CannotBe Successfully lmplemented Even a little exposure to large-scalesocial experimentation shows that treatments are often improperly or incompletely implemented and that differential attrition often occurs. Organizational obstaclesto experiments are many. They include the reality that different actors vary in the priority they attribute to random assignment, that some interventions seem disruptive at all levels of the organization, and that those at the point of service delivery often find the treatment requirements a nuisance addition to their aheady overburdened daily routine. Then there are sometimes treatment crossovers,as units in the control condition adopt or adapt components from the treatment or as those in a treatment group are exposed to some but not all of these same components. These criticisms suggestthat the correct comparison is not between the randomized experiment and better quasi-experiments when each is implemented perfectly but rather between the randomized experiment as it is often imperfectly implemented and better quasiexperiments. Indeed, implementation can sometimes be better in the quasiexperiment if the decision not to randomize is based on fears of treatment degradation. This argument cannot be addressedwell becauseit dependson specifying the nature and degree of degradation and the kind of quasi-experimental alternative. But taken to its extreme it suggeststhat randomized experiments have no special warrant in field settings becausethere is no evidencethat they are stronger than other designs in practice (only in theory). But the situation is probably not so bleak. Methods for preventing and coping with treatment degradation are improving rapidly (seeChapter 10, this vol- EXPERIMENTS RANDOMIZED I AAS random assignumel Boru ch,1997;Gueron,1,999;Orr, L999).More important, with the -.n, may still createa superiorcounterfactualto its alternativeseven (1'9961foundthat, flaws mentionedherein.FLr e*ample,Shadishand Ragsdale experirandomized without attrition, .o-p"..d with randomized."p..i-.tts nonrandommentswith attrition still yieldedbetter effectsizeestimatesthan did ranized experiments.Sometimes,of course,an alternativeto severelydegraded a control' domizaiion will be best,such as a strong interruptedtime serieswith poor rule to folBut routine rejectionof degradedrandomizedexperimentsis a to l,o*; it takescarefulstudy and judgmentto decide.Further,many alternatives flaws that experimentationare themselu.i ,ob;..t to treatmentimplementation of inferencesfrom them. Attrition and treatmentcrossovers thieatenthe validity'we also suspectthat implementationflaws are salientin exalso occur in them. hav6beenaround so long and experimenters f.ri-errt"tion becauseexperiments the quality "r. .o critical of eachothlr's work. By contrast,criteria for assessing (e'g',Datta, of implementationand resultsfrom othermethodsarefar more recent lesssubjected D97j,and they may thereforebe lesswell developedconceptuallS to peercriticism,and lessimprovedby the lessonsof experience. ExperimentationNeedsStrongTheoryand Standardized TreatmentlmPlementation rs Many critics claim that experimentationis more fruitful when an intervention is details basedon strongsubstantivetheory when implementationof treatment when imfaithful to that theor5 when the rlsearchsettingis well managed,and these plementationdoes,roi uury much betweenunits' In many field experiments' organiza' conditions are not met. For example,schools arclarge, complex, social iio"r *ith multiple programs,disputatiouspolitics, and conflicting stakeholder well as goals.Many progr"*, a"reimplementedvariablyacrossschooldistricts,as of standard f.ror, ..hoth, .Lrrroo-r, arri ,t.rdents.Therecan be no presumPli9n 1'977)' implementationor fidelity to programtheory (Berman& Mclaughlin, wellBut thesecriticismsur., i' fa-ct,misplaced.Experimentsdo not require implementaspecifiedprogram theories,good program management,standard a contrition, or treatmentsthat are tJtally ?aithful to theory' Experimentsmake. makesa bution when they simplyprobewhetheran intervention-as-implemented preceding marginal improvem.tttt.yord other backgroundvariability. Still, the suggests fa.tJ* can ieducestatisticalpower and so cloud causalinference.This should: experiments that in settingsin which *or. of these conditions hold, (L) uselargesamplesto detecteffects;(2) take painsto reducethe influenceof exmatraneousvariation either by designor through measurementand statistical worth studynipulation; and (3) studyimplementationquality both as a variable implement i"g * its own right in oid.r to ascertainwhich settingsand providers treatthl interventionbetterand asa mediatorto seehow implementationcarries ment effectsto outcome. 490 | r+.a cRtTtcAL ASSESSMENT OFOURA5SUMPTIONS Indeed,for many purposesthe lack of standardizationmayaid in understanding how effectivean interventionwill be undernormal conditionsof implementation.In the social world, few treatmentsare introduced in a standardand theory-faithful way. Local adaptationsand partial implementationare the norm. If this is the case, then someexperimentsshould reflect this variation and ask whetherthe treatment cancontinueto be effectivedespiteall the variation within groupsthat we would expectto find if the treatmentwerepolicy.Programdeveloperiand socialtheoristsmay want standardizationat high levelsof implementation,but policy analysrsshouldnot welcomethis if it makesthe researchconditionsdifferenifro- the practiceconditions to which they would like to generalize.Of course,it is most desiiableto be able to answerboth setsof questions-about policy-relevanteffectsof treatmentsthat are variably implementedand alsoabout the more theory-relevanteffectsof optimal exposureto the intervention.In this regard,one might recall recenteffortsio analyze the effectsof the original intent to treat through traditional meansbut alsoof the effectsof the actual treatmentthrough using random assignmentas an instrumental variable(Angristet al., 1996a\. ExperimentsEntailTradeoffsNot Worth Making The choiceto experimentinvolvesa number of tradeoffsthat someresearchers believeare not worth making (Cronbach,7982).Experimenrationprioritizeson unbiasedanswersto descriptivecausalquestions.But, givenfinite r.rour..r, someresearchers preferto investwhat they havenot into marginalimprovementsin internal validity but into promoting higher constructand externalvalidity. They might be content with a greaterdegreeof uncertainryabout the quality of a causalconnection in orderto purposivelysamplea