COMM 610 (Fall 2013): ACT: p. 1 COMM 610: SEMINAR IN ADVANCED COMMUNICATION THEORY (FALL 2013) “I think you should be a bit more explicit here in step two.” BRIAN H. SPITZBERG, Ph.D. Senate Distinguished Professor, San Diego State University COMM 610 (Fall 2013): ACT: p. 2 COMM 610: COMMUNICATION THEORY Professor Dr. Brian H. Spitzberg Semester Fall 2013 Office COMM BLDG 201 Schedule # 31824 Office Hours Tu &Th 10-11, Th 1-2, by Appt. Classroom COMM BLDG 209 Office Phone 619.594.7097 (email preferred) Mailbox COMM BLDG 237 E-mail spitz@mail.sdsu.edu Class Time Th 4-6:40 Text 1 Readings: A single set of hard-copy readings will be briefly checked out to the class, and the class will decide how to obtain their own personal copies. Syllabus Packet: Enormous work has gone into this packet with the intent that it serve as an ongoing resource to you in this course and beyond. The assignments and readings in it evolve over time, and there are occasional oversights or mistakes. It is therefore important that you: (a) print it out, (b) bring it to each class, (c) read through it at the beginning of the course and review it during the course, and (d) bring to the instructor’s attention any inconsistencies, confusions, or questions that arise. Axiom I: How we think about (theorize) the world has as much to do with what we (think we) know, as the methods we use to observe the world. Axiom II: The methods we use to observe the world are integrally related to the theories we use to think about the world. Axiom III: Theories are as much a tool (i.e., methodology) as are our observational procedures. Text 2 Objectives This course critically examines the role of theories and meta-theories in the progress of social science generally, and of communication theory specifically. It examines scholarly inquiry in light of (a) theory construction and evaluation, (b) evolution, social construction and accumulation of knowledge, and (c) influences of cultural, reflexive and anthropocentric biases (i.e., creating the world in our image). To obtain an advanced understanding of the nature and function of theories in the endeavors of communication as a social science and the investigation of the empirical world; To achieve an advanced comprehension of the tenets and comparative characteristics of communication-relevant theories and meta-theoretical perspectives; To demonstrate ability to analyze, synthesize, compare, contrast and create relevant theoretical literature and ideas. COMM 610 (Fall 2013): ACT: p. 3 COMM 610 SCHEDULE (SPRING 2013) Week 1 Date SP: ‘13 08-29 Topic Readings Course Orientation: A synoptic view of scholarship/science From Whence We Came: A Synoptic View of Scholarship Beauty in the eye of the beholder: What Theories Are, and What Makes Them Good After Theory: The Nature and Uses of MetaTheory “No Risk, No Gain?”: Justification, Verification, & Falsification of Theory Lewin's dictum: There is Nothing So Practical as a Good Theory (or is there?) Brother can you paradigm?: Paradigms and paradigm change Submit model papers Syllabus—read through prior to 1st class #1-5: Miller; Fuchs; HoyningenHuene; Berger; Craig #6-8: Sutton & Staw; Gregor; Spitzberg* (*: in syllabus) #9-11: Turner (x2); Wallis Assignments 2 09-05 3 09-12 4 09-19 5 09-26 6 10-03 7 10-10 8 10-17 9 10-24 10 10-31 11 11-07 12 11-14 Rose Colored Glasses: Traditional, Perceptual, Constructive, Postmodern Peeking at the Postmodern: Theory As Postmodern Process Deconstructing Theoretical Constructions: Scholarship as Text NCA: NO CLASS 13 11-21 THANKSGIVING: NO CLASS 14 11-28 15 12-05 16 12-12 Law of the Hammer?: Objective vs. Hermeneutic Empiricism Rescuing Realism: Patches & Parables VS. Life Is But a Game: The Politics of Scholarship Final Examination; Tuesday, 1900-2100 ** * These are recommended, but not required readings. ** NOTE: This is the final exam date! Tell your family, friends, and the people whose wedding you have to be in you cannot travel during this time on this date because it is scheduled as of the first day of class! JuxPo#1 #12-14: Popper (x 3) JuxPo#2 #15-17: Cohen; Sandelands; Alxeander & Colomy #18-20: Craig (x2); Anderson & Baym *: Spitzberg & Chagnon JuxPo#3 #21-22: Kuhn; Laudan et al. JuxPo#4 #23-24: Feyerabend; Lloyd #25-28: Gergen (x3); Ritzer et al. Model Synopsis #29-31: Greewald; Wallach & Wallach; Jost et al. #32-34: Bostrom & Donohew; Gilman; Chow JuxPo#5 Proposition Paper Final Exam COMM 610 (Fall 2013): ACT: p. 4 Assignment Overview Grade Scale Late Work Incompletes Juxtaposition Essays—Formulate juxtapositions of ideas, concepts, arguments, contradictions, quotes, or theoretical implications from five sets of readings during the semester. The schedule indicates the dates by which a minimum of these juxtapositions must have been completed. The specific requirements of this assignment in this syllabus packet, along with the grading rubric. (2 juxtapositions at 25 points each = 50 points). You get to choose which five weeks of the semester you will present on, but the instructor will solicit a distribution of presenters so that every week should have at least a few presenters. The juxtapositions will be presented as oral presentations toward the beginning of the class as a stimulus to conversation and debate. You are expected to treat these as oral presentations; thus, clarity and persuasiveness of presentation is taken into account. In other words, “wing it at your own risk!” [50 points] Model Synopsis—This paper will be no more than 5 pages, doublespaced, not including the model diagram, title page or references. The purpose of the paper is to present a first draft of a model that will be integrated into the final “Model and Proposition” paper. Text will explain the model, with supporting references. [50 points] Model and Proposition Paper—Develop a visual model of a process or phenomenon in which human communication plays a central role, and codify the theoretical knowledge claims that extend from that model in the form of axioms, theorems, hypotheses, and/or propositions. Length: 20-25 pages (not including title page, abstract, references, model, or tables. [100 points] Final Exam: Essay Examination—A take-home examination about the nature, function, scope, evolution, and utility of (1) theory; (2) paradigms; (3) meta-theory; and (4) alternatives to regnant paradigms and theories. [100 points] * Grades are based on a total point system, in which ‘a point is a point, is a point’. Letter grades are assigned based on .60, .70, .80, .90 main cuts, with .x3, and .x7 mid-grade cuts. There is no normative curving. A = 282-300 B+ = 261-269 C = 000-239 A - = 270-281 B = 249-260 B- = 240-248 Any paper turned in late will be reduced 10 points per weekday that passes beyond the scheduled due date, excepted only for university or professor recognized excuses. The credibility of excuse will depend in part on diligence in apprising the instructor of the situation. In all instances in which an assignment is late, an email should be sent to the instructor as soon as possible, with a Word version of the assignment attached. An “I” grade is assigned when a student cannot meet a clearly identifiable portion of course requirements within the academic term for unforeseen reasons. An incomplete is not provided because a course or schedule is too COMM 610 (Fall 2013): ACT: p. 5 difficult or because time was not managed sufficiently. Overview SDSU Definitions THE ACADEMIC DISHONESTY POLICY OF THE SCHOOL OF COMMUNICATION In any case in which an instructor identifies evidence for charging a student with violation of academic conduct standards or plagiarism, the presumption will be with that instructor’s determination. The instructor(s) will confer with the School Director to confirm the evidence. Once confirmed, the student will be informed and presented with the evidence. Some conditions and terms below clarify the School policy and procedure. “Cheating: Cheating is defined as the act of obtaining or attempting to obtain credit for academic work by the use of dishonest, deceptive, or fraud- ulent means. Examples of cheating include, but are not limited to copying, in part or in whole, from another's test or other examination; discussing answers or ideas relating to the answers on a test or other examination without the permission of the instructor; obtaining copies of a test, an examination, or other course material without the permission of the instructor; using notes, cheat sheets, or other devices considered inappropriate under the prescribed testing condition; collaborating with another or others in work to be presented without the permission of the instructor; falsifying records, laboratory work, or other course data; submitting work previously presented in another course, if contrary to the rules of the course; altering or interfering with the grading procedures; plagiarizing, as defined; and knowingly and intentionally assisting another student in any of the above. Plagiarism: Plagiarism is defined as the act of incorporating ideas, words, or specific substance of another, whether purchased, borrowed, or otherwise obtained, and submitting same to the university as one's own work to fulfill academic requirements without giving credit to the appropriate source. Plagiarism shall include but not be limited to: submitting work, either in part or in whole, completed by another; omitting footnotes for ideas, statements, facts, or conclusions that belong to another; omitting quotation marks when quoting directly from another, whether it be a paragraph, sentence, or part thereof; close and lengthy paraphrasing of the writings of another; submitting another person's artistic works, such as musical compositions, photographs, paintings, drawings, or sculptures; and submitting as one's own work papers purchased from research companies.” (source: http://www.sa.sdsu.edu/srr/cheating-plagiarism.html) COMM 610 (Fall 2013): ACT: p. 6 Intellectual contents Intellectual contents include all forms of ‘text’ produced by another person or persons. It includes: writings, course syllabi, course lectures and recordings of lectures, visual information such as models, videos, lyrics, software, etc. Intellectual The syllabus, lectures and lecture outlines are personally-copyrighted Property intellectual property of the instructor, which means that any organized recording for anything other than personal use, duplication, distribution, or profit is a violation of copyright and fair use laws. Proper source Proper attribution occurs by specifying the source of content or ideas. This is attribution done by (a) providing quotation marks around text, when directly quoted, and (b) clearly designating the source of the text or information relied upon in an assignment. Self-plagiarism Students often practice some form of ‘double-dipping,’ in which they write on a given topic across more than one course assignment. In general, there is nothing wrong with double-dipping topics or sources, but there is a problem with double-dipping exact and redundant text. It is common for scholars to write on the same topic across many publication outlets; this is part of developing expertise and the reputation of being a scholar on a topic. Scholars, however, are not permitted to repeat exact text across papers or publications except when noted and attributed, as this wastes precious intellectual space with repetition and does a disservice to the particular source of original presentation by ‘diluting’ the value of the original presentation. Any time that a writer simply ‘cuts-and-pastes’ exact text from former papers into a new paper without proper attribution, it is a form of selfplagiarism. Consequently, a given paper should never be turned in to multiple classes. Entire paragraphs, or even sentences, should not be repeated wordfor-word across course assignments. Each new writing assignment is precisely that, a new writing assignment, requiring new composition on the student’s part. Solicitation for Any student who solicits any third party to write any portion of an assignment ghost writing for this class (whether for pay or not) violates the standards of academic honesty. The penalty for solicitation (regardless of whether it can be demonstrated the individual solicited wrote any sections of the assignment) is F in the course and the student will be reported to Student Rights and Responsibilities. COMM 610 (Fall 2013): ACT: p. 7 Secondary citations Useful Aides Secondary citation is not strictly a form of plagiarism, but in blatant forms, it can present similar ethical challenges. A secondary citation is citing source A, which in turn cites source B, but it is source B’s ideas or content that provide the unique basis for the claims the student intends to make in the assignment. For example, assume there is an article by Jones (2006) in the student’s hands, in which there is a discussion or quotation of an article by Smith (1998). Assume further that what Smith seems to be saying is very important to the student’s analysis. In such a situation, the student should always try to locate the original Smith source. In general, if an idea is important enough to discuss in an assignment, it is important enough to locate and cite the original source for that idea. There are several reasons for these policies: (a) Authors sometimes commit citation errors, which might be replicated without knowing it; (b) Authors sometimes make interpretation errors, which might be ignorantly reinforced (c) Therefore, reliability of scholarly activity is made more difficult to assure and enforce; (d) By relying on only a few sources of review, the learning process is short-circuited, and the student’s own research competencies are diminished, which are integral to any liberal education; (e) By masking the actual sources of ideas, readers must second guess which sources come from which citations, making the readers’ own research more difficult; (f) By masking the origin of the information, the actual source of ideas is misrepresented. Some suggestions that assist with this principle: When the ideas Jones discusses are clearly attributed to, or unique to, Smith, then find the Smith source and citation. When the ideas Jones is discussing are historically associated more with Smith than with Jones, then find the Smith source and citation. In contrast, Jones is sometimes merely using Smith to back up what Jones is saying and believes, and is independently qualified to claim, whether or not Smith would have also said it; in such a case, citing Jones is sufficient. Never simply copy a series of citations at the end of a statement by Jones, and reproduce the reference list without actually going to look up what those references report—the only guarantee that claims are valid is for a student to read the original sources of those claims. A good place to learn about plagiarism is the tutorial on academic integrity at http://plagiarism.org/plagiarism-101/overview/; and at http://www.yorku.ca/tutorial/academic_integrity/caseintro.html A good place to learn about APA writing and citation style is: http://owl.english.purdue.edu/owl/resource/560/01/ A good place to learn about making better arguments is: http://www.readwritethink.org/files/resources/interactives/persuasion_map/ COMM 610 (Fall 2013): ACT: p. 8 TurnItIn.com The papers in this course will be submitted electronically in Word (preferably 2007, .docx) on the due dates assigned, and will require verification of submission to Turnitin.com. “Students agree that by taking this course all required papers may be subject to submission for textual similarity review to TurnItIn.com for the detection of plagiarism. All submitted papers will be included as source documents in the TurnItIn.com reference database solely for the purpose of detecting plagiarism of such papers. You may submit your papers in such a way that no identifying information about you is included. Another option is that you may request, in writing, that your papers not be submitted to TurnItIn.com. However, if you choose this option you will be required to provide documentation to substantiate that the papers are your original work and do not include any plagiarized material” (source: language suggested by the CSU General Counsel and approved by the Center for Student’s Rights and Responsibilities at SDSU). Consequences Course failure: Soliciting or reproducing a whole paper, paragraph, or of Plagiarism or large portions of unattributed materials without proper attribution, Cheating whether represented by: (a) multiple sentences, images, or portions of images; or (b) by percentage of assignment length, will result in assignment of an “F” in the course in which the infraction occurred, and a report to the Center for Student Rights and Responsibilities (CSRR2). Assignment failure: Reproducing a sentence or sentence fragment with no quotation marks, but with source citation, or subsets of images without source attribution, will minimally result in an “F” on the assignment, and may result in greater penalty, including a report to the CSRR, depending factors noted below. In this instance, an “F” may mean anything between a zero (0) and 50%, depending on the extent of infraction. Exacerbating conditions—Amount: Evidence of infraction, even if fragmentary, is increased with a greater: (a) number of infractions; (b) distribution of infractions across an assignment; or (c) proportion of the assignment consisting of infractions. Exacerbating conditions—Intent: Evidence of foreknowledge and intent to deceive magnifies the seriousness of the offense and the grounds for official response. Plagiarism, whether ‘by accident’ or ‘by ignorance,’ still qualifies as plagiarism—it is all students’ responsibility to make sure their assignments are not committing the offense. Assistance: Evidence that the student was not the original author of the work, due to soliciting the assistance or composition of another person or persons. Exceptions: Any exceptions to these policies will be considered on a caseby-case basis, and only under exceptional circumstances. HOWEVER, THERE ARE NO EXCUSES ALLOWED BASED ON IGNORANCE OF WHAT CONSTITUTES PLAGIARISM, OR OF WHAT THIS POLICY IS The School of Communication, as a representative of SDSU and higher education, Comportment expects students to engage in behavior that enhances the classroom learning environment. The Instructor is responsible not only to the individual student, but to COMM 610 (Fall 2013): ACT: p. 9 the collective group of students who constitute a class. This means that behavior disruptive to the classroom instruction is not tolerated. For the sake of the other students, the instructor may be required to intervene under various circumstances. Among the actions that are considered disruptive to the learning environment are: The use of cellphones and/or computers/laptops/tablets, whether for conversation, correspondence, emailing, texting, tweeting, or other activities (e.g., social media/Facebook), and when not directly related to the course and its instructional objectives, materials, or contents; Side conversations or discussion in a manner distracting to the instructor or fellow students; Ongoing or unrestricted interruption of instructor or fellow students, or otherwise attempting to monopolize classroom time or discussion; Reading, sleeping, snoring, moving about, yelling, harassing, bullying, or otherwise engaging in activities disrespectful of the instructor or students, or unrelated to the course, materials, or contents; Entering late, leaving early, or leaving often during lecture, especially when in a disruptive manner; Activity that in any way could be considered grossly inappropriate, threatening or dangerous. Certain other activities may be acceptable, but only with permission or by direction of the Instructor, who retains the authority to specify relevant restrictions. Such activities include: Filming, taping, or otherwise recording the class; Accessing the Internet during class; Use of computers/laptops/tablets may be permitted, but only if the students are seated in the front row(s) of the classroom. The Instructor reserves the right to establish additional reasonable expectations deemed necessary to maintain optimal learning conduct in the classroom. Each faculty member is the primary arbiter of classroom comportment. The faculty member has the authority to enforce this policy in a manner deemed suitable to the particular class in question. For example a student texting in class may be requested to turn the phone in to the instructor for the remainder of the class, or a student using a laptop or IPAD to access Facebook may be asked to close and shut down the technology for the remainder of the period. Should repeat offenses occur, with fair warning, each faculty member will determine fair and appropriate consequences for these behaviors. Should an emergency occur or require monitoring, or if students observe violations of this policy, they are encouraged to inform the instructor as soon as possible. Finally, all students are governed by the SDSU policy on cheating and plagiarism. See their coda at: http://csrr.sdsu.edu/cheating-plagiarism.html COMM 610 (Fall 2013): ACT: p. 10 THIS IS SERIOUS! PLAGIARISM IS A CRIME OF CONDUCT, NOT OF INTENT. THIS COURSE WILL HAVE ZERO-TOLERANCE FOR PLAGIARISM! WHY? BECAUSE: 1. A PLAGIARISM POLICY IS PUBLISHED IN THE UNIVERSITY CATALOG; 2. THE SCHOOL OF COMMUNICATION PLAGIARISM POLICY, COMPLETE WITH ELABORATED EXAMPLES, DEFINITIONS, AND CONSEQUENCES FOR TYPES OF PLAGIARISM, IS: a. ON THE SCHOOL OF COMMUNICATION BLACKBOARD SITE, b. ON THE SCHOOL OF COMMUNICATION WEBSITE, AND c. IN THE COURSE SYLLABUS; 3. A POWERPOINT LECTURE PRESENTED IN THIS COURSE ON “THE ESSENTIALS” FURTHER SPECIFIES THE NATURE OF PLAGIARISM; 4. YOU CAN TURN IN YOUR PAPER BEFORE IT IS DUE, SEE ITS ORIGINALITY RATING, FIX IT, AND TURN IT IN AGAIN BY SUBMISSION DEADLINE; 5. FINALLY, YOU SHOULD SIMPLY KNOW THAT IT IS UNETHICAL AND A ‘HIGH CRIME’ IN ACADEME TO MISREPRESENT ANYONE’S WORDS OR IDEAS, THROUGH IMPLICATION, WHETHER INTENDED OR NOT, a. THAT THEY ARE YOUR OWN, OR b. THEY ARE SOMEONE ELSE’S WHEN THEY ARE NOT. A final analogy: If you are taking a driving test to get a license, And you run a stop sign while the instructor is in the car, You fail the test then and there, and must wait for an opportunity to re-take the exam another time. So it is with plagiarism. THEREFORE, THERE IS NO EXCUSE FOR PLAGIARISM, AND NO EXCUSE WILL BE ACCEPTED. YOU ARE FOREWARNED. IF YOU PLAGIARIZE, YOU WILL FAIL THIS COURSE. COMM 610 (Fall 2013): ACT: p. 11 Source: http://plagiarism.org/plagiarism-101/overview COMM 610 (Fall 2013): ACT: p. 12 A FEW TIDBITS ABOUT SCIENCE AND THEORY “Both science and art have to do with ordered complexity.” Lancelot Law White, The Griffin, 1957 (in Kaplan: Science says) “The aims of scientific thought are to see the general in the particular and the eternal in the transitory.” A. N. Whitehead, Dictionary of scientific quotations (Mackay) “Common sense provides a kind of ultimate validation after science has completed its work; it seldom anticipates what science is going to discover” R. L. Ackoff, Decision making in national science policy, 1968 (in Kaplan: Science says) “It would be interesting to inquire how many times essential advances in science have first been made possible by the fact that the boundaries of special disciplines were not respected….Trespassing is one of the most successful techniques in science.” W. Köhler, Dynamics in psychology, 1940 (in Kaplan: Science says) “Beware of the problem of testing too many hypotheses; the more you torture the data, the more likely they are to confess, but confessions obtained under duress may not be admissible in the course of scientific opinion.” S. M. Stigler, in Nitecki & Hoffman, Neutral models in biology, (in Kaplan: Science says) “No one believes an hypothesis except its originator, but everyone believes an experiment except the experimenter.” W. I. B. Beveridge, The art of scientific investigation, (in Kaplan: Science says) Q: “Do you feel that scientists correct themselves as often as they should?” “More often than politicians, but not as often as they should.” Stephen Hawking (D. Solomon, New York Times Syndicate, SDU-T, Wed., 1.12.05.F10) “there are known knowns; there are things we know we know. We also know there are known unknowns; that is to say we know there are some things we do not know. But there are also unknown unknowns—the ones we don’t know we don’t know…. It is the latter category that tend[s] to be the difficult one” A political Haiku by Donald Rumsfeld, Economist, Dec. 6, 2003, p. 28 COMM 610 (Fall 2013): ACT: p. 13 “Ideas and theories become popular or unpopular at a certain time not because they are more or less ‘true’ but because the value systems that support them are activated or suppressed by ecological and institutional developments” (Hofstede, 1980, p. 323) “Admissions of ignorance and temporary mystifications are vital to good science” (Dawkins, The God delusion, 2006, p. 126) “Theories become clear and ‘reasonable’ only after incoherent parts of them have been used for a long time. Such unreasonable, nonsensical, unmethodological foreplay thus turns out to be an unavoidable precondition of clarity and empirical success. … Without a constant misuse of language there cannot be any discovery and any progress” (Feyerabend, Against method, p. 25) “Science is organized knowledge” Herbert Spencer “Science is built upon facts, as a house is built of stones; but an accumulation of facts is no more science than a heap of stones is a house” Henri Poincare “The aim of science is not to open the door to infinite wisdom, But to set a limit to infinite error” Bertolt Brecht “It is the customary fate of new truths to begin as heresies and to end as superstitions” Aldous Huxley “ignorance is never better than knowledge” Enrico Fermi “The ink of the scholar is more sacred than the blood of the martyr. Mohammed (570-632) COMM 610 (Fall 2013): ACT: p. 14 BACKGROUND APPETIZERS Professor’s note: For the ambitious—the following are nice overviews of some of the basic issues we will eventually get to in this course, from a perspective of philosophy of science (as opposed to the perspective of the communication discipline per se). These are not required readings, but if you feel the need or desire for “background” readings, these would be good to find. Klemke, E. D., Hollinger, R., & Kline, A. D. (1980). What is philosophy of science? In E. D. Klemke, R. Hollinger, & A. D. Kline (Eds.), Introductory readings in the philosophy of science (pp. 1-18). Buffalo, NY: Prometheus. Knorr Cetina, K. (1999). Epistemic cultures. London: Oxford University Press. Lakatos, I., & Feyerabend, P. (1999). For and against method (M. Motterlini, Ed.). Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Machlup, F. (1994). Are the social sciences really inferior? In M. Martin & L. C. McIntyre (Eds.), Readings in the philosophy of social science (pp. 5-19). Cambridge, MA: Bradford/MIT Press. [originally: Machlup, F. (1961). Are the social sciences really inferior? Southern Economic Journal, 17, 173-184] Tauber, A. I. (Ed.). (1997). Science and the quest for reality. Washington Square, NY: New York University Press. "Scientists make their fame on variance explained, but it's error variance that keeps careers sustained." B. Spitzberg (2007) “Science is a subtle and ongoing dance between an empirical world, and the ideas and symbols we use to comprehend that world; theory is the music, and methodology the choreography, by which the dance proceeds” B. H. Spitzberg, 2010 COMM 610 (Fall 2013): ACT: p. 15 WEEK I: ORIENTATION A SYNOPTIC VIEW OF SCHOLARSHIP/SCIENCE “Granting the existence of a discernible regularity in the phenomena being studied, it is conceivable, too, that some day the gravitational formula would have been discovered even if it had escaped Newton. None of this can be said of a sonata of Beethoven’s or a play of Shakespeare’s, or for that matter, of a history of Thucydides. These possess a uniqueness not characteristics of the discoveries of science” (Prior, Science and the humanities). “scientific truth has always contained an overwhelming difference from theological truth: it is provisional. … Science, unlike orthodox theology, has been capable of continuous, evolutionary growth. As Phaedrus had written on one of his slips, ‘The pencil is mightier than the pen.’” Robert A. Pirsig, Lila: An inquiry into morals, p. 222. “A new scientific truth does not triumph by convincing opponents and making them see the light, but rather because its opponents eventually die, and a new generation grows up that is familiar with it.” Max Planck, A scientific autobiography and other papers, 1949 Recommended: Altman, I., & Rogoff, B. (1987). World views in psychology: Trait, interactional, organismic, and transactional perspectives. In D. Stokols & I. Altman (Eds.), Handbook of environmental psychology (pp. 7-40). New York: John Wiley & Sons. Bochner, A. P. (2008, Oct.). Perspectives on theory and theorizing (colloquy). Spectra, 44 (9), 3-4, 10. Cronen, V. E. & Davis, L. K. (1978). Alternative approaches for the communication theorist: Problems in the laws-rules-systems trichotomy. Human Communication Research, 4, 120-128. Cushman, D. P. & Pearce, W. B. (1977). Generality and necessity in three types of theory about human communication, with special attention to rules theory. Human Communication Research, 3, 344-353. Gergen, K. J. & Morawski, J. (1980). An alternative metatheory for social psychology. In L. Wheeler (Ed.), Review of personality and social psychology (Vol. 1, pp. 326-352). Beverly Hills, CA: Sage. Nass, C. I., & Reeves, B. (1991). Combining, distinguishing, and generating theories in communication: A domains of analysis framework. Communication Research, 18, 240-261. Rosengren, K. E. (1989). Paradigms lost and regained. In B. Dervin, L. Grossberg, B. J. O'Keefe, & E. Wartella (Eds.), Rethinking communication (Vol. 1: Paradigm issues, pp. 21-39). Newbury Park, CA: Sage. Smith, T. J., III (1988). Diversity and order in communication theory: The uses of philosophical analysis. Communication Quarterly, 36, 28-40. COMM 610 (Fall 2013): ACT: p. 16 WEEK II: FROM WHENCE WE CAME: A SYNOPTIC VIEW OF SCHOLARSHIP "Those who cannot remember the past are condemned to fulfill it." G. Santayana "Some education in meta-theoretic thinking can be prophylactic for all of us." Meehl, 1993, p.720 “Our city of intellectual possibilities includes many mansions, and restriction to one great house will keep us walled off from much of nature’s truth” Stephen Jay Gould, Lying stones of Marrakech, 2000, p. 163 “Fields of learning are surrounded ultimately only by illusory boundaries— like the “rooms” in a hall of mirrors. It is when the illusion is penetrated that progress takes place.” W. S. Beck, Modern science and the nature of life, 1957, (in Kaplan: Science says) Differentiating Science, Humanities, and Religion as Ways of Knowing: (1) Miller, G. R. (1975). Humanistic and scientific approaches to speech communication inquiry: Rivalry, redundancy, or rapprochement. Western Speech Communication, 39, 230-239. (2) Fuchs, S. (2001). What makes sciences “scientific”? In J. H. Turner (Ed.), Handbook of sociological theory (pp. 21-35). New York: Kluwer Academic/Plenum. (3) Hoyningen-Huene, P. (2008). Systematicity: The nature of science. Philosophia, 36, 167-180. Assessing the Theoretical Status of the Communication Discipline (4) Berger, C. R. (1991). Communication theories and other curios. Communication Monographs, 58, 101-113. (5) Craig, R. T. (1993). Why are there so many communication theories? Journal of Communication, 43, 26-33. *Spitzberg—“Islands of Inquiry” (see end of syllabus for manuscript) Also (highly) recommended: Berger, C. R. (1992). Curiouser and curiouser curios. Communication Monographs, 59, 101-107. Bowman, J. P., & Targowski, S. S. (1987). Modeling the communication process: The map is not the territory. Journal of Business Communication, 24, 21-34. Burleson, B. R. (1992). Taking communication seriously. Communication Monographs, 59, 79-86. Donsbach, W. (2006). The identity of communication research. Journal of Communication, 56, 437-448. Eadie, W. F. (2009). Communication as a field and as a discipline. In W. F. Eadie (Ed.), 21st century communication: A reference handbook (pp. 12-21). Los Angeles, CA: Sage. Jiménez, L. G., & Guillem, S. M. (2009). Does communication studies have an identity? Setting the bases for contemporary research. Catalan Journal of Communication & Cultural Studies, 1, 1527. Powers, J. H. (1995). On the intellectual structure of the human communication discipline. Communication Education, 44, 191-222. COMM 610 (Fall 2013): ACT: p. 17 Proctor, R. (1992). Preserving the tie that binds: A response to Berger's essay. Communication Monographs, 59, 98-100. Purcell, B. (1992). Are there so few communication theories? Communication Monographs, 59, 94-97. Redding, C. (1992). Response to Professor Berger's Essay: Its meaning for organizational communication. Communication Monographs, 59, 87-93. Shields, D. C., & Cragan, J. F. (1998). Are there really so few communication theories? The joys of hindsight and the benefit of foresight. Paper presented at the Central States Communication Association Conference, Chicago, IL. Stanfill, M. (2012). Finding birds of a feather: Multiple memberships and diversity without divisiveness in communication research. Communication Theory, 22, 1-24. Also Recommend: Cohen, H. (1985). The development of research in speech communication: A historical perspective. In W. T. Benson (Ed.), Speech communication in the 20th century (pp. 282-298). Carbondale, IL: Southern Illinois University. Delia, J. G. (1987). Communication research: A history. In C. R. Berger & S. H. Chaffee (Eds.), Handbook of communication science (pp. 20-98). Newbury Park, CA: Sage. Farrell, T. B. (1987). Beyond science: Humanities contributions to communication theory. In C. R. Berger & S. H. Chaffee (Eds.), Handbook of communication science (pp. 123-139). Newbury Park: Sage. Geertz, C. (1980). Blurred genres: The refiguration of social thought. American Scholar, 49, 165182. Golden, J. L. (1987). Contemporary trends and historical roots in communication. A personal view. Central States Speech Journal, 38, 262-270. Leff, M. C., & Procario, M. O. (1985). Rhetorical theory in speech communication. In T. W. Benson (Ed.), Speech communication in the 20th century (pp. 3-27). Carbondale, IL: Southern Illinois University. Littlejohn, S. W. (1982). An overview of contributions to human communication theory from other disciplines. In F.E.X. Dance (Ed.), Human communication theory: Comparative essays (pp. 243-285). New York: Harper & Row. Pearce, W. B. (1985). Scientific research methods in communication studies and their implications for theory and research. In T. W. Benson (Ed.), Speech communication in the 20th century (pp. 255-281). Carbondale, IL: Southern Illinois University. Focus Questions: 1. What, if anything, differentiates a "school," a "discipline," a “perspective,” an "invisible college," and a paradigm? 2. What is the utility of academic disciplines? 3. Defend the position that "communication" either should be, or should not be, a discipline on the same level of prestige as psychology, sociology, philosophy, anthropology, etc. 4. What, if anything, in our history differentiates the discipline of communication from other more recognized disciplines? 5. What makes something scientific, and what makes something humanistic? Are these useful distinctions, and why or why not? 6. Are the “questions asked” really different from, and better than, “the methods used” in differentiating the sciences from the humanities? Why or why not? COMM 610 (Fall 2013): ACT: p. 18 Rhetorical Criticism as Theoretical “too many rhetorical critics in the past have forthrightly, but perhaps unwisely, rejected their obligations to tease theory from their research… the field of speech communication is, to that extent, the poorer. I … argue three points: (1) that a pronounced concern for theory could redirect some of our typical approaches to rhetorical criticism, (2) that properly conceived generic criticism must, by its nature, (2) fully respond to this call for theory-building, and (3) that rhetorical critics should encourage the work of desriptivists as well as that of judgmentalists.” Hart, R. P. (1976). CSSJ, 27, 70-77) Turtles & Theories: Dimitri: Tasso: Dimitri: Tasso: Dimitri: Tasso: If Atlas holds up the world, what hold up Atlas? Atlas stands on the back of a turtle. But what does the turtle stand on? Another turtle. And what does that turtle stand on? My dear Dimitri, it’s turtles all the way down! Rationality: “There is no such thing as absolute rationality; there are different rationalities colored by different culturally influenced values, and your rationality differs from mine; while there is no standard to determine which of the two is more ‘rational’” (Hofstede, 1980, p. 323) COMM 610 (Fall 2013): ACT: p. 19 WEEK III: BEAUTY IN THE EYE OF THE BEHOLDER: IDENTIFYING & EVALUATING THEORIES "Still the most satisfactory way of appraising the status ... of any science, is in terms of an inventory of its theories" D. Martindale “the mark of a high quality theory. It doesn’t just answer the question in some complex round-about way. It dissolves the question, so you wonder why you ever asked it” R. A. Pirsig, Lila: An inquiry into morals, p. 161. (6) (7) (8) Sutton, R. I., & Staw, B. M. (1995). What theory is not. Administrative Science Quarterly, 40 (3), 371-384. Gregor, S. (2006). The nature of theory in information systems. MIS Quarterly, 30(3), 611642. Spitzberg, B. H. (2000). “In theory”: On defining and evaluating theory. Abstracted, adapted and expanded from: Spitzberg, B. H. (2001). The status of attribution theory qua theory in personal relationships. In V. Manusov & J. H. Harvey (Eds.), Attribution, communication behavior, and close relationships (pp. 353-371). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Also recommended: Cornelissen, J. P. (2006). Making sense of theory construction: Metaphor and disciplined imagination. Organization Studies (01708406), 27(11), 1579-1597. doi:10.1177/0170840606068333 Pavitt, C. (2000). Answering questions requesting scientific explanations for communication. Communication Theory, 10, 379-404. Penman, R. (1992). Good theory and good practice: An argument in progress. Communication Theory, 2, 234-250. Witkin, S. L., & Gottschalk, S. (1988). Alternative criteria for theory evaluation. Social Service Review, 62, 211-224. Guetzkow, J., Lamont, M., & Mallad, G. (2004). What is originality in the humanities and the social sciences? American Sociological Review, 69, 190-212. Focus Questions: 1. Develop and defend a set of criteria for the evaluation of theory quality. 2. To what extent is theory evaluation and development a rational or social enterprise? Elaborate. 3. Make specific suggestions to enhance the comparative evaluation of theories. “Science is preeminently a rational activity, even though some irrational elements play a role.” Cohen (2003, p. 6) “Theorizing is only a semirational activity” (Hofstede, 1980, p. 323) COMM 610 (Fall 2013): ACT: p. 20 WEEK IV: MYTHS, MODELS, AND VISUALIZING THE WORLD AS (WE THINK) IT IS "Historically speaking all – or very nearly all – scientific theories originate from myths." K. Popper “The ultimate question in the evaluation of any theory is: What can I do with it?” J. A. Anderson, Communication theory: Epistemological foundations, p. 220. “all exciting science must be obsolescent from inception” S. J. Gould, 1995, Dinosaur in a haystack, p. 387. (9) Turner, J.H. (1985). In defense of positivism. Sociological Theory, 3, 24-30. (10) Turner, J.H. (1990). The misuse and use of metatheory. Sociological Forum, 5, 37-53. (11) Wallis, S. E. (2010). Toward a science of metatheory. Integral Review, 6, 73-120. Also recommended: Eysenck, H. J. (1987). "There is nothing more practical than a good theory" (Kurt Lewin)—True or false? In W. J. Baker, M. E. Hyland, H. Van Rappard, & A. W. Staats (Eds.), Current issues in theoretical psychology (pp. 49-64). North Holland: Elsevier Science. Stamp, G. H. (1999). A qualitatively constructed interpersonal communication model: A grounded theory analysis. Human Communication Research, 25, 531-547. Deetz, S. (2008). Engagement as co-generative theorizing. Journal of Applied Communication Research, 36, 289-297. Shields, D. C. (2000). Symbolic convergence and special communication theories: Sensing and examining dis/enchantment with the theoretical robustness of critical autoethnography. Communication Monographs, 67, 392-421. Soulliere, D., Britt, D. W., & Maines, D. R. (2001). Conceptual modeling as a toolbox for grounded theorists. Sociological Quarterly, 42, 253-269. Focus Questions: 1. Discuss the value of "grand" theorizing (i.e., the effort to develop more and more encompassing theories), as opposed to more midrange or "grounded" theoretical endeavors. 2. What could Sandelands mean by: “Causation cannot be explained, it must simply be understood. Causes do not have reasons” (p. 242)? 3. What are the possibilities for developing practical theory in communication? 4. Discuss the implications of the pejorative phrase "the ivory tower." Why has it been attached to academic work and to what extent is it deserved? Do you really believe that the sciences would ever have originated and grown if the way had not been prepared by magicians, alchemists, astrologers and witches whose promises and pretensions first had to create a thirst, a hunger, a taste for hidden and forbidden powers? Indeed, infinitely more had to be promised than could ever be fulfilled in order that anything at all might be fulfilled in the realms of knowledge. COMM 610 (Fall 2013): ACT: p. 21 Friedrich Nietzsche (in Thiessen, A sociobiology compendium, 1998) WEEK V: “NO RISK, NO GAIN”: JUSTIFICATION, VERIFICATION, & FALSIFICATION OF THEORY “The great tragedy of science—the slaying of a beautiful hypothesis by an ugly fact.” T. H. Huxley. Biogenesis and asiogenesis. Collected essays. 1893. "It is easy to obtain confirmations, or verifications, for nearly every theory – if we look for confirmations." K. Popper “Science is a long history of learning how not to fool ourselves.” R. Feynman (in Kaplan: Science says) (12) Popper, K. (1974). The problem of demarcation. In D. Miller (Ed.), Popper selections (pp. 118-130). Princeton, NJ: Princeton University. (13) Popper (1960). The growth of scientific knowledge. In D. Miller (Ed.), Popper selections (pp. 171-180). Princeton, NJ: Princeton University. (14) Popper, K. (1980). Science: Conjectures and refutations. In E. D. Klemke, R. Hollinger, & A. D. Kline (Eds.), Introductory readings in the philosophy of science (pp. 19-34). Buffalo, NY: Prometheus. “it is always possible to save a theory even in the face of disconfirmation Or to question a theory even in the face of supporting observational evidence… As a consequence, we are unable to argue that our theories are true, Or even that they have not been falsified” Cohen, 2003, p. 10 Science, from a Popperian perspective, is not about the process of confirmation through observation, because no amount of observation (i.e., induction, inference) can legitimately confirm a proposition (because there can never be enough observations of every instance of something, and the as yet unobserved instances might not conform to the proposition). Furthermore, propositions phrased in so vague, ambivalent, or general manner as to make the possibility of disconfirmation impossible are also not scientific. Such approaches are “pseudoscientific.” However, propositions phrased in such ways that they can be disconfirmed through observation are scientific (Spitzberg, 2002). The statement “Competent communicators are more satisfying conversationalists” cannot be proven because not competent communicators or conversations can be observed. It can, however, be disproven by a single observation of a competent communicator producing a dissatisfying conversation. Also recommended: Avgelis, N. (1989). Lakatos on the evaluation of scientific theories. In K. Gavroglu, Y. Goudaroulis, & P. Nicolacopoulos (Eds.), Imre Lakatos and theories of scientific change (pp. 157-167). Boston: Kluwer Academic. Chow, S.L. (1990). In defense of Popperian falsification. Psychological Inquiry, 1, 147-149. COMM 610 (Fall 2013): ACT: p. 22 Conway, L. G., III, & Schaller, M. (2002). On the verifiability of evolutionary psychological theories: An analysis of the psychology of scientific persuasion. Personality and Social Psychology Review, 6, 152-166. Ding, D. D. (2002). The passive voice and social values in science. Journal of Technical Writing and Communication, 32, 137-154. Frentz, T. S. (1983). Falsification procedures for behavioral research in communication. Southern Speech Communication Journal, 48, 269-282. Greenwald, A.G. & Pratkanis, A.R. (1988). On the use of "theory" and the usefulness of theory. Psychological Review, 95, 575-579. Ketelaar, T., & Ellis, B. J. (2000). Are evolutionary explanations unfalsifiable? Evolutionary psychology and the Lakatosian philosophy of science. Psychological Inquiry, 11, 1-21. Lustig, M. W. (1986). Theorizing about human communication. Communication Quarterly, 34, 451-459. MacKay, D.G. (1988). Under what conditions can theoretical psychology survive and prosper? Integrating the rational and empirical epistemologies. Psychological Review, 95, 559-565. Moser, K., Gadenne, V., & Schroder, J. (1988). Under what conditions does confirmation seeking obstruct scientific progress? Psychological Review, 95, 572-574. Papineau, D. (1989). Has Popper been a good thing? In K. Gavroglu, Y. Goudaroulis, & P. Nicolacopoulos (Eds.), Imre Lakatos and theories of scientific change (Vol. 111, Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, pp. 431-440). Boston: Kluwer Academic. Phillips, D. L. (1977). Ch. 7: The demarcation problem in science. Wittgenstein and scientific knowledge: A sociological perspective (pp. 142-168). London: Macmillan. Taylor, C. A. (1991). Defining the scientific community: A rhetorical perspective on demarcation. Communication Monographs, 58, 402-420. Wójcicki, R. (1995/96). Theories, theoretical models, truth: Part I: Popperian and non-Popperian theories in science. Foundations of Science, 3, 337-406. Focus Questions: 1. Identify the major tenets and counter-arguments of the Greenwald et al. thesis. What, if any, internal inconsistencies are there in their thesis? Discuss the implications of the disconfirmation dilemma for Popper's thesis of falsification. 2. What are the prospects and implications for a condition-seeking science? How would it relate to Sandelands' concerns about the practicality of theory? 3. What the heck is the modus tollens, and why does it seem so important to Popper? 4. Deconstruct or defend Popper's criterion of demarcation. 5. Given the social nature of theory development suggested in previous readings, what impact does Popperian falsification have in the actual development of theory? Elaborate. 6. What are the alternatives, and their implications, to abandoning a falsificationist scientific logic? 