Self-Enforcing Clientelism Chappell Lawson Associate Professor Massachusetts Institute of Technology clawson@mit.edu Kenneth F. Greene Associate Professor University of Texas at Austin kgreene@austin.utexas.edu Draft April 30, 2012 Abstract Recent research on clientelism focuses on deliberate exchanges between mercenary voters and strategic political brokers. In this “instrumentalist” view, machine politics is only sustainable where patrons can monitor voters’ actions – a situation that does not apply in many places known for clientelism. In this paper, we build a different theory of clientelism around the norm of reciprocity. If exchanges rely on clients’ feelings of obligation to return favors to their patrons, then clientelism can be self-enforcing and persist despite ballot secrecy. To support this argument, we draw on ethnographic reports, survey data, and experiments from a variety of countries, as well as split-sample experiments embedded in two new surveys on Mexico specifically designed to test our predictions. Our findings have implications for voting behavior, party organization, and the types of public policies that may diminish clientelism. 1. Introduction Political scientists have long been interested in relationships in which leaders exchange selective benefits for political allegiance.1 In developing countries, scholars typically group these relationships under the rubric of “clientelism”; followers are known as clients, leaders as patrons, and intermediaries as brokers. In the United States, analysts have referred to these same three groups as “constituents”, “bosses”, and “precinct captains”; the relationships among them are known as “machine politics” (Ostrogorski 1910, Gosnell 1937, Allswang 1977, Cox and Kousser 1981, Erie 1988). Despite extensive research in both contexts, however, political scientists have not produced a consensus on how such relationships are maintained. Recent theory argues that voters only comply with political brokers’ wishes if they believe that their vote choices are monitored and that they can thus be sanctioned if they fail to support the machine. This instrumentalist approach focuses on deliberate exchanges between voters who seek to extract tangible benefits and strategic political brokers who want to deliver votes to the politicians they serve as cheaply as possible (Dal Bó 2007; Kitschelt and Wilkinson 2007b; Nichter 2008; Stokes 2005). Such arguments emphasize the degree to which careful surveillance – or at least the credible threat of such surveillance (Chandra 2007) – ensures that constituents follow-through on their part of the clientelist bargain. Yet this instrumentalist approach has not fully resolved the problem of voter compliance, especially where ballot secrecy is well established. When clientelist exchanges are 1 In keeping with recent work (e.g., Kitschelt and Wilkinson 2007b, Stokes 2007), we consider benefits to be “selective” if they are excludable goods that can be distributed in a discretionary fashion. We conceive of “clientelism” as a relationship between patrons with access to resources that they trade for political support, and “vote-buying" as one possible manifestation of clientelism in which benefits are exchanged for votes. 1 asynchronous (i.e. brokers distribute benefits before an election in hopes of generating support on Election Day), clients may “defect” from the agreement after receiving their payoff (Stokes 2005). To diminish the incentive to renege, patrons not only must be able to monitor voters’ choices, either at the time they cast their ballots or after the fact, but they must be able to sanction individual voters who defect. Without identifying individual defectors, brokers cannot know which voters to sanction by withdrawing benefits in subsequent elections. Clientelism would then break down for one of two reasons. If brokers pay supporters and opponents alike, then the disincentive for voting against the machine disappears. In addition, clientelism may prove unsustainably costly (Dal Bó 2007). If brokers inadvertently sanction supporters, they would create spurned voters who would not support the machine in the future under any standard punishment-path strategy.2 Sanctioning groups of voters would only hasten clientelism’s demise because a machine that loses once in a constituency would withdraw benefits from some supporters who, in response, may not renew their support for the machine (see Levine and Pesendorfer 1995; also see Finan and Schecter 2009).3 Brokers can overcome these problems in some contexts. Some countries use partisan ballots, effectively eliminating ballot secrecy or permit party operatives in polling places, conveying the perception of monitoring even when voting is secret (see Kitschelt and Rozenas 2011). In other places, operatives use more clever tactics to violate the secret ballot and 2 If voters use “grim trigger”, then they would cease to be clients forever after not receiving a payoff in any given election cycle (Stokes 2005). If both brokers and voters use “tit-for-tat,” then a similar outcome would occur. 3 The logical implication is that clientelism based on instrumental calculations alone should be sustainable only where the machine has an unlimited budget (so that it can buy opponents) or where it holds monopoly power. 