greaterrangeof populationsof peopleor settings or, when a particular population is central to the research,in ordeito generate a formally representativesample.They might evenusethe resourcesto improve treatmentfidelity or to includemultiplemeasures of averyimportantoutcomeconstruct. If a consequence of this preferencefor constructand ixternal validity is to conducta quasi-experimentor evena nonexperimentrather than a randomizedexperiment, then so be it. Similar preferencesmake other critics look askancewhen advocatesof experimentationcounselrestrictinga study to volunteersin order to increasethe chancesof beingable to implementand maintainrandomassignment or when thesesameadvocatesadviseclosemonitoring of the treatmentto ensureits fideliry therebycreatinga situation of greaterobtruiivenessrhan would pertain if the sametreatmentwerepart of someongoingsocialpolicy (e.g.,Heckman,1992). In the languageof Campbelland Stanley(1,963;., theclaim was that ."p.ri*.rrt"tion traded off externalvalidity in favor of internal validiry. In the parlanceof this book and of Cook and Campbell(1979),it is that experimentatiortrades off both externaland constructvalidity for internal validiry to its detriment. Critics also claim that experimentsoveremphasize conservativestandardsof scientificrigor. Theseinclude (1) usinga conservativecriterion to protect against EXPERIMENTS RANDOMIZED | *tt to dewrongly concludinga treatmentis effective (p <.05) at the risk of failing that include tect true treatment;ffects;(2) recommendingintent-to-treatanalyses (3) denitreatment; as part of the treatmentthoseunits that have neverreceived gr"ting inferencesthat result from exploring unplanned treatment interactions of units, observations,settings,or times;and (4) rigidly purwith characteristics emerge suing a priori experimentalquestionswhen other interestingquestions about duriig " ,t,rdy. Mort laypersonsuse a more liberal risk calculusto decide poten.u,rrul inferencesin their own lives,as when they considertaking up some ii"ity lifesavingtherapy.Should not sciencedo the same' be lessconservative? make different tradeoffs betweenprotection Snoula it notlt least-sometimes againstincorrectinferencesand the failure to detecttrue effects? critics further obiectthat experimeptsprioritize descriptiveover explanatory whether causation.The criticsin qrrestionwould toleratemore uncertaintyabout processes the interventionworks in order to learn more about any explanatory acrossunits, settings'observations,and times' that havethe potentialto generalize qualitaFurther,,o-. critics pr.f!, to pursuethis explanatory knowledgeusing than tive meihodssimilar io thor. of th. historian,journalist, and ethnographer more opaque by meansof, sa5 structuralequation modeling that seemsmuch than the narrativereportsof theseother fields' critics alsodislikethe priority that experimentsgiveto providing policymakreal-time ers with ofren belated"rrri.r, about what works insteadof providing in interested rarely are help to serviceprovidersin local settings.Theseproviders They often preferrer,rrnmaryofwhat, ptogt"- has.achieved. " torrg-a.tayed elements ceiving.o.riin,ro.rsfeedbackabouttheir work and especiallyabout those letter to A recent oiprJ.ri.. that they can changewithout undue complication' theNew York Timescapturedthis preference: to approach issues Alan Krueger . . claims to eschew value iudgments and wants changesin edpostponing on insistence his (about educationalreform) empirically. Yet judgment a value itself is ucation policy until studiesby iesearchersapproach certainry in parts of public eduin favor of the status quo. In view of the tragic state of affairs 1999) (Petersen, cation, his judgment is a most questionableone. queswe agreewith many of thesecriticisms.Among all possible_research methquestionsconstituteonly a subset.And of all possiblecausal tions,cau-sal is not relevantio all typesof questionsand all typesof cirods,experimentation in cumstance.One needonly read the list of options and contingenciesoutlined experimentaCh"p,.r, 9 and L0 to appreciatehow foolhardy it is to advocate "gold standard"that will invariablyresultin tion on a routine basisas a causal tradeclearly interpretableeffect sizes.However,many of the criticisms about even overoffs are basedon artificial dichotomies,correctableproblems,-and imsimplifications.Experimentscan and should examinereasonsfor variable They pl.-.nt"tion, and they should searchto uncover mediating processes' '05 the for neednot use stringentalpha rates;only statisticaltradition argues that level.Nor needonJ restrict dataanalysesonly to the intent-to-treat'though 'aloJ lueururo.rdeJoru qf,ntu e sdeld drrprlerrlpuJetur ql1qlv\ ur surerSord rpuar ;o lurluerelm puorq dpursrrd -Jns eql ol pue qf,ntu oor drlPllu^ Ieurelur aztseqduraapreqr qf,Jeesar;o sururSord ur pa8raureaABr{stsaSSnsdrolsrq lpql sassau>lea^\ IertuaraJuragr ol uouuane Bur -llEf, orp arrrtaqrey .(rq8rlrodsaql uI erurl slr a^eq lsntu ad& drlPler d-rela) /lpll -EA pnJlsuof, Jo JaAo drrprlerr lEuJalxa IeuJalur 1o drerurrd eurlnoJ due -ro; 8ur1er lou eJEeM'T lardu{J uI Jealr oPELua.&\se 'esJnoJIO 'parseSSnsarreqsrrlr.rr tsed req.a'\sPeaJxadlrear8 sluaut-radxaeldrllnur Ja o senssrdrrpllel leuJalxa pug lrnrls -uol qloq sserppeol dlneder aql.slsdleue-Eleruur dlrrap lsoru aeso^4,se 1ng ,sans -sI asJl{t qroq Sulssarpp" ur r.lf,EarperFrll e^Er{ slueurradxa .paluerg lpnprlrpur 'larrr dlfsapou sanssr,{rrprlerr Ipuralxo puB lJnrlsuoJ r{foq sserppE ot r{f,rBrsar srueJSord;o dlpeder agr qrr^\ pessarduneJEaA\ ,1ser1uocdg letuaurr.ladxeIo '8ur1uru r{uo^\ tanau aJu lpql stJoapqJfarrnbar sluaurrradxeter{l tsa88nsol luet -.rodur ool sr s{Jo.&\rpqra 1no Surpurg .sanqod alouord IErJospaseq-sseua^rpa}Ja ol lue1Y\ol{1v\sJJelsrlaql Pue srolelsr8al asoql ro; d1-rrlnrrued 'cnerualqord eJoru uala dlqeqo-rdaru sJel\supJeell tnoqtr^ saurl aturl Buol-opelep qrns .re8uep IEar P sI uollEluaurtradxa arntreruardq8noqlly 'sploq uorlenlrs atues aql lsorule pue 'uerSor4 ruaurdolartaq IooqJS aqr uuSaq rauoJ sauef arurs sread 0t sl lI .sra/\,s 'sloogrs peleJelalf,eue8aq -uB ou urle-J drua11 PUPsluolutradxa ou aleq all\ Pue 'sfteJJe eruts sread SI sl fI JIeI{l rnoqe sJa^.r{sup Jeolf,ou e^Erl llrls o.