7. To some extent, the difference between falsification and verification is as follows: Verification: If p, then q; p observed; therefore q deduced as true Falsification: If p, then q; not q; therefore, p deduced as false To what extent, and in what ways, are these really distinct logics? COMM 610 (Fall 2013): ACT: p. 23 POPPER SELECTIONS “it is … boldness, together with the readiness to look out for tests and refutations, which distinguishes ‘empirical’ science from non-science, and especially from pre-scientific myths and metaphysics. I will call this proposal (D): (D) for ‘demarcation’. (Selections, p. 122) “a theory is scientific to the degree to which it is testable.” (Selections, p. 123) “The attribution or non-attribution of responsibility for [a theory test’s] failure is conjectural, like everything in science; and what matters is the proposal of a new alternative and competing conjectural system that is able to pass the falsifying test.” (Selections, p. 124) “As always, science is conjecture” (Selections, p. 126) “we must be constantly critical; self-critical with respect to our own theories, and self-critical with respect to our own criticism; we must never evade an issue” (Selections, p. 126) “the empirical content of a theory could be measured by the number of possibilities which it excluded” (Selections, p. 128) “If any of our conjectures goes wrong…then we have to change the theory. But there are … two kinds of changes; conservative and revolutionary. And among the conservative changes there are again two: ad hoc hypotheses and auxiliary hypotheses. (Selections, p. 128-9) “it is the aim of science to find satisfactory explanations…. By an explanation (or a causal explanation) is meant a set of statements of which one describes the state of affairs to be explained (the explicandum) while the others, the explanatory statements, form the ‘explanation’ in the narrower sense of the word (the explicans of the explicandum)” (Selections, p. 162) “an explanation …[consisting] of testable and falsifiable universal laws and initial conditions. … will be the more satisfactory the more highly testable these laws are and the better they have been tested” (Selections, p. 164) “every explanation may be further explained, by a theory or conjecture of a higher degree of universality. There can be no explanation which is not in need of a further explanation” (Selections, p. 165) “falsifications … teach us the unexpected; and they reassure us that, although our theories are made by ourselves, although they are our own inventions, they are none the less genuine assertions about the world; for the can clash with something we never made.” (Selections, p. 167) “the ‘depth’ of a scientific theory seems to be most closely related to its simplicity and so to the wealth of its content….Two ingredients seem to be required: a rich content, and a certain coherence or compactness (or ‘organicity’) of the state of affairs described” (Selections, p. 167) “the idea of independent evidence—can hardly be understood without the idea of discovery, of progressing to deeper layers of explanation: without the idea that there is something for us to discover, and something to discuss critically” (Selections, p. 169) COMM 610 (Fall 2013): ACT: p. 24 “The history of science, like the history of all human ideas, is a history of irresponsible dreams, of obstinacy, and of error. But science is one of the very few human activities—perhaps the only one—in which errors are systematically criticized and fairly often, in time, corrected” (Selections, p. 172) “in most fields we do not even know how to evaluate change” (Selections, p. 172) “we have a criterion of relative potential satisfactoriness, or of potential progressiveness…. This criterion … is extremely simple and intuitive. It characterizes as preferable the theory which tells us more; that is to say, the theory which contains the greater amount of empirical information or content; which is logically stronger; which has the greater explanatory and predictive power; and which can therefore be more severely tested by comparing predicted facts with observations.” (Selections, p. 173) “with increasing content, probability decreases, and vice versa; or in other words, … content increases with increasing improbability….This trivial fact has the following inescapable consequence: if growth of knowledge means that we operate with theories of increasing content, it must also mean that we operate with theories of decreasing probability” (Selections, p. 174) “The criterion of potential satisfactoriness is thus testability, or improbability: only a highly testable or improbable theory is worth testing, and is actually (and not merely potentially) satisfactory if it withstands severe tests” (Selections, p. 176) “It is in the rational choice of the new theory that the rationality of science lies, rather than in the deductive development of the theory” (Selections, p. 178) “science should be visualized as progressing from problems to problems—to problems of ever increasing depth. For a scientific theory—an explanatory theory—is, if anything, an attempt to solve a scientific problem….it is only through a problem that we become conscious of holding a theory” (Selections, p. 179) “Wittgenstein’s criterion of demarcation--…is verifiability, or deducibility from observation statements. But this criterion is too narrow (and too wide): it excludes from science practically everything that is, in fact, characteristic of it (while failing in effect to exclude astrology). No scientific theory can ever be deduced from observation statements, or be described as a truth-function of observation statements.” (Conjectures & refutations, p. 25-6) “the method of science is criticism, i.e., attempted falsification” (Conjectures & refutations, p. 26) “‘valid induction” is not even metaphysical: it simply does not exist. No rule can ever guarantee that a generalization inferred from true observations, however often repeated, is true” (Conjectures & refutations, p. 27) [Note: the claim “All ravens are black” can never be validly proven by observing ravens, however, it can be validly disproven—i.e., falsified—by observing a single non-black raven] “Only the falsity of the theory can be inferred from empirical evidence, and this inference is a purely deductive one.” (Conjectures & refutations, p. 29) “we do not prefer every non-falsified theory—only one which, in the light of criticism, appears to be better than its competitors: which solves our problems, which is well tested, and of COMM 610 (Fall 2013): ACT: p. 25 which we think, or rather conjecture or hope (considering other provisionally accepted theories), that it will stand up to further tests.” (Conjectures & refutations, p. 30) “every interesting and powerful statement must have a low probability; and vice versa: a statement with a high probability will be scientifically uninteresting, because it says little and has no explanatory power.” (Conjectures & refutations, p. 32) “It is easy to obtain confirmations, or verifications, for nearly every theory—if we look for confirmations. Confirmations should count only if they are the result of risky predictions;… Every ‘good’ scientific theory is a prohibition: it forbids certain things to happen. The more a theory forbids, the better it is. A theory which is not refutable by any conceivable event is nonscientific. Irrefutability is not a virtue of a theory (as people often think) but a vice. Every genuine test of a theory is an attempt to falsify it, or refute it. Testability is falsifiability;… Confirming evidence should not count except when it is the result of a genuine test of the theory;… Some genuinely testable theories, when found to be false, are still upheld by their admirers— for example by introducing ad hoc some auxiliary assumption, or by re-interpreting the theory ad hoc in such a way that it escapes refutation…. One can sum up all this by saying that the criterion of the scientific status of a theory is its falsifiability, or refutability, or testability.” (Conjectures & refutations, pp. 22-3) COMM 610 (Fall 2013): ACT: p. 26 WEEK VI: LEWIN'S DICTUM: NOTHING SO PRACTICAL AS A GOOD THEORY (OR IS THERE?) “A science without generalization is no science at all . . . Data without generalization is just gossip.” R. A. Pirsig, Lila: An inquiry into morals, p. 55. How seldom it is that theories stand the wear and tear of practice.” Anthony Trollope. Thackeray. 1879. “The quick harvest of applied science is the useable process, the medicine, the machine. The shy fruit of pure science is Understanding. L. Barnett, on Einstein’s completion of an equation for Unified Field Theory, Life, Jan. 9, 1950 (in Kaplan: Science says) “we can only legitimately stop where our facts stop” Charles Darwin (15) Cohen, B. P. (2003). Creating, testing, and applying social psychological theories. Social Psychological Quarterly, 66, 5-16. (16) Sandelands, L.E. (1991). What is so practical about theory? Lewin revisited. Journal for the Theory of Social Behavior, 20, 235-262. (17) Alexander, J. C., & Colomy, P. (1992). Traditions and competition: Preface to a postpositivist approach to knowledge cumulation. In G. Ritzer (Ed.), Metatheorizing (pp. 27-52). Newbury Park, CA: Sage. Recommended: Laudan, L. (1981). A problem-solving approach to scientific progress. In I. Hacking (Ed.), Scientific revolutions (pp. 144-155). Oxford: Oxford University. McKaughan, D. J. (2008). From ugly duckling to swan: C. S. Peirce, abduction, and the pursuit of scientific theories. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society, 44, 446-468. Nass, C. I., & Reeves, B. (1991). Combining, distinguishing, and generating theories in communication: A domains of analysis framework. Communication Research, 18, 240-261. Focus Questions: 1. Develop a case for theory and defend it. 2. Develop a case against theory and defend it. 3. What obligations do "science" in general, and theory-development in particular, have to "bettering humanity" or making a difference? Why? 4. How respectable is the communication discipline in terms of theory development? Defend your answer with examples and arguments. 5. Discuss the value of theoretical pluralism and diversity? Does it diffuse the identity of a discipline, or indicate its health? Why? COMM 610 (Fall 2013): ACT: p. 27 WEEK VII: ROSE COLORED GLASSES: TRADITIONAL, PERCEPTUAL, CONSTRUCTIVE, POSTMODERN "All social science is ideology." D. Martindale "In view of all the violent forces against it, scientific objectivity, when it is in fact realized, may be seen to have man of the characteristics of the moment of calm at the eye of a hurricane" D. Martindale “while scientists can be venal, science cannot. Science in pursuit of the true is self-correcting.” J. A. Andersen, Communication theory, p. 118 “something deep in the human psyche leads us to impose simple taxonomic schemes of distinct categories upon the world’s truly complex continual… the true basis for this propensity lies in our clear (and probably universal) preferences for dichotomous divisions. Division by four may denote an ultimate and completed dichotomization—a dichotomy of dichotomies” Stephen Jay Gould, Lying stones of Marrakech, 2000, p. 285 (18) Craig, R. T. (1999). Communication theory as a field. Communication Theory, 9, 119-161. (19) Craig, R. T. (2007). Pragmatism in the field of communication theory. Communication Theory, 17, 125-145. (20) Anderson, J. A., & Baym, G. (2004). Philosophies and philosophic issues in communication, 1995-2004. Journal of Communication, 54, 589-615. Also recommended: Altman, I., & Rogoff, B. (1987). World views in psychology: Trait, interactional, organismic, and transactional perspectives. In D. Stokols & I. Altman (Eds.), Handbook of environmental psychology (pp. 7-40). New York: John Wiley & Sons. Gergen, K. J. & Morawski, J. (1980). An alternative metatheory for social psychology. In L. Wheeler (Ed.), Review of personality and social psychology (Vol. 1, pp. 326-352). Beverly Hills, CA: Sage. Cushman, D. P. & Pearce, W. B. (1977). Generality and necessity in three types of theory about human communication, with special attention to rules theory. Human Communication Research, 3, 344-353. Cronen, V. E. & Davis, L. K. (1978). Alternative approaches for the communication theorist: Problems in the laws-rules-systems trichotomy. Human Communication Research, 4, 120-128. Rosengren, K. E. (1989). Paradigms lost and regained. In B. Dervin, L. Grossberg, B.J. O'Keefe, & E. Wartella (Eds.), Rethinking communication (Vol. 1: Paradigm issues, pp. 21-39). Newbury Park, CA: Sage. Smith, T. J., III (1988). Diversity and order in communication theory: The uses of philosophical analysis. Communication Quarterly, 36, 28-40. COMM 610 (Fall 2013): ACT: p. 28 WEEK IX: BROTHER CAN YOU PARADIGM?: PARADIGMS AND PARADIGM CHANGE "Thought paradigms - Kuhn calls them simply 'paradigms' - are conglomerations of exemplary thoughts. They include various fairy tales about what the 'real world' might be like all bound up in cover stories about how it may be known. They consist of thoughts wrapped up in thoughts about thoughts. And these devices serve as patterns both for knowledge itself, and for the acquisition of knowledge ... the methods of reality construction, the paradigms of thought, employed by modern scientists are formally synonymous with those used ... by most philosophers, theologians, and magicians, and by ordinary people in their everyday lives." Julienne Ford, Paradigms and fairy tales "Trying to predict precisely what new paradigm will emerge is almost as foolish as trying to control it." W.J. McGuire “the famous statement by Freud …’The most important scientific revolutions all include, as their only common feature, the dethronement of human arrogance from one pedestal after another of previous convictions about our centrality in the cosmos’” S. J. Gould, 1995, Dinosaur in a haystack, p. 234 “The important thing in science is not so much to obtain new facts as to discover new ways of thinking about them.” W. L. Bragg, in Koestler & Smithies, Beyond reductionism (in Kaplan: Science says) (21) Kuhn, T. S. (1970). Postscript-1969. The structure of scientific revolutions (2nd ed.). Chicago: University of Chicago. (22) Laudan, L., Donovan, A., Laudan, R., Barker, P., Brown, H., Leplin, J., Thagard, P., & Wykstra, S. (1986). Scientific change: Philosophical models and historical research. Synthese, 69, 141-223. Also recommended: Charland, M. (2003). The incommensurability thesis and the status of knowledge. Philosophy and Rhetoric, 36, 248-263. Guntau, M., & Laitko, H. (1991). On the origin and nature of scientific disciplines. In W.R. Woodward & R. S. Cohen (Eds.), World views and scientific discipline formation (Vol. 134, Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, pp. 17-28). Boston: Kluwer Academic. Irzik, G., & Grünberg, T. (1995). Carnap and Kuhn: Arch enemies or close allies? British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 46, 285-307. Koutougos, A. (1989). Research programmes and paradigms as dialogue structures. In K. Gavroglu, Y. Goudaroulis, & P. Nicolacopoulos (Eds.), Imre Lakatos and theories of scientific change (Vol. 111, Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, pp. 361-374). Boston: Kluwer Academic. COMM 610 (Fall 2013): ACT: p. 29 Martindale, D. (1979). Ideologies, paradigms, and theories. In W. E. Snizek, E. R. Fuhrman, & M. K. Miller (Eds.), Contemporary issues in theory and research: A metasociological perspective (pp. 7-24). Westport, CT: Greenwood. Masterman, M. (1970). The nature of a paradigm. In I. Lakatos & A. Musgrave (Eds.), Criticism and the growth of knowledge (Proceedings of the International Colloquium in the Philosophy of Science, Vol. 4, pp. 59-89). Cambridge: Cambridge University. Mayo, D. G. (1996). Ducks, rabbits, and normal science: Recasting the Kuhn’s-eye view of Popper’s demarcation of science. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 47, 271-290. Sarkar, H. (1983). A theory of method. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press. Seidman, S. S. (1987-88). Models of scientific development in sociology. Humboldt Journal of Social Relations, 15, 119-139. Focus Questions: 1. To what extent, and in what ways, is observation inherently "theory-laden"? 2. To what extent, and in what ways, does theory-laden observation affect the possibility of an objective science? 3. Discuss the implications of reflexivity for theory development and validation. 4. Discuss Chow's empiricist thesis, and its implications for a the typical "constructionist" attack on positivism. “the historical record reveals case after case where even the most ardent proponents are forced to relent on the basis of very local, but very powerful experimental tests. The Kuhn of normal science can explain this consensus quite naturally; the Kuhn of revolutionary science cannot. Mayo, 1996, p. 288 “The real voyage of discovery consists not in seeking new landscapes, but in having new eyes” Marcel Proust ** Bowman, J. P., & Targowski, A. S. (1987). Modeling the communication process: The map is not the territory. Journal of Business Communication, 24, 21-34. **Spitzberg, B. H., & Chagnon, G. (2009). Conceptualizing intercultural communication competence. In D. K. Deardorff (Ed.), The SAGE handbook of intercultural competence (pp. 2-52). Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage. COMM 610 (Fall 2013): ACT: p. 30 Focus Questions: 1. Identify, elaborate, and defend a paradigmatic taxonomy for the social sciences. 2. Discuss the role of generality and necessity in theory development and paradgimatic classification. 3. Compare and contrast two or more paradigmatic taxonomies, their strengths and weaknesses, and potential for conceptual hegemony. 4. Do people from different paradigms see the world differently (i. e., do ethnographers ‘see’ ducks, and scientists ‘see’ rabbits), or do they simply look for different things (i.e., do ethnographers look for ducks while scientists look for rabbits out of all the things they could look for)? “What we see of the real world is not the unvarnished real world but a model of the real world, regulated and adjusted by sense data— a model that is constructed so that it is useful for dealing with the real world.” R. Dawkins, The God delusion. Boston: Houghton Mifflin, p. 371 “A new scientific truth does not triumph by convincing opponents and making them see the light, but rather because its opponents eventually die, and a new generation grows up that is familiar with it.” Max Planck, A scientific autobiography and other papers, 1949 COMM 610 (Fall 2013): ACT: p. 31 WEEK X: PEEKING AT THE POSTMODERN: THEORY AS A POSTMODERN PROCESS “How can anyone not see that all observation must be for or against some view if it is to be of any service” Darwin, quoted by Stephen Jay Gould, Lying stones of Marrakech, 2000, p. 172 “Theory-free science makes about as much sense as value-free politics. Both terms are oxymoronic. All thinking about the natural world must be informed by theory, whether or not we articulate our preferred structure of explanation to ourselves. S. J. Gould, 1995, Dinosaur in a haystack, p. 419 "the natural world has a small or non-existent role in the construction of scientific knowledge." D. T. Campbell “How wonderful that we have met with a paradox. Now we have some hope of making progress.” Niels Bohr, The quantum dice, by L. I. Ponomarev, 1993 “the confirmation of even an observation sentence can never be complete in the sense that, no matter how large is the number of confirming observations, it may be false. Because observation sentences are fallible, they are naturally revisable; sometimes their revision may be affected by theoretical considerations. Therefore, all observational sentences are theory-dependent in the sense that they can be revised by theory. This means that Carnap’s mature philosophy rejects the idea of science based on the unshakeable, certain foundations of observation or sense-experience” (Irzik & Grünberg, 1995, p. 293) (23) Feyerabend, P. (1980). How to defend society against science. In E. D. Klemke, R. Hollinger, & A. D. Kline (Eds.), Introductory readings in the philosophy of science (pp. 55-65). Buffalo, NY: Prometheus. (24) Lloyd, E. A. (1996). The anachronistic anarchist. Philosophical Studies, 81, 247-261. Also recommended: Blalock, H. M. (1979). Dilemmas and strategies of theory construction. In W. E. Snizek, E. R. Fuhrman, & M. K. Miller (Eds.), Contemporary issues in theory and research: A metasociological perspective (pp. 119-135). Westport, CT: Greenwood. Tsou, J. Y. (2003). Reconsidering Feyerabend’s “anarchism.” Perspectives on Science, 11, 208-235. COMM 610 (Fall 2013): ACT: p. 32 WEEK XI: ECONSTRUCTING THEORETICAL CONSTRUCTIONS: SCHOLARSHIP AS TEXT "In his Micromegas Voltaire has an immensely wise alien come to visit earth. He has dozens of senses and can thus perceive much more of reality than humans can. He comes from a race devoted to the acquisition of wisdom and that lives thousands of years. On leaving earth, he leaves philosophers there a book containing all the knowledge that can ever be gained about the pure and ultimate nature of things. It has only blank pages." L. LeShan & H. Margenau, Einstein’s Space and Van Gogh’s Sky “The limits of my language mean the limits of my world” (5.6) “The world is my world: this is manifest in the fact that the limits of language (of that language which alone I understand) mean the limits of my world” (5.62) “We cannot think what we cannot think; so what we cannot think we cannot say either” (5.61) L. Wittgenstein (1961, Tractatus) (25) Gergen, K. J. (2001). Psychological science in a postmodern context. American Psychologist, 56, 803-813. (26) Gergen, K. J. (2001). Construction in contention: Toward consequential resolutions. Theory & Psychology, 11, 419-432. (27) Gergen, K. J., & Zielke, B. (2006). Theory in action. Theory & Psychology, 16, 299-309. (28) Ritzer, G., Zhao, S., & Murphy, J. (2001). Metatheorizing in sociology: The basic parameters and the potential contributions of postmodernism. In J. H. Turner (Ed.), Handbook of sociological theory (pp. 113-131). New York: Kluwer/Plenum. Also recommended: Gergen, K. J. (1978). Toward generative theory. Journal of Personality And Social Psychology, 36(11), 1344-1360. doi:10.1037/0022-3514.36.11.1344. Gergen, K. J. (1973). Social psychology as history. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 26, 309-320.Gergen, K. J. (1978). Toward generative theory. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 36, 1344-1360. Gergen, K. J. (1979). The positivist image in social psychological theory. In A. R. Buss (Ed.), Psychology in social context (pp. 193-212). New York: Irvington. Gergen, K. J. (1991). Emerging challenges for theory and psychology. Theory & Psychology, 1, 1335. Gergen, K. J. (2002). Beyond the empiricist/constructionist divide in social psychology. Personality and Social Psychology Review, 6(3), 188-191. doi:10.1207/S15327957PSPR0603_2 Gergen, K. J., & Morawski, J. (1980). An alternative metatheory for social psychology. In L. Wheeler (Ed.), Review of personality and social psychology (Vol. 1, pp. 326-352). Beverly Hills, CA: Sage. Ghoshal, S. (2005). Bad management theories are destroying good management practices. Academy of Management Learning & Education, 4, 75-91. Shotter, J. (1987). The rhetoric of theory in psychology. In W. J. Baker, M. E. Hyland, H. V. Rappard, & A. W. Staats (Eds.), Current issues in theoretical psychology (pp. 283-296). NorthHolland: Elsevier Science. COMM 610 (Fall 2013): ACT: p. 33 WEEK XIV: LAW OF THE HAMMER: OBJECTIVE VS. HERMENEUTIC EMPIRICISM “Many commentators have rightly implored us to make certain that young people encounter the ‘thrill’ of discovery. While this is undeniably desirable, it is arguably even more crucial that they experience the agony (if only on a modest scale) of having a pet hypotheses demolished by facts” T. W. Martin, Scientific literacy and the habit of discourse. Seed, (Sept/Oct 2007, p. 77) (29) Greenwald, A.G., Pratkanis, A.R., Leippe, M.R., & Baumgardner, M.H. (1986). Under what conditions does theory obstruct research progress? Psychological Review, 93, 216-229. (30) Wallach, L., & Wallach, M. A. (1994). Gergen versus the mainstream: Are hypotheses in social psychology subject to empirical test? Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 67, 233-242. (31) Jost, J. T., & Kruglanski, A. W. (2002). The estrangement of social constructionism and experimental social psychology: History of the rift and prospects for reconciliation. Personality and Social Psychology Review, 6, 168-187. Also recommended: Krueger, J. I. (2002). Postmodern parlor games. American Psychologist, 57, 461-462. McClintock, C. G. (1985). The metatheoretical bases of social psychological theory. Behavioral Science, 30, 155-173. Schlenker, B. R. (1974). Social psychology and science. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 29, 1-15. Wallach, L., & Wallach, M. A. (1994). Gergen versus the mainstream: Are hypotheses in social psychology subject to empirical test? Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 67, 233242. Focus Questions: 1. Identify the principal points of contention between Gergen and Schlenker. 2. Compare and contrast Gergen's "historical" and "hermeneutic" theses to the earlier empiricist theses of Berger, Chow, and Turner. Defend one "side." 3. What implications does Gergen's "historical" and "hermeneutic" theses have for the (a) paradigmatic (Kuhn) view of communication, and (b) the credibility and vitality of the discipline of communication. 4. Is there hope for "traditional" social science, as traditionally envisioned? Defend your answer. 5. Summarize a postmodern deconstructive view of traditional social science. 6. Identify the five most important flaws or challenges of theory development. Elaborate their nature and significance. 7. Identify the five most important flaws or challenges of metatheory. Elaborate their nature and significance. COMM 610 (Fall 2013): ACT: p. 34 WEEK XII: RESCUING REALISM: PATCHES AND PARABLES "Science is corrosive of all values which are based exclusively on simple epistemological processes" McClintock "Einstein's space is no closer to reality than Van Gogh's sky. The glory of science is not in a truth more absolute than the truth of Bach or Tolstoy, but in the act of creation itself. The scientist's discoveries impose his own order on chaos, as the composer or painter imposes his; an order that always refers to limited aspects of reality, and is based on the observer's frame of reference, which differs from period to period as a Rembrandt nude differs from a nude by Manet." A. Koestler (quoted by LeShan & Margenau, Einstein’s Space and Van Gogh’s Sky) "Certain it is that a conviction, akin to religious feeling, of the rationality of the world lies behind all scientific work of a higher order." A. Einstein “Unless our theories about the world are in significant parts true or approximately true, our scientific, and especially our linguistic success, cannot be explained” Sarkar, 1983, p. 12 (32) Bostrom, R. & Donohew, L. (1992). The case for empiricism: Clarifying fundamental issues in communication theory. Communication Monographs, 59, 109-129 (33) Gilman, D. (1992). What's a theory to do...with seeing? or some empirical considerations for observation and theory. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 43, 287-309. (34) Chow, S.L. (1992). Acceptance of a theory: Justification or rhetoric? Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour, 22, 447-474. Focus Questions: 1. Define "paradigm" and provide a defense or attack of the theoretical and/or pragmatic utility of such a concept. 2. Return to the first set of readings, and overlay and discuss the possible nexus of the notion of paradigms on the history of the discipline of communication. 3. Critique the Kuhnian model of paradigm change. 4. Compare and contrast the Kuhnian notion of paradigms with the empiricist thesis of neopositivists such as Berger, Chow, and Turner. COMM 610 (Fall 2013): ACT: p. 35 WEEK XIII: LIFE IS BUT A GAME: THE POLITICS OF SCHOLARSHIP "The following sentence is false. The preceding sentence is true." D. R. Hofstadter "There are trivial truths and great truths. The opposite of a trivial truth is plainly false. The opposite of a great truth is also true." N. Bohr. **Publication Games Colloquy: Zanna, M. P. (1992). My life as a dog (I mean editor). Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 18, 485-488. Higgins, E. T. (1992). Increasingly complex but less interesting articles: Scientific progress or regulatory problem? Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 18, 489-492. Funder, D. C. (1992). Psychology from the other side of the line: Editorial processes and publication trends at JPSP. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 18, 493-497. Schneider, D. J. (1992). Publication games: Reflections on Reis and Stiller. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 18, 498-503. Also Recommended: Agnew, N. M., & Pyke, S. W. (1969). The science game: An introduction to research in the behavioral sciences. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall. Andreski, S. (1972). Social sciences as sorcery. New York: St. Martin’s Press. Anonymous. (1987). The publication game: Beyond quality in the search for a lengthy vitae. Journal of Social Behavior and Personality, 2, 3-12. Anonymous. (1991). The publication game II: Editorial confrontation, or how to browbeat editors. Journal of Social Behavior and Personality, 6, 1-6. Ford, J. (1975). Paradigms & fairy tales: An introduction to the science of meanings (Vol. 1). London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. Ford, J. (1975). Paradigms & fairy tales: An introduction to the science of meanings (Vol. 2). London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. Lyotard, J-F. (1985). Just gaming (Theory and History of Literature, Vol. 20). Minneapolis, MN: University of Minneapolis Press. McCain, G., & Segal, E. M. (1969). The game of science. Belmont, CA: Brooks/Cole. O’Neill, J. (1972). Sociology as a skin trade: Essays toward a reflexive sociology. New York: Harper & Row. Paul, J. (1980). Laws of behavior: Fact or artifact? American Psychologist, 35, 1081-1083. Reis, H. T., & Stiller, J. (1992). Publication trends in JPSP: A three-decade review. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 18, 465-472. Sindermann, C. J. (1982). Winning the games scientists play. New York: Plenum Press. West, S. G., Newsom, J. T., & Fenaughty, A. M. (1992). Publication trends in JPSP: Stability and change in topics, methods, and theories across two decades. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 18, 473-484. COMM 610 (Fall 2013): ACT: p. 36 JUXTAPOSITION EXEMPLAR & TEMPLATE Name: Brian H. Spitzberg E-mail: spitz@mail.sdsu.edu COMM 610: Advanced Comm Theory Date: 09/11/2012 Jux #1 1st Claim(s)/Concept(s): Miller (1975) explicitly claims that the division of rhetorical and communication science is based on the questions asked, and not the methods they use. 2nd Claim(s)/Concept(s): Berger (1991) claims that a fundamental cause of the deficit of theories in the field of communication is the aversion to risk-taking in theoretical predictions. Juxtaposition(s): Asking questions doth not a discipline make! A question may be the beginning of a theory, but it is incapable of specifying the methodology by which it could be answered. The fundamental feature of “science” is not that it asks questions differently from rhetoric, but that it answers them differently. Rhetoric may address questions of “grand theory” and empirical nature (e.g., Fisher’s claim that some narratives are more likely to be effective [i.e., persuasive] than others, or Burke’s claim that scape-goating can effectively energize a rhetorical audience). The difference is that science does not hide behind historicism or ideographic presumptions regarding the generalizability of knowledge claims. Instead, science it makes predictions that run the risk of failure and provides a methodology for ascertaining success or failure, whereas rhetoric and humanities do not. Such falsifiable questions may indeed take different form than those in rhetoric or the humanities, but such a difference is meaningless unless the methods of falsification are presumed to permit the testing of such questions with an eye toward their truth-value or verisimilitude, which requires risk-taking. References (if any citations from non-syllabus sources): COMM 610 (Fall 2013): ACT: p. 37 COMM 610 (Spring 2013): Advanced Communication Theory: p. 38 JUXTAPOSITION EXEMPLAR & TEMPLATE Name: Brian H. Spitzberg E-mail: spitz@mail.sdsu.edu COMM 610: Advanced Comm Theory Date: 09/11/2012 Jux #1 1st Claim(s)/Concept(s): O’Boyle and Aguinis (2012) demonstrate in several populations that outstanding “performance outcomes are attributable to a small group of elite performers” or superstars (p. 106). 2nd Claim(s)/Concept(s): Burke and Harrod (2005) compare positive and negative partner evaluations, and find that “the greater the discrepancy in terms of being either over- or underevaluated, the greater the likelihood that the person will leave the relationship through separation or divorce” (p. .371). Ehrlinger et al. (2008) produce evidence that “poor performers are overconfident in estimates of how well they performed relative to others because they have little insight into the quality of their own performance,” whereas “top performers’ mistakenly modest relative estimates were produced by erroneous impressions of both their own objective performance and that of their peers” (p. 117). Juxtaposition(s): Superstars are overly modest, whereas incompetents are overly optimistic, in their self-evaluation. The overevaluations, however, work to the detriment to the incompetents, whereas the modesty bias has little or no negative consequence for top performers and superstars. Indeed, modesty may be part of what sustains the positive evaluations that others would have of superstars, and unmerited narcissism or halo-bias may be part of what restricts the performance of underperformers, and help explain why most people are under-performers. Yet, the Burke and Harrod (2005) research suggests that these under- and over-performers all are likely to prefer partners who verify their self-perceptions. This calibration would mean that superstars prefer partners who affirm the superstar’s more modest achievement, whereas underperformers would prefer partners who confirm the under-performer’s inflated self-evaluation. Again, this would suggest that superstars are kept humble by their intimate relationships, whereas underperformers would function best intimately with partners who sustain the under-performer’s selfdeception, even though the effect would be to make that person less capable of performing well for lack of an ability to accurately perceive self’s ability and other’s estimations of that ability. The implication is a triangulated self-reinforcing tendency for superstars to get better in social evaluations both within and without their intimate relationships, whereas the less competent performers get increasingly stuck by failed relationships that fail in part because the incompetent persons promote and seek confirmation for their own biased and inaccurate self-evaluations. The possibility of this social amplification process is not recognized by O’Boyle and Aguinis (2012) or Ehrlinger et al. (2008), illustrating the importance of theorizing beyond the individual or dyadic unit of analysis. References (if any citations from non-syllabus sources): COMM 610 (Spring 2013): Advanced Communication Theory: p. 39 REASONED JUXTAPOSITION OF READINGS For the weeks specified, all students will be expected to produce a reasoned juxtaposition of some concept(s) from at least two of the readings for that seminar, and turn it into the professor. It is recommended both as a reading heuristic for students, as well as an indication of the level at which students are critically reading the assigned readings. The materials must fit on one page, and must derive at least in part from the readings for that day’s readings (and may include in addition materials from other readings in the course). The entire assignment must fit on a single sheet of paper, and have font no smaller than 10-point Arial, 10-point Calibri or 11-point Times Roman (1-inch margins). Exemplary student juxtapositions should serve as bases for student lines of questions and oral argument during class discussions throughout the semester. Juxtapositions will be graded on a simple scale as follows: Assessment Rubric Either no assignment is turned in on time, or the materials are either not logically interconnected, or represent the most surface extraction of meanings from the readings, indicating a shallow or hurried reading of the course materials. Points 0 3 Relevant concepts are mentioned but are defined in a shallow manner; linkages among concepts are loose or strained; implications lack credibility or import. 5 8 Relevant concepts are formulated and connected, but the links are somewhat obvious and lacking in depth of intellectual challenge. 10 13 At least one substantive juxtaposition is identified, leading to a contradiction, paradox, or theoretical principle. The result is a single reasonable claim that furthers the content of the readings considered individually, but integrates or suggests little else beyond this single concept. 15 18 The contradiction, paradox or theoretical principle is unfolded into several directions, but the import or implications are inconsistent in quality or implications are left without explication. 20 23 Multiple implications are derived from the juxtaposition(s) of concepts identified in the readings. The implications are extended into multiple directions of analysis or synthesis with other concepts identified in the course. 25 “The reason science does manage to be astonishingly effective is not because large groups are automatically wiser or less prone to self-deception than individuals. History adequately demonstrates that, if anything, the opposite is more nearly the case. Science works because its core dynamics— not its methods or techniques per se—are rooted in pitting intellects against one another. Science eventually yields impressive answers because it compels smart people to incessantly try to disprove the ideas generated by other smart people. Martin, T. W. (2007). Scientific literacy and the habit of discourse. Seed (Sept/Oct), 76-77. COMM 610 (Spring 2013): Advanced Communication Theory: p. 40 INSTRUCTIONS FOR THE PROPOSITION/MODEL PAPER An Hypothetical Parable D: Daddy, what is an instinct? F: An instinct, my dear, is an explanatory principle. D: But what does it explain? F: Anything – almost anything at all. Anything you want it to explain. D: Don't be silly. It doesn't explain gravity. F: No. But that is because nobody wants "instinct" to explain gravity. If they did, it would explain it. We could simply say that the moon has an instinct whose strength varies inversely as the square of the distance . . . D: But that's nonsense, Daddy. F: Yes, surely. But it was you who mentioned "instinct," not I. D: All right – but then what does explain gravity? F: Nothing my dear, because gravity is an explanatory principle. D: Oh. Do you mean that you cannot use one explanatory principle to explain another? F: Hmm . . . hardly ever. That is what Newton meant when he said, "hypotheses non fingo." D: And what does that mean? Please. F: Well, you know what "hypotheses" are. Any statement linking together two descriptive statements is an hypothesis. If you say that there was a full moon on February 1st and another on March 1st; and then you link these two observations together in any way, the statement that links them is an hypothesis. D: Yes – and I know what 'non' means. But what's 'fingo.' F: Well, 'fingo' is a late Latin word for 'make.' It forms a verbal noun 'fictio' from which we get the word 'fiction.' D: Daddy, do you mean that Sir Issac Newton thought that all hypotheses were just made up like stories? F: Yes – precisely that. D: But didn't he discover gravity? With the apple? F: No, dear. He invented it. D: Oh. Adapted from: Heinz Von Foerster (1981). Rigor & Imagination: Essays from the Legacy of Gregory Bateson. COMM 610 (Spring 2013): Advanced Communication Theory: p. 41 DON'T PANIC “Hypotheses are the scaffolds which are erected in front of a building and removed when the building is completed. They are indispensable to the worker; but he must not mistake the scaffolding for the building. J. W. von Goethe, Maxims and reflections, 1893 (in Kaplan: Science says) “For every fact there is an infinity of hypotheses. The more you look, the more you see. R. M. Pirsig, Zen and the art of motorcycle maintenance, 1974. “Hypothesis, where successful, is a two-way street, extending back to explain the past and forward to predict the future. What we try to do in framing hypotheses is to explain some otherwise unexplained happenings by inventing a plausible story, a plausible description or history of relevant portions of the world” (Quine & Ullian, 1980, “Hypothesis,” p. 197) “The purpose of models is not to fit the data but to sharpen the questions” S. Karlin, 11th R. A. Fisher Memorial Lecture, Royal Society, April 20, 1983 (in Kaplan: Science says) “Being able to examine our models, critically evaluate them, and even discard them is far more scientifically literate than being able to regurgitate facts for a standardized test. … Ultimately, our models and descriptions of reality must be subject to two overriding criteria. How useful is this model, and how much does this model resemble our observations? Scientific literacy requires an understanding that science is only a model. We have to be able to jettison our models when our critical thinking leads us to that conclusion. Saus, S. (2007). Camelot is only a model: Scientific literacy in the 21st century. Seed, (Sept/Oct), 77-78. “Without a sense, or without the thought, a proposition would be an utterly dead and trivial thing.” Wittgenstein, Blue and Brown Books, 1958, p. 4 “The meaning of exactness best founded in intellectual history is the possibility of constructing a theoretical system of idealized models containing abstract constructs of variables and of relations between variables, from which most or all propositions concerning particular connections can be deduced.” Machlup, 2004, Readings in the philosophy of social science p. 11 COMM 610 (Spring 2013): Advanced Communication Theory: p. 42 General Instructions The purpose of a hypothesis paper is to develop a conceptual model, and a number of theoretical propositions deriving from that model, concerning communication. The paper in some ways is a review of literature to develop a rationale on a given communication concept or theory. It is different from typical literature reviews in a few important ways. Most reviews just summarize literature to provide a sense of ‘what is known’ in an area. In contrast, the model and hypothesis papers attempt to analyze the literature in ways that support a particular configuration of concepts or variables; the relationships of this configuration can then be formalized as hypotheses. Submission The paper will be turned in electronically, in Word 2007, through SafeAssign in Blackboard. The due date requires a time-stamp on the submission by the beginning of the seminar on the date specified in the syllabus schedule. Form, Organization and Style Sections. There should be seven basic parts to the paper. All pages should be paginated with a running head in the upper right of each page. The running head is a brief title (2-5 words). (1) Title page: The first part of the paper is a title page, with a title that indicates something about the topic of the paper, name, the class, semester and year. (2) Visual model: The second page is the visual model. (3) Proposition list: The third page of the paper is a proposition list, under the title of the paper (from the first page). The proposition list is a simple listing of the numbered propositions developed in the paper. There should be at least a space between each proposition. The proposition list reproduces the propositions, and only the propositions, in the order they are presented in the paper. (4) Introduction: Fourth, beginning on the fourth page, with the title of the paper reproduced at the top, some form of introduction should be presented. An introduction may do a number of things, such as briefly examining the history and importance of the concepts selected for analysis, discussing the relevance of these concepts to the course subject, introducing relevant theories, and/or explaining any basic terms, assumptions, or limitations that may be important. Assume this class as the audience, which means that the writing should be clear enough for them to comprehend fully the content, and intent, of the paper. The introduction should consist of approximately 2-5 paragraphs (or 1-2 pages). (5) Body: Fifth, the body of the paper consists of the propositions and the arguments for each proposition. This section of the paper proceeds by presenting a proposition and then developing a paragraph or two of explanation and support. The propositions should be numbered and set off from the text (e.g., bolded, italicized). The typical paper will develop between 8 and 10 propositions. Propositions are never prima facie; that is, they never stand on their own. Propositions always require some degree of explanation. This section of the paper should constitute the lion's share of the paper (approximately 70-80%). (6) Conclusion: Sixth, the conclusion section develops any number of points, such as providing a brief summary of the paper, a consideration of the limitations of the analysis, COMM 610 (Spring 2013): Advanced Communication Theory: p. 43 a critical conjecture about the status of the theory and/or research associated with the construct(s) examined, future implications of the analysis, or the importance of the analysis. (7) References: Seventh, the references section will provide the complete citations in most current A.P.A. style. (8) Model(s)/Diagram(s): Eighth, the figures or models used to integrate the model. It is often easiest to draw these in PowerPoint (or similar graphics program) and save as a .pdf, and then cut-and-paste into the paper. Length. Papers should be between 20 and 25 pages, not including title page, proposition list, tables, figures, or references. Spacing. Everything is double-spaced, except tables or figures, if such are included. Thus, the title page, abstract (if provided), text, headings, and reference list are all double-spaced. Miscellaneous. Use A.P.A. throughout. Do not leave big blank spaces between sections or hypotheses. The text should run continuously. Cite as often as desired, but quote very judiciously. In general, no quote should be longer than five lines long, and there should be no more than five quotes in the entire paper. I want to see your ideas and writing, not someone else’s ideas and writing. Make a copy of the paper before handing it in, as the original belongs to the professor. All the propositions will be reflected in the model in some way, but the model may be larger, more inclusive than represented by the propositions alone (i.e., all of the propositions are in the model, but all the model may not be in the propositions). Modeling Modeling is one of the zeniths of scientific reasoning. It incorporates analytic reasoning (i.e., breaking wholes into parts), synthetic reasoning (i.e., [re]assembling parts into wholes), and abstract reasoning (i.e., recognizing similar things across levels of abstraction and concreteness). It also is fundamental to theoretical reasoning (i.e., explaining how and why phenomena happen the way they do), and methodology (i.e., specifying hypotheses to be tested qualitatively or quantitatively, the results of which inform the validity of the underlying theory). Models serve various functions in science as in everyday life. A model is a visual simplification of concepts that exist in both a hypothesized conceptual form and an actual or potential observed form. For example, if you believe that as social skills decrease a person’s ability to meet others and develop satisfying relationships decreases, and that this in turn increases the person’s loneliness, and that increases in loneliness lead to increased interaction anxiety, then three conceptual components each potentially can be measured by a questionnaire or survey. Thus, you would have a very basic model that looks something like the following: Social Skills Loneliness Social Anxiety Notice that this model could have been formulated entirely differently. Some have argued that people develop anxiety through early learning experiences, which leads to a deficit COMM 610 (Spring 2013): Advanced Communication Theory: p. 44 of social skills, which thereby make the development of social relationships more difficult, leading to loneliness. These represent alternative models of reality, and either one can be reasonably argued and justified. Which one is “true” is irrelevant for the sake of formulating the model—the question is whether a good set of arguments can be developed in support of the model ultimately produced. Once you have a basic model, it is then relatively simple to start asking additional questions, such as how biology (e.g., sex, age, etc.), culture (e.g., ethnicity, regional identification, etc.), context (e.g., socio-economic status, intact family status, etc.), personal background (e.g., attachment disorder, relational history, etc.) or dispositions (e.g., self-esteem, attribution style, etc.) influence various components or relationships of the model. Most models follow simple rules: (1) Components on the left precede, at some point, the components to the right in real time. (2) Every conceptual component should have a measurement component. (3) Every arrow represents a direct effect of one concept on another. This effect does not have to be a causal relationship, but it usually implies such an influence. (4) Every component must have an arrow headed to at least one other component, and may have arrows to multiple other components. (5) The spatially closer two components are to one another, the more closely they are associated with one another than to components further away from one another. (6) Components can be grouped according to larger components (i.e., multiple indicators of a single concept; e.g., social skills above might be further indicated by coordination, expressiveness, attentiveness, and composure skills). (7) Every arrow is a potentially testable hypothesis (or proposition). The nature of these hypotheses is discussed next. Hypothesizing A hypothesis is a verbal or symbolic statement of relationship between two or more variables (e.g., Self-esteem is positively related to self-disclosure). A variable is any construct or concept that can be observed to take on different values (e.g., anxiety, self-disclosure, assertiveness, etc.). It takes the form of X = fY. A definition (e.g., self-esteem is the degree to which self is perceived positively) characterizes the nature of a variable, but not its relationship to other variables. It takes the form of X = Y. All of this is just a fancy way of saying that the hypothesis paper attempts to develop, through review and personal argument, a series of hypotheses on a given topic. Many of these hypotheses may be articulated in the existing research literature, they may be derived from conceptual models, or the products of creativity and imagination. There are two keys to this assignment: (1) Developing well-conceived and well-worded hypotheses, and (2) developing reasonable arguments for each hypothesis. Like any argument, it is made credible through the use of causal analysis, evidence, example, strong