2 overcome the problem of asynchronous exchange. For instance,in Mexico, brokers are rumored to have asked voters to photograph their marked ballot using cell phones. In Italy, operatives from the Christian Democratic Party reportedly distributed left shoes to its clients before elections with the promise of delivering the right shoes if it won (Chubb 1982). In many settings, however, parties and candidates have limited capacity to monitor voters’ choices, allowing instrumentally motivated voters to “take the money and run” and ultimately undermining machine politics. In recent work, some instrumentalist scholars have recognized this problem and attempted to grapple with it systematically (Piattoni 2001: 7, Kitschelt and Wilkinson 2007: 8, Magaloni 2006, Kitschelt and Rozenas 2011). For instance, Stokes (2005, 2007) argues that the monitoring problem is mitigated by local brokers who are deeply embedded in their communities and can guess at how their clients vote. Unfortunately, this key claim has not been testes systematically. However, research in experimental psychology shows that people are surprisingly bad at detecting when others are lying, even when they are trained to do so (Grohol 1999, Kohnken 1987, Kraut and Poe 1980).4 In addition, clientelism persists in many places where well-organized political machines do not operate.5 Thus, difficulties in monitoring and sanctioning voters continue to pose a serious challenge to instrumentalist theories of clientelism. Given the theoretical and practical problems with enforcement of the clientelist bargain 4 Using turnout at the polls or at campaign events does not necessarily improve brokers’ guesses about which individuals vote for the machine. 5 Examples include Nigeria and Benin (Van de Walle 2007: 64), Taiwan (Wang and Kurzman’s 2007: 233), Paraguay (Finan and Schecter 2009: 17), Sao Tomé e Principe (Vicente 2008), and Peru (González Ocantos et al. 2011a; Seawright 2011). 3 through external monitoring, we propose that machine politics can be supported by a psychological mechanism rooted in norms of reciprocity. Specifically, we argue that the receipt of gifts, favors, services, or protection creates feelings of obligation among voters, who then spontaneously support their political patrons. Under such circumstances, clientelism is selfenforcing. This norms-based approach to clientelism has roots in certain ethnographic studies from anthropology, sociology, and political science that emphasize the embeddedness of relationships between patrons and clients and the “moral economy” of exchanges between the two (Boissevain 1966, Wolf 1969, Powell 1970, Scott 1972, Lemarchand and Legg 1972, Johnson 1974, Scott 1976, Eisenstadt and Lemarchand 1981, Lomnitz 1982 , Chubb 1982, Komito 1984, Roniger and Günes-Ayata 1994, Gay 1994, Fox 1994, Auyero 2001, Calvo and Murillo 2004, Gay 2006, Krishna 2007, Schaffer and Schedler 2007). These largely descriptive studies have routinely emphasized norms of reciprocity as the basis for clientelist exchanges, but they lack a plausible psychological micro-foundation that is as conceptually well-grounded as the instrumentalist underpinnings of principal-agent models of vote-buying. We show that norms of reciprocity create a separate foundation for machine politics. The sense of obligation that brokers create through the provision of selective benefits can help politicians build clientelist networks even in the context of ballot secrecy. One implication is that clientelism may be much more entrenched than existing analyses would lead us to believe and will not necessarily disappear rapidly once ballot secrecy is enforced, as long as politicians have access to discretionary resources. Rather, purging clientelism from political life may require a normative component – specifically, that citizens reject on principle the exchange of votes for selective benefits because they feel a greater obligation to vote their conscience, to obey the law, and to support democratic institutions. Our argument also has ramifications for party organization. Because machine politics 4 can persist in the absence of active monitoring, politicians may not need the large-scale, deeply embedded organizations that would otherwise be required to monitor and sanction voters (Gyrzmala-Busse 2005; Kitschelt and Wilkinson 2007b; Stokes 2005, 2007). Rather, they can secure election by earning voters’ loyalty, somewhat akin to the way that politicians generate gratitude through constituency service and pork-barrel politics. The next section of this paper provides a systematic rationale for the “norms-ofobligation” interpretation of clientelism. We caution that the instrumentalist and norms-based approaches contrasted here are not synonyms for “rational choice” and “cultural” approaches. There is nothing inherently cultural about discharging one’s debts through acts of political support. The third section discusses observable implications of this approach and compares them to those of instrumentalist models; this section draws on ethnographic studies, surveys, and experiments, as well as on two new surveys from Mexico. The concluding section returns to the implications of our findings for electoral behavior, party organization, and public policy. 