&\puu .pasod -ord arain sJarlf,no^ .splp .uoryo oor Iooqtrs erurs srcad 0t A ou sr lI IIE ,.raddeq 'elgBpuedapun SFII sI lEql uollf,auuoJ lusnpr E tnogp suorsnlf,uoo leraua8 puorg Sutmerp >lsIJol sI uolluelJetul uE Jo srlaJJear{l uo sarpnts leluauuadxa Suorls o4 e^Pq ol 'spuno;8 IEIIuePI^ero lerrSoyuo elqrsneldurrdl-realf,arg drrprlerr leuralur ol slBarql ssaFn 'saf,uareJur da4;o dtr.rSalureql Sursrulordtuot lnoqlrd\ passoJl eq louupf, spunoq aruos 'lurod srql ot rrlaqledtuds d11erauafi are am qfinoqrly .ftget 'qrequo.r3 :og5t ''1" ''3'a) Ir r{luquorJ spoqlau lutuaurradxo ra8uorls aqr Bur -zrsuqdruasrue.rSo-rd tuory ueql serpnls leluaunradxeuou pue Iuluaur-radxa_isenb ;o dlerrlua uela ro dlrsoru lslsuof, rer{l qf,reasarJo sure-r8ordtuory peuJuel aq IIri\,\ uoupluroJul aroru Et'*:u"';rrx;;H:;r:::ilil? r'rrrpourr InJasn ilHt", ", 'lsa88ns stxel eruos su sluerue^ordur leur8rulu JeuIJ-JaAa plSrr se to 1uo3aqr pur '(salqerrul eq tou paau sluaur.radxg Surlelpau Jo sarnseau Burppe,.8.a)tuaqr;o ^{et salulleluoslnq 'saJJnosalartnber sarnparo-rdasaql ilV'{ooq srql ur peurllno spoqrau eqt Sursn pelpreua8aq plnoqs uortuzrlereua8 lesneolnoqp alqrssodse uolletuJotul qlntu sB puv 'sasseoordSurlelpau pue sauof,lno pepuelurun Burre -^oJsrp tE parurp uorllellor etvp a^nelrlenb aq plnor{s pue upJ aleql .saruof,lno pue 'stuerulearl 's8urpas (suos.rad;o sluerussasse dfrpryel lf,nJlsuof, ar{r puu ;o salduresJo sseualrleluasardar er.lrJo sasdyeue lulueurr.radxeuou eg osle plnoqs 'paqsqqnd aq uE3 sluaurrradxs tuoJJ sllnsoJ urrelul .dlsnorl Pue uBr erarll -nBf, suolsnlf,uol rraqf 3urqf,nof, PuE seleJ JoJJa ale8rgo.ld lsure8e Surpren8 hlo11u remod lptrrtsrlels pue droagl elrtuetsqns leql luatxe eqr ol suorlrrJal -uI 'srsdleur auo oq dlorruryap IEf,Itsllels aroldxa osle uet sJatuJurrradxg pFor{s sNoll_dwnssv uno lo l_Nty\sslssv tv)tl|u) v .tt I zov I EXPERIMENTS RANDOMIZED | 493 I Assumean InvalidModel Experiments Utilization of Research model of decision To somecritics, experimentsrecreatea naive rational choice among (the treatmaking. That is, one first lays out the alternativesto choose one collectsin*.rr,rt] then one decideson criteria of merit (the outcomes);then and finally formation on eachcriterion for eachtreatment(the data collection), empirical one makes a decisionabout the superior alternative.UnfortunatelS so simpleas the rawork on the useof socialsciencedaia showsthat useis not (c. \ufeiss6c Bucuvalas,1980; c''weiss, 1988)' tional choicemodelsuggests contexts'exFirst, evenwhen."-rir. and effectquestionsare askedin decision exp.ri-.nt"l resultsare still usedalong with other forms of information-from consensusof a isting theories,personaltestimony,extrapolationsfrom surveys' haverecentlybefieldlchims from expertswith intereststo defend,and ideasthat politics' person.o*. trendy.Decisionsare shapedpartly by ideology,interests, as much made by a ality, windows of-opportunity, and ualues;and they are individualor compolicy-shapirrg.o-*nrrity (cronbachet al., 1980) as by an overtime asear*i,,... Fuither,manydecisionsarenot so much madeasaccreted maker with few oplier decision,.orrrir"in later ones,leavingthe final decision are available,new tions ('Weiss,1980). Indeed,by the time ixperimental results decisionmakersand issuesmay havereplacedold ones. verdicts Second,.*p.rirn.nts often yield contestedrather than unanimous Disputes arise about that therefore have uncertain implications for decisions. resultsare valid' whether the causalquestionswere correctly framed, whether and whetherthe resultsentail a specific whetherrelevantoutcomeswere assessed, voucher decision.For example,reexaminationsof the Milwaukee educational (H' occurred ;"rdy offereddifferentconclusionsabout whetherand whereeffects SimilarlS 1'998,"1'999,2000)' 6cDu, 1.999;'Sritte, Fuller,2000;Greene,Peterson, classsizeexperiment(Finn differenteffect,ir., *.r. generatedfrom the Tennessee Light, 6c Sachs,1996)'Sometimes, EcAchilles,1.990;Hanusi'ek,1999;Mosteller, are at issue,but at other timesthe disputesreflectdeeply scholarlydisagreements conflictedstakeholderinterests. likely when Third, short-terminstrumentaluseof experimentaldata is more it is easierto the interventionis a minor variant on existingpractice.For example, criteriafor changetextbooksin a classroomor pills givenlo patientsor eligibility or to open entry than it is to relocatehospitalsto.underservedlocations ;;;;"* state' Becausethe day-carecentersfor welfare recipientsthroughout an entire to dramatically more feasible.tt""g.t are so ,ood.r, in scope,they are lesslikely on shor-t-terminaffecttheproble- ih.y address.So critics note that prioritizing is unlikelyto solve strumentalchangetendsto preservemost of the statusquo and that truly twist tr.rr.hunt social"probl.-s. bf course'thereare someexperiments from denselypoor the lion,stail andinvolvebold initiatives.Thus moving families deviations inner-citylocationsto the suburbsinvolveda changeof three standard 494 | 14.A CRIT|CAL ASSESSMENT OFOURASSUMPTTONS in the poverty level of the sending and receiving communities, much greater than what happens when poor families spontaneously move.'S7hethersuch a dramatic change could ever be used as a model for cleaning out the inner cities of those who want to move is a moot issue. Many would judge such a policy to be unlikely. Truly bold experiments have many important rationales; but creating new policies that look like the treatment soon after the experiment is not one of them. Fourth, the most frequent use of research may be conceptual rather than instrumental, changing how users think about basic assumptions,how they understand contexts, and how they organize'or label ideas. Some conceptual uses are intentional, as when a person deliberately reads a book on a current problem; for example, Murray's (1984) book on social policy had such a conceptual impact in the 1980s, creating a new social policy agenda. But other conceptual usesoccur in passing, as when a person reads a newspaper story referring to social research. Such usescan have great long-run impact as new ways of thinking move through the system, but they rarely change particular short-term decisions. These arguments against a naive rational decision-making model of experimental usefulnessare compelling. That model is rightly rejected. However, mosr of the objections are true not just of experiments but of all social sciencemethods. Consider controversies over the accuracy of the U.S. Census,the entirely descriptive results of which enter into a decision-making process about the apportionment of resourcesthat is complex and highly politically charged. No method offers a direct road to short-term instrumental use. Moreover, the obiections are exaggerated.In settings such as the U.S. Congress,decision making is sometimes influenced instrumentally by social scienceinformation (Chelimsky, 1998), and