reasons, and scholarly support. The most important thing is that every hypothesis should be carefully worded (read all these instructions to understand this warning) and arguments should answer two “why” questions: (1) Why are the variables related this way? (2) Why is the hypothesis likely to be true? The word “because” should figure prominently in the explanations. To explain a hypothesis means to make sensible how and why things are related the way they are. Theories are basically sets of conceptual links among hypotheses. For example, a person may want to explain the hypothesis: “As jealousy increases, the likelihood of relational violence increases.” Guided by an understanding of argument (e.g., see recommendations for writing that follow later in these instructions), this hypothesis could be argued thusly: Jealousy is a complex COMM 610 (Spring 2013): Advanced Communication Theory: p. 45 blend of emotions based on the perception that a person’s valued relationship is threatened by a third party or rival. [backing] Retzinger (1991) has reviewed evidence [grounds] that violence is likely to result from a combination of anger and shame, but neither alone [backing]. Because [warrant] anger creates an inner sense of expressive frustration and arousal, and shame provides a target for this expression (i.e., the partner and/or the rival), the jealous person is much more likely to engage in violence than non-jealous persons. [claim] This hypothesis may not apply to contexts in which strong moral, religious, or public restraints are in place (e.g., even jealous persons tend not to be overtly violent in public places). [rebuttal] The rebuttal is not necessary, but sometimes illustrates relative objectivity and openness of the author. In this explanation, other concepts (i.e., the theory of rage as proposed by Retzinger, with its components of anger and rage) are used to make the link between jealousy and violence sensible. More explanation could be provided for these concepts, more evidence reviewed in favor of Retzinger’s hypothesis, and so forth, but the basic elements of explanation and argument are there. The point is that explanation is neither mere restatement nor mere review of research or expert opinion. And please note, there is no quotation, and no need for quotation. Quotations should be used extremely sparingly—I want to see your writing, not someone else’s. Types of Hypotheses Below is a series of hypotheses to illustrate how they can differ. These hypotheses may seem overly sophisticated or technical right now. However, research of a topic has begun, hypothetical relations will begin to emerge either stated directly (i.e., in the form of hypotheses being tested) or indirectly (i.e., implied by the explanation and discussion of the concepts). The simplest, and weakest, form of hypothesis is a "non-directional" statement of relationship. For example: H1: Self-esteem is related to communication competence. While this is a hypothesis, it provides minimal information regarding the precise nature of the relationship. Avoid such statements in the paper. A more precise form is: H2: Self-esteem is positively related to interpersonal communication competence. (Note: This can be reworded as: “Persons high in self-esteem are significantly higher in communication competence than persons low in self-esteem”). Hypotheses can also vary by the form (or shape) of the relationship: H3: Motivation, knowledge and skills are curvilinear to perceived communication competence. (That is, they are positively related up to a moderately high range of competence, after which higher values lead to lower perceived competence). Finally, deductive construction allows the development of stronger, and more tightly controlled, theoretical arguments. For example, H4: H5: As [TV exposure] increases, [verbal skills] decrease. [A] [B] As [verbal skills] decrease, use of [physical violence] in conflict increases. COMM 610 (Spring 2013): Advanced Communication Theory: p. 46 H6: [B] [C] As [TV exposure] increases, use of [physical violence] in conflict increases. [A] [C] On the Art of Explanation “We cannot infer the events of the future from those of the present. Belief in the causal nexus is superstition” (Wittgenstein, Tractatus, 5.1361) Explanation implies the identification of some “bridge” (i.e., warrant, “because...,” etc.) that serves as an account of why one concept is related to another concept. It is an “animating mechanism,” that gives life to a concept. For example, one popular concept is that exposure to violence in the media causes violence in society. The natural question is why. Answering the “why” question gets at the concept of explanation. Even though seeing or hearing the equation: “media violence causes societal violence” seems like an explanation, it is not. It is missing the bridge, or animating mechanism. To illustrate, consider a few “non-explanations.” It is not an explanation to say media violence causes societal violence because: (1) media depictions of violence are increasing; (2) societal violence is increasing; (3) some people have engaged in crimes they saw on TV (“copy cat crimes”); (4) people believe what they see on TV; (5) research shows media violence increases societal violence. Each of these merely suggests correlation (rather than causation), repeats the original assertion, or simply provides backing for an explanation that is itself missing. To illustrate legitimate explanations, consider the following: Cultivation: Social learning theory claims that people learn both by direct experience (e.g., touching a hot stove) or observation of others (e.g., observing one’s sister touch a hot stove). Since we cannot or do not always directly experience things (e.g., robbing a bank), we look to real and imaginative role models (e.g., media figures and narratives). Thus, the crime and violence in the media provide models, and rewarding ones at that, for us we otherwise would not have had. Cognitive Availability: Our brain can be viewed as a library. If 90% of this library is filled with science fiction, and we are asked to respond to someone’s question for information, we are most likely to give them a fanciful piece of information, because that is what is most represented in our mind’s library. If, in watching media, most of the acts or ways of dealing with conflict we observe are violent in nature, it simply supplies more acts of violence to store in our mental repertoires, and thus, when we find ourselves in a conflict, violent acts are the most “available” to draw upon. Disinhibition: Growing up in a culture is largely about learning what one cannot or is not supposed to do. The very nature of culture is conformity and normative action within a given body of beliefs and behaviors. Exposure to violence in the media may make violence appear more normative than it is, and thus, make engaging in violence seem less deviant. In essence, it is not making violence seem more rewarding (cultivation) or available, but merely makes the violence within a person more acceptable. Fantasy Fulfillment: Freud and others might argue that daily life, as well as the normal tortures of growing up, fill us with tensions that are constantly repressed. These tensions struggle to “get out,” managing to manifest themselves mainly in the form of fantasy. Media violence may give form to these fantasies, making them more vivid and “real,” thereby COMM 610 (Spring 2013): Advanced Communication Theory: p. 47 stimulating the enactment of fantasies in life (e.g., who has not “fantasized” about hitting someone in the face—seeing it done may both “suggest” it, but stimulate the enactment of it). Desensitization: One of the reasons people avoid violence is that it hurts others. However, when violence is everywhere in the media, it can numb one’s sensibilities, and lower one’s ability to empathize. Further, the more cartoonish the violence, the more it seems it does not really hurt anyone. Such exposure to violence may take the “brakes” off using by making violence seem less hurtful, and thus, less costly to use. Excitation: Violence is a thrill. Through 5 million years of evolution, we have come to find violence a potential threat, a potential path to victory, and therefore, arousing. Thus, seeing violence in the media is itself, arousing, and this arousal stimulates our own arousal. Our arousal (adrenaline, muscular tension, etc.) needs to find an outlet, and is expressed in violence. Peer Group Mediation: Research on sexual violence indicates that people who engage in sexual violence are much more likely to have friends who approve of, and have engaged in, sexual violence. The suggestion is that peer groups mediate the transfer of violence. That is, if a peer group watches violence in the media, this peer group may then become self-reinforcing through its interaction, thereby serving as the proximal stimulus to its members’ violence. Spillover: Violence in the media provides models of behavior in certain contexts that are then available for generalization to contexts experienced in everyday life, both directly comparable to those observed in the media, as well as contexts largely unrelated. Thus, for example, a person may “copycat” behaviors witnessed in the media, but may also extend the function of the behaviors observed in one context (e.g., a drop kick in a professional wrestling program) to another context (e.g., a dispute with one’s brother). Cultural Chaos: Violence in the media may reflect the very breakdown of society, norms, and culture. If everyone is violent to everyone in the media, then this communicates a sense of despair, hopelessness, alienation and angst to the viewing public. This has the effects of both (1) inciting some to exploit the lawlessness (e.g., looting during natural disasters), (2) join the crowd (e.g., mob violence during the L.A. riots), (3) bystander apathy providing a permissive environment for violence. Each of these explanations offers slightly and sometimes substantively distinct sources of causation. For example, fantasy fulfillment, excitation and disinhibition tend to assume that we are by nature violent, and all that is needed is something in the media to take the restraints of society away. Cultivation and availability argue media instills violence in us. Peer-group mediation and cultural chaos tend to view media as having an effect on society at large, which only then affects our individual behavior. In all these examples concepts are elaborated to make sensible the link between violence in the media and in society. Co-occurrence makes no sense without an explanation, and it matters which explanation is offered. Do all of the explanations above seem equally believable? Were a politician to make a speech on fantasy fulfillment would it seem as reasonable as the cultivation explanation? Why? The “theory” cannot be evaluated until its explanatory rationale has been specified, and the brief examples above illustrate how significant, and distinct, such explanations can be. Finally, use theories, use concepts discussed in class, use concepts, rather than personal experience, anecdotes, examples, or intuitive explanations. The concepts and theories discussed in class represent an attempt to provide explanatory frameworks specifically to explain hypotheses. So use theories when possible to help explain the hypotheses. COMM 610 (Spring 2013): Advanced Communication Theory: p. 48 SELECTED EXAMPLES OF PUBLISHED HYPOTHESIS PAPERS Berelson, B., & Steiner, G. A. (1973). Human behavior: An inventory of scientific findings. New York: Harcourt, Brace & World. Berger, C. R., & Calabrese, R. J. (1975). Some explorations in initial interaction and beyond: Toward a developmental theory of interpersonal communication. Human Communication Research, 1, 99-112. Burgoon, J. K., & Jones, S. B. (1976). Toward a theory of personal space expectations and their violations. Human Communication Research, 2, 131-146. Burr, W.R., Leigh, G. K., Day, R. D., & Constantine, J. (1979). Symbolic interaction and the family. In W. R. Burr, R. Hill, F. I. Nye, & I. L. Reiss (Eds.), Contemporary theories about the family (pp. 42-111). New York: Free Press. Deutsch, M. (1949). A theory of co-operation and competition. Human Relations, 2, 129-152. Fincham, F. D. (1992). The account episode in close relationships. In M. L. McLaughlin, M. J. Cody, & S.J. Read (Eds.), Explaining one’s self to others: Reason-giving in social context (pp. 225-244). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum. Fisher, R. J. (1990). Chapter 5: An eclectic model of intergroup conflict. The social psychology of intergroup and international conflict resolution (pp. 87-115). New York: Springer-Verlag. Greene, J. (1984). A cognitive approach to human communication: An action assembly theory. Communication Monographs, 51, 289-306. Kaplowitz, S. A. (1978). Towards a systematic theory of power attribution. Social Psychology, 41, 131-148. Keyton, J., Ford, D. J., & Smith, F. L. (2008). A mesolevel communicative model of collaboration. Communication Theory, 18, 376-406. Liden, R. C., & Mitchell, T. R. (1988). Ingratiatory behaviors in organizational settings. Academy of Management Review, 13, 572-587. Mack, R. W., & Snyder, R. C. (1957). The analysis of social conflict—Toward an overview and synthesis. Journal of Conflict Resolution, 1, 221-248. Millar, F. E., & Rogers, L. E. (1988). Power dynamics in marital relationships. In P. Noller & M. A. Fitzpatrick (Eds.), Perspectives on marital interaction (pp. 98-120). Philadelphia: Multilingual Matters Ltd. Phillips, A. P., & Dipboye, R. L. (1989). Correlational tests of predictions from a process model of the interview. Journal of Applied Psychology, 74, 41-52. Rodgers, R. H. (1987). Postmarital reorganization of family relationships: A propositional theory. In D. Perlman & S. Duck (Eds.), Intimate relationships: Development, dynamics, and deterioration (pp. 239268). Newbury Park, CA: Sage. Sclenker, B. R., & Leary, M. R. (1982). Social anxiety and self-presentation: A conceptualization and model. Psychological Review, 92, 641-669. Seibold, D. R., & Spitzberg, B. H. (1982). Attribution theory and research: Formalization, critique, and implications for communication. In B. Dervin & M. J. Voight (Eds.), Progress in communication sciences (Vol. 3, pp. 85-125). Norwood, NJ: Ablex. Spitzberg, B. H. (1994). Intercultural effectiveness. In L. A. Samovar, & R. E. Porter (Eds.), Intercultural communication: A reader (7th ed., pp. 347-359). Belmont, CA: Wadsworth. Stech, E. L. (1979). A grammar of conversation with a quantitative empirical test. Human Communication Research, 5, 158-170. Wyer, R. S., Jr. (1980). The acquisition and use of social knowledge: Basic postulates and representative research. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 6, 558-573. Wyer, R. S., Jr., & Srull, T. K. (1986). Human cognition in its social context. Psychological Review, 93, 322359. COMM 610 (Spring 2013): Advanced Communication Theory: p. 49 SELECTIONS FROM SPITZBERG'S "CHAMBER OF HORRORS" Try to avoid the following pitfalls: (1) avoid statements of non-relationship (e.g., 'X is not related to Y'); (2) avoid including explanations in the hypothesis itself (e.g., "X is positively related to Y because of theory Z's rationale that..."); (3) avoid using prescriptive (e.g., "S's should do X when Y occurs") or purely descriptive non-probablistic (e.g., "X may/can be related to Y") wording; (4) avoid introducing terms into the hypothesis that have not been adequately explained, narrowed, or defined yet; and (5) avoid introducing categorical variables that distort the form of the relationship (e.g., "LOW X is positively related to HIGH Y's"); (6) avoid introducing set/subset redundancies in multiple hypotheses (e.g., P1: Females disclose more than males; P2: Androgynous females disclose more than androgynous males). Below are some of the "best of the worst" that have crossed my tired eyes. H1?: Knowledge also relates to mindlessness in an inverse parabolic function, in that they are positively related to each other until the mindlessness ceases to be mindless. H2?: Empathizing with co-workers strengths, weaknesses, and working style relates negatively towards escalating conflict resulting in an inability to see another's view. H3?: Equity restoring to a relationship is negatively related to low self-esteem individuals. H4?: Reactions in adolescents relate back to anxious, neurotogenic, disparging, masochistic, and manic depressive parents. H5?: Individual’s interaction with a caregiver as a child affects their relationship bondage with a potential partner as an adult. H6?: The purpose of negotiation is to resolve a disagreement between two or more parties. H7?: In certain negotiation circumstances nonverbal aspects of communication assume a greater significance than does verbal language. H8?: Levels of immediate physical and psychological trauma suffered by victims will vary. H9?: Child abuse is determined by the factors involved. H10?: The use of threats as an influence tactic does not exacerbate conflicts in general, but is limited to the occasions on which they are used. H11?: Conflicts are likely to be influenced by power. H12?: Sex differences are loosely related to relationship goals. H13?: Attraction is positively related and influential in choice of sexual partners. H14?: Males are negatively related to female interviewers of equal status; whereas females are not affected significantly to status and the sex of the interviewer. H15?: Mindlessness is negatively related to information processing in interactions. H16?: Deception is negatively related to the truth. H17?: Proximity increases physical closeness. H18?: Viewing the mediator’s role as folkloric trickster is positively related to their job title. H19?: Guests of a television talk show depend on the reaction of the audience for support of their heinous actions, therefore after the show is over whether or not they take the advice of the audience and change their way, depends on the reaction they received. H20?: Family hour will need to be changed back to true family hour. H21?: Hip hop is a response to conditions of property and disempowerment. H22?: Media coverage of the violent topics in Rap music helps alert people to the possible problems. COMM 610 (Spring 2013): Advanced Communication Theory: p. 50 ANYONE CAN FORMULATE THEORETICAL AXIOMS AND PROPOSITIONS Laws of Biological Inconvenience: 1. Law of Mechanical Repair: After your hands become coated with grease, your nose will begin to itch and you'll have to pee. 2. Law of Bio-Mechanics: The severity of the itch is inversely proportional to the reach. 3. Law of the Bath: When the body is fully immersed in water, the telephone rings. 4. Law of Gravity: Any tool, nut, bolt, screw, when dropped, will roll to the least accessible place in the universe. Laws of Social Activity and Impressions 5. Law of Probability: The probability of being watched is directly proportional to the stupidity of your act. 6. Law of Close Encounters: The probability of meeting someone you know INCREASES dramatically when you are with someone you don't want to be seen with. 7. Law of Random Numbers: If you dial a wrong number, you never get a busy signal - and someone always answers. Laws of (Bad) Luck & Self-Selection: 8. Law of Physical Surfaces: The chances of an open-faced jelly sandwich landing face down on a floor are directly correlated to the newness and cost of the carpet or rug. 9. Line Variation Law: If you change lines (or traffic lanes), the one you were in will always move faster than the one you are in now (works every time). 10. Seat Selection Corollary: At any event, the people whose seats are furthest from the aisle, always arrive last. They are the ones who will leave their seats several times to go for food, beer, or the toilet and who leave early before the end of the performance or the game is over. The folks in the aisle seats come early, never move once, have long gangly legs or big bellies and stay to the bitter end of the performance. The aisle people also are very surly folk. 11. Murphy's Law of Lockers: If there are only 2 people in a locker room, they will have adjacent lockers. 12. Wilson's Law of Commercial Marketing Strategy: As soon as you find a product that you really like, they will stop making it. Law of (Dis)Proof: 13. Law of the Result: When you try to prove to someone that a machine won't work, IT WILL!!! 14. Doctors' Corollary: If you don't feel well, make an appointment to go to the doctor, by the time you get there you'll feel better. But don't make an appointment, and you'll stay sick. 15. Law of Logical Argument: Anything is possible IF you don't know what you are talking about. Source: indeterminate—adapted from an extensively forwarded email. COMM 610 (Spring 2013): Advanced Communication Theory: p. 51 SOME OBJECT LESSONS ABOUT HYPOTHESES What follows are examples of flawed hypotheses taken from previous hypothesis papers. Each hypothesis is analyzed to illustrate common mistakes observed in the conceptualization and verbalization of hypotheses. It is your responsibility to study these examples, and thereby avoid the types of mistakes indicated. If you have questions about any of the issues raised, please raise them at the appropriate time in class. Otherwise, you are now considered forewarned. Recall that a hypothesis is any statement of relationship between or among variables. A variable is a concept that takes on different values. The entire function of science is to make the nature of the relationships among things understandable. The more precise the statement of relationship, the more understandable the hypothesis is. What follows is an effort to assist in making the hypotheses more precise. 1. MOOD IS POSITIVELY RELATED TO SEXUAL INITIATION. Overly generic variables: "Mood" may be positive or negative. Since mood is not specified, the hypothesis, as worded, implies that any increase in mood state will correspond to an increase in sexual initiation. Thus, as worded, an increase in depression increases sexual initiation, as would sadness anger, and so forth. The key is to understand that the term "mood" is a concept that can take on different values or levels (e.g., low to high, negative to neutral to positive, etc.). A hypothesis is an attempt to specify how their values or levels correspond to the values or levels of another concept, in this case, the occurrence of sexual initiation. The hypothesis intends to say "the experience of positively valenced or labeled states are positively related to the likelihood of sexual initiation." 2. LOW SELF-ESTEEM IS POSITIVELY RELATED TO INTERPERSONAL HOSTILITY. Mixing variable labels: Herein is one of the most common, insidious, yet subtle problems in writing hypotheses. By concerning itself with "low" self-esteem, this hypothesis effectively ignores "medium" and "high" self-esteem. When two-thirds of a variable's possible values are removed, its ability to "relate" to anything is eliminated because there is no real opportunity for the variable to vary beyond a very narrow range of values. The above statement intends to say simply: "Self-esteem is negatively related to interpersonal hostility" or "Low self-esteem persons are significantly more interpersonally hostile than high self-esteem persons." Think about what the terminology means! If something is categorized as "low" it needs to be compared to something that is "high." As an additional note, it is unclear if self-esteem relates to the frequency with which all hostile actions occur, the intensity of hostile actions, the duration of hostile actions, all three, some combination, or some other aspect of hostility. Hostility is likely to take on many different features. It assists the hypothesis to make these features clear in the hypothesis. Thus, "Self-esteem is negatively related to the frequency and breadth of interpersonally hostile behaviors." COMM 610 (Spring 2013): Advanced Communication Theory: p. 52 3. FRIENDSHIPS ARE HIGHLY VALUABLE TO OLDER MALES AND FEMALES. Overly definitional: This is overly definitional in form. First, does it imply the friendships are more valuable to older persons than younger person? (e.g., "The value of friendships for males and females increases as age increases"). Second, if a relationship is being identified that holds for all members of a set (i.e., persons), there is no need to specify all categories of that set (i.e., "males and females"). Thus, "The value of friendships increases as age increases." Third, to what is friendship "valuable"? Valuable in psychological health, physical health, social health, etc.? Thus, for example, "As age increases, the perceived value of friendship in preventing depression and loneliness increases." 4. MALES ARE POSITIVELY CORRELATED TO APPRECIATION OF OBSCENE HUMOR. Concepts not variable: "People" are not variables; their characteristics are. This hypothesis intends to compare 'maleness" to "femaleness. It makes the mistake of correlating categories. Categories are nominal level variables, whereas correlation requires ordinal level variables (recall COMM 350?). Gender, religion, ethnic group, etc. are categorical variables, and as such, should be framed as "difference" hypotheses rather than correlational hypotheses. Thus, "Males appreciate obscene humor significantly more than females." 5. SELF-DISCLOSURE IS POSITIVELY RELATED TO INTIMACY. Overly unidimensional concepts: On the face of it, this is sensible, right? Yet, this hypothesis is deeply flawed. First, anyone looking into the two concepts involved here, self-disclosure and intimacy, should soon find that they are multidimensional. This means that a valid use of the term actually implies many distinct but related concepts. For example, self-disclosure has been found to vary importantly in terms of breadth (number of topics), depth (intimacy of topics), reciprocity (degree to which partner discloses in response), honesty, and valence (positive or negative). Similarly, intimacy can be viewed in terms of domain (e.g., recreation I, sexual, social, emotional, etc.) or type (e.g., caring, commitment, interdependence, physical, etc.). The point is not that student papers have to agree with "the" view with which I am familiar, but that any responsible research effort will uncover the complexity (i.e., multidimensionality) of the concepts. In this case, the hypothesis implies that all forms of self-disclosure are equally related to all forms of intimacy. Is this sensible? It seems unlikely that as disclosure of negative information increases that sexual intimacy increases, yet this is exactly what the hypothesis implies until it is specified. Second, this is a perfect candidate for a curvilinear relationship. That is, extremely low or extremely high amounts of disclosure are likely to impede or inhibit intimacy respectively. Yet, this hypothesis implies that even at extremely high levels of disclosiveness that intimacy will also be extremely high. Third, would this hypothesis apply reasonably to all contexts? For example, does it apply to task-oriented groups, or superior-subordinate, or disengaging, relationships? Unlikely. COMM 610 (Spring 2013): Advanced Communication Theory: p. 53 6. ADULTERY, ALCOHOL ABUSE, AND FINANCIAL DIFFICULTIES ARE POSITIVELY RELATED TO DIVORCE. ‘NS’ hypothesis: This qualifies in the realm of an “NS” hypothesis (“No Shit!”). Technically there is nothing wrong with this hypothesis. However, it is about as unsurprising, and therefore, uninformative, as a statement can be. It’s a little like saying “Oxygen is important to human life.” Science has a healthy respect for demonstrating what is supposed to be true actually is true. But come on! Put a little imagination into the paper and come up with a statement that allows parents to think their children are learning something not already known without the degree. 7. AS MISUNDERSTANDINGS INCREASE, POOR COMMUNICATION INCREASES. Tautology: It is a little like saying that “X is true because it is X” (i.e., something is taken to be true because of the way in which it is defined). In this hypothesis, the question arises because for most commonsense notions, “misunderstanding” would be viewed as a form or subset of “poor communication.” Thus, if X “includes” Y, then it tends to make little logical sense to say that with more X, there will be more Y, since this is virtually true by definition of X. 8. A COWORKER WILL USE MORE INDIRECT COMPLIANCE-GAINING STRATEGIES WHEN ADDRESSING A SUBORDINATE. Lacking comparative condition: This sounds sensible. However, it is incomplete. Whenever the words “more” or “less” are used, the question arises “less (or more) than what?” In this case, it is not entirely clear which of the following phrases should be added to the end of the hypothesis: “...THAN WHEN ADDRESSING A SUPERIOR,” “...THAN DIRECT STRATEGIES,” or “THAN A COWORKER.” Complete the comparison implied by “more” or “less.” 9. SCHOLARS BELIEVE THAT ALCOHOLISM IS A DISEASE, WHILE OTHERS BELIEVE IT TO BE A BAD HABIT. Descriptive, not relational: This fails in three important senses. First, although it sounds like it is saying something substantive about the nature of alcoholism, it really is only saying something about what certain people believe about alcoholism, which was not the point of the paper. Second, it is not about communication, and therefore is not very topical to the assignment or major. Third, the hypothesis is definitional in content, not a hypothesis. There is no “relationship between variables” being described here. This hypothesis is stating something about what alcoholism is rather than what it is related to and how it is related. COMM 610 (Spring 2013): Advanced Communication Theory: p. 54 MODELS AND MODELING: A FUNDAMENTAL SCIENTIFIC LITERACY “Understanding that our scientific knowledge is ‘only’ a model is the key to true scientific literacy. Knowing this tells us that our science has built-in limitations, but that it does resemble reality in very fundamental ways. More importantly, that understanding gives us permission to use our models when they are useful— and permission to discard them when they no longer meet our needs. … Ultimately, our models and descriptions of reality must be subject to two overriding criteria: How useful is this model, and how much does this model resemble our observations. Scientific literacy requires an understanding that science is only a model.” Martin, T. W. (2007, Sept/Oct). Scientific literacy and the habit of discourse. Seed, pp. 77-78. Modeling is one of the zeniths of scientific reasoning. It incorporates analytic reasoning (i.e., breaking wholes into parts), synthetic reasoning (i.e., [re]assembling parts into wholes), and abstract reasoning (i.e., recognizing similar things across levels of abstraction and concreteness). It also is fundamental to theoretical reasoning (i.e., explaining how and why phenomena happen the way they do), and methodology (i.e., specifying hypotheses to be tested qualitatively or quantitatively, the results of which inform the validity of the underlying theory). Modeling involves developing a visual “map” of a “territory.” The territory is rarely known entirely, and in fact, sometimes it is only vaguely understood. The territory may have been observed in various ways, but seldom has it been observed in its entirety. Thus, a map is needed to navigate our way through this territory, and to guide the conduct of research into that territory, to see to what extent our map does a good job of representing that territory. Every territory, however, has a potentially infinite number of potential maps. Consider San Diego County. There are topographical, weather, road, tectonic activity, and photographic maps of the territory. Every one of these maps represents San Diego, but does so from a different point of view. A tectonic history map of San Diego is not likely to be very useful to someone seeking how to get from a house address in Ramona to a destination in the Gaslamp. Likewise, a road map is not likely to be very useful to a person seeking to predict where the next earthquake will occur. Furthermore, “the map is not the territory.” That is, the map is never the exact same thing as the territory. A map that completely represented a territory would be the territory. Thus, maps are abstractions. They are intended to be abstract representations. They are generally intended to have some degree of abstract generality as well. A map that only represents an extremely small and detailed event or place, and only represents a “snapshot” has limited value. Maps may change as the territory changes (this is why roadmaps are updated frequently), but they are usually intended to have some validity and value over time and space. This assignment involves the development of a type of map, which is here referred to as a model. Specifically, a model will be developed and arguments in defense of the model will be developed. The model will be developed to represent some communication process directly relevant to the course. Models vary by a number of various dimensions, any or all of which may be useful to consider as you ponder what kind of model to create. A partial list of such dimensions is explained below: COMM 610 (Spring 2013): Advanced Communication Theory: p. 55 (1) Abstraction Level: Models vary by the scope or level of abstraction they seek to represent. Marx’s theory of capitalist systems and social conflict was a very broad-based macro model of how societies evolve when property is privately owned. Janis’s mezzo model of groupthink attempts to explain why and how highly cohesive groups tend to reach premature consensus. Andersen’s cognitive valence model was developed to represent at a micro level how minute changes in intimacy behavior by one partner influences the response behaviors of the other partner. (2) Complexity: Some models are relatively simple, and hypothesize only a few relationships. For example, Spitzberg, Canary and Cupach predicted that the use of conflict strategies influences competence judgments, which then influence relationship quality. These three concepts produce a relatively small number of specific predictions. In contrast, Turner synthesized numerous theories and propositions to develop a model of social conflict that involves over 20 concepts and dozens of hypotheses. (3) Testability: Some models are relatively difficult to observe or test, and are therefore conjectural. Freud’s theories of the id, ego, and superego are highly conjectural because by definition, the unconscious is difficult to observe or test. In contrast, Cupach and Metts developed a model of how face-saving strategies are used to disengage from a relationship, which is relatively easy to test through surveys, narratives, or other techniques. A relatively easy litmus test for this dimension is to see how other scholars have “observed” (tested, measured, rated, scaled, coded, interviewed, etc.) the concepts in your model, if at all. If a concept has been previously studied by other scholars, then it can be tested or observed. If it is still a “hypothetical” concept, then it may be more conjectural in nature. (4) Recursiveness: Some models are strictly linear. That is, they progress from cause to effect. Other models are more processual, such that at various steps a given result may “feed back” into the process and influence prior processes. For example, a linear model might propose that lonely people are more likely to seek out parasocial relationships in the media than non-lonely people. In this case, loneliness causes media consumption behavior in a linear manner. In contrast, a model might propose that as lonely people consume more media, they are spending less time in social contexts, and therefore lose their social skills and confidence in their social abilities. In this model, then, the loneliness causes media behavior, which causes more loneliness, which causes more media behavior, and so forth. (5) Modeling Topoi: In general, all models have the potential for five basic types of concepts (variables, components, factors): a. Causes (also often referred to as antecedents, or “independent variables”): These are factors that influence subsequent events. As causes change, subsequent events change. Causes typically are further distinguished in two forms: distal and proximal. Distal causes are causes that occur “deep” in the process, typically meaning “far back” in time. Proximal causes are “closer” to the events or process being explained. So, for example, in modeling relationship aggression, distal causes might include whether a COMM 610 (Spring 2013): Advanced Communication Theory: p. 56 person grew up observing parent-to-parent aggression, and being the recipient of parental aggression. In contrast, proximal causes might include the amount of stress a person is experiencing in a job or school, and whether or not alcohol has been recently consumed. b. Context: The context is all those factors that influence how the situation is defined by those participating in a communicative process. Spitzberg, for example, has argued that contexts typically involve issues of culture, relationship type, physical situation, and goal or function of the communicative process. Related types of contextual factors might include time (e.g., slow cultures vs. fast cultures, early in a relationship vs. later in a relationship, etc.), activity level (e.g., a party vs. a classroom), or other such features. c. Individual Characteristics: These are features of the individuals involved that may influence how a process of communication unfolds. These features sometimes can be classified as causes or context factors, but may also be treated separately. For example, Spitzberg proposes that a person’s motivation, knowledge and skills increase the likelihood of engaging in communication that is perceived as competent by self and others. The motivation, knowledge, and skills themselves can be accounted for in part by the individual’s proximal and distal experiences (e.g., a person who received bad parenting growing up—i.e., a distal factor—may be least motivated to communicate competently in situations involving a partner who is behaving in ways similar to those parents—i.e., a more proximal factor). Traditionally, psychology has distinguished these as “traits” (i.e., stable predispositions to experience and react to the world in certain ways—e.g., low IQ) and “states” (i.e., temporary ways of experiencing a situation—e.g., situational shyness). d. Process: What are the communicative behaviors or processes being explained by the model? What do the causes and context influence a person or persons to do? For example, exposure to media violence and coming from a violent family background may intersect contexts of personal conflict to produce violent behavior as a process. e. Outcomes: What results from the confluence of these various components? For example, Spitzberg’s model proposes that as motivation, knowledge, and skills of interactants increase, they are more likely to engage in communication that is perceived to be appropriate and effective. These perceptions of appropriateness and effectiveness, in turn, are likely to result in greater attraction, persuasion, and relationship satisfaction and development. Thus, there are outcomes of competent interaction. (6) Component Functions: The various components described above can generally play a moderating or a mediating role. A moderating role means that the relationship between X and Z is significantly altered by the introduction or consideration of the variable Y. In contrast, a mediating role means that the relationship between X and Z disappears when the variable Y is introduced or considered. For example, a person who experienced parental violence as a child is more likely to engage in violence against a current romantic partner. However, if that person who experienced violence as a child is also consuming COMM 610 (Spring 2013): Advanced Communication Theory: p. 57 alcohol, that significantly increases the likelihood of engaging in violence against a current partner. Thus, alcohol moderates the relationship between childhood abuse and adult abuse. In contrast, the relationship between race and violent crime (Whites engage in less, Blacks engage in more) tends to disappear when controlling for socioeconomic status (SES), and thus, SES is a mediating variable. (7) Directionality: Some models represent relationships in indeterminate form, whereas other models specify the exact type of relationships anticipated. For example, a model might represent a link (or line) connecting “exposure to media violence” and “viewer’s violent behavior.” This link can be viewed as bi-directional (e.g., as a person’s exposure to violence increases, this person’s likelihood of engaging in violence increases, but also, as a person’s violent behavior increases, the more this person seeks out media content that reflects such violence). This link can also be specified as a particular type of relationship (e.g., consuming violent media increases the likelihood of behaving violently, but the reverse is not true—once a person engages in violence, consumption of violent media does not necessarily increase or decrease). Generally speaking, models consist of components and connections. The components represent some variable or process, and the connections consist of arrows or lines. A directional arrow indicates that a given variable causes or directly influences another variable. Thus, X Y means that X causes or influences Y. If the arrow is reversed (i.e., X Y), it means that Y causes or influences X. A double-sided arrow means that the relationship is reciprocal. If a sign is provided for an arrow (i.e., - or +), this indicates the type of relationship involved. A positive (or direct) relationship means that as X increases, Y increases, and as X decreases, Y decreases. A negative relationship means that as X increases, Y decreases, and as X decreases, Y increases. There is a third type of relationship that often describes communication processes—curvilinear. Although there are many types of curved lines that could represent the relationship between concepts, one of the most common is that as X increases, Y increases, to a point, beyond which, more X results in less Y. For example, as a person talks more and more, generally speaking, we tend to find this person more attractive and competent. However, as a person begins to talk during 80 or 90% of the time in a conversation, the more we tend to view this person as egotistical and narcissistic. Thus, talk time in a conversation is curvilinear to perceived competence (i.e., as talk time increases, perceived competence increases, to a point, beyond which, perceptions of competence decrease). (8) Formality: There are many potential ways of defining formality in a model, but for the purposes of this assignment, formality is the extent to which the model can be translated into hypotheses or specific propositions. For the most part, the more that the connectors of a model have directional and sign-specific connectors, the more formal the model will be. Informal models simply illustrate variables that affect one another, but do not specify how or in what specific ways each of the components is related to the other components of the model. Formal models specify not only which components affect which other components (and by implication, what components are not related to one another), they specify the exact predicted type of relationship among components of the model. (9) Spatial Logic: Most (but not all) models follow relatively simple rules: (1) Components on the left precede, at some point, the components to the right in real time (except when COMM 610 (Spring 2013): Advanced Communication Theory: p. 58 there are feedback loops or arrows). (2) Every arrow represents a direct effect of one concept on another. This effect does not have to be a causal relationship, but it usually implies such an influence. (3) Every component must have an arrow headed to at least one other component, and may have arrows to multiple other components. (4) The spatially closer two components are to one another, the more closely they are associated with one another than to components further away from one another. (5) Components can be hierarchically grouped according to larger components (i.e., multiple indicators of a single concept; e.g., social skills above might be further indicated by coordination, expressiveness, attentiveness, and composure skills). (6) Every arrow is a potentially testable hypothesis (or proposition). This assignment requires that a model of some communicative process be developed, explained, and defended. The following minimum requirements apply: (1) (2) The model must be in some central way directly related to communication. There must be at least five components with at least one component each representing cause, context, individual factor, process, and outcome. More components can be provided, but there must be at least one component that fits each of these component types. (3) There must be at least five directional arrows. There can be far more, but at least five must be provided. (4) At least 10 formal propositions emerging from the model must be formally stated as hypotheses. More propositions can be articulated, but there must be at least five. (5) Each component must have at least one scholarly journal article that provides backing for arguments related to that component. (6) The complete model must be capable of being summarized in an abstract 500 words or less. (7) The model must be rendered in a visual form (preferably using the drawing tools in Word, or PowerPoint, which is subsequently saved as an image and imported into Word). (8) The paper, and the reference list, must be in A.P.A. (5th ed.) format, with 1-inch margins, double-spaced, and either 11-point Arial (normal) or 12-point Times Roman font. The pages of the paper should have a running head, which includes serial pagination. (9) The entire paper cannot be more than 7 pages in length (not including appended article ‘first-page prints’), such that: a. Title page (= 1 page; which includes student name, red id#, class #, class title, semester/year, and of course, a title that represents the topic of the model). b. Model visual figure (= 1 page) c. Proposition list (= 1 page) d. Abstract (= 1-2 pages) e. Reference list (= 1-2 pages) (10) The abstract provides both explanation and argument in support of the model. The idea is to explain the overall model (i.e., “make sense” of it), and provide key arguments along the way for as many of the key links or relationships as possible within the space allotted. Arguments will typically consist of backing (i.e., sources, evidence, citations, quotations, statistics), claim (i.e., the arrow or proposition), and warrant(s) (i.e., the reason why the claim is sensible or valid). COMM 610 (Spring 2013): Advanced Communication Theory: p. 59 Sample models will be displayed in class, illustrating some of the many ways in which communication theories, processes, and concepts can be visually modeled and explained. Students may adapt already existing models, but when doing so, must cite the existing model, and explain how the student model differs from, or advances, the existing model. As an exemplar of different types of models and their theoretical value and comparison, see: Spitzberg, B. H., & Chagnon, G. (2009). Conceptualizing intercultural communication competence. In D. K. Deardorff (Ed.), The SAGE Handbook of intercultural competence (pp. 2-52). Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage. COMM 610 (Spring 2013): Advanced Communication Theory: p. 60 THINKING IN TOULMANESQUE TERMS DATA CLAIM WARRANT DISCOVERY METHODS N hrs exposure media violence/ hrs viewing + Experimental exposure/ no exposure Pos. r of violence exposure & violent behavior Given that exposure provides social learning models … Therefore, violence in the media reinforces violence in society INTERPRETIVE METHODS Most TV interpersonal violence is men against women Therefore, media portray violence in gender exploitative & harmful ways Thereby, normalizing violence against women… CRITICAL METHODS Parental involvement In children’s media habits decreases exposure to violence Therefore, congress should adopt parental control technology mandates Therefore, technological fixes exist that protect freedom of speech… “There are two modes of cognitive functioning, two modes of thought, each providing distinctive ways of ordering experience, of constructing reality. The two (though complementary) are irreducible to one another. Efforts to reduce one mode to the other or to ignore one at the expense of the other inevitably fail to capture the rich diversity of thought. Each of the ways of knowing, moreover, has operating principles of its own and its own criteria of well-formedness. They differ radically in their procedures for verification. A good story and a wellformed argument are different natural kinds. Both can be used as means for convincing another. Yet what they convince of is fundamentally different: arguments convince one of their truth, stories of their lifelikeness. The one verifies by eventual appeal to procedures for establishing formal and empirical proof. The other establishes not truth but verisimilitude. … The types of causality implied in the two modes are palpably different. The term then functions differently in the logical proposition ‘if x, then y’ and in the narrative recit ‘The king died, and then the queen died.’ One leads to a search for universal truth conditions, the other for likely particular connections between two events—mortal grief, suicide, foul play. … a story … is judged for its goodness as a story by criteria that are of a different kind from those used to judge a logical argument as adequate or correct.” Brunner, J. (1986). Actual minds, possible worlds. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. COMM 610 (Spring 2013): Advanced Communication Theory: p. 61 PROPOSITION/MODEL PAPER EVALUATION SHEET Name: E-mail: Brief Title: 0 1 Red ID: Email: 2 3 4 Form displays: multiple types & instances within type of writing or grammatical errors in expositional text, &/or displays inconsistency in rule application; frequent reediting or rephrasing to achieve more professional voice is suggested. 0 1 2 1 2 3 1 2 3 3 1 2 3 Model concepts involve partially incomplete, occasionally unclear or unarticulated interrelationships among the components; &/or some paths through the model are vague; &/or some component labeling is inconsistent or uninformative. -3 SUBSTANCE—RESEARCH 5 6 7 Some key claims of the source(s) are articulated or delineated, but there are some inconsistencies in the detail, gravity, or evidentiary basis provided in explicating the claims. 4 Model is mostly a typology or list of concepts, with incomplete, unclear or unarticulated interrelationships among the components; &/or overall paths through the model are vague; &/or component labeling is inconsistent or uninformative. -1 -2 COMMENTS: Only minor or one or two propositions need editing for sake of clarity. 4 The key claims of the source(s) are not clearly articulated or delineated. Specific reference to passages in the book(s) is not consistently provided, or not provided in sufficient detail or accuracy to test the claims. 0 Form displays: few types & instances within type of writing or grammatical errors in expositional text, &/or inconsistency in rule application; occasional re-editing or rephrasing to achieve more professional voice is suggested. 8 SUBSTANCE—MODEL 5 6 7 Model concepts involve partially incomplete, occasionally unclear or unarticulated interrelationships among the components; &/or some paths through the model are vague; &/or some component labeling is inconsistent or uninformative. -4 APA STYLE -5 -6 -7 9 10 Writing displays professional composition, and grammatical form. 8 9 voice, 10 Propositions are both logically sound, but sophisticated in their thematic connection &/or articulation of complex relationships. SUBSTANCE—ARGUMENTATION 4 5 6 7 8 Model is mostly a typology or list of concepts, with incomplete, unclear or unarticulated interrelationships among the components; &/or overall paths through the model are vague; &/or component labeling is inconsistent or uninformative. 0 FORM—WRITING 5 6 7 SUBSTANCE—PROPOSITIONS 4 5 6 7 The key claims are not clearly articulated or delineated. Propositions fail by level of scaling, relationship, or syllogistic entailment. “Object lessons” or “list of horrors” are repeated. 0 Date: Course: 9 10 Model is typologically innovative &/or comprehensive, with clear and articulated interrelationships among the components; & overall paths through the model are easy to follow; & component labeling is consistent and informative. 8 9 10 Several key claims are clearly identified, articulated, and the evidentiary basis of them in the source(s) is elaborated. 8 9 10 Model is typologically innovative &/or comprehensive, with clear and articulated interrelationships among the components; & overall paths through the model are easy to follow; & component labeling is consistent and informative. -8 -9 -10 Grade: COMM 610 (Spring 2013): Advanced Communication Theory: p. 62 ANTHROPOCENTRISMS "Many different root metaphors have been put forth to represent the essential nature of human beings: Homo faber, Homo economicus, Homo politicus, Homo sociologicus, "psychological man," "ecclesiastical man," Homo sapiens, and of course, "rational man." I propose that Homo narrans be added to the list....The Homo narrans metaphor is thus an incorporation and extension of Burke's definition of "man" as the "symbol-using (symbol-making, symbol-misusing) animals....It holds that symbols are created and communicated ultimately as stories meant to give order to human experience and to induce others to dwell in them in order to establish ways of living in common, in intellectual and spiritual communities in which there is confirmation for the story that constitutes one's life." Fisher, W.R. (1987). Human communication as narration. Columbia: U. of S. Carolina. pp. 62-3. "What kind of man would homo rhetoricus be?... rhetorical man must have felt an overpowering selfconsciousness about language..... Rhetorical man is an actor; his reality public, dramatic.... The lowest common denominator of his life is a social situation. And his motivations must be characteristically ludic, agonistic. He thinks first of winning, of mastering the rules the current game enforces. He assumes a natural agility in changing orientations.... Rhetorical man is trained not to discover reality but to manipulate it.... Homo rhetoricus cannot, to sum up, be serious. He is not pledged to a single set of values and the cosmic orchestration they adumbrate." Lanham, R.A. (1976). The motives of eloquence: Literary rhetoric in the renaissance (pp. 3-5). New Haven: Yale. "Man is above everything else the talking animal—homo loquens. The overwhelming majority of human beings spend a great deal of their time talking an listening to each other." (p.3). "Homo loquens has received the gift of speech which marks him off from all other creatures that we know about and is undoubtedly responsible for his development up to the point which he has now reached." (p. 167). Fry, D. (1977). Homo loquens: Man as a talking animal. Cambridge: Cambridge University. "In a rhetorical masterstroke, Turner (1986, p. 81) subversively redefined the fundamental terms of discussion in ethnography by defining humankind as homo performans, humanity as performer, a cultureinventing, social performing, self-making and self-transforming creature." Conquergood, D. (1991). Rethinking ethnography: Towards a critical cultural politics. Communication Monographs, 58, 187. "We do not need to settle the philosopher's question of what is the essential condition for the existence of intentionality, nor buy Brentano's famous criterion that intentionality is the distinctive mark of the mental, to recognize that human beings think and plan and intend, that if rats do so they do it at a much lower level, that sunflowers probably do not, and that stones certainly do not.... [These] systems do not possess the capacity to think worry, regret, plan, and intend... There are a number of other things that human beings do that no infrahuman animal does, so far as we know. Only man speculates about nonpractical, theoretical matters; only man worships; only man systematically goes about seeking revenge, years later, for an injury done to him; only man carries on discussions about how to make decisions; ..." Meehl, P.E. (1978). Theoretical risks and tabular asterisks: Sir Karl, Sir Ronald, and the slow progress of soft psychology. Journal of Consulting and Clinical Psychology, 46, 806-834. “For heuristic purposes, let’s invent a new species designation: Homo symbolicus. . . . More than any other group of species, hominids’ behavioral adaptations have determined the course of their physical evolution, rather than vice versa. . . . The origin of ‘humanness’ can be defined as that point in our evolution where these tools became the principle source of selection on our bodies and brains. It is the diagnostic trait of Homo symbolicus.” Deacon, T. (1997). The symbolic species: The co-evolution of language and the human brain. London: AllenLane, Penguin Press. 341, 345. COMM 610 (Spring 2013): Advanced Communication Theory: p. 63 STATUS SCENARIOS OF THE COMMUNICATION DISCIPLINE (Spitzberg, 1999) I. Communication as “discipline”: “Merely one among many” Literary Criticism Psychology COMMUNICATION Sociology Anthropology Philosophy II. Communication as “Inter-discipline”: a “crossroads” or “intersection” (ala Littlejohn) COMMUNICATION Psychology Sociology Miscellaneous Anthropology Literary Criticism Philosophy III. Communication as “Pan-discipline”: a topic domain cutting across disciplines. Psychology Sociology Anthropology Philosophy Literary Criticism COMMUNICATION IV. Communication as “Meta-discipline”: a “McKeonesque” architectonic COMMUNICATION Psychology Sociology Anthropology Philosophy Literary Criticism COMM 610 (Spring 2013): Advanced Communication Theory: p. 64 Educational Sports Medical Group Communication Business Social Interaction Theories Public Comm. Individual Theories Legal Tier 4 Tier 3 Tier 2 Message Related Theories Tier 1 Representative continua used to distinguish levels Public Number of people Agent controlling communication event Interpersonal Cultural Comm. Family Theories Communicator Centered Situation Centered Context Centered Message- Centered Levels of Communication Group Interpersonal Dyadic/Triadic -------------------------------------------------------------------------Large (> 10) Mod. (> 3, < 9) Dyadic/Triadic One to many can contribute Degree of formality expected in event Religious High Leader with agenda, but all contribution(s) Mutual control of course & Determined by agenda but some Low Intermediate, when relevant Moderately high informality expected Degree of personal information exchanged Low Adapted from Powers, J. H. (1995). On the intellectual structure of the human communication discipline. Communication Education, 44, 11-22. COMM 610 (Spring 2013): Advanced Communication Theory: p. 65 DISTINGUISHING THE SCIENCES FROM THE HUMANITIES Science: The systematic application of method and observation in the pursuit of discovery and testing of reasoned conjectures regarding the description and explanation of worldly phenomena. Or, the systematic search for explicable and replicable pattern(s)? Humanities: The textual exploration of the myriad meanings and implications of personal and human existence and possibilities? Traditional dualities: HUMANITIES SCIENCES PROCEDURAL CONCERNS Imaginative (mentalistic) The possible (the imaginable) Bricolage (using whatever is available) Progressively distinctive Empirical (inter-observability) The testable & observable (predictable) Systematic (deduction, induction, probability) Progressively corrective ETHICAL CONCERNS Private (audience of the self) Openness to experience & experiencable Self-examining/reflective Adopting critical stance Public (audience of the peers & the world) Skeptical of experience & the known Self-correcting Eschews critical standpoint PHILOSOPHICAL CONCERNS Embrace self-reflexivity Reflexively interdependent Idiosyncratic Ideological (theological, axiological) Celebration of ineffability Control self-reflexivity Reflexively independent Generalizable Theoretical Reduction of ineffability “hermeneuticists and positivists share more than reciprocal insults. They share that idealized, and perhaps outmoded, conception of objective science in which there is no place for a science of subjectivity. That conception can be crudely reiterated by reference to what I shall call ‘the standard dichotomies,” a parallel series of oppositions beginning with the opposition between the objective versus the subjective and ending with the opposition between the natural sciences versus the humanities. The series runs as follows: objective versus private, controlled versus free, reliable versus unreliable, systematic versus unsystematic, automatic (mechanical) versus willed (purposive), explanation versus understanding, prediction versus understanding, explained-by-reference-to-causallaw versus understood-by-reference-to-intentions, general versus context-specific, regular versus irregular, discovered versus constructed, value-free versus value-saturated, formal versus informal, materialist versus idealist, one versus many, instrumental versus symbolic, motion versus action, science versus humanity” (Shweder, 1986, p. 177) Notice what dualities are not considered part of the distinction (e.g., creativity? artistry, etc.) Science “seeks” to account for the enduring patterns of variation of human and nonhuman form, function, and process. But the form, function and process(es) of seeking are themselves deeply “human” and thus, intrinsically humanistic. COMM 610 (Spring 2013): Advanced Communication Theory: p. 66 PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE “Recent developments in the philosophy of science and related areas of philosophy, and in the philosophies of the various special sciences, have progressed to a point where a new ‘postpositivist’ consensus has emerged….there has evolved a consensus about which more specific philosophical and scientific matters any adequate general philosophical conception of science must account for, along with a consensus about the broad outlines of the relevant philosophical positions, options, and argumentative strategies. Roughly, the recent developments that have led to the new consensus are: 1. The emergence of sophisticated realist and neo-Kantian alternatives to traditional empiricist conceptions of science, and of more sophisticated post-positivist version of empiricism in response to them. 2. The development of ‘naturalistic’ or ‘causal’ conceptions of reference and of the definitions of natural kind (magnitude, property,…) terms as alternatives to the standard empiricist conceptions of such matters. 3. Corresponding naturalistic developments in epistemology. 4. Critiques (and consequent reformulations) of the Humean conception of causal relations and of the associated covering-law account of explanation. 5. A greatly increased emphasis on the relevance of the history of science for work in the philosophy of science and a consequent de-emphasis of the alleged distinction between ‘context of invention (or discovery)’ and ‘context of confirmation (or justification).’ 6. The emergence of a distinct and philosophically important post-positivist literature in the philosophies of the various ‘special sciences’ (especially biology, psychology, and history), particularly the emergence of a nonreductionist account of the relation between the special sciences and the more basic physical sciences. 7. A similar post-positivist reevaluation of issues in the philosophy of physics. The resulting picture of scientific knowledge, of scientific language, and of causation and explanation is vastly more complex than the simple account dictated by traditional logical positivism and, consequently, is philosophically much richer. The newly emerging consensus resulting from this picture appears to have roughly the following components: a. Scientific methodology is ineliminably theory-dependent, and the depth of its theorydependence rules out any simple verificationist conception of science. The serious contenders among general positions in the philosophy of science are scientific realism and neo-Kantian constructivism—both of which arose as responses to the apparent theory-dependence of scientific methods—and sophisticated post-positivist versions of empiricism that arose as responses to these positions. b. Foundationalist conceptions of knowledge in general, and of scientific knowledge in particular, are untenable in many of the ways suggested by defenders of causal or naturalistic conceptions of knowledge, both because of the theory-dependence of scientific methods and for independent reasons arising from causal theories of perception. Any account of scientific knowledge must embody at least some naturalistic elements, whatever its author’s ultimate position on epistemological matters. COMM 610 (Spring 2013): Advanced Communication Theory: p. 67 c. For similar reasons, we must acknowledge that the definitions of scientific concepts and of terms in scientific language are theory-dependent; any adequate account of the semantics of scientific knowledge must reflect this fact and must—whatever its author’s ultimate position on semantic matters—reflect some of the insights of causal or naturalistic conceptions of definition and of reference. d. Because of the importance of ‘naturalistic’ considerations in the philosophy of science, the ‘natural history’ of scientific theorizing—the history of science—provides a very important constraint on theories in the philosophy of science. The distinction between context of discovery and context of confirmation is correspondingly less important than positivists imagined. e. The Humean conception of causation and the associated covering-law conception of explanation are by no means obviously correct; they must compete with both constructivist and naturalistic alternatives. f. Materialist conceptions of both biological and psychological matters are well confirmed, but materialism within a special science does not require the sort of syntactic reducibility to physics anticipated by logical positivists. The biological and social sciences can be ‘autonomous’ from the physical sciences even on the assumption of materialism. A reductionist approach in a special science requires a defense in terms of the special features of that science rather than in terms of an appeal to a generally reductionist analysis of materialism. g. Because they are arguably autonomous, the various special sciences (and their histories) are as relevant for the philosopher of science as are the physical sciences. h. Because of the importance of naturalistic approaches in the philosophy of science, and because many methodological disputes within the various special sciences have a heavily philosophical component, there is an important and appropriate dialectical interaction between research in the philosophy of science and research in the various special sciences.” Boyd, R., Gasper, P., & Trout, J. D. (1991). In R. Boyd, P. Gasper, & J. D. Trout (Eds.), The philosophy of science (xi-xiii). Cambridge, MA: Bradford/MIT Press. COMM 610 (Spring 2013): Advanced Communication Theory: p. 68 CRITERIA FOR EVALUATING THEORIES (Spitzberg, 2013) “Standards compete just as theories compete and we choose the standards most appropriate to the historical situation in which the choice occurs” Feyerabend (1980, “How to defend…”, p. 59) I. NECESSARY CONDITIONS: 1. Explanatory Power: The theory must provide a sensible account of the phenomena of concern 2. Construct and Conditionship Specification: The theory must indicate the nature of the constructs and the relationships among these constructs (i.e., necessity, sufficiency, parameters, function form, generality, etc.) 3. Boundary Specification: The theory must indicate the domain of its legitimate scope and relevance 4. Intra-Boundary Generality: The theory must provide statements of relationship that hold across all phenomena of concern 5. Internal Consistency: The theory must maintain logical consistency of all statements of conditionship, assumptions, and units 6. External consistency: The theory must avoid contradiction of "known" data 7. Verifiability: The theory must be potentially verifiable, such that it is: A) Operational: A sufficient number of the theoretical units must be capable of being measured/observed B) Falsifiable: It must be possible to establish conditions under which statements of the theory can be observed to be true/untrue II. DESIRABLE CONDITIONS: 1. Precision: The more the theory allows prediction of phenomena, the better the theory: A) End State Prediction: Prediction of some identifiable "outcome" of the phenomena behavior B) Phase State Prediction: Prediction of various stages or evolving states of behavior toward an end state 2. Parsimony: The more elegant and simple the theory, the better the theory 3. Correspondence with Observables: The more of the theory units that are observable, the better the theory 4. Breadth: The broader the scope or range of the theory, the better the theory; i.e., verisimilitude 5. Control: The greater the potential for strategic manipulation of the phenomena, the better the theory 6. Heurism/Novelty/Progressiveness: The more novel content, and the more the theory suggests in the way of new scientific endeavors, the better the theory. The more the theory explains new facts or counterintuitive facts, the better the theory. 7. Synthesis: The more the theory facilitates the organization and inclusion of ideas and information, the better the theory COMM 610 (Spring 2013): Advanced Communication Theory: p. 69 III. RELATIVE CONDITIONS: 1. Competition Principle: Theories should compete favorably vis-à-vis their rivals (Colomy, 1991); “theory evaluation is primarily a comparative affair” (Laudan, 1981, p. 145); “There is no falsification before the emergence of a better theory” (Lakatos, 1970, p. 119). 2. Money in the Bank Principle: “We are warranted in continuing to conjecture that a theory has high verisimilitude when it has accumulated ‘money in the bank’ by passing several stiff tests” (Meehl, 1990, p. 115) 3. Damn Strange Coincidences Principle: “The main way a theory gets money in the bank is by predicting facts that, absent the theory, would be antecedently improbable” (Meehl, 1990, p. 115). 4. Aesthetics: “A good theory is a plausible theory, and a theory is judged to be more plausible and of higher quality if it is interesting rather than obvious, irrelevant or absurd, obvious in novel ways, a source of unexpected connections, high in narrative rationality, aesthetically pleasing, or correspondent with presumed realities” (Weick, 1989, p. 517). IV. CRITICAL CONDITIONS: 5. Generative capacity: “the capacity to challenge the guiding assumptions of the culture, to raise fundamental questions regarding contemporary social life, to foster reconsideration of that which is ‘taken for granted,’ and thereby to generate fresh alternatives for social action” (Gergen, 1994, Toward transformation…, p. 109) 6. Counter-suggestiveness: “What we need here is an education that makes people contrary, counter-suggestive, without making them incapable of devoting themselves to the elaboration of any single view” (Feyerabend, 1980, p. 63) IV. DEFINITION: "A theory is a verifiable conceptual system of interrelated formal or informal propositions explaining conditionship among a set of phenomena, which is generalizable within a defined domain, and is internally consistent and externally sensible." (Spitzberg, 1998) COMM 610 (Spring 2013): Advanced Communication Theory: p. 70 CRITERIA FOR EVALUATING ETHNOGRAPHIC WORK Ethnographic writing is higher quality when it reveals the following characteristics: 1. Multi-voiced text: Captures diverse, competing voices—it questions realism and raise contradictions. It raises as many voices as possible, and these voices often contradict one another. 2. Critical text: Exposes the politics of how values, race, class, and gender work their way into our interactions and have consequences. 3. Catalytic text: Awakens moral sensibilities of the reader, becoming a catalyst, moving us or those participating to action. 4. Dialogic text: Captures dialogue within the scene in ways that we identify or become identified with the characters. 5. Processual text: Explicates a process of communicating. 6. Reflexive text: Reveals author’s positioning—physically, ideologically, and emotionally. Minimizes distance between reader and author. 7. Embodied text: Describes the scene, thickly, lushly, utilizing all the senses in ways that engages reader and brings them close. Thick description, feeling like you were there. 8. Temporal text: Indicates the passage of time in its multiple forms, not necessarily sequentially, representing the elapsing of time. Also, don’t be a “weekend ethnographer.” Adapted from: Scarduzio, J. A., Giannini, G. A., & Geist-Martin, P. (2011). Crafting an architectural blueprint: Principles of design for ethnographic research. Symbolic Interaction, 34(4), 447-470. doi:10.1525/si.2011.34.4.447 . COMM 610 (Spring 2013): Advanced Communication Theory: p. 71 COMPARATIVE PERSPECTIVES ON THEORY EVALUATION “Examples of the heuristic statements of currently competing methods are: (1) Popper’s heuristic advice: Adopt the theory that is best corroborated [Note: i.e., has withstood the most severe attempts at falsification]. (2) Lakatos’ heuristic advice: Adopt the theory that exhibits an empirically progressive problemshift. “a series of theories is theoretically progressive (or ‘constituted a theoretically progressive problem-shift’) if each new theory has some excess empirical content over its predecessor, that is, if it predicts some novel, hitherto unexpected fact. Let us say that a theoretically progressive series of theories is also empirically progressive (Or ‘constitutes an empirically progressive problemshift’) if some of this excess empirical content is also corroborated, that is, if each new theory leads us to the actual discovery of some new fact…Finally, let us call a problemshift progressive if it is both theoretically and empirically progressive, and degenerating if it is not” (Lakatos, 1970, p. 118) (3) Kuhn’s heuristic advice: Adopt the theory that is simple, consistent, fecund, and so on, and that most responds to the scientists’ tutored and practiced intuitions. (4) Laudan’s heuristic advice: Adopt the theory that exhibits the highest rate of problem-solving effectiveness, in which “problems” represent claims about the world that have yet to be satisfactorily explained. [Note 1: verisimilitude—truth—is relatively irrelevant to this criterion. Note 2: “the problem-solving effectiveness of a theory is determined by the number of problems solved minus the number of anomalies” (p. 114)]. TMT1 (Theoretical Merit) = ((Neps + Ncps ) – (Neap x Ieap) + (Ncpp x Ccps, ))/TM2 Where: T1 = Theory 1 Neps = N of empirical problems solved Neap = N of empirical anomalies produced Ncps = N of conceptual problems solved Ieap = Importance of anomalies Ncpp = N of conceptual problems produced Ccps = Centrality of conceptual problems (5) Feyerabend’s heuristic advice: Adopt any theory [Note: because the more alternative conceptualizations, the more likely they will compete and converge, or that the best will emerge].” (Sarkar, 1983, p. 162; “Notes” reflect Spitzberg’s interpretative additions) (6) Penman’s “good theoretic” paradigm: Adopt the theory that conceptualizes human behavior as voluntary, knowledge as socially constituted and historically embedded, is selfreflective about agency and intervention, and can serve as a basis for moral evaluation. “Good communication theory and good communication practice would be those that enrich our experience and increase our options and opportunities for actions. Bad communication, conversely, restricts or negates our experiences and options” (Penman, 1992, p. 241) COMM 610 (Spring 2013): Advanced Communication Theory: p. 72 (7) Czubaroff’s “deliberative” advice: Adopt the theory/paradigm that receives the most credible prima facie case in the fabric of scientific rhetoric. Thus, (1) it identifies a need for a change, (2) it details a plan to meet the need, and (3) it argues the relative benefits of the proposed plan. In the matrix of disciplinary debate surrounding competing paradigms, “The rhetorically astute scientific advocate will take into account four dimensions of the communication situation. First, the advocate will, as far as possible, respect situational rules of communication procedure and proof….Second, the rhetorically sensitive scientific advocate will systematically analyze the dispute….Third, the effective scientific advocate will distinguish and take into account the goals of the scientific advocacy situation and the goals of the individual scientific advocates….Finally, the effective scientific advocate will identify and analyze the audience which is to judge the advocacy” (Czubaroff, 1989, pp. 34-35). (7) Alexander & Colomy’s “competitive” advice: “The primary motor of social scientific change is conflict and competition between and within traditions” (p. 39). “Most schools contain two or more tradition segments….the longer a school persists the more segments it will create.… Relations among tradition segments are always competitive, but the competition ranges from the friendly…to more divisive forms” (pp. 42-43). “Competition is hardly an infallible mechanism for advancing knowledge. Competition between and within schools is as much a sociological process as an epistemological one, and the dynamics that propel it can impede genuine knowledge cumulation. Plainly put, the traditions or tradition segments that win in the social sciences do not always have the best arguments” (Alexander & Colomy, 1992, p. 44). (8) Social constructionist advice: Adopt the theory that meets the following criteria best: “(1) The theory should be explicitly critical….(2) The theory should recognize that humans are active agents….(3) The theory should account for the life experiences of the client….(4) The theory should promote social justice” (Witkin & Gottschalk, 1988, pp. 219-220). (9) Power ratio: “The power of a theory can be measured by the amount it explains divided by the amount that must be assumed for that explanation. A theory that needs to make hundreds of assumptions Is not much better than a description of what you observe. A powerful theory is one that can explain lots and lots of observations while hardly making any assumptions” (Richard Dawkins: interview: San Diego Union-Tribune, Monday, April 20, 2009, p. E-1). COMM 610 (Spring 2013): Advanced Communication Theory: p. 73 ELABORATIONS ON COMPARATIVE PERSPECTIVES ON THEORY EVALUATION “Some attack methods as pandering to mob psychology (so says Lakatos about Kuhn), some maintain that their opponents have missed the main point of scientific activity (so says Kuhn about Popper), some charge that the empirical facts that methods bring forward in support of their methodological claims are irrelevant (so says Popper about Kuhn), some argue that the problem of demarcation others pursue is a pseudoproblem (so says Laudan about Popper), and, finally, some maintain that the whole enterprise of methodology rests on a mistake (so says Feyerabend)” (Sarkar, 1983, p. 7) According to Lakatos, “A series of theories is an empirically progressive problem-shift if, and only if, (1) each subsequent theory contains the unrefuted content of an earlier theory and is itself the result of adding an auxiliary hypothesis to the previous theory in order to accommodate an anomaly; (2) some novel consequences are theoretically derived from any member of the series that could not have been derived from an earlier member; and (3) at least some of these novel consequences have been empirically tested and found to be corroborated” (Sarkar, 1983, p. 9) [Note: thus, Popper would view adoption of ad hoc’ed theories as irrational—i.e., pseudoscientific—whereas Lakatos views adoption of ad hoc theories as rational if they are substantively progressive, p. 11] “For the dogmatic falsificationist, … empirical counterevidence is the one and only arbiter which may judge a theory “ (p. 96). “Dogmatic falsificationism, however, is untenable. It rests on two false assumptions …. The first assumption is that there is a natural, psychological borderline between theoretical or speculative propositions on the one hand and factual or observational (or basic) propositions on the other….The second assumption is that if a proposition satisfies the psychological criterion of being factual or observational (or basic) then it is true; .… These assumptions are complemented by a demarcation criterion: only those theories are ‘scientific’ which forbid certain observable states of affairs and therefore are factually disprovable. Or, a theory is ‘scientific’ if it has an empirical basis” (pp. 97-98) “The methodological falsificationist separates rejection and disproof …. a new demarcation criterion: only those theories—that is non‘observational’ propositions –which forbid certain ‘observable’ states of affairs, and therefore may be ‘falsified’ and rejected, are ‘scientific’: or, briefly, a theory is ‘scientific’ (or ‘acceptable’) if it has an empirical basis’….probabilistic theories may qualify now as ‘scientific’ [through the specification of statistical ‘rejection rules’] (Lakatos, 1970). “it is not difficult to see at least two crucial characteristics common to both dogmatic and our methodological falsificationism which are clearly dissonant with the actual history of science: that (1) a test is—or must be made—a two-cornered fight between theory and experiment so that in the final confrontation only these two face each other; and (2) the only interesting outcome of such confrontation is (conclusive) falsification: …However, history of science suggests that (1’) tests are—at least—three-cornered fights between rival theories and experiment and (2’) some of the most interesting experiments result, prima facie, in confirmation rather than falsification” (Lakatos, 1970, p. 115) “Coherentists stress the need for appropriate types of conceptual linkages between our beliefs, while correspondentists emphasize the grounding of beliefs in the world….The problem-solving COMM 610 (Spring 2013): Advanced Communication Theory: p. 74 model, on the other hand, explicitly acknowledges that both concerns are co-present….the problem-solving model argues that the elimination of conceptual difficulties is as much constitutive of progress as increasing empirical support. Indeed, on this model, it is possible that a change from an empirically well-supported theory to a less well-supported one could be progressive, provided that the latter resolved significant conceptual difficulties confronting the former” (Laudan, 1981, p. 147) The Myth of Confirmation: “The confirmation of theories empirically occurs through its predictions, which take the form: if H is true, then P is true….But … the observation of the consequent, P, allows no conclusion about the existence or truth value of H. … The alternative is to deny the consequent. Again elementary logic tells us that the absence of the consequent, notP, entails the absence of the antecedent, not-H. …Unfortunately, this method produces a paradoxical result in which all kinds of irrelevant evidence must be accepted as confirmatory. For example, the claim that all humans have DNA can, on logical (but unreasonable) grounds, be confirmed by observing things without DNA such as coffee cups, Toyota Corollas, antique washboards, spandex, and so on, all of which are nonhuman” (Capella, 1997, p. 60) "We don't know until we try, and then we still won't know. This is, in fact, the whole point of science, it's simple elegant heuristic: trying and having some 'danger of refutation'" (McClintock, '85, 169) "the pathos of science is contained in the disciplined acceptance of findings, however inconvenient, awkward, embarrassing, or dismaying they may be" (Martindale, '79, 22) "as long as a concept is vague and beset by many meanings, it remains indestructible" (Proshansky, '81, 108) "When the researcher's faith in the theory cannot be shaken by disconfirming data, it is inappropriate to describe the research strategy as theory testing" (Greenwald et al., '86, 220) “Data adjudicates theory, but theory also drives and inspires data” (Gould, 1995, p. 149) “All observation is a partnership between mind and nature, and all good partnerships require compromise” (Gould, 1995, p. 214). “It is our job to stay whole, not to be swallowed, in compromise, . . . . We are small, though our ideas may be powerful. If we merge without maintaining our distinctiveness, we are lost” (Gould, 1995, p. 234) COMM 610 (Spring 2013): Advanced Communication Theory: p. 75 CONDITIONSHIP “There is no compulsion making one thing happen because another has happened. The only necessity that exists is logical necessity” L. Wittgenstein (1961, Tractatus) “Conditionship” in this usage refers to specification of the type of relationship. In social sciences, relationships take on many forms, and reveal many potential features. For example, we often refer to concepts being “positively related,” “negatively related,” “curvilinearly related,” or merely “significantly different” (e.g., higher or lower than something else). For our immediate purposes, however, we are interested in the features of “necessity” and “sufficiency.” Relationships can be necessary, sufficient, both, or neither. A necessary relationship means that when X occurs, Y necessarily occurs (i.e., Y “must” occur). A sufficient relationship means that when X occurs, it is sufficient to produce Y (i.e., nothing else is needed for Y to occur). Thus for example, in examining why a person contracted a disease, one could make arguments such as: (1) Necessary but not sufficient (“He was exposed to people who were already infected with AIDS”). In this instance, in order to contract AIDS, a person necessarily has to come into contact with others, or their bodily substances, that are HIV positive. However, mere exposure does not always lead to infection, and therefore is not a sufficient cause in every case. (2) Sufficient but not necessary (“He shot up with an HIV-infected needle”). In this instance, he might have contracted AIDS any number of other ways (intercourse, blood transfusion, etc.), so no single way is “necessary.” Any one of these ways, however, is sufficient to cause infection. (3) Necessary and sufficient (“She hemorrhaged giving birth and had to be given an immediate transfusion, which turned out to be HIV contaminated blood”). In this instance, a person who under all reasonable circumstances would never have come into contact with contaminated blood “had” to be so exposed, and this exposure was sufficient to give her an infection. (4) Neither necessary nor sufficient (“The dentist got AIDS from working with infected clients”). In this instance, the dentist could have taken any number of effective precautions, he might have contracted it from any number of other activities, and so forth. These concepts can also be useful in the process of defining and distinguishing concepts. Consider a recent example of such relations by Cupach & Spitzberg (in press): “Although some authors collapse lust and other elements of sexuality under a more general rubric, lust is usefully distinguished from sexual arousal (e.g., erect penis, swollen clitoris) and sexual behavior (e.g., intercourse, oral copulation). The awareness of one’s own physical stimulation does not necessarily entail desire for sexual union, although arousal can be either a precursor to or a consequence of lust. One can experience lustful desire without concomitant physical arousal. Similarly, sexual activity can occur with or without lust. The experience of lust may motivate sexual activity, or sexual activity may breed lust that leads to further sexual activity. However, sometimes the lust object does not desire sexual activity with the lustful person and sexual union is thwarted, which suggests the possibility of unrequited lust.” Now, a question might arise, is “sexual arousal” necessary for erection? Similarly, Sternberg’s theory of love claims that “passion” is a necessary component of lust, and a sufficient component of lust only when unaccompanied by either intimacy or commitment. COMM 610 (Spring 2013): Advanced Communication Theory: p. 76 Once you master these concepts, they provide powerful parameters for analyzing theories. The greater the “necessity” implied by the propositions of a theory, the more causal it tends to be, and the more open the theory is to formal propositional formulation. The current zeitgeist of the social sciences is that human behavior is rarely motivated in necessary ways (i.e., we almost never “have to” end up doing one action versus another; we instead have “choice”). Thus, when theories are referred to as being more “action-based” theories, the notion of “action” typically implies that “choice” and free will are integral to the theory. However, once such choice is built into the propositions, they no longer cohere to traditional deductive formulations. For example, consider the traditional form of a deductive syllogism: If X, then Y. If Y, then Z. Therefore, if X, then Z. This syllogism only works if the “if-then” conditions are “necessary.” If instead, there is only a probability or sufficiency in the “if-then” relations, the conclusion does not deductively follow: If X, then probably Y. If Y, then probably Z. Therefore, if X, then Z? Maybe, maybe not. Furthermore, in the context of more “action” based or “pragmatic” theories of human behavior, the conditionship becomes one of choice-based necessity (which would be considered an oxymoron by many classical theorists): If I desire X, and I believe Y is an action that will obtain X, I will choose to perform Y. Such conditional statements represent a “rule-based” logic of conditionship, and one in which the future can cause the present, rather than locating the efficient cause in exclusively in the past. COMM 610 (Spring 2013): Advanced Communication Theory: p. 77 FALSIFICATION VS. VERIFICATION 1. One way of thinking about the difference: Verification: If p, then q; p observed; therefore q deduced as true Falsification: If p, then q; not q; therefore, p deduced as false 2. Another way: Theories must suggest “counterfactual conditionals” (Meehl, p. 719): A. e.g., Hooke’s law states that “stress is proportional to strain.” This necessarily implies the counterfactual conditional that “if strain increases 5 units, and stress does not increase 5 units proportionally, then Hooke’s law is falsified. B. e.g., Spitzberg: “the perception of a person’s communication competence a probabilistic function the person’s motivation, knowledge, and skills.” This portrays no necessary relationship, and instead is based on a probabilistic relationship. It cannot be falsified in a strict sense, but it can be verified if a statistically significant relationship is found between competence perceptions and each of the other three variables. 3. Meehl also uses the following illustration: A. All crows are black: 1. To confirm: Crow1 is black, crow2 is black, etc., therefore, (A) is probably true 2. To disconfirm: Crown is non-black; therefore (A) is false B. No non-white birds are crows [the logical converse of (A)]: 1. To confirm: Non-white bird1 is a crow, non-white bird2 is a crow, etc., therefore, (B) is probably true 2. To disconfirm: This parrot is non-white and not a crow, therefore, (B) is false and (A) is made more probably true? 4. Much of the falsification debate, as suggested in the examples or approaches above, hinge on the concept of “necessity.” Necessity has to do with the formal requirements of a theory’s propositions. That is, does a theoretical proposition take a necessary form (e.g., “If X, Y must occur”), a rule-governed/systemic form (e.g., “If X, Y probably occurs”), or a merely possibility form (e.g., “If X, Y may occur”). Anything less than a necessary relationship is not likely to be falsifiable. Furthermore, necessary relationships tend to imply causal relationships, and thereby entail all the logical and epistemic assumptions that attend such reasoning (e.g., reductionism, positivism, etc.). COMM 610 (Spring 2013): Advanced Communication Theory: p. 78 SHERMER’S SCIENTIFIC BOUNDARY DETECTION KIT The “boundary detection kit” is Shermer’s (2001) attempt to provide a basis for differentiating “normal science” from “borderlands science” (i.e., potential or nascent science) from “nonscience.” He claims it is best applied by beginning with the following question: “If I were to ask the holders of the claim if they feel that they and their beliefs were fairly treated, how would they respond?” (p. 17) 1. “How reliable is the source of the claim?” Do the claimants make mistakes or have their other claims been shown to be in error? 2. “Does this source often make similar claims?” Do the claimants go beyond the facts of the case in other domains or on other topics? 3. “Have the claims been verified by another source?” Have experts or scholars outside of the inner group of claimants made or confirmed similar claims? 4. “How does this fit with what we know about the world and how it works?” How does the claim fit in the context of current knowledge? 5. “Has anyone, including and especially the claimant, gone out of the way to disprove the claim, or has only confirmatory evidence been sought?” Has there been a legitimate consideration or search for disconfirming evidence? 6. “In the absence of clearly defined proof, does the preponderance of evidence converge to the claimant’s conclusion, or a different one?” Has evidence from a broad variety of domains been brought to bear on the validity of the claim? 7. “Is the claimant employing the accepted rules of reason and tools of research, or have these been abandoned in favor of others that lead to the desired conclusion?” Are normatively accepted methodologies applied, or are the methods exotic or unique to the claim? 8. “Has the claimant provided a different explanation for the observed phenomena, or is it strictly a process of denying the existing phenomena? Is the explanation an outgrowth of current or prior explanations, or is it tethered to entirely novel concepts and/or assumptions? 9. “If the claimant has proffered a new explanation, does it account for as many phenomena as the old explanation?” Occam’s razor, or the preference for parsimony, asks that when two explanations account equally for the same phenomena, the simpler explanation is preferred. 10. Do the claimants’ personal beliefs and biases drive the conclusions, or vice versa? Adapted from: Shermer, M. (2001). The borderlands of science: Where science meets nonsense. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 17-25. COMM 610 (Spring 2013): Advanced Communication Theory: p. 79 DEMARCATION (ALA FUCHS) “here is a hypothetical list of empirical features that distinguish science from metaphysics and religion: 1. Religion/non-sciences thrive in mystification; sciences thrive in demystification. 2. Religion & metaphysics look backward; “science looks forward and expects to make further progress in the future.” (p. 34) 3. Metaphysics prefers its sages; science has little interest in sages or cults of personality. 4. “Religions offer and deliver salvation, not knowledge or expertise. Religions do not do ‘research.’ …. The truth of a religion … is already known…. In sharp contrast, the truth of a science is in its future, not past. Part of what that which makes a science scientific is, then, the discarding and overcoming of its past. The past appears as an incomplete version and prehistory of the present.” (p. 29) 5. Non-sciences generate perspectives toward reality; sciences externalize reality. 6. Non-sciences debate their foundations (i.e., what they are and what they should do), whereas “science forgets is origins and brackets its foundations or presuppositions.” (p. 34) 7. “A science is organized into specialized research professions making continuous advances in highly restricted areas of expertise.” (p. 34) 8. “Research is done in more or less circumscribed programs or projects for which function can be obtained.” (p. 34) 9. “The previous results of a science are the conditions for the current work which generates future results.” (p. 34) 10. “A science goes to work on relations, not essences.” (p. 34) 11. “At the uncertain and intensely competitive frontiers of a science, rapid discoveries and innovations are being made. These form the backbone of the reputational structure. High reputations go to discoverers, not sages, priests, or guardians of traditions. 12. Laboratories and equipment allow a science to perform experiments on a select arrangement of variables under controlled conditions. 13. A science institutionalizes nonideological modes of observing, or “objectivity.”” (p. 34) 14. “In fact, the truths of science are rather shallow and superficial, as opposed to, say, the Truth in a metaphysics or religion, which is deeper, more profound, and longer lasting than mere facts of the matter” (p. 31) 15. “Science cannot even ask the sorts of questions metaphysics or religion ask” (p. 31) 16. “what makes science scientific ultimately is its technical success in bringing about predictable and observable effects. Science works because it is true, and we know it to be true since it works” (p. 32) 17. “Religion and metaphysics do not ‘cumulate’ or make ‘advances.’…. What makes a science scientific then also is its high instrumental and experimental capacity for progress” (p. 33) Source: Fuchs, S. (2001). What makes sciences “scientific”? In J. H. Turner (Ed.), Handbook of sociological theory (pp. 21-35). New York: Kluwer Academic/Plenum. COMM 610 (Spring 2013): Advanced Communication Theory: p. 80 GOING REFLEXIVE ON GERGEN Gergen’s argument tends toward the following structure and logic: 1. Theories are language systems 2. Language systems are symbolic in nature. 3. Symbols are referentially arbitrary (due to indexicality, contextuality, cultural embeddedness, locality, etc.) 4. Arbitrary referentiality invalidates verificationism and falsificationism, which are discourses predicated on strict operational assumptions of referentiality among symbols, operations, practices, and “reality” 5. The social sciences are fundamentally different from physical sciences: The human action of greatest interest to social scientists is linguistic, and language has no nonarbitrary (fixed) spatiotemporal referential existence, 6. Language instead operates in locally situated and constructionist forms. 