experiments frequently contribute to that use as part of a researchreview on effectivenessquestions. Similarlg policy initiatives get recycled, as happened with school vouchers, so that social science data that were not used in past years are used later when they become instrumentally relevant to a current issue (Polsby, 1'984; Quirk, 1986).In addition, data about effectivenessinfluence many stakeholders' thinking even when they do not use the information quickly or instrumentally. Indeed, researchsuggeststhat high-quality experiments can confer exrra 'Weiss credibility among policymakers and decision makers (C. & Bucuvalas, 1980)' as happened with the Tennesseeclasssize study. We should also not forget that the conceptual use of experiments occurs when the texts used to train professionalsin a given field contain results of past studies about successfulpractice (Leviton 6c Cook, 1983). And using social sciencedata to produce incremental change is not always trivial. Small changescan yield benefits of hundreds of millions of dollars (Fienberg,Singer,& Tanur, 1985). SociologistCarol'Weiss,an advocate of doing research for enlightenment's sake, says that 3 decadesof experience and her studies of the use of social sciencedata leave her "impressed with the utility of evaluation findings in stimulating incremental increasesin knowledge and in program effectiveness.Over time, cumulative incrementsare not such small potatoes after all" ('Weiss,1998, p. 31,9).Finallg the usefulnessof experimentscan be increased by the actions outlined earlier in this chapter that involve comple- ott EXPERIMENTS RANDOMIZED I mentingbasicexperimentaldesignwith adjunctssuchas measuresof implemenprotation a-ndmediationo, qualitativemethods-anything that will help clarify gram processand implementationproblems.In summarSinvalid modelsof the commonthan ir.foln.rs of experimintalresultsseemto us to be no more nor less 'we have learned invalid modelslf th. use of any other social sciencemethods. their much in the last severaldecadesabout use, and experimenterswho want 1'99I). of thoselessons(Shadishet al., work to be usefulcan take advantages Differfrom the TheConditionsof Experimentation Conditionsof Policylmplementation if were Experimentsare often doneon a smalleiscalethan would pertain services relei-il.-r.rted state-or nationwide,and so they cannot mimic all the details intervenu"rr, ,o full policy implementation.Hencepolicy implementationof an For ex,i"" -ry yi.ta aiff.rint o,rt.omesthan the experiment(Elmore, 1996)' size, class ample, t"r.d partly on researchabout the benefits of reducing and Caliiornia implementedstatewidepoliciesto have more classes Tennessee classwith fewer studentsin each.This required many new teachersand new teachnew those of rooms.However,becauseof a nationalteachershortage,some of ers may havebeenlessqualifiedthan thosein the experiment;and a shortage have may that classroomsled to more .rs. of trailers and dilapidatedbuildings further. harmedeffectiveness enthuSometimesan experimentaltreatmentis an innovation that generates experisiasticeffortsto implementit well. This is particularly frequentwhen the that ment is done by a charismaticinnovator whosetacit knowledgemay exceed pr^ctrce of thosewho would be expectedto implementthe program in ordinary may factors These and whosecharismamay inducehigh-qualityimplementation. is imgeneratemore srr...srfoi outcomesthan will be seenwhen the intervention plementedasroutine PolicY. Policy implementationmay also yield different-resultswhen experimental practreatmentsare implementedin a fashionthat differs from or conflictswith psychotherapy ticesin real-*orld application.For example,experimentsstudying and outcomeoften standardizetreatmentwiih a manual and sometimesobserve but correct the therapistfor deviatingfrom the manual (shadishet al., 2000); effecthesepracticesare rare in clinicallractice. If manualizedtreatmentis more might tive (bhambless& Hollon, 1998; Kendall, 1998), experimentalresults transferpoorly to practicesettings. policy Raniom assigrrm.ntmay also changethe program from the intended implementation(i{eckman,l992l. For ixample, thosewilling to be randomized may -"y diff.r from those for whom the treatment is intended; randomizatLon with changepeople'spsychologicalor social responseto treatment compared those"wlroself-selecttreatment;and randomizationmay disrupt administration clients' and implemenrationby forcingthe programto copewith a differentmix of I 496 | 14.A CR|T|CAL ASSESSMENT OF OURASSUMPTIONS Heckman claims this kind of problem with the Job taining PartnershipAct "calls into question 0TPA) evaluation the validity of the experimentalestimates as a statementabout theJTPAsystemas a whole" (Heckman,1.992, p. ZZ1,). In many respects,we agreewith thesecriticisms,thoughit is worth noting several responsesto them. First, theyassumealack of generalizabllityfrom experiment to policy but that is an empirical question.Somedata suggesrthar generalization may be high despite differencesbetweenlab and field (C. Anderson, LindsaS & Bushman, 1999) or betweenresearchand practice (Shadishet al., 2000). Second,it can help to implement.treatment underconditionsthat aremore characteristicof practiceif it doesnot unduly compromiseother researchpriorities. A little forethoughtcan improve the surfacesimilarity of units, trearments, observations,settings,or timesto their intendedtargets.Third, someof thesecriticismsare true of any researchmethodologyconductedin a limited context,such as locally conductedcasestudiesor quasi-experiments, becauselocal implementation issuesalwaysdiffer from large-scaleissues.Fourth, the potentiallydisruptive natureof experimentallymanipulatedinterventionsis sharedby many locally 'rrr"or"h invented novel programs, euen uhen they are not studied by any methodologyat all.Innovation inherentlydisrupts,and substantiveliteraturesare rife with examplesof innovationsthat encounteredpolicy implementationimpediments(Shadish,1984). However,the essentialproblem remainsthat large-scalepolicy implementation is a singularevent,the effectsof which cannot be fully known exceptby doing the full implementation.A singleexperiment,or evena smallseriesof ri-ilrt ones,cannotprovidecompleteanswersabout what will happenif the intervention is adoptedas policy. However,Heckman'scriticism needsreframing.He fails to distinguishamongvalidity types(statisticalconclusion,internal,.onrtro.., external). Doing so makesit clearthat his claim that suchcriticism"calls into question the validity of the experimentalestimatesasa sratementabout the JTPA,yrt.rr, ", a whole" (Heckman,1.992, p.221,)is reallyabout externalvalidityand construcr validity,not statisticalconclusionor internalvalidity.Exceptin thenarrow econometricstraditionthat he understandably cites(Haavelmo,7944;Marschak ,7953; Tinbergen,1956),few socialexperimentersever claimedthat experimentscould describethe "systemas a whole"-even Fisher(1935)acknowledged this tradeoff. Further,the econometricsolutionsthat Heckman suggestscannot avoid the sametradeoffsbetweeninternal and externalvalidity. For example,surveysand certain quasi-experiments can avoid someproblemsby observingexistinginterventionsthat have aheadybeenwidely implemented,but the validity of tleir estimatesof program effectsare suspectand may themselves changeif the program were imposedevenmore widely as policy. Addressingthesecriticismsrequiresmultiple lines of evidence-randomized experimentsof efficacyand effectiveness, nonrandomizedexperimentsthat observeexistinginterventions,nonexperimentalsurveysto yield estimatesof representativeness, statisticalanalysesthat bracketeffectsunder diverseassumpd;ns, J EXPERIMENTS RANDOMIZED II Ot qualitative observation to discover potential incompatibilities between the interventiol and its context of likely implementation, historical study of the fates of similar interventions when they were implemented as policg policy analysesby those with expertisein the type of intervention at issue,and the methods for causal generalizationin this book. The conditions of policy implementation will be difi.r.rr, from the conditions characteristic of any rese^rchstudy of it, so predicting generalizationto policy will always be one of the toughest problems. Flawed ls Fundamentally lmposingTreatments the Growthof Local with Encouraging Compared Solutionsto Problems Experimentsimposetreatmentson recipients.Yet som,elate 20th-centurythought ,.rjg.rt, that imposedsolutionsmay be inferior to solutionsthat are locally gen.rJr".a by thoseiho h"n. the problem. Partly,this view is premisedon research findings of few effectsfor the Great Societysocialprogramsof the 1960sin the UniteJ States(Murrag 1.984;Rossi, L987),with the presumptionthat a portion of the failurewas due to the federallyimposednatureof the programs.Partly,the view reflectsthe successof late 2Oth-centuryfree market economicsand conservative political ideologiescompared with centrally controlled economiesand more fi|eral political beliefs.Experimentallyimposedtreatmentsare seenin some quartersas beinginconsistentwith suchthinking' IronicallS the first objectionis basedon resultsof experiments-if it is true that impos.i progr"*s do not work, experimentsprovided the evidence.Moreover,thesetro-.ff..t findingsmay havebeenpartly due to methodologicalfailures of experimentsas they were implementedat that time. Much progressin solving practicalexperimentalproblemsoccurredafter,and partly in responseto, those If so,it is prematureto assumetheseexperimentsdefinitivelydemonexperiments. stiated no effect,especlalygiven our increasedability to detectsmall effectsto6c shroder,1,997;LipseSL992;Lipsey6c'Wilson,!993). day ' (D. Greenberg iistinguish betweenpolitical-economiccurrencyand the effects We must also'We of interventions. know of no comparisonsof, say,the effectsof locally generatedversusimposedsolutions.Indeed,the methodologicalproblemsin doing such comparisonsare daunting, especiallyaccuratelycategotizinginterventionsinto the two categoriesand unlonfounding the categorieswith correlatedmethoddifferences.Bariing an unexpectedsolutionto the seeminglyintractableproblemsof causalinferencein nonrandomizeddesigns,answeringquestionsabout the effects of locally generatedsolutionsmay requireexactlythe kind of high-qualityexperimentatioi being criticized.Though it is likely that locally generatedsolutions may indeedhavesignificantadvantages,it also is likely that someof thosesolutions will haveto be experimentallyevaluated. I 498 | 14.A CRIT|CAL ASSESSMENT OF OURASSUMPTTONS CAUSALGENERALIZATION: AN OVERLY COMPLICATED THEORY? Internal validity is best promoted via random assignment,an omnibus mechanism that ensuresthat we do not have many assumptions to worry about when causal inferenceis our goal. By contrast, quasi-experimentsrequire us to make explicit many assumptions-the threats to internal validity-that we then have to rule out by fiat, by design,or by measurement.The latter is a more complex and assumption-riddled processthat is clearly inferior to random assignment.Something similar holds for causal generalization,in which random selectionis the most parsimonious and theoretically justified method, requiring the fewest assumptionswhen causalgeneralization is our goal. But becauserandom selectionis so rarely feasible,one instead has to construct an acceptabletheory of generaliz tion out of purposive sampling, 'We a much more difficult process. have tried to do this with our five principles of generalizedcausal inference.These, we contend, are the keys to generalizedinference that lie behind random sampling and that have to be identified, explicated, and ano assessed assessedif rt we are to make make better general inferences, rnterences,even rt if they are not perfect ones. But these principles are much more complex to implement than is random sampling. Let us briefly illustrate this with the category called American adult women. We could represent this category by random selection from a critically appraised register of all women who live in the United Statesand who arc at least 21 years of age.I7ithin the limits of sampling error, we could formally generalizeany characteristics we measured on this sample to the population on that register. Of course, we cannot selectthis way becauseno such register exists.Instead,one does onet experiment with an opportunistic sample of women. On inspection they all '1,9 turn out to be between and 30 years of age, to be higher than average in achievementand abilit5 and to be attending school-that is, we have useda group of college women. Surface similarity suggeststhat each is an instance of the category woman. But it is obvious that the modal American woman is clearly not a college student. Such students constitute an overly homogeneoussample with respect to educational abilities and achievement,socioeconomicstatus, occupation, and all observable and unobservable correlates thereof, including health status, current employment, and educational and occupational aspirations and expectations. To remedy this bias, we could