7. Therefore, linguistically liberating, deconstructionist, constructionist, and ethnographic interpretive methods are appropriately suited to the study of language behavior; 8. In addition, language is constitutive, and scientific discourses operate as privileged and colonializing discourses, which constrain human action 9. Therefore, social scientific methods should be yoked to a study of the social good (“Rather than searching for means of cleansing scientific discourse from prescriptive implication….[scientists] should improve their skills in creating ‘images of the good’ rather than seeking escape” Gergen, “Correspondence versus autonomy” 1986, p. 154). Among the problems with his psychosis are: 1. The argument fails by its logical inconsistency: it fails to the extent his own use of words and arguments are presupposed to have generalized argumentative coherence and credibility—if you believe him, it is because his words in a generalized context had a generalized impact on a generalized other, which of course, contradicts the presumption that language cannot work this way. COMM 610 (Spring 2013): Advanced Communication Theory: p. 81 2. The argument fails empirically: a. Research indicates that scientific uses of words and symbols employs them in more constrained ways, such that the words are more ‘indexical’ of specifiable referents than everyday lay usage (Clark & Paivio, 1989). This demonstrates that “arbitrariness” is not a dichotomy, but a continuum, and therefore, science as a practice, can approach nonarbitrariness—it does not have to achieve it in toto in order to engage it in practice in ways that reveal a substrate of reality. That is, we can employ language in constrained enough ways so as to get a better picture of social action—as better telescopes give us better pictures of distant objects, but never give us “complete” images of these objects. b. Research indicates that social science is not fundamentally different from the physical sciences. Meta-analyses of social scientific research demonstrate that its findings compare favorably, or at least equally, with the ‘hard sciences’ (Hedges, 1987). c. Research indicates that even laypersons “perceive the world and can label the world as it is.” Research, for example, demonstrates that people locate colors on a color wheel closer to color labels prototypical of those colors, even when linguistically primed to “construct” the colors differently (see Sternberg color experiments, reviewed by Chow). 3. The argument fails on the presupposition of linguistic and social contextuality: Just because meanings and behaviors vary by contexts does not mean they are not subject to lawful explanation and prediction. Again, Darwin’s theory is a theoretical law of variation across contexts (indeed, because of contexts). 4. The argument fails on ethics: If language is indeed “constructive” and “contextual,” then the claim that we should be especially disinclined to recommend scientists to improve at creating “images of the good” (e.g., Oppenheimer vs. Bethe). Either creating images of the good is just as useless as creating linguistic theoretical accounts (i.e., arbitrariness), or creating images of the good give scientists undue colonializing constructionist power. COMM 610 (Spring 2013): Advanced Communication Theory: p. 82 AN ACTION-THEORETIC PARADIGM FOR ASSESSING THE FORMS AND FUNCTIONS OF SOCIAL KNOWLEDGE* I. A framework for inquiry into and assessment of alternative types of scientific work: A. Inquiry re: The forms of social science (How does one learn about disciplinary resources?) 1. What are the properties of each form? What is it good for? What is it bad for? 2. How does it relate to other forms? To what extent is it independently variable? What elective affinities/incompatibilities does it have with forms of other features? B. Inquiry re: The relationships among different forms 1. Mutually irrelevant (wholly different problem) 2. Cross-cutting (different definitions of the problem) 3. Competitive (similar problem, different solutions) 4. Collaborative (same problem, different parts) 5. Complementary (same problem, different aspects) 6. Architectonic (different tasks, hierarchically or sequentially integrated) C. Inquiry re: The functions of social science (How does one produce non-alienated social knowledge?) 1. What are the defensible objectives of social scientific inquiry? How are they defended? 2. What are the most appropriate features and forms for each function? D. The critical assessment of features and forms (How does one identify excellent, decent, wasteful, alienated, or harmful social science?) 1. Criteria of validity: a) accuracy; b) logical consistency; c) clarity; d) completeness or scope 2. Criteria of significance: a) heuristic value; b) appropriateness to content of inquiry; c) appropriateness to purpose of inquiry; d) quality of relevant purposes and values 3. Criteria of quality of execution: a) extent to which forms are properly or elegantly realized b) extent to which forms remain linked to defensible purposes II. Toward a critical inventory of the forms of disciplined social knowledge A. Categorical frameworks (How does one conceptualize the units and organization of social phenomena?) B. Empirical procedures (How does one make observations?) 1. Unobtrusive-noninduced (direct observation, content analysis) 2. Unobtrusive-induced (questionnaires, concealed experiments) 3. Intrusive-noninduced (participant observation) 4. Intrusive-induced (depth interviews, lab experiment) D. Explanatory logics (How does one relate sets of variables?) 1. Genetic (explaining Y as a consequence of some antecedent process or event) 2. Compositional (explaining Y as a consequence of the properties of its constitutive elements) 3. Structural (explaining Y as a consequence of its position in a set of ordered relationships) 4. Functional (explaining Y with reference to the needs of X that it fulfills) E. Epistemic methods (Where does one start, toward what does one move, and how does one proceed?) F. Interpretations (How does one relate observations of phenomena to notions of what is real?) 1. Ontological: reality is transcendent, appearances are imperfect manifestations thereof 2. Entitative: reality is underlying nature, appearances are secondary derivatives thereof 3. Essentialist: reality is phenomena, properties and causes 4. Existentialist: (reality is phenomenal, socially constructed G. Epistemic products (How does one organize and present findings?) *Abstracted and adapted from: Levine, D. N. (1986). The forms and functions of social knowledge. In D. W. Fiske & R. A. Shweder (Eds.), Metatheory in social science: Pluralisms and subjectivities (pp. 271-283). Chicago: University of Chicago. COMM 610 (Spring 2013): Advanced Communication Theory: p. 83 IS THEORY USEFUL AND/OR APPLICABLE The rationale: The premise of most traditional science is that theory is the essential vehicle of scientific progress, providing the context and explanation of discovery, application, and understanding. This premise is summarized pithily by Lewin’s famous dictum: “There is nothing so practical as a good theory.” Sandelands takes issue with this basic premise, arguing that practicality is a function of understanding, not explanation. This claim requires the explication of the underlying nature of understanding and explanation as they apply to practical application. The distinction: Explanation is: Involves knowing “that” Literal/Linguistic Intellectual Generalized Concerns new ideas Derivative Secondary Abstractive Analytical Based on conceptual analysis Explicable Linguistically precise Outcome-oriented Understanding is: Involves knowing “how” Experiential Behavioral Particularistic Concerns existing ideas Original Primary Extractive Synthetic Based on behavioral refinement Inexplicable Linguistically evocative Process-oriented The argument: I. Analysis destroys unity and wholeness of the phenomenon (“we murder to dissect”) II. Hume: no basis for inferring effects from causes. Causation cannot be explained, only understood (there are no a priori reasons, only those connections we attribute) III. There are always multiple explanations, each of which depends on one’s perspective—seeing presupposes a perspective—Wittgenstein’s rabbit. (Implication: no one theory can claim exclusive jurisdiction over a phenomenon) IV. The whole is not understandable through parsing, but rather by gestalt (as evidenced by attempts to “explain” vs. “understand” visual illusions) V. Explanation is linguistic, precise, and denotative, rather than evocative The conclusion: In general, all knowledge (including explanation) presupposes and begins with understanding (p. 241). Implication: theory itself is not practical. It is understanding that is practical, not theory. Conceptual Analysis Application Explanation Understanding Paradox? Is Sandelands trapped by the fact that he is attempting to evoke our understanding through the use of literal language (i.e., a “theoretical explanation” of the concept of understanding?). If so, is he disproving the utility of theory by his very theory of theory? “theory being the knowledge that explains things, and practices being the knowledge that get(s) things done” (p. 235) “It is one thing to know the rules or laws of social behavior, and another to act according to those rules or laws” (p. 236) “The reason why explanations cannot lead to understanding is because words denote rather than evoke” (p. 246) COMM 610 (Spring 2013): Advanced Communication Theory: p. 84 Adapted from: Sandelands, L. E. (1990). What is so practical about theory? Lewin revisited. Journal for the Theory of Social Behavior, 20, 235-262. COMM 610 (Spring 2012): Advanced Communication Theory: p. 85 A theory is ‘born’ A theory matures e.g.: A theory is ‘dies’? e.g.: Creative nomenclature Theft Discovery/ Ingenuity Loan Eclectic Bricolage e.g.: Conceptual heurism Empirical heurism Measurement proliferation Contextual branching Advisee Inbreeding Falsifi-cation Editorial gulag Creative nomenclature Ennui & disinterest Progenitors die Continuing theoretical threats and issues: 1. Wobegon effect: We live in a field where (we think? we hope?) all theories are better than average. How do we ascertain relative or comparative utility of theories or programs of research? 2. There is a general lack of (training in and application of) meta-theoretical reflexivity: formalization, falsification standards, integration & comparative differentiation, etc. 3. Relative few theories seek to delineate their scope & domain parameters: identifying the contextual parameters of the theory’s applicability. What are the degrees of incommensurability across research programs? 4. Functional ambivalence: Under what conditions does the theory backfire, under what conditions are the hypothesized relationships curvilinear, and are such possibilities even envisioned as possible? 5. How can body-snatcher theories (i.e., theories that are merely relabled or massaged reconfigurations of previous theories) and zombie theories (i.e., theories that just won’t die) be identified (and put to rest)? 6. What is the yardstick of “progress” in a given theoretical arena: (a) progressiveness (Lakatos?), (b) revolution (Kuhn), (c) elimination of false knowledge claims & theories (Popper), (d) results engineering (Greenwald et al.), (e) number of publications, or (f) tenure and a regular academic salary? COMM 610 (Spring 2012): Advanced Communication Theory: p. 86 A ‘Kuhnian’ View of Paradigmatic Effects On Perception and Interpretation (Spitzberg, 2003) Phenomenal World Sensation Perception Paradigms Interpretation Theories Symbolic ‘Translation’ O B S E R V A T I O N Expectations COMM 610 (Spring 2012): Advanced Communication Theory: p. 87 MAPPING THE META-THEORETICAL TERRAIN: #1 NATURE OF REALITY & KNOWLEDGE KNOWERKNOWN RELATIONSHIP EPISTEMOLOGICAL ISSUE (1) To what extent is knowledge a priori? WORLDVIEW I Knowledge is discovered. It is in no way a priori. (2) To what extent is reality universal? (3) To what extent is knowledge explicit? (4) Where is the locus of reality? (5) By what process is knowledge achieved? Reality is absolute and immutable, to be received or discovered. Knowledge is explicit. WORLDVIEW II Part of knowledge is a priori. What we know emerges from structures that are part of human existence. Reality results from human interpretation. Reality is in flux and …[contextual] Most knowledge is implicit or tacit. Reality is in the world, outside the person. Reality is in personal experience. Knowledge arises from sensory experience…. Reality is thus discovered systematically by controlled observation… Knowledge is a perceptual process, shaped by individual … interpretation. Knowledge is a construction, … a transaction between knower and known. Knowledge is constructed by symbolic interaction… Humans act with purpose and are therefore entirely different from non-human objects. (6) To what extent is Knowledge is discovered by the observer knowledge social? alone. (7) How are humans different Humans are basically objects, controlled by from or the same as the same features and operations. nonhuman objects? STRUCTURE OF (8) Does knowledge consist of Reality is best understood via analysis, or Reality is process [consisting of] relations REALITY understanding parts or knowledge of parts. and functions…. Its structure is imposed. wholes? (9) What is the structure of Objects in reality have discernible structure Events are part of goal-seeking processes. reality? and predictable, machine-like operations. (10) Why do events happen? Events are caused. Adapted from: Littlejohn, S.W. (1982). An overview of contributions to human communication theory from other disciplines. In F.E.X. Dance (Ed.), Human communication theory: Comparative essays (pp. 243-285). New York: Harper & Row. COMM 610 (Spring 2012): Advanced Communication Theory: p. 88 MAPPING THE META-THEORETICAL TERRAIN: #2 A SYSTEMATIZATION OF THEORETICAL ALTERNATIVES SYSTEMS VIEW REDUCTIONIST VIEW LEVEL 1: SPECIFICATION OF MOLAR OR MOLECULAR PERSPECTIVE LEVEL 1(a): Specification of system type LEVEL 2: SPECIFICATION OF TYPE(S) OF NECESSITY OPERATING Open Entails logical necessity; can entail practical, and/or nomic necessity Closed Entails logical necessity; may result in discovery of Nomological relationships Nomic necessity Practical necessity LEVEL 3: SPECIFRICATION Various mechanisms may Various models and Various mechanisms may be postulated for the OF METCHANISMS be postulated for the calculi; various logics expression of nomic or practical necessity THROUGH WHICH expression of all three NECESSITY OPERATES types of necessity Adapted from: Cronen, V. E. & Davis, L. K. (1978). Alternative approaches for the communication theorist: Problems in the laws-rules-systems trichotomy. Human Communication Research, 4, 120-128. Note: In response to article by Cushman & Pearce (1977; HCR, 3, pp. 344-353): “Nomic necessity depends on locating a causal relationship between two classes of objects. Nomic necessity carries deterministic force.” “Logical necessity depends on definitional force and applies to systems of relationships defined as internally consistent.” “Practical necessity depends on the type and amount of normative force an actor feels to perform (or not perform) a given activity in a specified way” (Cushman & Pearce, 1977, p. 345) COMM 610 (Spring 2012): Advanced Communication Theory: p. 89 MAPPING THE META-THEORETICAL TERRAIN: #3 SOCIOLOGY OF RADICAL CHANGE Radical Humanism Radical structuralism French Existentialism S U B J E C T I V E Mediterranean Marxism Russian social theory Critical Theory Conflict theory Solipsism Phenomenology Hermeneutics Integrative theory Systems theory Phenomenological Sociology Ethnomethodology & Ethnography O B J E C T I V E Objectivism Interactionism & social action theory Interpretive Sociology Micro-sociology & conversation analysis Functionalist Sociology SOCIOLOGY OF REGULATION Adapted from: Burrell, G., & Morgan, G. (1979). Sociological paradigms and organizational analysis. Aldershot, England: Gower. p. 29. COMM 610 (Spring 2012): Advanced Communication Theory: p. 90 MAPPING THE META-THEORETICAL TERRAIN: #4 APPROACH TOWARD DISTIN-GUISH SCIENTIFIC GOOD vs. BAD DEMARSCIENCE CATION SKEPTICISM No DEMARCATION Yes Relativism Statute ELITISM Case LEGAL ANALOGY CHARACTERISTICS OF APPROACH PROGRESSIVE? SCIENTIFIC EXEMPLAR CHANGE Revolutionary Progressive Yes Yes Kuhn; Polyani; Yes Toulmin Adapted from Phillips, D. L. (1977). Wittgenstein and scientific knowledge: A sociological perspective. London: Macmillan. Yes Revolutionary Feyerabend Popper; Lakatos ELITIST? Yes No Yes No: ignores past Yes: consistent with past Yes: ignores past CHANGE IS ‘VIOLENT’? MAPPING THE META-THEORETICAL TERRAIN: #5 CHARACTERISTIC OBJECTIVE LOCATION OF OPERATION COMPONENT ELEMENTS CRITERIA MISTAKE ORIENTATION IDEOLOGY SCIENTIFIC THEORY Prescriptive Descriptive/Explanatory World of action World of thought Values Axiology Laws Explanation/Prediction Good vs. Bad True vs. False Explaining mistakes away or deforming them to be “Correcting” existing knowledge claims in light of new consistent with premises evidence KEYSTONE EVIDENCE There is no “fact” that could topple ideology There are many “facts” that could topple ideology Adapted from: Martindale, D. (1979). Ideologies, paradigms, and theories. In W. E. Snizek, E. R. Fuhrman, & M. K. Miller (Eds.), Contemporary issues in theory and research: A metasociological perspective (pp. 7-24). Westport, CT: Greenwood. COMM 610 (Spring 2012): Advanced Communication Theory: p. 91 MAPPING THE META-THEORETICAL TERRAIN: #6 Element Ontology Epistemology Common Methodologies Paradigm Constructivism Multiple local and specific ‘constructed’ [symbolically negotiated] realities Realism Reality is ‘real’ but only imperfectly & probabilistically apprehensible Positivism Reality is real and apprehensible Modified objectivist: findings probably true Objectivist: findings are true Subjectivist: findings are created through negotiated interpretations of actors and observers Hermeneutic, dialectical, engagement by researcher/observer with the world Criticism ‘Virtual’ reality shaped by social, economic, ethnic, political, cultural, and gender values, crystallized over time Subjectivist: findings are value-mediated Case studies, convergent Experiment, surveys, Dialogical, dialectical interviews, triangulation, verification or falsification engagement by interpretation of research of hypotheses, primarily researcher as by qualitative & through quantitative transformative agent of quantitative methods methods change Adapted from: Healy, M., & Perry, C. (2000). Comprehensive criteria to judge validity and reliability of qualitative research within the realism paradigm. Qualitative Market Research: An International Journal, 3(3), 118-126. Note: “Ontology is ‘reality,’ epistemology is the relationship between that reality and the researcher, and methodology is the technique used by the researcher to investigate that reality; adapted from Perry et al. (1997, p. 547) based on Guba and Lincoln (1994)” (p .119) COMM 610 (Spring 2012): Advanced Communication Theory: p. 92 MAPPING THE META-THEORETICAL TERRAIN: #7 Type of Philosophical orientations Positivism Type of first-order sociological theories Nomological Type of metatheoretical reflections on sociological theorizing Purpose Process Criterion Products To discover universal Methodological Theoretical accumulation social laws codification Hermeneutics Interpretive To understand Fusion of existential Enlightenment intersubjective meanings horizons Critical Postmodernism Normative To seek social justice Social praxis Human emancipation Postmodernism Relativistic To construct local Deconstruction Delegitimation narratives (decentering, establish and maintain dialogue, reject grand narratives and principle of progress) Adapted from: Ritzer, G., Zhao, S., & Murphy, J. (2001). Metatheorizing in sociology: The basic parameters and the potential contributions of postmodernism. In J. H. Turner (Ed.), Handbook of sociological theory (pp. 113-131). New York: Kluwer/Plenum. . COMM 610 (Spring 2012): Advanced Communication Theory: p. 93 MAPPING THE META-THEORETICAL TERRAIN: #8 Questions: Sign recognition Sign interpretation Traditional Empiricism Adequate stimulus Hard wired Meaning maker Site of interpretation Semiosis Semiosis engaged Aurhorial intent Semiotic product Interpretation conclusion Sensory system Individual Sensory engagement Liminal engagement Directs interpretation Isomorphic representation Moment of sensation Perceptual Empiricism Adequate stimulus Hardware & software combo Perceiving subject Socialized individual Perceived stimulus Cognition initiated Directs interpretation Perceived representation Cognitive recognition Constructive Empiricism Difference boundaries Practical accomplishment Postmodern Empiricism Difference boundaries Actional accomplishment Situated subject Ideological collective Ideological engagement Collectively managed Point of comparison Positioned interpretation Enactment of subjectivity Acting subject Social action Action engagement As initiated as action As required by action Contingent interpretation Enactment of acting subject Adapted from: Anderson, J. A. (1996). Communication theory. NY: Guilford, p. 60. See theory list and levels at: http://www.utwente.nl/cw/theorieenoverzicht/Alphabetic%20list%20of%20theories/ COMM 610 (Spring 2012): Advanced Communication Theory: p. 94 MAPPING THE META-THEORETICAL TERRAIN: #9 UNITS OF ANALYSIS TIME & CHANGE TRAIT Person, psychological qualities of persons. Assumes stability; change infrequent in present operation; change occurs according to pre-established rules. INTERACTIONAL Psychological qualities of person & social or physical environment treated as separate underlying entities with interaction between parts Change results from interaction of separate person & environment entities; change often occurs in accord with underlying regulatory mechanisms (e.g., homeostasis); time & change not intrinsic to phenomena ORGANISMIC Holistic entities composed of separate person & environment components, elements or parts whose relations & interactions yield nonsummative qualities of the whole TRANSACTIONAL Holistic entities composed of “aspects,” not separate parts or elements; aspects are mutually defining; temporal qualities are intrinsic features of wholes. Change results from interaction of person & environment entities. Change occurs in accord with underlying regulatory mechanisms (e.g., homeostasis, equifinality). Assumes stability & control. Stability/change are intrinsic & defining features of human phenomena; change occurs continuously; directions of change are emergent & not pre-established. Adapted from: Altman & Rogoff, 1987; Handbook of Environmental Psychology Selected Goals and Philosophy of Science CAUSATION OBSERVERS OTHER Emphasizes material causes, Separate, objective, & Focus on universal laws of i.e., cause internal to detached from phenomena; functioning according to few phenomena equivalent observations by principles associated with different observers. person qualities; study predictions & trait manifestations Emphasizes efficient causes, Separate, objective, & Focus on elements & i.e., antecedent-consequent detached from phenomena; relations between elements; relations, “push” ideas of equivalent observations by seeks laws of relations causation different observers between variables & parts of system; understand system by prediction & control & by cumulative additive information regarding relations among elements Emphasizes final causes, i.e., Separate, objective, & Focus on principles that teleology, “pull” toward ideal detached from phenomena; govern the whole; state. equivalent observations by emphasizes unity of different observers. knowledge, principles of holistic systems & hierarchy of subsystems; Identify principles & laws of whole system. Emphasizes formal causes, Relative: observers are Focus on event, i.e., i.e., description & aspects of phenomena; confluence of persons, space, understanding of patterns, observers in different & time; describe & shapes, & form of ‘locations’ (physical & understand patterning & phenomena. psychological) yield different form of events; open to information about principles but more so in phenomena. accounting for event; pragmatic application of rules/laws to situations. COMM 610 (Spring 2012): Advanced Communication Theory: p. 95 MAPPING THE META-THEORETICAL TERRAIN: #10 Phenomenal Operational STYLES Naturalistic Communication Focus: Primary focus Experience is: Meaning is: Knowledge is: Prime faculty: General method: Methodological ideal: Ultimate Truth Criterion: Mode of Argument: Process/Channel Things The experienced Caused Discovered Sensation Science/Observation Objectivity Replication Falsification Source/Receiver Thoughts The experience Created Created Imagination Rationality/Logic Formal perfection Consistency Demonstration Effects Actions/Rules Experiencing Produced Produced Emotion Technology Practical efficacy Success Justification Necessity: Reduction style: Exemplar: Philosophical exemplar: Empirical-logical Causal process B.F. Skinner? Newtonian physics? Practical Mental creations Shannon & Weaver? Mathematical physics? Practical Practices Mead; Garfinkel? Deweys’ functionalism DIMENSIONS Phenomenological Postmodern? Message/Feedback Words The experienceable Shared Articulated Reason Hermeneutics Transcendence Consensus Dialogic communication Rationality Language games Habermas? Schutz’s phenomenology Text? Meanings? Experiencing? Manifold? Evoked? Play? Deconstruction? Emancipation? Individuality Criticism? *Smith, T. J., III. (1988). Diversity and order in communication theory: The uses of philosophical analysis. Communication Quarterly, 36, 28-40 Intentional? Empistemes/Memes? Giddens? Lyotard; Barthes COMM 610 (Spring 2012): Advanced Communication Theory: p. 96 MAPPING THE META-THEORETICAL DOMAIN: #11 RATIONAL EMPIRICISM WHAT COUNTS AS DATA UNIT OF ANALYSIS UNIT OF OBSERVATION The pure product of Irrelevant or cognition unspecified Reductionistic, theory Individual neutral MECHANISTIC EMPIRICISM Reductionistic, theory neutral Individual ‘atoms’ related by oneway causal forces SKEPTICAL EMPIRICISM Reductionistic, but perceptually distorted POSITIVISM Reductionistic: observations are not theory-laden Individual events manifest in perception The smallest individual unit is preferred RATIONALISM TYPE OF DATA HOW DO DATA COUNT? DATA & CAUSATION DATA & THEORY Qualitative Unspecified Qualitative/no minal Data reflect telic forces manifest in objects Quantitative, preferably at interval or ratio level unspecified Data reflect nomic force manifest in corpuscles of mass Quantitative, preferably interval or ratio-level Qualitative or quantitative Data & theory are isomorphic Exemplification: data exemplify logically necessary relationships Data accumulate to create theory Causation cannot be unspecified determined—only associations among observations Statistical associations are Knowledge ‘seepts up’ surrogates for causation from particular findings, organized as covering laws Statistical associations reflect Data support or fail to cognitive processes postulated support by theorist Statistical associations may Data support or fail to reflect nomic, logical, or support aspects of practical forces, and reflexive theorist’s model. relations. CONSTRUCTIVISM Variable, depending on Individual knower epistemology invoked by is the basic unit theory HUMAN SYSTEMS Holonic, reductionism is Variety of levels Quantitative or rejected. The whole is not and units of qualitative assumed to be an analysis are aggregation of parts. employed. Data are theory-laden. Adapted from: Dance, F. E. X. (1982). Human communication theory. New York, NY: Harper & Row. COMM 610 (Spring 2012): Advanced Communication Theory: p. 97 MAPPING THE META-THEORETICAL TERRAIN: #12 CONVERSATION ANALYSIS INTERACTIONAL SOCIOLINGUISTICS CRITICAL DISCOURSE ANALYSIS DISCURSIVE PSYCHOLOGY ACTION-IMPLICATIVE DISCOURSE ANALYSIS META-THEORETICAL APPROACH Empirical Interpretive Critical Interpretive Interpretive/critical THEORETICAL FOCUS Location and nature of social structuring processes How linguistic action and sense-making is shaped by culture Role of talk/text in maintaining power relationships and accomplishing resistance Rhetorical and linguistically constructive nature of basic psychological processes Problems, conversational techniques, and situated ideals of communicative practices KINDS OF CONTEXTUAL INFORMATION Strictly within text (context = immediately prior talk) Interviews with focal cultural members to check proposed interpretations Historical, social, political conditions at time of text Description of rhetorical situation (likely speaker goals, audience, situation) Description of rhetorical situation (gained through interviews and observation) DOMINANT TEXT TYPE Informal everyday exchanges Institutional and interpersonal exchanges between culturally different persons Public texts (e.g., newspapers, radio, reports), interviews about social controversies (e.g., racism) Talk situations in which persons experience conflict either within self or with another (e.g., couple’s therapy) Routine institutional occasions in which actors experience problems (interviews with actors and talk from the occasion) Source: Tracy, K. (1995). Action-implicative discourse analysis. Journal of Language and Social Psychology, 14, 195-215. COMM 610 (Spring 2012): Advanced Communication Theory: p. 98 MAPPING THE META-THEORETICAL TERRAIN: #13 Seven Traditions of Communication Theory PHENOMEN- CYBERNETIC SOCIOOLOGICAL PSYCHOLOGICAL RHETORICAL SEMIOTIC Communication theorized as: The practical art of discourse Intersubjective mediation by signs Experience of otherness; dialogue Information processing Problems of communication theorized as: Social exigency requiring collective deliberation and judgment Art, method, communicator, audience, strategy, commonplace, logic, emotion Misunderstanding of gap between subjective viewpoints Absence of, or failure to sustain, authentic human relationship Sign, symbol, icon, index, meaning, reference, code, language, medium, (mis)understanding Power of words; value of informed judgment; improvability of practice Understanding requires common language; omnipresent danger of miscommunication Meta-discursive vocabulary such as: Plausible when appeals to meta-discursive commonplaces such as: SOCIOCULTURAL CRITICAL PRAGMATIC Expression, interaction, & influence (Re)production of social order Discursive reflection Noise; overload; underload; a malfunction or ‘bug’ in a system Situation requiring manipulation of causes of behavior to achieve specified outcomes Experience, self & other, dialogue, genuineness, supportiveness, openness Source, receiver, signal, information, noise, feedback, redundancy, network, function Behavior, variable, effect, personality, emotion, perception, cognition, attitude, interaction Conflict; alienation; misalignment; failure of coordination Society, structure, practice, ritual, rule, socialization, culture, identity, co-construction Hegemonic ideology; systematically distorted speech situation Ideology, dialectic, oppression, consciousnessraising, resistance, emancipation All need human contact, should treat others as persons, respect differences, seek common ground Identity of mind and brain; value of information and logic; complex systems can be unpredictable Communication reflects personality; beliefs & feelings bias judgments; people in groups affect one another The individual is a product of society; every society has a distinct culture; social actions have unintended effects Self-perpetuation of power & wealth; values of freedom, equality & reason; discussion produces awareness, insight Naturalness & rationality of traditional social order; objectivity of science & technology Pluralistic community; coordination of practical activities through discourse & reflexive activity Incommensurabiolity, nonparticipation, nonreflexivity or dogmatism, defective discourse practices Community, pluralism, interdependence, interests, consequences, the real meaning of anything is the practical difference it makes. We need to cooperate despite our differences; everyone has a view deserving equal hearing Mere words are Words have Communication is Humans and Humans are rational Individual agency Certain truths cannot Interesting not actions; correct meanings skill; the word is machines differ; beings; we know our & responsibility; be denied, some when appearance is not & stand for not the thing; emotion is not own minds; we know absolute identity differences are too reality; style is not thoughts; codes & facts are objective logical; linear what we see of self; fundamental to be challenges substance; media are neutral and values order of cause & naturalness of the overcome, there can meta-discursive opinion is not channels subjective effect social order be no cooperation commonplaces truth with evil or falsehood such as: Adapted from: Craig, R. T. (1999). Communication as a field. Communication Theory, 9, 119-161. Craig, R. T. (2007). Pragmatism in the field of communication theory. Communication Theory, 17, 125-145.MAPPING THE META-THEORETICAL TERRAIN: COMM 610 (Spring 2012): Advanced Communication Theory: p. 99 #13, cont. Topoi for Argumentation Across Traditions RHETORICAL SEMIOTIC PHENOMENOLOGICAL CYBERNETIC SOCIOPSYCHOLOGICAL SOCIOCULTURAL CRITICAL PRAGMATISM RHETORIC The art of rhetoric can be learned only by practice We do not use signs; rather they use us Langue is a fiction; meaning & intersubjectivity are indeterminate Rhetoric reflects traditionalist, instrumentalist, & individualist ideologies Meaning is not fixed by a code; it is a site of social conflict PHENOMEN-OLOGICAL Authenticity is a dangerous myth; communication must be artful, hence strategic Practical reason cannot (or should not) be reduced to formal calculation Effects are situational and cannot be precisely predicted Self & other are semiotically determined subject positions & exist only in/as signs Functionalist explanations ignore subtleties of sign systems Socio-psychological “effects” are internal properties of sign systems Rhetorical theory is culture bound & overemphasizes individual agency vs. social structure Sign systems aren’t autonomous; they exist only in the shared practices of actual communities Intersubjectivity is produced by social processes that phenomenology fails to explain Cybernetic models fail to explain how meaning emerges in social interaction Socio-psychological “laws” are culture bound & biased by individualism Rhetoric relies on traditional commonplaces, defeats reflexivity All use of signs is rhetorical Intervention in complex systems involved technical problems rhetoric fails to grasp “Meaning” consists of functional relationships within dynamic information systems Phenomenological “experience” must occur in the brain as information processing The observer must be included in the system, rendering it indeterminate Communication involved circular causation, not linear causation Rhetoric lacks good empirical evidence that is persuasive techniques actually work as intended SEMIOTICS Strategic communication is inherently inauthentic & often counter-productive Langue-parole & signifier-signified are false distinctions. Languaging constitutes world Other’s experience is not experienced directly but only as constituted in ego’s consciousness Functionalism fails to explain meaning as embodied & conscious The subject-object dichotomy of sociopsychology must be transcended SOCIO-CULTURAL Sociocultural rules, etc., are contexts & resources for rhetorical discourse Sociocultural rules, etc., are all systems of signs The social life-world has a phenomenological foundation The functional organization of any social system can be modeled formally Practical reason is based in particular situations, not universal principles There is nothing outside of the text Critique is immanent in every authentic encounter with tradition Self-organizing systems models account for social conflict & Change Sociocultural order is particular & locally negotiated but theory must be abstract & general Critical theory imposes an interpretive frame, fails to appreciate local meanings Sociocultural theory privileges consensus over conflict & change CRITICAL Sociocultural theory is vague, untestable, ignores psychological processes that underlie all social order Critical theory confuses facts & values, imposes a dogmatic ideology PRAGMATISM Lacks specificity of an art; pluralistc community is merely an intellectual ideal Coordination depends on a shared code; community is constituted symbolically Experience of the other with an eye to consequences is not a genuine experience of the other Overestimates agency, underestimates degree to which determinism of complex systems can be captured by formal models Pragmatic consequences are not most usefully assessed through rigorous empirical procedures; “there is nothing so practical as a good theory” Overestimates agency, underestimates the influence and persistence of cultural patterns and social structures Inadequately accounts for power relations, systematic distortion; differences negotiated in political struggle; praxis seeks reclaiming of conflict AGAINST… CYBERNETICS SOCIO-PHYSIOLOGICAL Adapted from: Craig, R. T. (1999, 2007) [see above] Semiotics fails to explain factors that influence the production & interpretation of messages Phenomenological introspection falsely assumes self-awareness of cognitive processes Cybernetics is too rationalistic; e.g., it underestimates the role of emotion Socio-psychological theories have limited predictive power, even in laboratory Individual consciousness is socially constituted, thus ideologically distorted Cybernetics reflects the dominance of instrumental reason Socio-psychology reflects ideologies of individualism, instrumentalism Critical theory is elitist & without real influence on social change Intersubjective mediation occurs in coordinated practical activities, not through signs alone;… Experience of the other means taking the perspective of the other in interaction; I-Thou depends on Us-Them “Contingency goes all the way down” (Russill, 2004, p. 173), … Given contingency, consequences for practical action cannot be reduced to predictable effects Sociocultural theory underestimates agency of social actors and negotiability of cultural patterns/structures All normative principles are contingent; diverse identities and structural power differences do not preclude pluralistic community Dilemma of reflexivity: inquiry, when instituted (routinized/ritualized) as social practices becomes nonreflexive. Paradox of pluralism: A standpoint that can take no particular standpoint COMM 610 (Spring 2012): Advanced Communication Theory: p. 100 MAPPING THE META-THEORETICAL TERRAIN: #14 EMPIRICAL: Privileges observation, measurement, presence, experience Privileges postmodernism, erasur REFLEXIVE FOUNDATIONAL: Privileges modernism, certainty, causality, closure Privileges theory, frameworks, concepts, values ANALYTICAL: Adapted from: Anderson, J. A., & Baym, G. (2004). Philosophies and philosophic issues in communication, 1995-2004. Journal of Communication, 54, 589-615. COMM 610 (Spring 2012): Advanced Communication Theory: p. 101 RELATIONS AMONG PARADIGMS BASED ON INTER-CITATIONS Los Alamos National Laboratory (http://www.wired.com/wiredscience/2009/03/mapofscience/) COMM 610 (Spring 2012): Advanced Communication Theory: p. 102 http://www.eigenfactor.org/map/maps.htm COMM 610 (Spring 2012): Advanced Communication Theory: p. 103 http://scimaps.org/maps/map/illuminated_diagram__134/: The science base map was created using more than 7.5 million papers published in 16,000 separate journals between 2001 and 2005 in Thomson Reuters’ Web of Science and Elsevier’s Scopus databases. Exactly 554 COMM 610 (Spring 2012): Advanced Communication Theory: p. 104 subdisciplines of science—groups of journals—and their interrelations were identified and placed on the surface of a sphere. The spherical layout was then flattened using a Mercator projection to create a two-dimensional version of the map. Disciplines are further aggregated into 13 broad disciplines that are color-coded and labeled. Overlaid on this map are five million paper records from MEDLINE published in mostly biomedical areas between 2000 and 2009 associated with 554 subdisciplines based on the titles of the journals in which they appear. COMM 610 (Spring 2012): Advanced Communication Theory: p. 105 • • Comprised of 7,121 journals from 2000: each dot is a journal; Journals grouped by discipline; Larger fonts = more major areas of science; Smaller labels = disciplinary topics of nearby large clusters of journals Source: http://scimaps.org/static/docs/meeting-doc/06-08-30-slides/data-borner.pdf COMM 610 (Spring 2012): Advanced Communication Theory: p. 106 http://metamodern.com/2009/05/20/a-map-of-science/ Comm 610: Advanced Communication Theory: 107 PARADIGMS Definition "In his seminal work on paradigms and scientific revolutions, Kuhn (1970) gave the word 'paradigm' more than 20 different meanings. For our purposes, ... a paradigm is 'the complete constellation of beliefs, values, techniques, etc., shared by the members of a scientific community.' We add Morgan's (1980) clarification that a paradigm 'denotes an implicit or explicit view of reality' and that 'it contains [a discipline's] core assumptions that characterize and define [its] worldview.' (p. 129). Value of Paradigms "A discipline, as well as the theory(ies) which constitute a discipline, needs a paradigm for the following reasons: (1) A paradigm constitutes "the essence" of the discipline. (2) A paradigm constitutes "the worldview" of its adherents. (3) Scientists in the discipline use the statement of the paradigm to establish the problems which it has to solve. (4) The scientific establishment works usually in the direction of the prevailing paradigm, i.e., its rules and procedures are directed by the currently accepted paradigm... (5) The paradigm is directly implicated in the design of the instruments, apparatus, and methodologies used to solve the problems of the discipline... (6) A paradigm is essential to discover (a) anomalies [unresolved questions inconsistent with paradigmatically predicted results] ... and (b) 'dilemmas [epistemological or methodological debates pitting disciplinary groups against one another].' (p. 130) Level of a Paradigm "a paradigm must be a 'metatheory' which embodies all the concepts needed to express the ideas of the discipline....It is clear that a paradigm has to be a metatheory, i.e., a theory that lends direction to other theories. It has to be 'general,' 'universal,' and 'comprehensive' enough to contain all other theories. (p. 131) Criteria for Paradigm "A paradigm should help to provide answers to at least the following six fundamental questions. (1) What are the main sources of knowledge of the discipline? (2) What constitutes the object of study of the discipline? (3) What are the main schools of thought underlying the discipline? (4) What are the main purposes of the discipline? (5) What are the significant instrumentalities (methodologies) used by the discipline and, by derivation, its main activities? (6) What are the anomalies and unresolved problems which are facing the discipline? Source: van Gigch, J. P., & Le Moigne, J. L. (1989). A paradigmatic approach to the discipline of information systems. Behavioral Science, 34, 128-150. Comm 610: Advanced Communication Theory: 108 PARADIGM CONFLICTS When deciding among paradigms (in this instance, between qualitative and quantitative), there are several possible strategies available. Among them are the following: Type 1: DENIAL: Technically, not a solution, in that it refuses to admit to a conflict. Instead, three denial tactics are available: (1) Differences among paradigms are more imaginary or thematic than substantive; (2) differences are only due to paradigms attacking "straw men" ideological positions; (3) the "semanticist response" in which the differences are viewed as linguistic in nature (see Levine, 1986), and subject to disambiguation. Type 2: APATHY: Views paradigm conflicts as relatively unimportant to the accomplishment of science, or to individual scholarly endeavors. Type 3: SKEPTICISM (RELATIVISM, NIHILISM): Certain knowledge is certainly unknowable (note contradiction). Type 4: SOLIPSISM: Only personal views of reality matter. Paradigms are arbitrated on the basis of personal relevance or reality. Type 5: METHODOLOGICAL DESIGN: Differences among paradigms can be resolved through design of specific “crucial” experiments and studies that will validate one or another paradigm. Type 6: METHODOLOGICAL PLURALISM: Attempt to apply different methodologies to pursue thematic truths or principles (Booth, as reviewed in Levine, 1986). Compared to DESIGN above, this approach accept multiple methodologies. Compared to ANARCHISM below, this approach accepts the validity or usefulness of methods but not rhetoric per se. Type 7: ANARCHISM: Ala Feyerabend's counterinduction, or "anything goes." Similar to Booth's "Polemicist Response" of letting everyone 'get out there and fight' (see Levine, 1986). The counterinduction occurs in many arenas, including rhetorical, rather than just methodological. Type 8: ECLECTICISM: The validity claims of different perspectives all make legitimate claims, and a discipline copes with differences by integrating and patching over, and patching together, various components; similar to generalizing theoretical approaches. Type 9: DOMAIN-BASED CRITERIA: Determine the values to which different paradigms cater, those the researcher concurs, and select the most appropriate. Type 10: COMPLEMENTARITY: Differences exist, but will disappear when it is recognized that paradigms are complementary (either sequentially or processually) in either completing one another or fine-tuning one another. Type 11: REPLACEMENT/SUBSUMPTION: An attempt to resolve differences between/among extant paradigms by developing a new, encompassing, synthesizing paradigm. Type 12: NORMATIVE: Normative practice establishes a pragmatic set of solutions to extant theory. Adapted liberally from: Levine, D. N. (1986). In D. W. Fiske & R. A. Shweder (Eds.), Metatheory in social science (pp. 271-284). Chicago: University of Chicago. Rossiter, C. M. (1977). Models of paradigmatic change. Communication Quarterly, 25, 69-73. Schwandt, T. A. (1989). Solutions to the paradigm conflict: Coping with uncertainty. Journal of Contemporary Ethnography, 17, 379407. Comm 610: Advanced Communication Theory: 109 PARADIGMS & DATA-OBSERVER INTERACTION 1. 2. 3. 4. 5. All communication is behavioral (and thus, empirical) , all communication is observable. , all communication is potential data. , all communication is interpretable. All interpretation is a function of: a. Sensationperception b. Beliefstheories c. Methodology 6. So, can methodology ‘constrain’ interpretation? (We know they can to some degree— otherwise, we could not demonstrate the existence of perceptual illusions, coordinate pragmatic features of our world such as language and collective activity, etc.) 7. The question then becomes: Are some methods (or logics) better at constraining (tethering?): a. Senses/perceptions b. Interpretations c. Theories? 8. Qualitative and quantitative scholars trust their data observations (with understood limitations), but they differ in the kinds of explanations they offer. Methodologies Data Paradigm Observer Biases/ Beliefs (35) Bostrom, R. N. (2003). Theories, data, and communication research. Communication Monographs, 70, 275-294. (36) Pavitt, C. (2004). Theory-data interaction from the standpoint of scientific realism: A reaction to Bostrom. Communication Monographs, 71, 333-342. Bostrom, R. N. (2004). Empiricism, paradigms, and data. Communication Monographs, 71, 343-341. Comm 610: Advanced Communication Theory: 110 POSTMODERNISM I. The Traditional Era (400 B.C. to 1900s A.D.) A. Rationalism vs. Empiricism 1. Plato vs. Aristotle 2. Descarte, Kant & Hegel 3. Francis Bacon & Inductivism B. Husserl & Phenomenology II. The Modern Era (early 1900s to 1960s) A. The Linguistic Turn 1. Wittgenstein & Language Games 2. Sassure & Structuralism B. The Relativity Turn 1. Impressionism/Cubism/Abstract Expressionism 2. Jazz 3. Physics, Heisenberg & Schrodinger's Cat 4. New Literary forms (short stories, nonrhyming poetry) C. The Critical Turn 1. Marxist Critique & the Frankfurt School 2. Feminist Critique D. The Scientific/Artistic Axis: Despite the revolutions in form, epistemologically most artists and scientists still presumed "a reality" and the prospect of a transcendent or supraordinate or "grand narrative" perspective from which to judge the relativity of multiple perspectives III. The Post-Modern Era A. Emphasis on the "Local": Reaction against "grand narratives" (e.g., Marxism, Science, a single "privileged" history, etc.) B. Loss of the Past: We can no longer hold onto our past, as it represents as many different histories as we choose to read into it C. Heterogeny of Perspective: fragmentation, a cannibalization of the Past, Being no longer bound by the past, we can choose to use it (in terms of styles, topics, agendas, etc.) D. Unfocused Present: "we seem increasingly incapable of fashioning representations of our current experience" (Sarup, 1993, p.181). E. Replacement of Metaphors: Modernity was characterized by metaphors of time and memory; whereas post-modernity seems more dominated by the metaphor of space: the alienated masses in the urbanized chaos of space, our everchanging maps of the world, etc. F. The Myth of Progress: Marxism claimed progress through ideology; post-modernity claims the impossibility of progress in any "real" sense G. Knowledge as Primary Force of Production: Art and knowledge as impression vs. expression; knowledge as conformity/power vs. liberation; knowledge as progression vs. creation; knowledge through mind vs. body/subconscious IV. Whence "Truth"? A. Does Post-Modernism deny Truth? Most interpreters argue "no," since truth can be (1) local, and (2) there, but not knowable from any grand narrative scheme B. Truth may become existential, in the sense that everyone has their own truths, which can sometimes be evoked in larger groups, in ways that enrich our experience Comm 610: Advanced Communication Theory: 111 IS IT PAST POST-TIME FOR POST-MODERNISM? Brian H. Spitzberg, Ph.D. School of Communication, S.D.S.U. Interpersonal Communication Theory Panel W.S.C.A., Mesa, AZ, February 2009 The fact that you are here in this place at this time is prima facie evidence that abstract concepts are capable of communication, and that communication pragmatically is capable of coordinating our actions in regard to spatio-temporal referents. The evolving criticisms of critical/interpretive spokespersons, such as Gergen, to a lesser extent, Anderson and Craig, and those inappropriately attributed to scholars such as Kuhn, is that hypotheticodeductive approaches are fundamentally flawed because: (a) the realm of human experience is too subtle and rich to be reduced to causal hypotheses or the methods employed to measure, test, and represent such experience; and (b) reality is socially constructed, and therefore, the scientific methodology is tautologically corrupted by the theory-dependence of the observational process. Both of these lines of attack are themselves ill-informed and flawed. First, the claim is that human experience, unlike physical or biological domains, is an actional realm, characterized by intention and choice, and therefore, abeyant to a teleological form of causation rather than traditional Aristotelian forms of causal determination. For the future to cause the present is assumed to vitiate traditional axiomatic forms of theory construction and validation due to the inherent break in the causal chain between past and present. There are several problems with this criticism, including: Just because we have not yet found human experience to be highly predictable is not proof that it is not predictable (and some programs of research are revealing certain human experiences to be highly predictable); Many presumptively actional phenomena may possess far more tangible spatio-temporal and tangible existence; e.g., Fisher/Aron: passionate love in fMRI scans Second, the claim is made that the socially constructed nature of knowledge infects the research process in ways that invalidate the ability to claim “objective” or “externally validated” observations in test of our theoretical conjectures. This line of criticism is also fundamentally flawed: First, such a claim is self-reflectively invalidating, in that it claims that all claims are subject to subjectivity, and therefore there is theory-free reference point against which the validity of this criticism may be evaluated. By opening all knowledge claims to linguistic relativism, no one argument is any more valid than another, and therefore, an argument claiming the invalidity of scientific epistemologies is equally refuted by any reasoned response; Second, the very evidence often adduced to support the linguistic and theoretical biases of knowledge often rely upon the very scientific method being critiqued as invalid; Third, research on cognitive psychology (e.g., color experiments) demonstrates that we actually largely perceive the same world, independent of beliefs. We are able, and may be inclined, to Comm 610: Advanced Communication Theory: 112 elaborate belief-consistent explanations, but the data of experience themselves are not particularly sensitive to preexisting beliefs or theories, much less, language; Fourth, the process of scientific and methodological rigor and procedure was formulated a priori to any particular theoretical commitments, so the epistemology is independent of the theories that seek to be confirmed or infirmed by its application; Fifth, scientific debates often occur within paradigms, indicating that differences can be argued over data despite sharing a common cultural, linguistic, and even general theoretical foundation; Sixth, the auxiliary hypotheses employed to manage the fallout of experiments are themselves subject to rigorous experiment, test, observation, and evidence, so that no part of the process is arbitrary; Seventh, to argue the linguistic/cultural relativity of perception is to require allusion to evidence of such. Such allusion presupposes the ability of data to provide ‘objective’ evidence in claims of rhetorically-constructed knowledge, which is a self-contradictory claim; Eighth, scientific observation is only theoretically tautological Comm 610: Advanced Communication Theory: 113 Selected Recommended Sources Bostrom, R. N. (2003). Theories, data, and communication research. Communication Monographs, 70, 275-294. Bostrom, R. N. (2004). Empiricism, paradigms, and data. Communication Monographs, 71, 343-341. Charland, M. (2003). The incommensurability thesis and the status of knowledge. Philosophy and Rhetoric, 36, 248-263. Chow, S. L. (1992). Acceptance of a theory: Justification or rhetoric? Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour, 22, 447-474. Fuchs, S. (2001). What makes sciences “scientific”? In J. H. Turner (Ed.), Handbook of sociological theory (pp. 21-35). New York: Kluwer Academic/Plenum. Gilman, D. (1992). What's a theory to do...with seeing? or some empirical considerations for observation and theory. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 43, 287-309. Greenwald, A. G., Pratkanis, A. R., Leippe, M. R., & Baumgardner, M. H. (1986). Under what conditions does theory obstruct research progress? Psychological Review, 93, 216-229. Irzik, G., & Grünberg, T. (1995). Carnap and Kuhn: Arch enemies or close allies? British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 46, 285-307. Jost, J. T., & Kruglanski, A. W. (2002). The estrangement of social constructionism and experimental social psychology: History of the rift and prospects for reconciliation. Personality and Social Psychology Review, 6, 168-187. Koutougos, A. (1989). Research programmes and paradigms as dialogue structures. In K. Gavroglu, Y. Goudaroulis, & P. Nicolacopoulos (Eds.), Imre Lakatos and theories of scientific change (Vol. 111, Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, pp. 361-374). Boston: Kluwer Academic. Krueger, J. I. (2002). Postmodern parlor games. American Psychologist, 57, 461-462. Laudan, L., Donovan, A., Laudan, R., Barker, P., Brown, H., Leplin, J., Thagard, P., & Wykstra, S. (1986). Scientific change: Philosophical models and historical research. Synthese, 69, 141-223. Martindale, D. (1979). Ideologies, paradigms, and theories. In W. E. Snizek, E. R. Fuhrman, & M. K. Miller (Eds.), Contemporary issues in theory and research: A metasociological perspective (pp. 7-24). Westport, CT: Greenwood. Mayo, D. G. (1996). Ducks, rabbits, and normal science: Recasting the Kuhn’s-eye view of Popper’s demarcation of science. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 47, 271-290. Pavitt, C. (2004). Theory-data interaction from the standpoint of scientific realism: A reaction to Bostrom. Communication Monographs, 71, 333-342. Popper, K. (1980). Science: Conjectures and refutations. In E. D. Klemke, R. Hollinger, & A. D. Kline (Eds.), Introductory readings in the philosophy of science (pp. 19-34). Buffalo, NY: Prometheus. Spitzberg, B. H. (2000). On defining and evaluating theory. Abstracted and adapted from: Spitzberg, B. H. (2001). The status of attribution theory qua theory in personal relationships. In V. Manusov & J. H. Harvey (Eds.), Attribution, communication behavior, and close relationships (pp. 353-371). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Turner, J. H. (1985). In defense of positivism. Sociological Theory, 3, 24-30. Turner, J. H. (1990). The misuse and use of metatheory. Sociological Forum, 5, 37-53. Wallach, L., & Wallach, M. A. (1994). Gergen versus the mainstream: Are hypotheses in social psychology subject to empirical test? Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 67, 233-242. Wallach, L., & Wallach, M. A. (1994). Gergen versus the mainstream: Are hypotheses in social psychology subject to empirical test? Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 67, 233-242. Comm 610: Advanced Communication Theory: 114 SCIENCE AS A GAME (ala Spitzberg, 2009) I. II. Context: Framing the Game A. The field as multi-paradigmatic (sans dominant grand unifying theories) B. The search for synthesis The Meaning(s) of the Metaphor A. The nature of games: 1. Rationality: A presumption that strategic play can render optimal outcomes 2. Agents: “An individual agent is called a player (or sometimes, an “actor”). The player exercises human intelligence, assessing “his” party’s situation, selecting from the available courses of action and committing his party [which may be himself] to this selection” (p. 86) parties (“something with a unitary interest to promote,” Goffman, 1969, p. 86) 3. Tokens: “An individual may function as a token, that is, a means of expressing and marking openly a position that has been taken” (p. 87) 4. Moves: a choice, enacted or performed as a tactical selection; “A move, analytically speaking, is not a thought or decision or expression, or anything else that goes on in the mind of a player; it is a course of action” p. 90) 5. Utility function: the “ordering, weak or strong, of aims and goals” of an agent or actor (p. 91) 6. Normative constraints, whether imposed externally or self-imposed 7. Style of play: a characteristic, or predictable, pattern of moves 8. Information state: “the knowledge the opponent may possess about the important features of his own situation” and the other players or agents (p. 95) 9. Consensual rules & repertoires of moves/tactics 10. Motives can often be inferred by moves, but they are not isomorphic; further, both/either ends and means can be valued 11. Both self and audience, and front-stage and back-stage, perspectives are considered 12. The game can sometimes be gamed (“Another important attribute of players is their integrity, that is, the strength of their propensity to remain loyal to a party once they have agreed to play for it, and not to instigate courses of action on behalf of some other party’s interests, notably their own” p. 97) 13. Strategic interaction: “Two or more parties must find themselves in a wellstructured situation of mutual impingement where each party must make a move and where every possible move carries fateful implications for all of the parties. In this situation, each player must influence his own decision by knowing that the other players are likely to try to dope out his decision in advance, and may even appreciate that he knows this is likely. Courses of action or moves will then be made in light of one’s thoughts about the others’ thoughts about oneself. An exchange of moves made on the basis of this kind of orientation to self and others can be called strategic interaction” p. 101) Comm 610: Advanced Communication Theory: 115 B. The game of scholarship 1. The Main Objective: Sustain an engaging living 2. The Field of Play: The “discipline” and “profession” 3. The Official Rules: get Ph.D., get good letters, good position, publications, grants, tenure, a 2-day-a-week schedule and an office with a window 4. The Moves: papers, publications, publications, committees, visibility 5. The Players: the taxpayers, high-level administrators (trustees, presidents, etc.), mid-level administrators (e.g., V.P., Deans, etc.), low-level administrators (e.g., Chairs, committees, etc.). C. Possible Strategies: 1. Path of least resistance (i.e., get tenure, then rest on laurels) 2. Maximum visibility (quantity and self-promotion) 3. Stealth: (i.e., good “worker bee” or “flying under the radar”) 4. Administrative aspirations: seeking money and power III. Possible Points & Paradoxes: A. Theories, studies, and publications may not be a search for truth as much as a search for status B. Just because a game may not be “about seeking truth” doesn’t mean that truth may not be a likely by-product of the process C. Games evolve, but generally only in ways that largely preserve the “traditions” (and therefore resist radical change—lest the game itself cease to exist) D. The “culture of committee meetings” is analogous to the coach’s meetings, league meetings, etc., through which the “business” of the game is sustained and promoted “truth’s ultimate unattainability does not necessarily negate the value of truth as a regulating ideal for science…In other words, truth as a product of the scientific process is different from truth as a regulating ideal that may guide epistemic activity. … Donald Campbell (1994) … [argued] that ‘the world as it is’ is a ‘co-selector’ of consensual beliefs among scientists” (Jost & Kruglanski, 2002, p. 173) We may not have any philosophically assured epistemology to render access to the truth. However, playing the game as if we do may have the effect of moving us closer to the truth. In this sense, therefore, that Kuhn (1969) rejects the charge that he is a relativist: “Scientific development is… a unidirectional and irreversible process. Later scientific theories are better than earlier ones for solving puzzles…that is not a relativist’s position, and it displays the sense in which I am a convinced believer in scientific progress” (p. 169) Comm 610: Advanced Communication Theory: 116 “An appropriately programmed perceptual mechanism has survival value” (Kuhn, Structure, p. 161). “The world is not invented or constructed…. Creatures born into it must take it as they find it” (Kuhn, Road since…, p. 101). “Insofar as the structure of the world can be experienced and the experience communicated, it is constrained by the structure of the lexicon of the community which inhabits it” (Kuhn, Road since…, p. 101). “The essential function of the concept of truth is to require choice between acceptance and rejection of a statement or a theory in the face of evidence shared by all” (Kuhn, Road since …, p. 99). “Producing knowledge capable of claiming scientific legitimacy involves certain obligations and rights on the part of the researcher It is a question of playing the game of science, observing – and being seen to observe – its procedural rules and committing to its norms. Once these obligations are fulfilled, the social scientist can lay claim to the rights of procedural or formal, though not substantive, consensus: he/she deserves to be listened to because he/she has played the game” (Hynes et al., 2011, p. 298). A few sources: Barash, D. P. (2003). The survival game: How game theory explains the biology of cooperation and competition. New York, NY: Henry Holt. Brumback, R. A. (2009). Impact factor wars: Episode V—The empire strikes back. Journal Of Child Neurology, 24(3), 260-262. doi:10.1177/0883073808331366 Coren, S. (1982). The game of academe. Canadian Psychology/Psychologie Canadienne, 23(2), 97-101. doi:10.1037/h0081249 Fejes, A., Johansson, K., & Dahlgren, M. (2005). Learning to play the seminar game: Students' initial encounters with a basic working form in higher education. Teaching In Higher Education, 10(1), 29-41. doi:10.1080/1356251052000305516 Goffman, E. (1969). Strategic interaction. Philadelphia, PA: University of Pennsylvania Press. Hynes, M., Sharpe, S., & Greig, A. (2011). Appearing true in the social sciences: Reflections on an academic hoax. Journal of Sociology, 48, 287-303. Comm 610: Advanced Communication Theory: 117 Source: Brumback (2009) Source: Coren (1982) Comm 610: Advanced Communication Theory: 118 A SELECTED QUANDARY OF THEORETICAL ISSUES PARADIGMS The Nature of Paradigms: Paradigms consist of a (1) creative aspect (hypothesis generation) and (2) critical aspect (hypothesis testing) (McGuire, '73, 447) “Paradigms organize theories, which organize science, which validates theories, which justifies paradigms” (Spitzberg, 2002) "Within the confines of a given paradigm an inquirer decides (a) how to conceptualize and stipulate a problem, (b) whether to use a substantive theory (and which one) to guide the investigation, (c) what will be admitted as data..., and (e) what criteria will be applied to judge the integrity of the approach to and solution of the problem" (Schwandt, '89, 390) Differences between ideology and scientific theory: (1) Objective: prescription vs. description/explanation (2) Location of operation: action vs. thought (3) Components: values/axiology vs. laws/explanation (4) Criteria: good/bad vs. true/false (Martindale, '79, 8) ["All social science is ideology" (Martindale, '79, 10)] "I think science--both 'normal science' and 'revolutionary, paradigm-replacing science"--differs from less promising, non-cumulative, and personalistic enterprises like politics, psychotherapy, folklore, ethics, metaphysics, aesthetics, and theology in part because of its skeptical insistence on reliable (intersubjective, replicable) protocols that describe observations" (Meehl, '78, 813) Four Paradigms (McKeon, elaborated by Smith, '88): (1) phenomenal: laws, positivism, empirical necessity (2) operational: operationalism, sophists, logical necessity (3) naturalistic: p (4) phenomenological: phenomenology, practical necessity Four Paradigms (Phillipson, '72): (1) Behaviorist: Actor-impulses, Order-balance, Form-laws (2) Functionalist: Actor-needs, Order-system maintenance, Form-Pattern (3) Voluntarist: Actor-interests, Order-domination/compromise, Form-projects Four Paradigms (Altman & Rogoff, '87): (1) Trait: individual units, material causes, separate observers (2) Interactional: person X env. units, efficient causes, separate observers (3) Oganismic: holistic units, final causes, separate observers (4) Transactional: holistic units with aspects, formal causes, observers are phenomena Making factual generalizations about similar phenomena not encompassed by the observations constitutes science; drawing factual or aesthetic/value conclusions about the observed phenomena constitutes rhetoric (Miller, '75, 232-3) “Viewing theories as affective and morally charge[d] symbolic frameworks of world order, suggests that it is, in part, a theory’s capacity to secure nonlogical commitments that account for the crystallization of a school. Moreover, a school functions then not simply as a vehicle of collective reason but as a form of moral community” (Seidman, 1987-88, p.134) Comm 610: Advanced Communication Theory: 119 Coping With Multiple Paradigms: Multiple levels of explanation are required, given that explanation should be "pitched" at the level of the phenomenon (Cronen & Davis, '78; McDermott, '75) Strategies to resolve paradigm conflict: (1) denial: differences are thematic-not paradigmatic (2) co-optation: paradigms are complementary (3) supremacy: decisive test (4) replacement: synthesis or dialectic new paradigm (5) primacy of method: use method, not theory (6) anarchism: pluralism (Schwandt, '89) "The choice of one paradigm over another is not subject to empirical proof, for each carries its own criteria of acceptability" (Krippendorf, '84, 24; see also Smith, '88) "... in science ... it is often difficult to separate what is extremely radical from what is pathological." (J. B. Cohen) "In effect, some of the greatest conceptual strides are to be made when the theorist can bracket the accepted realities and fumble toward the articulation of the absurd." (Gergen, 1986, p.157) "What appears from the outside like a faith, a fiction, or a fantasy comes to feel from the inside like a rational enterprise." (R. A. Shweder) THE NATURE OF EXPLANATION Types of explanation: causal vs. teleological (McDermott, '75) Types of generality: syntactical & domain (Cushman & Pearce, '77) Types of necessity: nomic, logical, practical (Cushman & Pearce, '77; Cronen & Davis, '78) Generality reduces to generality (Cronen & Davis, '78) Forms of Conditionship: 1. Reversible or irreversible (if X, then Y and if Y then X; vs. if X, then Y, but if Y, then ?) 2. Deterministic of stochastic (if X, then always Y; vs. if X then probably Y) 3. Sequential or coextensive (if X, then later Y; vs. if X then also Y) 4. Sufficient or contingent (if X, then Y regardless; vs. if X then Y but only if Z) 5. Necessary or substitutable (if X, and only if X, then Y; vs. if X, then Y, but if Z, then also Y) (Zetterberg, in McDermott, p.90) "To the extent that the mind furnishes the categories of understanding, there are no real-world objects of study other than those inherent within the mental makeup of persons. There are no objects save those for which there are preceding categories.... in the act of comprehension, object and concept are one; objects reduce to the mental a priori." (Gergen, 1976, P. 141). “The success of theoretical explanations is the success of science itself.” (Mos & Boodt, 1990, p. 75) “Not every guess is a hypothesis and not every hypothesis can be denominated a theory” (Mos & Boodt, 1990, p. 82) Comm 610: Advanced Communication Theory: 120 PROBLEMS AND PARADOXES CONCEPTUAL: The "Self-Reflective Systems" Paradox: Language is both object and instrument of theory construction (McDermott, '75) "It is therefore a characteristic of systems involving their observers that they develop their own definition of the very system in which the observers participate" (Krippendorf, '84, 33) Scientific discovery feeds back into the system it is studying, thereby altering it (McClintock, '85, 164) Theory can become a self-fulfilling prophecy (McClintock, '85, 164) The Induction/Deduction Dilemma: Induction ultimately involves deduction (McDermott, '75) "Induction ... is a myth. It is neither a psychological fact, nor a fact of ordinary life, nor one of scientific procedure" (Popper, '80, 27) "Only the falsity of the theory can be inferred from empirical evidence, and this inference is a purely deductive one" (Popper, '80, 29) "No rule can ever guarantee that a generalization inferred from true observations, however often repeated, is true.... And the success of science is not based upon rules of induction, but depends upon luck, ingenuity, and the purely deductive rules of critical argument" (Popper, '80, 27) Inductiondiscover and deductionjustification, but not vice versa (McDermott, '75) "No scientific theory can ever be deduced from observation statements, or be described as a truth-function of observation statements" (Popper, '80, 25-6) The Heisenberg Dilemma: Heisenberg Principle: the process of measurement changes the nature of the phenomenon (thus rendering exact knowledge impossible) (McClintock, '85, 160) Precision and generalization are mutually exclusive (Blalock, '79, 125) The Complexity/Validity Conundrum: A complex theory is required to know what constructs to eliminate to achieve parsimony, yet complexity must be generated from simpler models (Blalock, '79, 134) "We may not be able to explain our own cognitive functioning if it turns out to be more complex than the cognitive capability we possess to explain it. And the same obtains for explaining our social behaviors" (McClintock, '85, 163) “In his romantic paean The Tables Turned, William Wordsworth wrote: ‘Sweet is the lore which nature brings; Our meddling intellect Misshapes the beauteous form of things: We murder to dissect’” (Gould, 1985, p.377) Comm 610: Advanced Communication Theory: 121 The Practicality of Theory: “...one is left to wonder if theory is more practical than other narrative forms such as poetry, essays, or major works of fiction. Certainly, these too are important contexts of thinking and full of ideas that potentially relate to practice in the same way. It is not established and probably naive to insist that theory enjoys priority over these other narrative forms in deserving the appellation ‘practical’” (Sandelands, 1990, p. 258). “. . . all exciting science must be obsolescent from inception . . .” (Gould, 1995, p. 373). “My suspicion is that the universe is not only queerer than we suppose, but queerer than we can suppose” (J. B. S. Haldane, quoted by Gould, 1995, p. 387, emphasis added) “Theory-free science makes about as much sense as value-free politics” (Gould, 1995, p. 419) METHODOLOGICAL: Methodological Myopia: "available research designs, methods, and measurement techniques are singularly instrumental in determining just how social problem questions will be asked and answered." (Proshansky, '81, 128) "the nature and significance of theoretical endeavors in the behavioral sciences...is inextricably rooted in the empirical strategies and methodological orientations that define the research process in these fields of inquiry" (Proshansky, '81, 101) “All methods are in the pursuit of truth, and that goal is not achieved by ignoring contributions from certain methods” (Lieberson, 1992, p.3) The Ineffability of the Real: "Measurement problems are solved at the expense of generalizability" (Blalock, '79, 130) "The phenomenal integrity of human behavior and experience is lost in the fundamental requirement of the approach that theoretical formulations must be cast in terms that directly allow derived concepts and propositions to be objectively defined and thereby made operationally precise" (Proshansky, '81, 104) The Complexity of Complexity: The more complex the theory, the more impossible it is to ascertain which part needs refinement (McClintock, '85, 165) The more complex the theory, the more alternative models that can be constructed employing the same components (McClintock, '85, 171) "any single behavioral event is almost by definition subject to multiple interpretations by an external observer" (McClintock, '85, 163) Popper’s Paradox: “Notoriously, ... Popper is quite explicit that good theories are bold and therefore likely to be false” (Papineau, 1989, p. 432). Comm 610: Advanced Communication Theory: 122 Falsifying Falsification: Falsifiability is a partial function of: (1) precision, (2) specification of conditions under which predictions are expected to hold, [see also Meehl, '78, 818] (3) and extent to which measurement is as accurate as variations in prediction relative to theoretical rivals (Blalock, '79, 123; see also Greenwald et al., '86 re: condition-seeking as a form of verification) The Disconfirmation Dilemma: nonconfirming results allow attribution of failure to (1) inferences from theory to prediction, (2) procedure development, (3) data analysis & testing (Greenwald et al., 1986; see also Blalock, '79, 126; Proshansky, '81, 116) PEARLS OF WISDOM Ethnocentrism: “The famous statement by Freud . . .: The most important scientific revolutions all include, as their only common feature, the dethronement of human arrogance from one pedestal after another of previous convictions about our centrality in the cosmos.” (Gould, 1995, p. 164-165). The Nature of Theory: "whereas the statement of 'facts' can be judged true or false, ... this criterion of truth cannot help to determine which of an infinite number of true facts to include or exclude from any explanation. And it is the very important role of theories or models to limit our search for explanation to some realizable number of facts" (McClintock, '85, 158) "Still the most satisfactory way of appraising the status...of any science, is in terms of an inventory of its theories" (Martindale, '79, 19) "All human research...involves conceptions, assumptions, and other generalizations about people, what they are like, how they behave, and how they think and feel" (Proshansky, '81, 105) "Historically speaking all--or very nearly all--scientific theories originate from myths..." (Popper, '80, 24) The Nature of Meta-Theory: “The goal is to use theories to build better ones, not to become sociological monks copying and reciting passages from the sacred texts” (Turner, 1990, p.44). The Nature of Science: "The ordinary conception of the scientific method is false; it is actually a form of illustration. Science does not progress--at least not in a linear sense--but undergoes periodic convulsive revolutions as one noncomparable faith replaces another" (Martindale, '79, 14) "Science is corrosive of all values which are based exclusively on simple epistemological processes" (McClintock, '85, 162) "In view of all the violent forces against it, scientific objectivity, when it is in fact realized, may be seen to have many of the characteristics of the moment of calm at the eye of a hurricane" (Martindale, '79, 12) "every scientist has a vested interest in the preservation of the status quo" (Cohen, '85, 18) Comm 610: Advanced Communication Theory: 123 "science is an exceptional enterprise in that revolutionary activity has been institutionalized" (Cohen, '85, 19) "In human affairs there is no major achievement without passion" (Martindale, '79, 10) "Passionate interest in a particular outcome can create selective perception and distorted interpretation such that one sees only evidence and argument for his/her cause. But only a scoundrel will manufacture evidence" (Martindale, '79, 10) "some of the greatest strides are to be made when the theorist can bracket the accepted realities and fumble toward the articulation of the absurd." (Gergen, 1976, p. 157) Paradox and Reflexivity: “Bohr has written, ‘There are trivial truths and great truths. The opposite of a trivial truth is plainly false. The opposite of a great truth is also true.’” (McGuire, 1973, p.455) “It is not how things are in the world that is mystical, but that it exists. … We feel that even when all possible scientific questions have been answered, the problems of life remain completely untouched. Of course there are then no questions left, and this itself is the answer.” (L. Wittgenstein, 1961, Tractatus, 6.52) “There are, indeed, things that cannot be put into words. They make themselves manifest. They are what is mystical.” (L. Wittgenstein, 1961, Tractatus, 6.522) Misc. "We must openly accept all ideologies and systems as means of solving humanity's problems. One country, one nation, one ideology, one system is not sufficient." Dalai Lama "The point of philosophy is to start with something so simple as not to seem worth stating, and to end with something so paradoxical that no one will believe it." Betrand Russel "The ability to simplify means to eliminate the unnecessary so that the necessary may speak." Hans Hoffman "Reality is merely an illusion, albeit a very persistent one." Albert Einstein "There are two ways to slide easily through life; to believe everything or to doubt everything. Both ways save us from thinking." Alfred Korzybski "The invariable mark of wisdom is to see the miraculous in the common." Ralph Waldo Emerson The Statement Below is True: The Statement In This Box is False So is The Statement Above This One! Comm 610: Advanced Communication Theory: 124 BRAIN TEASERS & WHEEZERS “We live within the words of language, the shapes of poetry and plastic art, the structure of music, the framework of religious representation and religious beliefs. And it is only within these [media] that we ‘know’ each other. This intuitive knowledge does not yet have the character of ‘science’” (Cassirer, 1961, p. 143). “When it raises itself to the knowledge of universal laws for which there is no difference between the near and the distant, natural science becomes master of the distant. … This form of universality is closed to the science of culture. It cannot renounce anthropomorphism and anthropocentrism. … Its goal is not the universality of laws; but neither is it the individuality of facts and phenomena. In contrast to both, it sets up an ideal of knowledge of its own. What it seeks to realize is the totality of the forms in which human life is realized.” (Cassirer, 1961, p. 144) “This fundamental idea of modern [scientific] research found its decisive philosophical legitimation in Descartes’ concept of mathesis universalis. The cosmos of universal mathematics, the cosmos of order and measure, comprehends and exhausts all knowledge. … That this fundamental idea of classical philosophical rationalism not only fertilized and extended science, but that it gave to science a wholly new meaning and goal… The development of systems of philosophy from Descartes to Malebranche and Spinoza, and from Spinoza to Leibniz affords unbroken evidence of this.” (Cassirer, 1961, p. 49) “[According to Vico] Hence the unavoidable alternative which our knowledge faces: it can orient itself toward the real, but in this case it can never completely penetrate its object, but describes it instead only piecemeal and empirically, with respect to particular properties and characteristics; or it can achieve complete insight, an adequate idea, which constitutes the nature and essence of the object, but then knowledge never leaves the sphere of its own concept formation.” (Cassirer, 1961, p. 53) “with the resources peculiarly its own, language is not able to generate scientific knowledge, or even to arrive at it. Nevertheless, it is an indispensable stage on the way to it; it constitutes the only medium in which the knowledge of things can arise and progressively develop.” (Cassirer, 1961, p. 58) “Each of the humanistic disciplines develops determinate concepts of form and style and uses them in arriving at a systematic survey, a classification and differentiation of the phenomena with which it concerns itself. These concepts of form are neither ‘nomothetic’ nor ‘idiographic.’ They are not nomothetic for their function is not to establish general laws from which the individual phenomena can be deductively inferred. But neither do they admit of being reduced to historical inquiry.” (Cassirer, 1961, p. 120) “We understand a science in its logical structure only when we have arrived at clarity as to the manner in which it achieves the subsumption of the particular under the universal. But in solving this problem we must be on our guard against a one-sided formalism. For there is no general schema which we may refer to or invoke. This problem is common to all the sciences; but its solution leads in many directions.” (Cassirer, 1961, p. 135) “‘the particular’ says Goethe, ‘is always more than a match for the universal; the universal always has to accommodate itself to the particular.’” (Cassirer, 1961, p. 135) Comm 610: Advanced Communication Theory: 125 “A particular mode of signifying may be unimportant but it is always important that it is a possible mode of signifying. And that is generally so in philosophy: again and again the individual case turns out to be unimportant, but the possibility of each individual case discloses something about the essence of the world” (Wittgenstein, Tractatus, 3.3421) “The artist, the scientist, the founder of a religion, are able to perform truly great achievements only if they abandon themselves completely to their work, if they neglect their own being for it. But, as soon as it finally stands before its creator, the finished product is never simply a thing of satisfaction; it is, at the same time, a disappointment.” (Cassirer, 1961, p. 193) “The creative process must always satisfy two different conditions: one the one side, it must tie itself to something existing and enduring, and, on the other, it must be receptive to new use and application— this alters what [in other respects] remains the same. Only in this way does one succeed in doing justice to both the objective and the subjective demands [implicit in the creative act].” (Cassirer, 1961, p. 200) “we can now define more sharply the specific difference which exists between process [Werden] in ‘nature’ and process in ‘culture.’ … Mobility and permanence are the rightful claim of both; but these two factors appear in a different light the moment we shift our gaze from the world of nature to the human world…. [In the world of nature] the individual is of no distinctive importance here; “ (Cassirer, 1961, p. 214) “But in the cultural phenomena…the coming-to-be and the activity of individuals are linked to that of the species in a very different and profoundly formative manner….These works of language, poetry, plastic art, and religion, become ‘monuments,’ the symbols of recognition and remembrance of human kind” (Cassirer, 1961, p. 215) “The burning of the library at Alexandria annihilated many things of priceless value for our knowledge of antiquity; most of Leonardo’s paintings are lost to us because the colors in which they were painted have not lasted. But even in these cases the works as such remain tied to the whole of culture as if by invisible threads.” (Cassirer, 1961, p. 216) “what is expressed linguistically, in imagery, in plastic form, is embodied in language and art and endures henceforth through it. It is this process which distinguishes the mere transformation [Umbildung] taking place in the sphere of organic emergence from the formation [Bildung] of humanity. The former is a passive occurrence, the latter is active. Accordingly, the former leads simply to variations, whereas the latter leads to enduring creations” (Cassirer, 1961, pp. 216-17). “Nature … is here independently of our theories of it.” (Northrop, 1947, p. 276) “social institutions … confront the scientist with two quite different questions: (1) What is the character of social institutions in fact? … (2) How ought social institutions to be? … The first of these two types of questions is factual; the second is normative. Thus, whereas natural science faces only problems of fact, social science is confronted with problems of fact and with problems of value. … The generalizations appropriate for these two types of problem are fundamentally different. … It is important to have different names for these two types of theory in social science. It seems appropriate to call them factual social theory and normative social theory respectively. A factual social theory is one which is false if it is not in complete accord with what is the case. … Comm 610: Advanced Communication Theory: 126 A normative social theory designates what ought to be, rather than what is….None corresponds perfectly to any de facto state of affairs anywhere. They designate possible ideals, rather than the actual. Thus, by its very nature a normative social theory differs always in part and perhaps even in toto from what is in fact the case. This means that the scientific method for determining normative social theory cannot be that of natural science applied to social facts. The latter method is appropriate for factual social theory. It is inappropriate for normative social theory.” (Northrop, 1947, pp. 255-257) “Scientific inquiry in any field must begin with some method taken over a priori from some other field, but with the character of the problems of its own field and the analysis of these problems. A subject becomes scientific not by beginning with facts, with hypothesis, or with some pet method brought in a priori, but by beginning with the peculiar character of its particular problems. … these problems are of two fundamentally different types: (1) problems of fact and (2) problems of value.” (Northrop, 1947, p. 274) “the notion of a human society involves a scheme of concepts which is logically incompatible with the kinds of explanation offered in the natural sciences” (Winch, 1958, p. 72) “social interaction can more profitably be compared to the exchange of ideas in a conversation than to the interaction of forces in a physical system” (Winch, 1958, p. 128) “constantly I felt I was moving among two groups…who had almost ceased to communicate at all…” (Snow, 1964, p. 2) “I believe the intellectual life of the whole of western society is increasingly being split into two polar groups” [literary intellectuals vs. scientists] (Snow, 1964, p. 3) “Literary intellectuals at one pole—at the other scientists…. Between the two a gulf of mutual incomprehension—sometimes (particularly among the young) hostility and dislike, but most of all lack of understanding” (Snow, 1964, p. 4) “Non-scientists tend to think of scientists as brash and boastful” (p. 4) “the tone, restricted and constrained, with which literary intellectuals are at home: it is the subdued voice of their culture” (Snow, 1964, p. 5) “The non-scientists have a rooted impression that the scientists are shallowly optimistic, unaware of man’s condition. On the other hand, the scientists believe that the literary intellectuals are totally lacking in foresight, peculiarly unconcerned with their brother men, in a deep sense anti-intellectual, anxious to restrict both art and thought to the existential moment” (Snow, 1964, p. 5) “At one pole, the scientific culture really is a culture, …there are common attitudes, common standards and patterns of behaviour, common approaches and assumptions.” (Snow, 1964, p. 9) “This polarization is sheer loss to us all. To us as people, and to our society” (Snow, 1964, p. 11) “Intellectuals, in particular literary intellectuals, are natural Luddites” (Snow, 1964, p. 22) Comm 610: Advanced Communication Theory: 127 “It is permissible to lump pure and applied scientists into the same scientific culture, but the gaps are wide. Pure scientists and engineers often totally misunderstand each other. Their behaviour tends to be very different” (Snow, 1964, p. 31) “This is a line that once I tried to draw myself: but thought I can still see the reasons, I shouldn’t now. The more I have seen of technologists at work, the more untenable the distinction has come to look” (Snow, 1964, p. 67) “The scientific process has two motives: one is to understand the natural world, the other is to control it.” (Snow, 1964, p. 67) [Snow recognizes that as speaking as an Englishman] “In the United States, for example, the divide is nothing like so unbridgeable” (Snow, 1964, p. 69) “It is probably too early to speak of a third culture already in existence. But I am now convinced that this is coming” [from] “social historians” (Snow, 1964, pp. 70-1) -------------------------------“Man is unique not because he does science, and he is unique not because he does art, but because science and art equally are expressions of his marvelous plasticity of mind.” J. Bronowski, The ascent of man, 1973 (in Kaplan: Science says) “Every science begins as philosophy and ends as art.” W. Durant, The story of philosophy, 1926 (in Kaplan: Science says) “The greatest scientists are always artists as well.” Einstein, 1923, Durham Morning Herald, Aug. 21, 1955, (in Kaplan: Science says) “Both the man of science and the man of art live always at the edge of mystery, surrounded by it. Both, as the measure of their creation, have always had to do with the harmonization of what is new with what is familiar, with the balance between novelty and synthesis, with the struggle to make partial order out of chaos…. This cannot be an easy life.” J. R. Oppenheimer, in Jung, Brighter than a thousand suns, 1958 Comm 610: Advanced Communication Theory: 128 Selected References Becker, S. L. (1989). The rhetorical tradition. In S. S. King (Ed.), Human communication as a field of study: Selected contemporary views (pp. 27-42). Albany, NY: State University of New York Press. Cassirer, E. (1961). The logic of the humanities (transl. C. S. Howe). New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. Cohen, H. (1985) The development of research in speech communication: A historical perspective. In W.T. Benson (Ed.), Speech communication in the 20th century (pp. 282-298). Carbondale, IL: Southern Illinois University. Comstock, G. (1983). The legacy of the past. Journal of Communication, 33, 42-50. Delia, J.G. (1987). Communication research: A history. In C.R. Berger & S.H. Chaffee (Eds.), Handbook of communication science (pp. 20-98). Newbury Park, CA: Sage. Farrell, T.B. (1987). Beyond science: Humanities contributions to communication theory. In C.R. Berger & S.H. Chaffee (Eds.), Handbook of communication science (pp. 123-139). Newbury Park: Sage. Golden, J. L. (1987). Contemporary trends and historical roots in communication. A personal view. Central States Speech Journal, 38, 262-270. Gonzalez, H. (1988). The evolution of communication as a field. Communication Research, 15, 302-308. (see also: Peters, J. D. (1988). The need for theoretical foundations: Reply to Gonzalez. Communication Research, 15, 309-317. Harper, N. L. (1979). Human communication theory: The history of a paradigm. Rochelle Park, NJ: Haden Book Co. Katz, E. (1983). The return of the humanities and sociology. Journal of Communication, 33, 41-52. Leff, M.C., & Procario, M.O. (1985). Rhetorical theory in speech communication. In T.W. Benson (Ed.), Speech communication in the 20th century (pp. 3-27). Carbondale, IL: Southern Illinois University. Littlejohn, S.W. (1982). An overview of contributions to human communication theory from other disciplines. In F.E.X. Dance (Ed.), Human communication theory: Comparative essays (pp. 243285). New York: Harper & Row. Miller, G.R. (1975). Humanistic and scientific approaches to speech communication inquiry: Rivalry, redundancy, or rapprochement. Western Speech Communication, 39, 230-239. Northrop, F. S. C. (1947). The logic of the sciences and the humanities. New York: Macmillan. Powers, J. H. (1995). On the intellectual structure of the human communication discipline. Communication Education, 44, 191-222. Prior, M. E. (1962). Science and the humanities. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University. Rogers, E. M., & Chaffee, S. H. (1983). Communication as an academic discipline: A dialogue. Journal of Communication, 33, 18-30. Rosengren, K. R. (1983). Communication research: One paradigm, or four? Journal of Communication, 33, 185-207. Schramm, W. (1983). The unique perspective of communication: A retrospective. Journal of Communication, 33, 6-17. Comm 610: Advanced Communication Theory: 129 Schramm, W. (1989). Human communication as a field of behavioral science: Jack Hilgard and his committee. In S. S. King (Ed.), Human communication as a field of study: Selected contemporary views (pp. 13-26). Albany, NY: State University of New York Press. Shweder, R. A. (1986). Explanation in the social sciences and in life situations. In D. W. Fiske & R. A. Shweder (Eds.), Metatheory in social science: Pluralisms and subjectivities (pp. 163196). Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Snow, C. P. (1961). The two cultures and the scientific revolution. New York: Cambridge University Press. Snow, C. P. (1964). The two cultures: and a second look (2nd ed.). New York: Cambridge University Press. Sorensen, G. (1993). Social science: A framework for communication inquiry. In S. A. Deetz (Ed.), Communication yearbook 16 (pp. 557-572). Newbury Park, CA: Sage. Wallace, K. R. (Ed.). (1954). History of speech education in America: Background studies. New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts. Winch, P. (1958). The idea of a social science and its relation to philosophy. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. Wittgenstein, L. (1961). Tractatus logico-philosophicus (D. F. Pears & B. F. McGuinness, transl.). London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. Comm 610: Advanced Communication Theory: 130 Perspectives on Theory and Theorizing Art Bochner NCA President In February 2008, Dawn Braithwaite and Brian Spitzberg organized a panel for the Western Communication Association Convention on the topic, “The Status of Theory in Interpersonal Communication.” The panel drew a large and enthusiastic audience. After the convention, several of those in attendance wrote to me, urging that I discuss the panel in one of my editorials. Not wanting to speak for any of my colleagues on the panel, I asked Brian Spitzberg to collect short versions (akin to abstracts) from each panelist and to encourage each to broaden the scope of their argument(s) beyond the realm of interpersonal communication. I hope these all too brief representations of rather complex arguments will stimulate further discussion and debate on CRTNET or in Spectra. *** Engaging Theory As we edited two recent theory books, we seized the opportunity to examine the “lay of the land” of the theories guiding scholarship. We recognize that scholars differ, at times greatly, concerning how to study, develop, and evaluate theories. We recognize that there are different types of theories that need to be evaluated in different ways, as scholars use different meta-theoretical discourses, paradigms, or intellectual traditions to study a phenomenon of interest. The complexities are compounded as researchers rarely explicitly articulate their metatheoretical commitments, although we believe they should do so more often. It is important to identify the paradigm represented in order to understand and intelligently evaluate the work. In our books on interpersonal and family communication theory, we examined all studies after 1990 to identify theories used, paradigmatic underpinnings, and the amount of theory-based research. Taken together, we found the vast majority of work in interpersonal and family communication was post-positivist (80%, higher in interpersonal), 17% interpretive, and a small amount was critical. We discovered that interpersonal had a higher degree of theory-based work (69%) and 43% in the comparatively newer sub-discipline of family communication. Of course, we realize these numbers may not be mirrored across the discipline. What are some implications of these findings? Briefly, first, we contend that scholars should strive for theory-centered research whenever possible, as theory helps researchers bring both intelligibility and coherence to their findings and theory helps us intelligently launch new research. Second, while all excellent research is valuable, interpersonal and family communication would benefit from increased paradigmatic balance; our ability to shed light on some of the most important issues in the lives of humans rests in our ability to embrace and apply multiple perspectives and methods to capture the complexity that is communication. Thus, we argue that multiple perspectives should have a comparable presence at the scholarly table. Dawn O. Braithwaite & Leslie A. Baxter *** A Role for Biology We don’t often deal with covering laws in communication, but here’s one worth considering: All communicative acts are biological acts. It derives from the acknowledgement that, as biological beings, humans can perform no action whatsoever without engaging in anatomical and physiological activity. Every behavior requires neurological and motor coordination to enact, and has effects on metabolic, immune, muscular, and/or endocrine processes. Therefore, every human act is a biological one, and because communicative acts are human acts, they are therefore biological acts as well. Comm 610: Advanced Communication Theory: 131 If you cringe when reading these words, you’re proving my point. Your act of decoding and interpreting these statements—which required the involvement of your eyes and your brain—produced a noticeable physiological effect. That effect isn’t a social construction. Rather, it represents your biological engagement with the communication process you’re enacting right now. This covering law doesn’t deny that communication is also symbolic, cultural, political, aesthetic, spiritual, and social. Like many human activities, communication is subject to complex interactions between a range of internal and external influences. What makes this statement a covering law and not simply an observation is that it applies equally to all communication behaviors. The case could be made that not every communicative act is cultural, or social, or political, for instance—many are, but some are not. But every communicative act is biological. I know this proposition will strike some as unreasonably deterministic, but it need not be. Calling a behavior biological doesn’t necessarily imply that it is also uncontrollable. What it does imply is that communication has implications for physical health and that some patterns of communicating may have more positive physical consequences than others. As a discipline, we can capitalize on this observation by identifying how communication contributes not only to social and relational well-being but also to our physical health. Kory Floyd *** Reviving Popper Theories rarely die due to contradictory evidence; they die because their originators die (or move into administration). So, how do (and should) theories evolve? Flaws in the hypothetico-deductive model are apparent: (a) as Popper observed, verification is easy, whereas falsification is hard; (b) but a disconfirmation dilemma arises because non-observations of a predicted phenomenon can be attributed to methodology or context rather than the theory. Such problems have led some critical and interpretive scholars to deride scientific methods as logically flawed, and scientific theories as too blunt to explain human action. Popper distrusted interpretive world views, and proffered a criterion of demarcation: A theory is scientific if it makes risky predictions (e.g., physics), and pseudo-scientific (e.g., astrology) if its predictions are impermeable to observational contradiction. With these ideas in mind, I make three claims. First, social scientists will make better theories the bigger the risks they take. Such predictions improve methods, rid the field of flawed claims more efficiently, and enhance the credibility of accumulated claims that survive more rigorous observational tests. Claims to epistemological superiority cannot be made without the following phrase (repeat after me): “This prediction, and therefore the theory from which it is derived, are false.” Second, without an equivalent criterion of quality, critical and interpretive approaches will permit indefinite perpetuation of potentially flawed claims. Third, social scientific approaches reveal clear potential for cumulative knowledge, despite the existence of human choice. Research has predicted with 94% accuracy which couples fail. Interpersonal communication research has used self-report methods to predict as much as 40% of the variance in stress-related hormones. Meta-analyses continue to demonstrate accumulated and theoretically predicted effects, and resolve questions requiring a strictly empirical and quantitative epistemological criterion. Any criticism of the failures of scientific approaches will need to provide some alternative for the accumulation of knowledge rather than merely identify what scientific approaches have yet to resolve. Brian Spitzberg *** Theories as Useful Vocabularies Communication studies can be viewed as a field of discourse that seeks to relate beings to other beings. Stories are the best ways to achieve this kind of relating. Richard Rorty observed that when you Comm 610: Advanced Communication Theory: 132 weigh the good and the bad the social novelists have achieved against the good and bad the social theorists have done, you find yourself wishing there had been more stories and fewer theories. If we take our lessons from the novelists rather than the scientists, then we don’t ask “how can we achieve control over the uncertainties of life?” Instead, we ask ‘how can we arrange things to be more comfortable with each other and with others who are different from us?” “How can we change our institutions so that everyone’s right to be understood, heard, and be given a voice, has a better chance to be achieved?” Theory-making is a vocation aimed at developing vocabularies that are useful for particular purposes. As Ken Gergen points out “the chief product of research is language.” Thus, a theorist inevitably functions as a social constructionist who invents language that mediates and/or creates social realities. Moreover, all theories and theoretical discourses are constitutive of their referential fields. In my ideal world of inquiry, an interactional conception of communication—how the practices of speaking, hearing, and conversing enable us to make our way through the world—would displace the transmission or depiction notion of communication in which language is viewed as nothing more than a vehicle or tool for describing or inscribing a preexisting ontological world. This conversational model of inquiry assumes that all attempts to speak for, write about, or represent other people’s lives necessarily are partial, situated, and mediated ways of creating and/or inscribing values. Thus communication inquiry necessarily is a site of moral responsibility. It is time to break the hold of certain disciplinary norms that idealize the importance of universals over particulars, stability over change, graphs over stories, and the ahistorical over the contingent. In my view, all research is storytelling, whether you call it empiricism, interpretivism, or criticism. Art Bochner *** Comm 610: Advanced Communication Theory: 133 “IN THEORY, …”: ON DEFINING AND EVALUATING THEORY IN COMMUNICATION SCIENCES Running Head: “In theory, ...” A Précis by Brian H. Spitzberg School of Communication San Diego State University 10.16.2K Portions of this manuscript previously appeared in: Spitzberg, B. H. (2001). Attribution theory qua theory. In V. Manusov & J. H. Harvey (Eds.), Attribution, communication behavior, and close relationships (pp. 353-371). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. **** Comm 610: Advanced Communication Theory: 134 “IN THEORY, …” ON DEFINING AND EVALUATING THEORY IN COMMUNICATION SCIENCES Consider the following statements, which are not entirely uncommon in everyday interaction: “In theory, I would think that . . .” “My theory about that is . . .” “You know, I have a theory about that. . .” These expressions reflect an ever-present drive to account for, explain, or make sense of the world around us. As Kurt Lewin opined, perhaps there really is “nothing more practical as a good theory” (Eysenck, 1987; Marrow, 1969; Sandelands, 1990). We employ theories in our everyday process of enacting and co-creating practical achievements. Yet, we have only rudimentary ideas of the precise nature, constituents, or criteria of theories. We use theories every day, but know little about their nature. A primer in the nature and evaluation of theories is therefore in order. Defining Theory A theory is formally defined here as a verifiable conceptual system of interrelated propositions explaining conditionship among a set of phenomena. These propositions may be formal, as in axiomatic theories or causal models, or informal, as in elaborate metaphors. These propositions may be explicit, as in mathematical formulae, or implicit, as in a diagrammatic model or narrative description of a process. The essence of a theory is that it explains a set of phenomena. “Explain” may be understood in a primitive sense as the offering of an account or narrative structure that renders an event, set of events, phenomenon or process comprehensible. Comprehension ordinarily, and perhaps necessarily, is tied to notions of causality, function, and underlying structure (Corrigan & Denton, 1996; cf. Sandelands, 1990). The role of causality in understanding suggests a difference between description and explanation; description does not require causal analysis but explanation does. A theory may accomplish a number of things, such as prediction, but ultimately, in the social sciences, to be a theory it must proffer an explanation. In its most essential function, explanation is an answer to the “why” question—why does X happen the way it does? The most logical candidate theoretical answer, therefore, will tend to begin with an implicit or explicit conjunction: because. . . . Evaluating Theory The subsuming criterion for theory evaluation is quality. A theory is higher in quality to the extent it more adequately accounts for a phenomenon (Pavitt, 2000) compared to its competitor candidate accounts, and to the extent that it furthers accumulation of general and precise knowledge over time. There are many criteria that provide reasonable approaches to ascertaining theoretical adequacy. To facilitate their description, a list of such criteria is reviewed, categorized into intrinsic and extrinsic qualities. Intrinsic qualities are those that can be evaluated internal to the theory itself, or within the domain of scholarly activity directly relevant to the theory. Intrinsic criteria can be categorized as either necessary or desirable. Necessary characteristics are those functions a theory must fulfill in order to even be considered a theory (vs. a primitive metaphor, a story, a description, a taxonomy, etc.). Desirable characteristics are those features of the theory that connote generally higher quality the more of these characteristics (e.g., parsimony) the theory Comm 610: Advanced Communication Theory: 135 possesses. Extrinsic qualities are those characteristics of the theory that get applied and assessed by the relevant school, invisible college, discipline, paradigm (in Kuhn’s “collective practices” sense), and/or society that represent the audiences to which the theory is addressed. The intrinsic and extrinsic criteria are summarized in Table 1. These criteria are not exhaustive, original, or even entirely consistent (Blalock, 1979; Eysenck, 1987; Freese, 1980; McClintock, 1985; Stamp, Vangelisti, & Knapp, 1994). They also do not reflect many of the larger meta-theoretical issues involved in theory construction (e.g., Turner, 1985, 1990, 1991). They do reflect much of the content of traditional, or modernist, approaches to the aesthetics of theory evaluation. A brief foray into these criteria will facilitate the examination of attribution theory. - - - Insert Table 1 about here - - Intrinsic Qualities Necessary conditions. A theory must explain a process, events, or phenomena. To do so, a basic understanding of the concepts relevant to this explanation, and their interrelationship, must be provided. This explanation must be more abstract than the referent. This is at least one difference between scientific theory and either history or ethnography. In providing an abstract explanation, a theory must apply equally across its intended domain or scope and the domain must consist of potentially more than one context or episode. For example, a theory of attributional influence that does not apply to marital decision-making, for example, would not be a “theory of attributional influence.” A theory’s propositions must also avoid direct contradiction. A theory should not claim that in context C, stimulus S produces internal attributions (X) and external attributions (Y), if X and Y are defined in by the theory as mutually exclusive categories. A diversion into verification. A theory must be verifiable. Here a detour is necessary. The original positivist and covering law model (Carnap, 1953; Hempel, 1965) represented an elaborate formal logical system to assess the validity of theories. One of the basic assumptions of this model was that mapping rules (i.e., rules of correspondence) could be formulated to link the symbols of a theory (e.g., its terms and relations) to their respective referents in the world being theorized. This is a necessary assumption if theories are going to be verifiable and/or falsifiable through observation of the empirical world. Popper (1959) attempted to fortify the basic soundness of the positivist agenda by demarcating between science and pseudo-science. Science, he claimed, must be potentially falsifiable (and by extension, deductive rather than inductive). Conversely, pseudo-science is indestructible. As Popper (1980) explicates: (1) It is easy to obtain confirmations, or verifications, for nearly every theory—if we look for confirmations. (2) Confirmations should count only if they are the result of risky predictions; . . . (3) Every “good” scientific theory is a prohibition: it forbids certain things to happen. The more a theory forbids, the better it is. (4) A theory which is not refutable by any conceivable event is nonscientific. Irrefutability is not a virtue of theory (as people often think) but a vice. (5) Every genuine test of a theory is an attempt to falsify it, or to refute it. Testability is falsifiability; . . . Comm 610: Advanced Communication Theory: 136 (6) Confirming evidence should not count except when it is the result of a genuine test of the theory; . . . (7) Some genuinely testable theories, when found to be false, are still upheld by their admirers—for example by introducing ad hoc some auxiliary assumption, or by reinterpreting the theory ad hoc in such a way that it escapes refutation. . . . One can sum up all this by saying that the criterion of the scientific status of a theory is its falsifiability, or refutability, or testability. (Popper, 1980, pp. 22-23) Despite the strength and clarity of these pronouncements, cracks soon developed in the Popperian edifice. Specifically, it was soon realized that theories are never tested in pure form. Instead, theoretical propositions are tested in a form that can be simplified and symbolically represented as follows: If (T . At . Cp . AI . Cn) (O1 O2) T is the theory being assessed. At is the set of auxiliary theories or assumptions that bridge the theory to the specific statements being tested. Cp is the ceteris paribus condition presuming “all things being equal.” Ai is the auxiliary theory representing measurement and instrumentation. Cn is the specific conditions of the experimental situation. O1 and O2 represent mutually exclusive possible outcomes. Thus, the formula above reads roughly as: Given theory T, and assuming At (e.g., boundary conditions such as contextual parameters), all things being equal (Cp), and given valid measurement (AI) and experimental conditions (Cn), then O1 will occur, and O2 will not occur. If the theory predicts O1, and instead, O2 is observed, Popper’s deductive modus tollens claims that the theory must be rejected (Chow, 1990, 1992; Gergen, 1991; Meehl, 1990; Papineau, 1989). However, because the theory (T) is not the only feature being tested, it is possible to attribute the failure to observe the predicted O1 to any of the auxiliary theories and/or assumptions of At through Cn, rather than falsify the theory T itself. This “ad hockery” represents the basis for a disconfirmation dilemma (Greenwald, Pratkanis, Leippe, & Baumbgardner, 1986). Specifically, the disconfirmation dilemma is that when results of an attempt to verify or falsify a theory do not provide support for the theory, the researcher(s) have no way of determining whether it is the theory itself, the interpretive extensions of the theory, or the methodology to blame. (Conversely, but seldom noted, a confirmation dilemma can occur, such that supportive results could be due to methodological chance—as in alpha error—or due to a mistaken interpretive extension of the theory that happens to conform to observation). Ad hockery is the process of creating theoretical bandages, or conceptual repairs, when research fails to support a theory. This dilemma is inimical to the concept of Popperian falsification, even if many have sought to shore up the logic of disconfirmation (Chow, 1990, 1992; Meehl, 1990). Other problems arose in the Popperian paradigm. For example, intuitively, Popper’s dictum of falsification leads to a rather bizarre paradox: The better the theory, the more likely it is to be false (Papineau, 1989). That is, elaborate articulation of an obviously false theory would be aesthetically “scientific” from Popper’s perspective because of its high degree of falsifiability. This paradox is partly resolved by the realization that Popper was not intending an aesthetic criterion so much as a definitional criterion, a criterion of demarcation. As such, falsifiable theories, or theories with high levels of falsifiable content, are ‘scientific,’ rather than pseudoscientific. Scientific theories can be presumed to be preferable (at least, to scientists), and therefore there are aesthetic impliations built into the demarcation candidate, but a theory Comm 610: Advanced Communication Theory: 137 that is highly falsifiable, and survives persistent efforts to falsify it, resolves the paradox by displaying its scientific nature as well as its validity as a conduit of knowledge. This, of course, assumes that such theories are possible in the social sciences, and this is not an easy assumption to demonstrate with the current state of theoretical knowledge in the social sciences. A diversion into paradigms. Lakatos (1970) sought to fortify Popper’s philosophy by developing a notion of “progressiveness.” Specifically, Lakatos argued that programs of research can be viewed as progressive or degenerative based on the fruitfulness of the associated ad hockery. If ad hoc auxiliary theories and speculations are increasingly valuable in refining a theory, its core assumptions, and its research directions, then the program can be considered progressive. If, in contrast, the ad hoc theorizing increasingly calls into question the fundamental assumptions of the theory, or if the theory increasingly requires piecemeal patchwork that is problematic to the very coherence of the theory, the program can be considered degenerative or regressive (Metaxopoulos, 1989). Progress is revealed in part by the accretion of new auxiliary concepts and hypotheses that extend the theory itself. In essence, over time a good theory possesses excess theoretical content relative to its predecessor(s) and therefore accomplishes not only what prior theory accomplished, but even more (Avgelis, 1989; Meehl, 1990). This also means that theory evaluation is intrinsically comparative; a theory’s quality can only be judged relative to its competitors (Avgelis, 1989; Colomy, 1991; Laudan, 1981; Nash & Wardell, 1993). Feyerabend (1970, 1975) decided to forego altogether Popper’s desire to maintain a demarcation between science and nonscience. Proposing an anarchistic epistemology, or a treatise against method, he argued that science fundamentally is no different from other forms of knowing. He further argued for a process of counterinduction, the generation of “unreasonable, nonsensical, unmethodical foreplay. . . . constant misuse of language” (Feyerabend, 1990, p. 25), as well as the introduction of hypotheses that “are inconsistent either with well-established theories or with well-established facts” (p. 26). “What remains are esthetic judgments, judgments of taste, and our own subjective wishes” (p. 90). Unlike Popper, therefore, ad hockery in this scheme is celebrated. A theoretical field is healthiest when it is most bedeviled by rival theories and hypotheses. Such theoretical pluralism is viewed as the best “method” through which to find the most useful theoretical approaches (Avgelis, 1989; Churchland, 1992). If the three approaches of Popper, Lakatos and Feyerabend were to be analogized to legal concepts (Phillips, 1977), Popper could be viewed as proposing law by statute, in which validity is determined by the rules. Lakatos would be proposing case law, in which the merit of each present case is determined relative to competing case exemplars. In contrast, Feyerabend recommends legal relativism, in which everything is decided in the context of present circumstances. Both Lakatos and Feyerabend view theory evaluation as comparative, although Lakatos believes that theories progress only with certain types of surplus content, whereas Feyerabend appears accepting of the value of all surplus content. These differing conceptions of science and theory received a rather unexpected thorn in their paws with Pepper’s (1957) notion of “world hypotheses” and especially Kuhn’s (1970) conception of paradigm and scientific change through revolution rather than accumulation, validation, and refinement (Masterman, 1970). Kuhn’s conception of paradigmatic revolution in Comm 610: Advanced Communication Theory: 138 particular, purported that the received view (D’Andrade, 1986) of science is fundamentally flawed. Science does not change because theories are felled by the axes of strict tests. Instead, a new worldview solves nagging problems that the normal science of the regnant paradigm is incapable of resolving. This paradigm shift is revolutionary in the sense that it does not build on the past so much as replace it. The basis upon which the change occurs is not so much a rational process, as it is a gestalt shift. From this perspective, “there is no neutral algorithm for theory-choice, no systematic decision procedure which, properly applied, must lead each individual in the group to the same decision” (Kuhn, 1970, p. 164). At some level, scientific revolutions are progressive, but not in the sense that they increasingly achieve “truth status.” Rather, they are progressive in the sense that theories become better at solving puzzles that existing theories seem incapable of solving. As Kuhn (1970) admits, “I do not doubt, for example, that Newton’s mechanics improves on Aritstotle’s and that Einstein’s improves on Newton’s as instruments for puzzlesolving” (p. 169). However, these improvements are not assumed to be entirely rational nor tied to “truth” so much as to paradigmatic value judgments of theoretical “accuracy, simplicity, fruitfulness, and the like” (p. 164). Theory evaluation, in this sense, is fundamentally comparative and subjective relative to the collective practices, values, and exemplars of the prevailing paradigm. Thus, the evaluation of theories is not ultimately a matter of “mere” hypothesis-testing, which is ultimately limited in its capacity to resolve theoretical debates (see Hunter, 1997; Meehl, 1978, 1990; cf. Chow, 1990). Despite the lack of access to the “Truth” afforded by the hypothetico-deductive perspective, the concept of verisimilitude (i.e., “truth-likeness”) has been retained by many, if not most, scientists. Verisimilitude is taken to be the practical collective consensus regarding the validity of a set of theoretical statements. In everyday contexts such as courts, boardrooms and families, the question of whether a word means one thing or another, and whether something is “there” or not, are practical achievements, and in most cases can be resolved to the satisfaction of those involved (Schegloff, 1992). The possibility may therefore exist for natural language, semantic and realist conceptions of theory (e.g., Bhaskar, 1978; Clark & Paivio, 1989; Greene, 1994; Suppe, 1989). This digression on verifiability and paradigmatic progress is necessary because the evaluation of a theory cannot proceed along the straightforward lines of calculating the number or percentage of hypothesis tests it passes, much less in comparing the ratio of successful hypothesis tests to the ratio of another theory. As much as such a process may render a certain appearance of objectivity in such judgments, reality does not disclose its mysteries so conveniently. There is value in successful research, but it serves as only one among many barometers of a theory’s merits. Among the additional criteria that are often drafted to account for a theory’s quality are the following. Desirable conditions. Generally speaking, the more specific a theory is in specifying its propositions, the better it is. Prediction is a desirable but not necessary aspect of propositions. For example, Darwin’s theory of evolution is highly explanatory, but lacks any predictive power in a number of senses, as it cannot specify the direction or form of evolutionary changes. It is immensely heuristic as it has generated new hypotheses modeled on evolutionary predictions in many disciplines, but the end products of the evolutionary process are relatively Comm 610: Advanced Communication Theory: 139 unpredictable by virtue of the impact of local circumstances in determining what faculties are, or are not, adaptive to those environments. If predictions are to be useful, the concepts of the theory need to be observable. The more observable the content of the theory is, the easier it should be to assess the verisimilitude of the theory. Furthermore, the more specifically a theory identifies its scope conditions, the better it is. Theories that subsume more concepts are generally considered preferable to those that subsume fewer. However, theories that are simple and “elegant” are generally preferable to those that are complex and conceptually extensive. These latter two criteria often produce tension, but they are not logically incompatible. At its core, for example, E = mc2 is simultaneously universal in scope, specific, and parsimonious. In contrast, formulae such as B = P E (i.e., Behavior is a function of Person times Environment) is universal and parsimonious, but far from specific in its empirical content and operationalization. Extrinsic Qualities To a large extent, the criteria above may be applied to a theory knowing little else beyond the theory itself and the available research relevant to the theory. However, as Lakatos, Feyerabend, and Kuhn have established, theories are rarely actually adopted, retained, or rejected purely on their own intrinsic merits. Instead, any given theory is evaluated in part by the disciplinary matrix within which it is applied, and within which it is competing for acceptance. This matrix applies practical, cultural and ideological criteria in the evaluation of these theories. Extrinsic criteria, in other words, concern qualities of performance and aesthetics from the perspective of the research culture that uses the theory, rather than strictly formal or rational characteristics. One of the cultural preferences for theories is that the theories permit intervention into and manipulation of the phenomenon. For example, to the extent that attribution theory guides improvements in marital therapy, it would be desirable. Theories that are heuristic (i.e., suggestive of future questions and applications) are also viewed as preferable. Perhaps as a holdover of the received view of science, theories that are efficient in subsuming existing theories are also generally preferable. In addition, science may not have access to “the” truth as a reference point from which to evaluate theories. However, groups of scholars nevertheless can collectively make theoretical predictions that are supported and replicated. The accumulation of supportive hypothesis tests, especially when these tests are strict or concern parameters or intervals (see Meehl, 1990), therefore represents “money in the bank” (i.e., empirical success) in which the coin of the realm consists of “damn strange coincidences” (i.e., empirical novelty). Finally, theories tend to be viewed as better to the extent that they reflect the core metaphorical images of self that culture upholds, and to the extent the theory fits the contemporary aesthetic preferences of that culture. “A good theory is a plausible theory, and a theory is judged to be more plausible and of higher quality if it is interesting rather than obvious, irrelevant or absurd, obvious in novel ways, a source of unexpected connections, high in narrative rationality, aesthetically pleasing, or correspondent with presumed realities” (Weick, 1989, p. 517). Comm 610: Advanced Communication Theory: 140 A Word About Paradigms Popper (1959, 1980) attempted to draw a bright line of demarcation between science and pseudo-science by the criterion of risky predictions that are falsifiable through inferential processes. Deductive methods could not provide such a line, as they are predicated on initial claims, which themselves must be verified, and no amount of observing instances in support of a universal claim can guarantee the validity of that claim. In contrast, a single falsifying instance can lead to the rejection of a claim. Conceptual systems such as astrology, religion, and Freudian theory are considered pseudo-scientific because they make no claims that when confronted by contradictory evidence leads to the forfeiture of belief in the conceptual system itself. Any conceptual system that is impervious to empirical contradiction, or that makes no claims that can be empirically contradicted in the event they are false claims, is not science. The criterion of scientific status is the positing of predictions that are at risk if they are, in fact, empirically untrue. This line of demarcation provided a potential distinction between two approaches to both conceptual theorizing (i.e., the ways in which questions and propositions are formulated) as well as methodology (e.g., experimentation and falsificationist observations). However, the methods by which falsification is sought are subject to multiple attributions of failure, only one of which is the theory at test, resulting in a disconfirmation dilemma (Greenwald et al., 1986). One implication is that alternative approaches need to be identified by which the progress of knowledge accumulation can be ascertained. That is, does science change over time in ways that represent progress toward more valid knowledge, or at least through the rejection of less valid knowledge? Attempts to redress this problem by identifying alternative criteria of progress have been proposed by others (e.g., Lakatos, 1970; Laudan et al., 1986). A potentially radical reformulation of the problem of how science changes over time was proffered by Kuhn (1970), who popularized the concept of paradigms. Although highly problematic in definition (Masterman, 1970), Kuhn broadly considers a paradigm a collective set of practices among a group of scholars. This set of collective practices indicate that these professionals tend to have similar grounding assumptions and beliefs, similar language, similar methodological artifacts and metaphors, and similar procedures for pursuing their knowledge claims. In their more sociological sense, such paradigms might be considered traditions (Alexander & Colomy, 1992; Craig, 1999), domains (Anderson & Baym, 2004), styles (Smith, 1988), or forms of metatheorizing (Ritzer, Zhao, & Murphy, 2001). At least two potentially radical implications arose from Kuhn’s (1970) conceptualization. First, paradigms change through revolution rather than routine scientific activity. It was posited that paradigms proceed by facilitating normal science, a form of puzzle-solving in which investigation is relatively routine, with disagreements negotiated by similar standards of quality. Change occurred incrementally, with accumulation of new knowledge understood within the conceptual boundaries of the existing paradigm. Such paradigms would, in the process of such puzzle-solving, discover certain anomalies that resisted resolution from the presumptions and practices of the current paradigm. At some point, a new paradigm is proposed that radically reorganizes the presumptions and relations among conceptual components of the previous paradigm, like a light switch illuminating a previously shadowy Comm 610: Advanced Communication Theory: 141 environment. Thus, change is not “progressive” so much as “reformulating” by demonstrating the virtual irrelevance of the former map, and substituting an entirely new (type of) theoretical map of the territory. Thus, the concept of progress is problematized by suggesting that much of the science produced in the former paradigm is made irrelevant to the presumed progress in the new paradigm. It was asking many of the wrong questions. Second, any field of endeavor may have multiple paradigms, but these paradigms are incommensurable (Kuhn, 2000). Like religions, cultural matrices of everyday life or speech communities a paradigm is philosophically and pragmatically self-encapsulated, such that a practitioner of a given paradigm finds nothing of additive or complementary value in any other extant paradigm. Such incommensurability suggests that much of science consists of belief systems or mental templates that may or may not be tethered directly to the empirical world. Thus, Kuhn has been criticized as a relativist by many critics, illustrated by the visualization of scientists approaching questions from non-competitive paradigms of perspective that have no obvious communication mechanism for resolving competing claims about the empirical world. The core aspect of relativism implicit in the conceptualization of incommensurable paradigms is that truth claims are unyoked from correspondence rules of veracity (Kuhn, 2000). Instead, although “the rules of the true/false game are … universals for all human communities…, the result of applying those rules varies from one speech community to another” (Kuhn, 2000, p. 100). If rules of correspondence do not characterize the practice of science, it questions the prospect of a progressive science. Here, however, Kuhn recants: “the world is not invented or constructed….Creatures born into it must take it as they find it” (p. 101). Since the title “the real world” cannot be “denied” (p. 102), it raises the question of how science does progress toward an increasingly accurate picture of the real world. Kuhn is not very specific on the mechanisms of this progress, but he accepts the truth of the scientific march toward truth. He postulates that “scientific development is, like biological, a unidirectional and irreversible process. Later scientific theories are better than earlier ones for solving puzzles in the often quite different environments to which they are applied. That is not a relativist’s position, and it displays the sense in which I am a convinced believer in scientific progress” (Kuhn, 1970, p. 169). Many have struggled with the problem of paradigm change (e.g., Levine, 1986; Rossiter, 1977; Schwandt, 1989). It seems reasonable to conjecture that normal puzzle-solving accumulates progressive knowledge that sets important foundations from which new paradigms can progress in more dramatic ways, and that both moderate and more radical forms of change owe some of their progressive nature to the cultures of scientific practice. This returns the presumption of progress to the prospect of a softer but nevertheless visible demarcation between science and alternative paradigms of practice. Science is not infallible, but it may instead be systematically less infallible than alternative approaches to knowledge. In essence, it may be that the game of science works in part because the practice of systematically acting as if we are approaching the truth creates a set of competitive and comparative cultural practices that progressively erode the less viable and valid perspectives in favor of those that, over time, better approximate the empirical world. Cultural rituals, practices, religions, and other collective practices may accumulate perspectives that are progressive, but they do so in an ongoing effort toward promotion of accepted practices. Science may have refined an approach that explicitly and simultaneously demands both attempts at promotion and Comm 610: Advanced Communication Theory: 142 contradiction of operating premises and practices, always with the crucible of decision referred at some level to the empirical world. A Note About “Science” The belief that there is a monolithic “scientific method” or scientific paradigm has been considered unrealistic by most practicing scientists for some time. Science is almost as variegated as its practitioners and their respective investigative pursuits. There are some common tendencies or orientations, however, that characterize most working scientists. First, science is critically reflective. This may sound uncharacteristic, compared to its paradigmatic cousins such as ethnography and critical studies. Science is critically reflective in the following senses: (1) Science is fundamentally oriented toward disproving its own presuppositions; (2) Science is reflectively aware of, and must take pains to control for, rival hypotheses to its accounts, including the potential biasing effects of observer viewpoint and activities; (3) Science is skeptical of claims without the potential for replication or generalizability in, of, and through experience. Second, science is cumulatively progressive. Unlike religion, which is fundamentally conservative in holding to tradition, belief and faith, science is radical in its ongoing pursuit of newer, better, understandings. Religious institutions may occasionally mimic science (as in declaring sections of a text as apocryphal), but such mimicry is predicated less on external evidence, and instead based on concerns of consistency with prior presumptive beliefs or ideologies. Science never forgets the past (so as neither to repeat its mistakes nor forget to benefit from its previous discoveries), but it is fundamentally forward-looking toward what is yet unknown. It cannot rest on its foundations nor accept any article of faith without test or observation. Instead, it must continuously build upon, evolve, expand, and innovate new ways and contents of understanding. No text is without potential error, and no text or article of faith is beyond doubt. Thus, the past is mere prelude to the present, and the present is always geared to a future that renders the present partially inadequate. It is in this sense that traditional religion seeks to reify its past as the strictures of the present; to accept that what once was known must be cherished as inviolate in the present. Science, in contrast, views the past as something to grow beyond. Third, science is a dialectic between thought and method, and among induction, deduction, and abduction. The thought-method dialectic means that no theory can stand alone—it must be subject to methodological test, observation, and evidence. Yet, no method can stand alone, as all products of methods have theoretical implications that must organize the products of such methodological application. Data without theory are little more than noise, and theory without data is little more than a story. The induction-deduction-abduction dialectic means that science relies on all three modes of thought as a tripod of knowledge accumulation. Deduction reasons from interconnected general principles to further principles (as in the syllogism: 1. If X, then Y; 2. if Y, then Z; 3. , if X, then Z). Through deduction, theoretical axioms and hypotheses can be chained out (Wallach & Wallach, 1994). Induction reasons from examples to generalization, and is the foundation for the hypothetico-deductive model in which hypotheses can be tested according to observations compared to probabilistic random distributions (i.e., the p < .05 significance level). Abduction is a mode of thought that combines induction and deduction in moving from hypotheses to tests and back to hypotheses, engaging the interactions between explanations and data. Comm 610: Advanced Communication Theory: 143 Modeling Modeling is one of the zeniths of scientific reasoning. It incorporates analytic reasoning (i.e., breaking wholes into parts), synthetic reasoning (i.e., [re]assembling parts into wholes), and abstract reasoning (i.e., recognizing similar things across levels of abstraction and concreteness). It also is fundamental to theoretical reasoning (i.e., explaining how and why phenomena happen the way they do), and methodology (i.e., specifying hypotheses to be tested qualitatively or quantitatively, the results of which inform the validity of the underlying theory). Models serve various functions in science as in everyday life. A model is a visual simplification of concepts that exist in both a hypothesized conceptual form and an actual or potential observed form. For example, if you believe that as social skills decrease a person’s ability to meet others and develop satisfying relationships decreases, and that this in turn increases the person’s loneliness, and that increases in loneliness lead to increased interaction anxiety, then three conceptual components each potentially can be measured by a questionnaire or survey. Thus, you would have a very basic model that looks something like the following: Social Skills Loneliness Social Anxiety Notice that this model could have been formulated entirely differently. Some have argued that people develop anxiety through early learning experiences, which leads to a deficit of social skills, which thereby make the development of social relationships more difficult, leading to loneliness. These represent alternative models of reality, and either one can be reasonably argued and justified. Which one is “true” is irrelevant for the sake of formulating the model—the question is whether a good set of arguments can be developed in support of the model ultimately produced. Once you have a basic model, it is then relatively simple to start asking additional questions, such as how biology (e.g., sex, age, etc.), culture (e.g., ethnicity, regional identification, etc.), context (e.g., socio-economic status, intact family status, etc.), personal background (e.g., attachment disorder, relational history, etc.) or dispositions (e.g., self-esteem, attribution style, etc.) influence various components or relationships of the model. Most models follow simple rules: (1) Components on the left precede, at some point, the components to the right in real time. (2) Every conceptual component should have a measurement component. (3) Every arrow represents a direct effect of one concept on another. This effect does not have to be a causal relationship, but it usually implies such an influence. (4) Every component must have an arrow headed to at least one other component, and may have arrows to multiple other components. (5) The spatially closer two components are to one another, the more closely they are associated with one another than to components further away from one another. (6) Components can be grouped according to larger components (i.e., multiple indicators of a single concept; e.g., social skills above might be further indicated by coordination, expressiveness, attentiveness, and composure skills). (7) Comm 610: Advanced Communication Theory: 144 Every arrow is a potentially testable hypothesis (or proposition). The nature of these hypotheses is discussed next. Hypothesizing A hypothesis is a verbal or symbolic statement of relationship between two or more variables (e.g., Self-esteem is positively related to self-disclosure). A variable is any construct or concept that can be observed to take on different values (e.g., anxiety, self-disclosure, assertiveness, etc.). It takes the form of X = fY. A definition (e.g., self-esteem is the degree to which self is perceived positively) characterizes the nature of a variable, but not its relationship to other variables. It takes the form of X = Y. All of this is just a fancy way of saying that the hypothesis paper attempts to develop, through review and personal argument, a series of hypotheses on a given topic. Many of these hypotheses may be articulated in the existing research literature, they may be derived from conceptual models, or the products of creativity and imagination. There are two keys to this assignment: (1) Developing well-conceived and well-worded hypotheses, and (2) developing reasonable arguments for each hypothesis. Like any argument, it is made credible through the use of causal analysis, evidence, example, strong reasons, and scholarly support. The most important thing is that every hypothesis should be carefully worded (read all these instructions to understand this warning) and arguments should answer two “why” questions: (1) Why are the variables related this way? (2) Why is the hypothesis likely to be true? The word “because” should figure prominently in the explanations. To explain a hypothesis means to make sensible how and why things are related the way they are. Theories are basically sets of conceptual links among hypotheses. For example, a person may want to explain the hypothesis: “As jealousy increases, the likelihood of relational violence increases.” Guided by an understanding of argument (e.g., see recommendations for writing that follow later in these instructions), this hypothesis could be argued thusly: Jealousy is a complex blend of emotions based on the perception that a person’s valued relationship is threatened by a third party or rival. [backing] Retzinger (1991) has reviewed evidence [grounds] that violence is likely to result from a combination of anger and shame, but neither alone [backing]. Because [warrant] anger creates an inner sense of expressive frustration and arousal, and shame provides a target for this expression (i.e., the partner and/or the rival), the jealous person is much more likely to engage in violence than non-jealous persons. [claim] This hypothesis may not apply to contexts in which strong moral, religious, or public restraints are in place (e.g., even jealous persons tend not to be overtly violent in public places). [rebuttal] The rebuttal is not necessary, but sometimes illustrates relative objectivity and openness of the author. In this explanation, other concepts (i.e., the theory of rage as proposed by Retzinger, with its components of anger and rage) are used to make the link between jealousy and violence sensible. More explanation could be provided for these concepts, more evidence reviewed in favor of Retzinger’s hypothesis, and so forth, but the basic elements of explanation and argument are there. The point is that explanation is neither mere restatement nor mere review of research or expert opinion. And please note, there is no quotation, and no need for quotation. Quotations should be used extremely sparingly—I want to see your writing, not someone else’s. Comm 610: Advanced Communication Theory: 145 Types of Hypotheses Below is a series of hypotheses to illustrate how they can differ. These hypotheses may seem overly sophisticated or technical right now. However, research of a topic has begun, hypothetical relations will begin to emerge either stated directly (i.e., in the form of hypotheses being tested) or indirectly (i.e., implied by the explanation and discussion of the concepts). The simplest, and weakest, form of hypothesis is a "non-directional" statement of relationship. For example: H1: Self-esteem is related to communication competence. While this is a hypothesis, it provides minimal information regarding the precise nature of the relationship. Avoid such statements in the paper. A more precise form is: H2: Self-esteem is positively related to interpersonal communication competence. (Note: This can be reworded as: “Persons high in self-esteem are significantly higher in communication competence than persons low in self-esteem”). Hypotheses can also vary by the form (or shape) of the relationship: H3: Motivation, knowledge and skills are curvilinear to perceived communication competence. (That is, they are positively related up to a moderately high range of competence, after which higher values lead to lower perceived competence). Finally, deductive construction allows the development of stronger, and more tightly controlled, theoretical arguments. For example, H4: As [TV exposure] increases, [verbal skills] decrease. [A] [B] H5: As [verbal skills] decrease, use of [physical