use a more complex purposive sampling design that selectswomen heterogeneouslyon all these characteristics.But purposive sampling for heterogeneousinstances can never do this as well as random selection can, and it is certainly more complex to conceive and execute.I7e could go on and illustrate how the other principles faclhtate generalization. The point is that any theory of generalization from purposive samples is bound to be more complicated than the simplicity of random selection. But becauserandom selection is rarely possible when testing causal relationships within an experimental framework, we need these purposive alternatives. NONEXPERIMENTALALTERNATIVES I 499 Yet most experimental work probably still relies on the weakest of these alternatives, surfaci similarity.'We seek to improve on such uncritical practice. Unfortunately though, there is often restricted freedom for the more careful selection of instancesof units, treatments, outcomes, and settings, even when the selection is done purposively.It requires resourcesto sample irrelevanciesso that they are heterogeneouson many attributes, to measure several related constructs that can be discriminated from each other conceptually and to measure a variety of possible explanatory processes.This is partly why we expect more progress on causal generalization from a review context rather than from single studies. Thus, if one researcher can work with college women, another can work with female schoolteachers, and another with female retirees, this creates an opportunity to see if thesesourcesof irrelevant homogeneity make a difference to a causal relationship or whether it holds over all these differ6nt types of women. UltimatelS causal generalizationwill always be more complicated than assessing the likelihood that a relationship is causal.The theory is more diffuse, more recent, and lesswell testedin the crucible of researchexperience.And in some quarters there is disdain for the issue,given the belief and practice that relationshipsthat replicate once should be consideredas generaluntil proven otherwise' not to speak oithe belief that little progressand prestigecan be achieved by designingthe next experiment to be some minor variant on past studies. There is no point in pret.nding that causal generalization is as institutionalized procedurally as other methods in the social sciences.'Wehave tried to set the theoretical agendain a systematic way. But we do not expect to have the last word. There is still no explication of causal generalizationequivalent to the empirically produced list of threats to internal validiry and the quasi-experimental designsthat have evolved over 40 years to rule out thesethreats. The agendais set but not complete. RIM ENTALALTERNATIVES NONEXPE Though this book is about experimentalmethodsfor answeringquestionsabout it is a mistaketo believethat only experimentalapproachesare .".rr"l hypotheses, used for thir p,r.pose.In the following; we briefly consider severalother approaches,indiiating the major reasonswhy we havenot dwelt on them in detail. basicallSthe reasonis that we believethat, whatevertheir merits for someresearchpurposes,they generatelessclearcausalconclusionsthan randomizedexor suchas regression-discontinuity perimentsor eventhe bestquasi-experiments interruptedtime series The nonexperimentalalternativeswe examineare the major onesto emerge in variousacademicdisciplines.In educationand parts of anthropologyand sociologg one alternativeis intensivequalitativecasestudies.In thesesamefields,and also-in developmentalpsychologythere is an emerginginterestin theory-based 500 | 14.A CR|T|CAL ASSESSMENT OFOURASSUMPTTONS causal studies basedon causal modeling practices.Across the social sciencesother than economics and statistics, the word quasi-experiment is routinely used to justify causal inferences,even though designsso referred to are so primitive in structure that 'We causal conclusions are often problematic. have to challenge such advoc acy of low-grade quasi-experiments as a valid alternative to the quality of studies we have been calling for in this book. And finally in parts of statistics and epidemiology, and overwhelmingly in econometrics and those parts of sociology and political science that draw from econometrics,the emphasisis more on control through statistical manipulation than on experimental design.I7hen descriptive causal inferencesare the primary concern, all of these alternatives will usually be inferior to experiments. IntensiveQualitativeCaseStudies The call to generate causal conclusions from intensive case studies comes from several sources. One is from quantitative researchersin education who became disenchanted with the tools of their trade and subsequently came to prefer the qualitative methods of the historian and journalist and especiallyof the ethnographer (e.g.,Guba,198l, 1,990;and more tentatively Cronbach, 1986).Another is from those researchersoriginally trained in primary disciplines such as qualitative anthropology (e.g.,Fetterman, 19841or sociology (Patton, 1980). The enthusiasm for case study methods arises for several different reasons. One is that qualitative methods often reduce enough uncertainty about causation to meet stakeholderneeds.Most advocatespoint out that journalists,historians, ethnographers, and lay persons regularly make valid causal inferences using a qualitative processthat combines reasoning, observation, and falsificationist procedures in order to rule out threats to internal validity-even if that kind of language is not explicitly used (e.g.,Becker,1958; Cronbach,1982). A small minority of qualitative theorists go even further to claim that casestudiescan routinely replace experiments for nearly any causal-sounding question they can conceive (e.g.,Lincoln & Guba, 1985). A secondreasonis the belief that suchmethodscan also engagea broad view of causation that permits getting at the many forces in the world and human minds that together influence behavior in much more complex ways than any experiment will uncover.And the third reasonis the belief that case studies are broader than experiments in the types of information they yield. For example, they can inform readers about such useful and diverse matters as how pertinent problems were formulated by stakeholders, what the substantive theories of the intervention are, how well implemented the intervention components were, what distal, as well as proximal, effects have come about in respondents' lives, what unanticipated side effects there have been, and what processes explain the pattern of obtained results.The claim is that intensivecasestudy methods allow probes of an A to B connection, of a broad range of factors conditioning this relationship, and of a range of intervention-relevant questions that is broader than the experiment allows. I .J NONEXPERIMENTALALTERNATIVES | 501 I Although we agree that qualitative evidence can reduce some uncertainfy about cause-sometimes substantially the conditions under which this occurs are usually rare (Campbell, 1975).In particular, qualitative methods usually produce unclear knowledge about the counterfactual of greatest importance, how those who receivedtreatment would have changedwithout treatment. Adding design featuresto casestudies,such as comparison groups and pretreatmentobservations, clearly improves causal inference. But it does so by melding case-study data collection methods with experimental design.Although we consider this as a valuable addition ro ways of thinking about casestudies, many advocatesof the method would no longer recognize it as still being a case study. To our way of thinking, casestudies are very relevant when causation is at most a minor issue; but in most other caseswhen substantial uncertainry reduction about causation is required, we value qualitative methods within experiments rather than as alternatives to them, in ways similar to those we outlined in Chapter 12. Evaluations Theory-Based This approach has beenformulated relatively recently and is describedin various books or specialjournal issues(Chen & Rossi, 1,992;Connell, Kubisch, Schorr,& 'Weiss, 1.995;Rogers,Hacsi, Petrosino,& Huebner, 2000). Its origins are in path analysis and causal modeling traditions that are much older. Although advocates have some differenceswith each other, basically they all contend that it is useful: (1) to explicate the theory of a treatment by detailing the expected relationships among inputs, mediating pfocesses,and short- and long-term outcomes; (2) to measure all the constructs specified in the theory; and (3) to analyzethe data to assessthe extent to which the postulated relationships actually occurred. For shorter time periods, the available data may addressonly the first part of a postulated causal chain; but over longer periods the complete model could be involved. Thus, the priority is on highly specific substantive theorS high-quality measurement,and valid analysisof multivariate explanatory processesas they unfold in time (Chen & Rossi, 1'987,1,992). Such theoretical exploration is important. It can clarify general issueswith treatments of a particular type, suggestspecific researchquestions,describehow the intervention functions, spell out mediating processes,locate opportunities to remedy implementation failures, and provide lively anecdotesfor reporting results ('Weiss,1'998). All th.r. serveto increasethe knowledge yield, evenwhen such theoretical analysisis done within an experimental framework. There is nothing about the approach that makes it an alternative to experiments. It can clearly be a very important adjunct to such studies,and in this role we heartily endorsethe approach (Cook,2000). However, some authors (e.g., Chen 6c Rossi, 1,987, 1992; Connell et al., 1,995l have advocated theory-based evaluation as an attractive alternative to experiments when it comes to testing causal hypotheses.It is attractive for several i.urorrr. First, it requires only a treatment group' not a comparison group whose 502 | 14.A CRTT|CAL ASSESSMENT OFOURASSUMPTTONS agreement to be in the study might be problematic and whose participation increasesresearchcosts. Second, demonstrating a match between theory and data suggeststhe validity of the causal theory without having to go through a laborious processof explicitly considering alternative explanations. Third, it is often impractical to measure distant end points in a presumed causal chain. So confirmation of attaining proximal end points through theory-specified processescan be used in the interim to inform program staff about effectivenessto date, to argue for more program resourcesif the program seemsto be on theoretical track, to justify claims that the program might be effective in the future on the as-yet-notassesseddistant criteria, and to defend against premature summative evaluations that claim that an intervention is ineffective before it has been demonstrated that the processesnecessaryfor the effect have actually occurred. However, maior problems exist with this approach for high-quality descriptive causalinference(Cook, 2000). First, our experiencein writing about the theory of a program with its developer (Anson et al., 1,991)has shown that the theory is not always clear and could be clarified in diverse ways. Second, many theories are linear in their flow, omitting reciprocal feedback or external contingenciesthat might moderate the entire flow. Third, few theories specify how long it takes for a given processto affect an indicator, making it unclear if null results disconfirm a link or suggestthat the next step did not yet occur. Fourth, failure to corroborate a model could stem from partially invalid measuresas opposedto invalidity of the theory. Fifth, many different models can fit a data set (Glymour et a1.,1987;Stelzl, 1986), so our confidencein any given model may be small. Such problems are often fatal to an approach that relies on theory to make strong causal claims. Though some of theseproblems are present in experiments (e.g.,failure to incorporate reciprocal causation, poor measures),they are of far less import because experiments do not require a well-specified theory in constructing causal knowledge. Experimental causal knowledge is less ambitious than theory-based knowledge, but the more limited ambition is attainable. Weaker Quasi-Experi ments For some researchers,random assignment is undesirable for practical or ethical reasons, so they prefer quasi-experiments. Clearly, we support thoughtful use of quasi-experimentation to study descriptive causal questions. Both interrupted time series and regression discontinuity often yield excellent effect estimates. Slightly weaker quasi-experiments can also yield defensible estimates,especially when they involve control groups with careful matching on stable pretest attributes combined with other design features that have been thoughtfully chosen to addresscontextually plausible threats to validity. However, when a researchercan choose, randomized designsare usually superior to nonrandomized