violence] in conflict increases. [B] [C] H6: As [TV exposure] increases, use of [physical violence] in conflict increases. [A] [C] On the Art of Explanation “We cannot infer the events of the future from those of the present. Belief in the causal nexus is superstition” (Wittgenstein, Tractatus, 5.1361) Explanation implies the identification of some “bridge” (i.e., warrant, “because...,” etc.) that serves as an account of why one concept is related to another concept. It is an “animating mechanism,” that gives life to a concept. For example, one popular concept is that exposure to Comm 610: Advanced Communication Theory: 146 violence in the media causes violence in society. The natural question is why. Answering the “why” question gets at the concept of explanation. Even though seeing or hearing the equation: “media violence causes societal violence” seems like an explanation, it is not. It is missing the bridge, or animating mechanism. To illustrate, consider a few “non-explanations.” It is not an explanation to say media violence causes societal violence because: (1) media depictions of violence are increasing; (2) societal violence is increasing; (3) some people have engaged in crimes they saw on TV (“copycat crimes”); (4) people believe what they see on TV; (5) research shows media violence increases societal violence. Each of these merely suggests correlation (rather than causation), repeats the original assertion, or simply provides backing for an explanation that is itself missing. In contrast, to illustrate legitimate explanations, consider the following: Cultivation: Social learning theory claims that people learn both by direct experience (e.g., touching a hot stove) or observation of others (e.g., observing one’s sister touch a hot stove). Since we cannot or do not always directly experience things (e.g., robbing a bank), we look to real and imaginative role models (e.g., media figures and narratives). Thus, the crime and violence in the media provide models, and rewarding ones at that, for us we otherwise would not have had. Cognitive Availability: Our brain can be viewed as a library. If 90% of this library is filled with science fiction, and we are asked to respond to someone’s question for information, we are most likely to give them a fanciful piece of information, because that is what is most represented in our mind’s library. If, in watching media, most of the acts or ways of dealing with conflict we observe are violent in nature, it simply supplies more acts of violence to store in our mental repertoires, and thus, when we find ourselves in a conflict, violent acts are the most “available” to draw upon. Disinhibition: Growing up in a culture is largely about learning what one cannot or is not supposed to do. The very nature of culture is conformity and normative action within a given body of beliefs and behaviors. Exposure to violence in the media may make violence appear more normative than it is, and thus, make engaging in violence seem less deviant. In essence, it is not making violence seem more rewarding (cultivation) or available, but merely makes the violence within a person more acceptable. Fantasy Fulfillment: Freud and others might argue that daily life, as well as the normal tortures of growing up, fill us with tensions that are constantly repressed. These tensions struggle to “get out,” managing to manifest themselves mainly in the form of fantasy. Media violence may give form to these fantasies, making them more vivid and “real,” thereby stimulating the enactment of fantasies in life (e.g., who has not “fantasized” about hitting someone in the face—seeing it done may both “suggest” it, but stimulate the enactment of it). Desensitization: One of the reasons people avoid violence is that it hurts others. However, when violence is everywhere in the media, it can numb one’s sensibilities, and lower one’s ability to empathize. Further, the more cartoonish the violence, the more it seems it does not really hurt anyone. Such exposure to violence may take the “brakes” off using by making violence seem less hurtful, and thus, less costly to use. Excitation: Violence is a thrill. Through 5 million years of evolution, we have come to find violence a potential threat, a potential path to victory, and therefore, arousing. Thus, seeing violence in the media is itself, arousing, and this arousal stimulates our own arousal. Our Comm 610: Advanced Communication Theory: 147 arousal (adrenaline, muscular tension, etc.) needs to find an outlet, and is expressed in violence. Peer Group Mediation: Research on sexual violence indicates that people who engage in sexual violence are much more likely to have friends who approve of, and have engaged in, sexual violence. The suggestion is that peer groups mediate the transfer of violence. That is, if a peer group watches violence in the media, this peer group may then become self-reinforcing through its interaction, thereby serving as the proximal stimulus to its members’ violence. Spillover: Violence in the media provides models of behavior in certain contexts that are then available for generalization to contexts experienced in everyday life, both directly comparable to those observed in the media, as well as contexts largely unrelated. Thus, for example, a person may “copycat” behaviors witnessed in the media, but may also extend the function of the behaviors observed in one context (e.g., a drop kick in a professional wrestling program) to another context (e.g., a dispute with one’s brother). Cultural Chaos: Violence in the media may reflect the very breakdown of society, norms, and culture. If everyone is violent to everyone in the media, then this communicates a sense of despair, hopelessness, alienation and angst to the viewing public. This has the effects of both (1) inciting some to exploit the lawlessness (e.g., looting during natural disasters), (2) join the crowd (e.g., mob violence during the L.A. riots), (3) bystander apathy providing a permissive environment for violence. Each of these explanations offers slightly and sometimes substantively distinct sources of causation. For example, fantasy fulfillment, excitation and disinhibition tend to assume that we are by nature violent, and all that is needed is something in the media to take the restraints of society away. Cultivation and availability argue media instills violence in us. Peer-group mediation and cultural chaos tend to view media as having an effect on society at large, which only then affects our individual behavior. In all these examples concepts are elaborated to make sensible the link between violence in the media and in society. Co-occurrence makes no sense without an explanation, and it matters which explanation is offered. A “theory” cannot be evaluated until its explanatory rationale has been specified, and the brief examples above illustrate how significant, and distinct, such explanations can be. Conclusion Understanding and explaining ultimately rely upon some underlying concept of causation, whether viewed in narrative, idiographic, historical, or analytical ways. Causation, in turn, is represented by propositions, whether formal (e.g., X is positively related to Y) or informal (e.g., X happened because Y and Z happened in context C). Theories are the conceptual tools that permit such explanations to be formalized, and eventually tested in the crucible of social science and academic discipline. If a theory is poorly conceptualized and constructed, it cannot be tested adequately. Such a theory thereby provides signposts to paths down which scholarly inquiry should not continue. Until the field becomes more schooled in and adept at theory construction, however, such errant crusades are likely to continue. Comm 610: Advanced Communication Theory: 148 References Alexander, J. C., & Colomy, P. (1992). Traditions and competition: Preface to a postpositivist approach to knowledge cumulation. In G. Ritzer (Ed.), Metatheorizing (pp. 27-52). Newbury Park, CA: Sage. Anderson, J. A. (1996). Communication theory: Epistemological foundations. New York: Guilford. Anderson, J. A., & Baym, G. (2004). Philosophies and philosophic issues in communication, 1995-2004. Journal of Communication, 54, 589-615. Avgelis, N. (1989). Lakatos on the evaluation of scientific theories. In K. Gavroglu, Y. Goudaroulis, & P. Nicolacopoulos (Eds.), Imre Lakatos and theories of scientific change (Vol. III, Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, pp. 157-167). Boston: Kluwer Academic. Berger, C. R. (1991). Communication theories and other curios. Communication Monographs, 58, 101-113. Bhaskar, R. (1978). A realist theory of science. Atlantic Highlands, NJ: Humanities Press. Blalock, H. M. (1979). Dilemmas and strategies of theory construction. In W. E. Snizek, E. R. Fuhrman, & M. K. Miller (Eds.), Contemporary issues in theory and research: A metasociological perspective (pp. 119-135). Westport, CT: Greenwood. Burleson, B. R. (1992). Taking communication seriously. Communication Monographs, 59, 7986. Carnap, R. (1953). Testability and meaning. In H. Feigl & M. Brodbeck (Eds.), Readings in the philosophy of science (pp. 47-92). New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts. Chafetz, J. S. (1978). A primer on the construction and testing of theories in sociology. Itasca, IL: F. E. Peacock. Chow, S. L. (1990). In defense of Popperian falsification. Psychological Inquiry, 1, 147-149. Chow, S. L. (1992). Acceptance of a theory: Justification or rhetoric? Journal for the Theory of Social Behavior, 22, 447-474. Churchland, P. M. (1992). A deeper unity: Some Feyerabendian themes in neurocomputational form. In S. Davis (Ed.), Connectionism theory and practice (pp. 30-50). New York: Oxford Press. Clark, J. M., & Paivio, A. (1989). Observational and theoretical terms in psychology: A cognitive perspective on scientific language. American Psychologist, 44, 500-512. Colomy, P. (1991). Metatheorizing in a postpositivist frame. Sociological Perspectives, 34, 269286. Corrigan, R., & Denton, P. (1996). Causal understanding as a developmental primitive. Developmental Review, 16, 162-202. Craig, R. T. (1993). Why are there so many communication theories? Journal of Communication, 43, 26-33. Craig, R. T. (1999). Communication theory as a field. Communication Theory, 9, 119-161. D’Andrade, R. (1986). Three scientific world views and the covering law model. In D. W. Fiske & R. A. Shweder (Eds.), Metatheory in social science: Pluralisms and subjectivities (pp. 1941). Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Comm 610: Advanced Communication Theory: 149 Diesing, P. (1991). How does social science work?: Reflections on practice. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh. Eysenck, H. J. (1987). “There is nothing more practical than a good theory” (Kurt Lewin) – True or false? In W. J. Baker, M. E. Hyland, H. Van Rappard, A. W. Staats (Eds.), Current issues in theoretical psychology (pp. 49-64). North-Holland: Elsevier Science Publishers. Feyerabend, P. K. (1970). Against method: Outline of an anarchistic theory of knowledge. In M. Radner & S. Winokur (Eds.), Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science (Vol. 4, Analyses of theories and methods of physics and psychology, pp. 17-130). Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota. Feyerabend, P. (1975). Against method: Outline of an anarchistic theory of knowledge. London: NLB. Freese, L. (1980). Formal theorizing. In A. Inkeles, N. J. Smelser, & R. H. Turner (Eds.), Annual review of sociology (Vol. 6, pp. 187-212). Palo Alto, CA: Annual Reviews Inc. Fuhrman, E., & Snizek, W. (1990). Neither proscience nor antiscience: metasociology as dialogue. Sociological Forum, 5, 17-36. Gergen, K. J. (1973). Social psychology as history. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 26, 309-320. Gergen, K. J. (1979). The positivist image in social psychological theory. In A. R. Buss (Ed.), Psychology in social context (pp. 193-212). New York: Irvington. Gergen, K. J. (1986). Correspondence versus autonomy in the language of understanding human action. In D. W. Fiske & R. A. Shweder (Eds.), Metatheory in social science: Pluralisms and subjectivities (pp. 136-162). Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Gergen, K. J. (1991). Emerging challenges for theory and psychology. Theory & Psychology, 1, 13-35. Gergen, K. J. (1994). Toward transformation in social knowledge (2nd ed.). London: Sage. Gilman, D. (1992). What’s a theory to do . . . with seeing? Or some empirical considerations for observation and theory. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 43, 287-309. Greenberg, J., Solomon, S., Pyszczynski, T., & Steinberg, L. (1988). A reaction to Greenwald, Pratkanis, Leippe, & Baumgardner (1986): Under what conditions does research obstruct theory progress? Psychological Review, 95, 566-571. Greene, J. O. (1994). What sort of terms ought theories of human action incorporate? Communication Studies, 45, 187-211. Greenwald, A. G., Pratkanis, A. R., Leippe, M. R., & Baumgardner, M. H. (1986). Under what conditions does theory obstruct research progress? Psychological Review, 93, 216-229. Greenwald, A. G., & Pratkanis, A. R. (1988). On the use of “theory” and the usefulness of theory. Psychological Review, 95, 575-579. Harré, R. (1981). The positivist-empiricist approach and its alternative. In P. Reason & J. Rowan (Eds.), Human inquiry: A sourcebook of new paradigm research (pp. 3-17). London: John Wiley & Sons. Hedges, L. V. (1987). How hard is hard science, how soft is soft science? The empirical cumulativeness of research. American Psychologist, 42, 443-455. Hempel, C. G. (1965). Aspects of scientific explanation. New York: Free Press. Hempel, C. G., & Oppenheim, P. (1948). Studies in the logic of explanation. Philosophy of Science, 15, 135-175. Comm 610: Advanced Communication Theory: 150 Horkheimer, M. (1972). Critical theory: Selected essays. New York: Herder and Herder. Hunter, J. E. (1997). Needed: A ban on significance testing. Psychological Science, 8, 3-7. Kuhn, T. S. (1970). The structure of scientific revolutions (2nd ed.), New York: New American Library (with University of Chicago Press). Lakatos, I. (1970). Falsification and the methodology of scientific research programmes. In I. Lakatos & A. Musgrave (Eds.), Criticism and the growth of knowledge (Proceedings of the International Colloquium in the Philosophy of Science, Vol. 4, pp. 91-195). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Laudan, L. (1981). A problem-solving approach to scientific progress. In I. Hacking (Ed.), Scientific revolutions (pp. 144-155). Oxford: Oxford University. Laudan, L., Donovan, A., Laudan, R., Barker, P., Brown, H., Leplin, J., Thagard, P., & Wykstra, S. (1986). Scientific change: Philosophical models and historical research. Synthese, 69, 141223. Levine, D. N. (1986). In D. W. Fiske & R. A. Shweder (Eds.), Metatheory in social science (pp. 271-284). Chicago: University of Chicago. Lyotard, J-F. (1991). The postmodern condition: A report on knowledge. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota. MacKay, D. G. (1988). Under what conditions can theoretical psychology survive and prosper? Integrating the rational and empirical epistemologies. Psychological Review, 95, 559-565. Marros, A. J. (1969). The practical theorist: The life and work of Kurt Lewin. New York: Basic Books. Marshall, J. C. (1977). Minds, machines and metaphors. Social Studies of Science, 7, 475-488. Masterman, M. (1970). The nature of a paradigm. In I. Lakatos & A. Musgrave (Eds.), Criticism and the growth of knowledge (pp. 59-90). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Mayo, D. G. (1996). Ducks, rabbits, and normal science: Recasting the Kuhn’s-eye view of Popper’s demarcation of science. British Journal of the Philosophy of Science, 47, 271-290. McClintock, C. G. (1985). The metatheoretical bases of social psychological theory. Behavioral Science, 30, 155-173. McGuire, W. J. (1973). The yin and yang of progress in social psychology. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 26, 446-456. Meehl, P. E. (1978). Theoretical risks and tabular asterisks: Sir Karl, Sir Ronald, and the slow progress of soft psychology. Journal of Consulting and Clinical Psychology, 46, 806-834. Meehl, P. E. (1990). Appraising and amending theories: The strategy of Lakatosian defense and two principles that warrant it. Psychological Inquiry, 1, 108-141. Metaxopoulos, E. (1989). A critical consideration of the Lakatosian concepts: “Mature” and “immature” science. In K. Gavroglu, Y. Goudaroulis, & P. Nicolacopoulos (Eds.), Imre Lakatos and theories of scientific change (Vol. III, Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, pp. 203-214). Boston: Kluwer Academic. Moser, K., Gadenne, V., & Schröder, J. (1988). Under what conditions does confirmation seeking obstruct scientific progress? Psychological Review, 95, 572-574. Papineau, D. (1989). Has Popper been a good thing? In K. Gavroglu, Y. Goudaroulis, & P. Nicolacopoulos (Eds.), Imre Lakatos and theories of scientific change (Vol. III, Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, pp. 431-440). Boston: Kluwer Academic. Comm 610: Advanced Communication Theory: 151 Pavitt, C. (2000). Answering questions requesting scientific explanations for communication. Communication Theory, 10, 379-404. Penman, R. (1992). Good theory and good practice: An argument in progress. Communication Theory, 2, 234-250. Pepper, S. C. (1957). World hypotheses: A study in evidence. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press. Phillips, D. L. (1977). Wittgenstein and scientific knowledge: A sociological perspective. London: Macmillan. Pollock, D., & Cox, J. R. (1991). Historicizing “reason”: Critical theory, practice, and postmodernity. Communication Monographs, 58, 170-178. Popper, K. (1959). The logic of scientific discovery. New York: Basic Books. Popper, K. (1980). Science: Conjectures and refutations. In E. D. Klemke, R. Hollinger, & A. D. Kline (Eds.), Introductory readings in the philosophy of science (pp. 19-34). Buffalo, NY: Prometheus. Purcell, W. M. (1992). Are there so few communication theories? Communication Monographs, 59, 94-107. Reddy, M. J. (1979). The conduit metaphor—A case of frame conflict in our language about language. In A. Ortony (Ed.), Metaphor and thought (pp. 284-324). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Rosenau, P. M. (1992). Post-modernism and the social sciences: Insights, inroads, and intrusions. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Rossiter, C. M. (1977). Models of paradigmatic change. Communication Quarterly, 25, 69-73. Sandelands, L. E. (1990). What is so practical about theory? Lewin revisited. Journal for the Theory of Social Behavior, 20, 235-262. Schegloff, E. A. (1992). Repair after next turn: The last structurally provided defense of intersubjectivity in conversation. American Journal of Sociology, 97, 1295-1345. Schlenker, B. R. (1974). Social psychology and science. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 29, 1-15. Schwandt, T. A. (1989). Solutions to the paradigm conflict: Coping with uncertainty. Journal of Contemporary Ethnography, 17, 379-407. Shotter, J. (1987). The rhetoric of theory in psychology. In W. J. Baker, M. E. Hyland, H. Van Rappard, A. W. Staats (Eds.), Current issues in theoretical psychology (pp. 283-296). NorthHolland: Elsevier Science Publishers. Shotter, J. (1990). The myth of mind and the mistake of psychology. In W. J. Baker, M. E. Hyland, R. van Hezewijk, & S. Terwee (Eds.), Recent trends in theoretical psychology (Vol. 2, pp. 63-71). New York: Springer-Verlag. Simons, H. W. (1990). The rhetoric of inquiry as an intellectual movement. In H. W. Simons (Ed.), The rhetorical turn: Invention and persuasion in the conduct of inquiry (pp. 1-31). Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Smith, T. J., III (1988). Diversity and order in communication theory: The uses of philosophical analysis. Communication Quarterly, 36, 28-40. Smythe, W. E. (1990). Mental representation and meaning: Arguments against the computational view. In W. J. Baker, M. E. Hyland, R. van Hezewijk, & S. Terwee (Eds.), Recent trends in theoretical psychology (Vol. 2, pp. 261-266). New York: Springer-Verlag. Comm 610: Advanced Communication Theory: 152 Stamp, G. H., Vangelisti, A. L., & Knapp, M. L. (1994). Criteria for developing and assessing theories of interpersonal communication. In F. L. Casmir (Ed.), Building communication theories: A socio/cultural approach (pp. 167-208). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. Suppe, F. (1974). The structure of scientific theories. Urbana, IL: University of Illinois Press. Suppe, F. (1989). The semantic conception of theories and scientific realism. Urbana, IL: University of Illinois Press. Thorngate, W. (1976). “In general” vs. “it depends”: Some comments of the Gergen-Schlenker debate. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 2, 404-410. Toulmin, S. (1990). Cosmopolis: The hidden agenda of modernity. New York: Free Press. Turner, J. H. (1985). In defense of positivism. Sociological Theory, 3, 24-30. Turner, J. H. (1990). The misuse and use of metatheory. Sociological Forum, 5, 37-53. Turner, J. H. (1991). Developing cumulative and practical knowledge through metatheorizing. Sociological Perspectives, 34, 249-268. Vroon, P. A. (1987). Man-machine analogs and theoretical mainstreams in psychology. In W. J. Baker, M. E. Hyland, H. Van Rappard, & A. W. Staats (Eds.), Current issues in theoretical psychology (pp. 393-414). North-Holland: Elsevier Science Publishers. Wallach, L., & Wallach, M. A. (1994). Gergen versus the mainstream: Are hypotheses in social psychology subject to empirical test? Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 67, 233-242. Weick, K. E. (1989). Theory construction as disciplined imagination. Academy of Management Review, 14, 516-531. Witkin, S. L., & Gottschalk, S. (1988). Alternative criteria for theory evaluation. Social Service Review, 62, 211-224. Wittgenstein, L. (1958). The blue and brown books. New York: Harper & Row. Comm 610: Advanced Communication Theory: 153 Table 1. CRITERIA FOR EVALUATING THEORIES I. NECESSARY CONDITIONS: 1. Explanatory Power: The theory must provide a sensible account of the phenomena of concern 2. Construct and Conditionship Specification: The theory must indicate the nature of the constructs and the relationships among these constructs (i.e., necessity, sufficiency, parameters, function form, generality, etc.) 3. Boundary Specification: The theory must indicate the domain of its legitimate scope and relevance 4. Intra-Boundary Generality: The theory must provide statements of relationship that hold across all phenomena of concern 5. Internal Consistency: The theory must maintain logical consistency of all statements of conditionship, assumptions, and units 6. External consistency: The theory must avoid contradiction of "known" data 7. Verifiability: The theory must be potentially verifiable, such that it is: A) Operational: A sufficient number of the theoretical units must be capable of being measured/observed B) Falsifiable: It must be possible to establish conditions under which statements of the theory can be observed to be true/untrue II. DESIRABLE CONDITIONS: 1. Precision: The more the theory allows prediction of phenomena, the better the theory: A) End State Prediction: Prediction of some identifiable "outcome" of the phenomena behavior B) Phase State Prediction: Prediction of various stages or evolving states of behavior toward an end state 2. Parsimony: The more elegant and simple the theory, the better the theory 3. Correspondence with Observables: The more of the theory units that are observable, the better the theory 4. Breadth: The broader the scope or range of the theory, the better the theory; i.e., verisimilitude 5. Control: The greater the potential for strategic manipulation of the phenomena, the better the theory 6. Heurism/Novelty: The more novel content, and the more the theory suggests in the way of new scientific endeavors, the better the theory. The more the theory explains new facts or counterintuitive facts, the better the theory. 7. Synthesis: The more the theory facilitates the organization and inclusion of ideas and information, the better the theory Comm 610: Advanced Communication Theory: 154 III. RELATIVE CONDITIONS: 7. Competition Principle: Theories should compete favorably vis-à-vis their rivals (Colomy, 1991); “theory evaluation is primarily a comparative affair” (Laudan, 1981, p. 145); “There is no falsification before the emergence of a better theory” (Lakatos, 1970, p. 119). 8. Money in the Bank Principle: “We are warranted in continuing to conjecture that a theory has high verisimilitude when it has accumulated ‘money in the bank’ by passing several stiff tests” (Meehl, 1990, p. 115) 9. Damn Strange Coincidences Principle: “The main way a theory gets money in the bank is by predicting facts that, absent the theory, would be antecedently improbable” (Meehl, 1990, p. 115). 10. Aesthetics: “A good theory is a plausible theory, and a theory is judged to be more plausible and of higher quality if it is interesting rather than obvious, irrelevant or absurd, obvious in novel ways, a source of unexpected connections, high in narrative rationality, aesthetically pleasing, or correspondent with presumed realities” (Weick, 1989, p. 517). IV. CRITICAL CONDITIONS: 11. Generative capacity: “the capacity to challenge the guiding assumptions of the culture, to raise fundamental questions regarding contemporary social life, to foster reconsideration of that which is ‘taken for granted,’ and thereby to generate fresh alternatives for social action” (Gergen, 1994, Toward transformation…, p. 109) 12. Counter-suggestiveness: “What we need here is an education that makes people contrary, counter-suggestive, without making them incapable of devoting themselves to the elaboration of any single view” (Feyerabend, 1980, p. 63) IV. DEFINITION: "A theory is a verifiable conceptual system of interrelated formal or informal propositions explaining conditionship among a set of phenomena, which is generalizable within a defined domain, and is internally consistent and externally sensible." (Spitzberg, 1998) Comm 610: Advanced Communication Theory: 155 Islands of Inquiry Foreword: Spitzberg, B. H. (in press). Islands of inquiry. Foreword for: G. Merrigan & C. L. Huston. Communication research methods (3rd ed.). New York: Oxford University Press. By Brian H. Spitzberg School of Communication San Diego State University Imagine an island archipelago in the vast, uncharted sea of science. Long ago intrepid explorers from a nation state far, far away settled the islands of this archipelago. Once the various islands were settled, the peoples found themselves separated by shark-infested waters, treacherous reefs and inaccessible ports. Consequently, little commerce today occurs between natives of these separate islands. Over time, the peoples developed alternative customs, rituals, religions, values, dialects, and modes of exchange. Because each island produces slightly different desirable natural resources, the various peoples of these islands face a fundamental choice: do they compete to take the territories across the waters by force, or do they find sufficient commonality to negotiate normative and mutually compatible relations for continued commerce? Conflict is costly, but may be seen as a means to possess the entire archipelago, the entire territory with all the resources and power entailed by the success of such a conflict. In contrast, a negotiated cooperative arrangement may reduce the total resources available to each individual island, but enable greater benefits by avoiding the costs of waging war and arranging complementary exchanges of the best each culture has to offer. Conflict can make a group stronger by steeling the motives to pull together against the external enemies, yet it can also reveal the weaknesses and fractures of a given group, and potentially, the entire overthrow of one’s own cherished culture. The methodological “cultures” of social scientists are a lot like these separate island cultures. They each have their rules, customs, beliefs and values. Each knows the others exist, but they engage in relatively little commerce and often view each other with suspicion and incredulity. Conflict, or at least indifference, occurs more often than cooperation. Social science began in the ancient, perhaps primal, desire to understand the world around us. Long ago, Eastern and Western traditions evolved across and into various eras, cultures and locales of enlightenment. As it was increasingly realized that scientific methods for understanding the world could be cumulative and increasingly valid, the approaches to understanding the physical world were increasingly extended to investigating the social world. These scholars eventually evolved into “tribes” of methodological and theoretical disciplines and associations. These tribes settled distinct islands of academe, often only dimly aware of the practices and beliefs of the tribes occupying the academic programs across continents, universities, colleges, departments, and even hallways and faculty Comm 610: Advanced Communication Theory: 156 room tables. The methods by which these tribes became acculturated and accustomed became claims to their natural resources of the “truth(s)” of the world, and the academic prestige implied by successful claims to this domain. Over time, these different methods have more often fomented indifference, alienation, and occasional struggles for respect, rather than negotiated cooperation. Scholars peer derisively at the alien practices of the heathen tribe across these methodological divides, and chant the righteousness of their own personal beliefs and customs. The domain of truth is often viewed as a limited resource, and any successful claims by other tribes result in territory no longer available to conquer except through renewed conflict. These territorial skirmishes often strengthen the spirits of believers and sometimes eliminate more destructive or flawed cultural customs of certain tribes; but often the ongoing battles serve no higher purpose than to fuel the conflict itself. The tribes intuitively understand that identifying a foil, or a common enemy, helps reinforce the resolve of the group. The destructiveness of the conflicts is typically exacerbated by the tendency of the different cultures to employ distinct symbols, vocabularies and dialects. Misunderstandings become common, even when negotiation efforts are pursued in the interest of cooperation. Social scientists have developed different methodological idioms of scholarly inquiry. These methodological practices represent distinct cultures, sometimes cooperating, but more often competing, to claim the larger territory of social science. Even when representatives of these distinct cultures claim publicly the importance of “getting along,” in private conversations with those of their own tribes, the rhetoric generally becomes incendiary and resentful of the others’ intrusions into territories more “rightly” reserved for one’s own endeavors. Competition for the sake of competition may have reached the limits of its evolutionary value. Two millennia have helped hone a verdant array of methodological islands. Productive progress in the future may well require more than a mere truce. Instead, the academic archipelago of social sciences may need a common bill of rights, a common sense of collective purpose and a common recognition of each other’s contributions. Unfortunately, such a revolution is not in the immediate offing. Before such a revolution can occur, however, bridges must be forged between and among the academic islands. This textbook lays the preliminary pontoons, in two important ways: First, by locating the nature of methods in the nature of argument, and second, by representing the broader scope of methods currently employed by the communication discipline. By locating the central underlying architecture of all methods in the structure of arguments, this text helps decode the Rosetta Stone of methodological languages, the symbolic intersection through which negotiations for collective commerce in the pursuit of knowledge must progress. No matter what else a method attempts to accomplish, it must rely upon, and establish the validity of, its practices through argument. Every method guides the production, collection and analysis of data, which consist of artifact(s), observation(s), case(s), example(s), or counts of something. But data alone prove nothing. Data only become meaningful in the crucible of argument, which connects the data through warrants to claims. Warrants are the reasons, rationale, or answer to the question “why” should I believe the claim being made by this research. The claim is the conclusion, or the particular proposition (e.g., hypothesis, value Comm 610: Advanced Communication Theory: 157 judgment, belief statement, etc.), which contextualizes the reasonableness of the data in connection with a claim. The claim, once established, may then become the warrant for subsequent arguments. Warrants are the bridges between data and claim, and claims so established serve as bridges to further arguments. This textbook examines ways of knowing as arguments. When a scholar has reached a conclusion, it stands as a privileged claim—a claim that this scholar’s method has provided specialized insight. Scholars apply a specialized method that they have apprenticed in their education to master, and this method serves as a way of privileging their voice compared to any given layperson’s view of the world. This does not invalidate the layperson’s views—it only suggests that methods provide a more reasoned or systematic approach to knowing than the average person will have had the opportunity or expertise to apply to making claims about some particular topic of investigation. There are many ways of scholarly knowing, but four illustrative paradigms in the communication discipline consist of discovery, conversation/textual analysis, interpretation, and critical approaches. These will be defined and detailed more extensively throughout the text, but for now, they can be illustrated in general ways. The discovery method assumes a singular objective reality, and although no method can reveal this objective truth in the social world, the discovery method uses various methods of objectification, including experiments, control, and quantification in an attempt to inch ever closer to that reality. The conversation/textual method assumes that because communicators accomplish everyday life based only on the behaviors they display through their communication (as opposed to reading each other’s minds), researchers can understand such behavior best by observing and precisely analyzing such naturally occurring activities. The interpretive method assumes that reality is socially constructed; that there are as many realities as there are people perceiving and influencing such perceptions through their communication. The critical method assumes that reality is always influenced by underlying systems of often hidden influence and power, and such structures must be evaluated through an evaluative perspective that reveals these hidden forces, thereby presenting opportunities for pursuing more noble or practical ends. If these paradigms are analyzed through the lens of the rationales they rely upon, they might look something like the following arguments: Comm 610: Advanced Communication Theory: 158 Figure 1. Diagramming the underlying arguments of different ways of knowing. DATA: All methodological paradigms engage in systematic selection, collection, observation, and interpretation of empirical communication-relevant data. WARRANT: Given these data, the methodological rationale provide justification for rendering the following claim(s)… CLAIM: Given these data and warrant(s), each of the following paradigms claims that…: From the interpretive paradigm perspective, this is a new frame for understanding these texts and their implications. From the discovery paradigm perspective, these data reveal new information about the generalizable nature of reality. From the critical paradigm perspective, these data enlighten the role of constraints, power, and exploitation, and point to possibilities for improving communication, society, and the human condition. Each paradigm or method can be further elaborated into its own particular rationale. The discovery paradigm presupposes that in any given process, there is a set of causes and effects, and that methods properly designed to manage or control for subjectivity of the researcher(s), and translating observations into quantifiable measurements, can reveal something about how causes associate with such effects. This approach to knowing implies an argument such as the following. Comm 610: Advanced Communication Theory: 159 Figure 2. Diagramming the underlying argument for the discovery paradigm. DATA: Communication is a cause, and is caused by, complex but specifiable underlying processes. CLAIM: Therefore, probability, measurement, design, theoryand hypothesis-testing render generalizable conclusions about cause-effect relations. WARRANT: Given statistical or experimental control of extraneous, mediating and moderating variables, causal influences can be identified to a reasonable level of probability (by excluding null and competing hypotheses). As another example, let’s say that in meticulously observing everyday conversation, you recognize a highly complex process through which people achieve social life. That is, apologies, compliments, requests, and the “events” of everyday life are accomplished through a subtle choreography of move and countermove of behavior. In such a dance, thoughts, values and beliefs are actually irrelevant to uncovering the structure of such accomplishments. An interactant cannot peer into your mind during a conversation; he or she recognizes an apology through the structure of the behavior observed, and therefore, such behavior is also observable by a researcher. The data of everyday accomplishments exists in behavior. If this is accurate, then it seems reasonable that all inferences about what conversationalists are attempting to achieve through interaction is exclusively “available” to others through their behavior. Several arguments could be derived from this rationale, but consider for the moment the following: Comm 610: Advanced Communication Theory: 160 Figure 3. Diagramming the underlying argument for the conversation/textual analysis paradigm. DATA: Everyday conversation is accomplished exclusively through mutually observable behavior. CLAIM: Subjective thoughts of interactants are irrelevant to understanding how interaction is accomplished. WARRANT: Interactants have no access to others’ subjective thoughts, yet accomplish everyday tasks through interaction. In contrast, interactants often make judgments about what others are doing through their behavior. In so doing, sometimes making one attribution rather than another may be an important determinant of how a person behaves in response to others’ behavior. For example, if you think you deserve an apology from someone, and this person provides what seems a cursory or inappropriate apology, you are likely to devalue this person’s apology. If you think this person provided an insincere apology because he or she thought you didn’t deserve an apology, you might begin disliking this person. Further, you might respond by seeking further apology, or avoid interacting with this person in the future. In short, your attributions or subjective thoughts about this person’s behavior directly influence your interaction with this person. Consequently, an argument can be derived as follows: Comm 610: Advanced Communication Theory: 161 Figure 4. Diagramming the underlying argument for the interpretive paradigm. DATA: Subjective thoughts affect motives and means of interaction. CLAIM: Subjective thoughts are essential to understanding how interaction is accomplished. WARRANT: Interactants seek to understand others’ behavior by making subjective attributions about why the others behaved/said what they did. Finally, the world may reveal disparities and distortions that imply underlying forces at work, which sustain themselves through power, deception, manipulation, and bias. Such hidden forces require critics to expose them, and to provide an evaluative standard against which such exploitative practices might be revealed and the victims of such distortions thereby liberated to empower their own interests. The rationale underlying this paradigm might look like the following. Figure 5. Diagramming the underlying argument for the critical paradigm. DATA: There are forms of exploitation, deprivation, corruption, and distortion in life. CLAIM: Critical inquiry and evaluations need to reveal these forms of exploitation, thereby pointing the way to better ways of pursuing life. WARRANT: Such disparities and distortions could only be sustained to the extent that they are hidden or masked by powerful interests, groups, and individuals. Comm 610: Advanced Communication Theory: 162 These various arguments lead to very different claims (i.e., methods) of understanding social interaction. For example, to the conversation analyst, only people’s naturally-occurring behaviors count as data, whereas in ethnographic or interpretive methods, both thoughts and behaviors count as data. Discovery researchers will experiment with people, whereas interpretive and conversation analytic researchers take people’s behavior for what it is, or was, and do not seek to introduce new stimuli to the investigation context. It follows that what counts as a theory can differ substantially across these paradigms. In one, behavior explains behavior, whereas in another, perceptions and feelings explain behavior. Conversation analytic researchers don’t see the relevance of the findings of survey (discovery) researchers, and survey researchers have difficulty seeing how to generalize the conclusions of conversation analysts without a cognitive theoretical context. So it is with all methodological arguments—they are the ways we know, and the ways we choose to know often seem to preclude other ways of knowing. The collective practices and vocabularies of scholars represent what Thomas Kuhn (1970) referred to as paradigms, and he believed them to be incommensurable. That is, a paradigm answers all the questions it needs to, in much the same way a religion is meant to do, and consequently, there is no need to borrow from another paradigm, just as most people find no need to borrow religious beliefs from another religion. So the islands upon which these researchers dwell are isolated by the arguments they make. But maybe, just maybe, if they recognize this fact, they can begin to understand why they reside on different islands in the first place, and how their respective tribes differ. Maybe they can begin to see how their arguments relate to each other, and begin a dialogue through which cooperation, rather than conflict, can be begun (Craig, 1999). Perhaps they can learn to “talk each other’s language” (Kuhn, 1970), and thereby better understand their differences. This textbook, by excavating the underlying basis of these differences, lays the initial bridges (and warrants) for this dialogue to begin. This dialogue is facilitated to the extent the various tribes and their customs are known. Arguments are most competent when adapted to their audiences, including those with whom we argue (i.e., other practitioners), as well as other interested parties (e.g., granting agencies, foundations, the media, etc.). Another strength of this text is a fair representation of the domain of the discipline. Few survey textbooks, for example, do justice to conversation analysis, or only give shallow consideration of critical and rhetorical methods. In contrast, this textbook recognizes the legitimacy of these methods as equivalent because their endeavors are predicated on the same discourse of argument. As Walter Fisher (1978) claimed, all arguments are ultimately erected on the foundations of underlying values, and “no analytically grounded hierarchy of values will ever claim universal adherence” (p. 377). Nevertheless, having an understanding of the multiple cultures of values with which one may seek congress, the better the dialogue can become in the service of that engagement. Nowhere is this dialogue more important than in the initial enculturation of students, beginning your own intrepid voyages into the often turbulent waters of the communication discipline. Just as it is easier developmentally to learn multiple languages early in the process of language learning, so it is easier to accept multiple Comm 610: Advanced Communication Theory: 163 methodologies before any single methodological argument has fortified its armaments and defenses against the other scholarly cultures with which it competes. Distinct cultural groups need not engage in similar practices to reap the benefits of mutual understanding and cooperation. The potential distance and competition among islands of inquiry is an old concern. Scholars have previously suggested that the key differences are in the questions that each culture seeks to answer. The types of questions asked can be important frames for arguments—such as determining what kind of argument represents a sensible response. People have suggested, for example, that there need be no competition between religion and science (Gould, 1999) or science and humanities (Gould, 2003; Miller, 1975), because these magisteria ask different types of questions, and thereby avoid encroachment upon one another’s terrirtories. Others, however, have suggested that the differences between religion and science, for example, go far deeper than just the questions asked—they go to issues such as their orientation to skepticism, openness to new knowledge and discovery, and the degree to which faith is placed in preserving the past versus accumulating, revising, and correcting, and accumulating the past (Fuchs, 2001). In the case of the arguments posed for the methods encountered in this text, for the most part, the big questions addressed are the same—why do people communicate the ways they do, and how does such communication affect the human condition? Instead, the major differences in the paradigms of inquiry examined in this text have to do with ways of answering any such questions, and this “how” question is addressed by different methods, representing different kinds of arguments for pursuing understanding. The journey is not an easy one. Forging relations with strange cultures and territories seldom is. There are many barriers that even the most motivated and capable among us face in building bridges across the waves and shoals of these methodological divides (Bryman, 2007). On the other hand, there are usually great benefits to developing an acquaintance and ongoing relationship with these cultures. Eventually, with enough trade, commerce, and experience in multiple cultures of research, scholars may become truly multi-lingual and multi-cultural, appreciating their indigenous culture and yet fully appreciating and engaging other cultures as well. There are many fruits of knowledge to taste and experiences to pursue that can only derive from encounters with those beyond the borders of our own comfortable domains. Therefore, go forth, and may you find the value of the voyage worthwhile. And for the few of you who will ever get the privilege of applying such arguments in the service of knowledge, may you get some glimpse of the excitement that derives from knowing something no one else knows, of discovering something no one else has discovered, or of seeing further than anyone else has previously seen. The risks of being wrong are great, but the potential of charting new routes or discovering new islands, or even building new bridges, holds its own rewards for those willing to venture forth with a spirit of scholarly adventure. This text will help you greatly along your way, providing as it does the charts and compass needed for the voyage ahead. Brian H. Spitzberg School of Communication San Diego State University Comm 610: Advanced Communication Theory: 164 30 December 2002 References Bryman, A. (2007). Barriers to integrating quantitative and qualitative research. Journal of Mixed Methods Research, 1, 8-22. Craig, R. T. (1999). Communication theory as a field. Communication Theory, 9, 119161. Fisher, W. R. (1978). Toward a logic of good reasons. Quarterly Journal of Speech, 64, 376-384. Fuchs, S. (2001). What makes sciences “scientific”? In J. H. Turner (Ed.), Handbook of sociological theory (pp. 21-35). New York: Kluwer Academic/Plenum. Gould, S. J. (1999). Rocks of ages: Science and religion in the fullness of life. New York: Ballantine. Gould, S. J. (2003). The hedgehog, the fox, and the magister’s pox: Mending the gap between science and the humanities. New York, NY: Harmony Books. Kuhn, T.S. (1970). The structure of scientific revolutions (2nd ed.). Chicago: University of Chicago. Miller, G. R. (1975). Humanistic and scientific approaches to speech communication inquiry: Rivalry, redundancy, or rapprochement. Western Speech Communication, 39, 230-239. Comm 610: Advanced Communication Theory: 165 “there is greater happiness than building theories and accumulating facts in silence and solitude” Charles Darwin, in a letter to his fiancée Emma, 1839