designs. This is especially true of nonrandomized designs in which little thought is given to such matters as the quality of the match when creating control groups, j NONEXPERIMENTALALTERNATIVES I tOl includingmultiple hypothesistestsrather than a singleone' generatingdata from severalpr.tr."t*.nt time points rather than one, or having severalcomparison groupsto createcontrolsthat bracketperformancein the treatmentgroups.Inare comparedwith thosefrom I..d, when resultsfrom typical quasi-experiments randomizedexperimentson the same topic, several findings emerge.Quasiexperimentsfrequentlymisestimateeffects(Heinsman& Shadish,1'996;Shadish & Ragsdale,t9961.Tiresebiasesare often large and plausiblydue to selectionbiof more distressedclientsinto psychotherapytreatasessrrchas the self-selection ment conditions(Shadishet al., 2000) or of patientswith a poorer prognosisinto controlsin medicalexperiments(Kunz & Oxman,1'9981.Thesebiasesare espethat usepoor quality control groupsand have cially prevalentin quasi-experiments 6cRagsdale,l996l.So,if the higheiattrition(Heinsmar$cShadish,'1,996;Shadish more crediblethan thosefrom obtainedfrom randomizedexperimentsare an"swers on theoreticalgroundsand are more accurateempirically,then quasi-experiments ,'h. ".g,.r-entsfor randomizedexperimentsare evenstrongerwhenevera high degr.. oI uncertaintyreductionis requiredabout a descriptivecausalclaim. are not equal in their ability to reduceuncerBecauseall quasi-experiments tainty about."ur., *. -"ttt to draw attention againto a common but unfortuis beingdone natepracticein manysocialsciences-tosaythat a quasi-experiment in order to provide justificationthat the resultinginferencewill be valid. Then a designis describedthat is so deficientin the desirablestrucquasi-experimental tural featuresnoted previously,which promote better inference,that it is probanoted the term bly not worth doing. Indeed,over the yearswe have__repeatedly biing usedto justify designsthat fell into the classthat Campquasi-experiment and that Cook and Campbell bell and'stanley(196i) labeledas uninterpretable Theseare the simplestforms of the generallyuninterpretable. (1,9791labeled'as cannot be an alternadesignsdiscussedin Chapters4 and 5. Quasi-experiments tive to randomizedexperimentswhen the latter are feasible,and poor quasi-exwhen_thelatperimentscan neverbi a substitutefor strongerquasi-experiments i., "r. also feasible.Just as Gueron (L999) has remindedus about randomized haveto be fought for, too. They are rarely experiments,good quasi-experiments handedout as though on a silverplate. StatisticalControls In this book,we haveadvocatedthat statisticaladjustmentsfor groupnonequivalence are best urrd oBt designcontrolshavealreadybeenusedto the maximum in order to a minimum. So we are not opponentsof statisticaladto reducenonequivalence justmenttechniquessuchasthoseadvocatedby the statisticiansand econometricians describedin the appendixto Chapter5. Ratheqwe want to usethem as the last resort.The positionwe do not like is the assumptionthat statisticalcontrolsare sowell developeithat they can be usedto obtain confidentresultsin nonexperimentaland weak iuasi-e*perimentalcontexts.As we saw in Chapter 5, researchin the past 2 504 | ta. a cRtTtcAL AsSEssMENT OFOURASSUMPT|ONS I decadeshas not much supported the notion that a control group can be constructed through matchingfrom somenational or state registrywhen the treatmentgroup comesfrom a morecircumscribedand localsetting.Nor hasresearchmuchsupported the useof statisticaladjustmentsin longitudinalnationalsurveysin which individuals with differentexperiences are explicitly contrastedin order to estimatethe effectsof this experiencedifference.Undermatchingis a chronic problem here,as are consequencesof unreliabilityin the selectionvariables,not to speakof specificationerrors dueto incompleteknowledgeof the selectionprocess.In particular,endogeneity prob'We lemsarea realconcern. areheartenedthat more recentwork on statisticaladjustmentsseemsto be moving toward the position we represent,with greateremphasis beingplacedon internal controls,on stablematchingwithin suchinternalcontrols, on the desirabilityof seekingcohort controlsthroughthe useof siblings,on the useof pretests sorrccf,e(Jon on the rne same same measures measures aS tne posttest, on the posttest, On the tne Uulrty utiliw Ot of SUCh suchpretest PrstssLs collected measures collected at several different times, and on the desirability of studying inter- 'We ventionsthat areclearlyexogenousshocksto someongoingsystem. arealsoheartenedby the progressbeingmadein the statisticaldomainbecause it includesprogress on designconsiderations, aswell ason analysisper se(e.g.,Rosenbaum,1999a).Ve areagnosticat this time asto the virtuesof the propensityscoreandinstrumentalvariable approachesthat predominatein discussionsof statisticaladiustmenr.Time will tell how well tell well they they pan out relative to the results from randomizedexperiments.'We have surely not heard the last word on this topic. CONCLUSION 'We cannot point to one new development that has revolutionized field experimentation in the past few decades,yet we have seena very large number of incremental improvements. As a whole, these improvements allow us to create far better field experiments than we could do 40 years ago when Campbell and Stanley (1963) first wrote. In this sense,we are very optimistic about the future. Ve believe that we will continue to see steadg incremental growth in our knowledge about how to do better field experiments. The cost of this growth, howeveq is that field experimentation has become a more specializedtopic, both in terms of knowledge developmentand of the opportunity to put that knowledge into practice in the conduct of field experiments. As a result, nonspecialistswho wish to do a field experiment may greatly benefit by consulting with those with the expertise,especiallyfor large experiments, for experiments in which implementation problems may be high, or for casesin which methodological vulnerabilities will greatly reducecredibility. The same is true, of course, for many other methods. Case-studymethods, for example, have become highly enough developed that most researcherswould do an amateurishjob of using them without specializedtraining or supervisedpractice. Such Balkanization of. methodolog)r is, perhaps, inevitable, though none the lessregrettable.\U7ecan easethe regret somewhat by recognizingthatwith specialization may come faster progress in solving the problems of field experimentation.