2. Reciprocity and Obligation in Clientelist Exchange Our approach is based on the notion that powerful instincts of reciprocity cause people to feel indebted to those who provide them with benefits of more than token significance. When the recipient cannot discharge this debt of obligation materially, patron-client relationships may emerge. Of course, not all such debts generate clientelism. After detailing the psychological foundation for reciprocity, we generate more specific hypotheses about the conditions under which feelings of obligation promote clientelism. Reciprocity is a fundamental element of human social interaction. Norms of reciprocity are recognized at a very young age (Harris 1970, Dreman and Greenbaum 1973, Birch and Billman 1986) and, although cultural differences can influence the expression of these norms (Herrmann et al. 2008, Gächter and Herrmann 2008), the concept and practice of reciprocity are 5 essentially universal (Heinrich et al. 2005). This component of human nature appears to be evolutionarily “hard-wired” (Hammerstein 2003, Gintis et al. 2003, Berg et al. 1995, Ornstein 1980, Trivers 1971, Simmel and Wolff 1950). Recent research in genetics and neuroscience even identifies some of the specific alleles and biological pathways that underlie reciprocal exchange (McCabe et al. 2001, Sanfey et al. 2003, de Quervain et al. 2004, Cesarini et al. 2008, Fowler et al. 2008). Instincts of reciprocity can powerfully influence behavior (see Fehr and Fischbacher 2002, Elster 1989: 192-214; Dawes and Thaler 1988: 195). For instance, experimental research shows that people often treat others fairly even when they face an incentive to do otherwise (McCabe et al. 1996, McCabe et al. 2003, Berg et al. 1995). Several years ago, two leading behavioral economists remarked that, “the obligation to reciprocate is so strong that we take it for granted” (Carmichael and MacLeod 1997: 502). Scholars from various disciplines have now documented the role of reciprocity in a wide range of social activities, but it has not yet been used as the basis for understanding political clientelism.6 Instincts of reciprocity lead people to feel indebted to those who provide them with gifts, services, favors, or protection (Mauss 1990, Sherry 1983). Among individuals of similar status, such obligations are often discharged by providing a good of comparable worth to the original “gift”.7 But not all recipients have the wherewithal to pay their patrons back in kind. Patron-client relationships may emerge when recipients discharge their debt by according the giver greater 6 One potential criticism of this literature is that reciprocity’s role has not been experimentally tested for large-scale transactions. Fortunately, voting is a low-cost activity that falls well within the scope of the gains at stake in the experiments on the effect of reciprocity. 7 Debts can also be discharged by maintaining a long-term relationship in which mutual assistance is taken for granted as in friendship or marriage. 6 social status, esteem, or loyalty (Weinstein et al. 1969, Bienenstock and Bianchi 2004). This exchange creates a status hierarchy among previous equals (Rao 2001, Aragon 1996, Bartlett 1980).8 In the political sphere, recipients typically reciprocate patronage through outward manifestations of allegiance and shows of solidarity (Forster 1963; Scott 1972, Eisenstadt and Roniger 1984) – such as voting for a particular candidate, attending rallies, volunteering on a campaign, contributing their energy to projects sponsored by patrons, or joining protests when urged to do so (Harik 2004: 81-110, 147-62, Cambanis 2006, Radnitz 2010). Status hierarchy has long been the core of clientelism as conceptualized by scholars in anthropology and sociology. As Lomnitz puts it (1988: 47): Loyalty in unbalanced exchange relations is the basis for political support…The patron provides security of employment, political protection, and dependability in unexpected circumstances of need in exchange for loyalty, expressed through personal commitment to the patron in labor, political support, and ideological allegiance. Political clientelism becomes established when it is clear to both sides that recipients can never repay benefits in kind, turning one group into perpetual recipients of material goods, services, favors, or protection and the other group into perpetual providers. As Scott characterizes it, the “patron is in a position to supply unilaterally goods and services which the potential client and his family need for their survival and well-being” (1972: 93). 8 Where status hierarchies already exist, exchanges between social superiors and subordinates reinforce them (Aragon 1996: 49-50, Weiner 1980). Gifts from followers to leaders (tribute) help to secure protection or assistance, whereas gifts from leaders to followers cultivate gratitude and sustain bonds of loyalty. 7 A key question concerns the conditions under which feelings of obligation become activated in service of clientelism, and thus why scholars observe variation in the extent of machine politics across individuals, communities, and countries (even where politicians have similar levels of access to discretionary resources). We underscore two important limitations on the power of obligation to activate clientelist relations. First, not all gifts automatically activate instincts of reciprocity. Token items (e.g., a pen bearing a party logo) may be taken as a gesture of introduction or courtesy, rather than as the “quid” in a quid pro quo. Likewise, items distributed to everyone who happens to be on a street corner at a particular moment could be interpreted similarly as materials meant to attract attention or to announce a candidate’s presence, rather than as part of an exchange relationship. The same holds if the benefits distributed are interpreted by recipients as repayments for past good behavior or as entitlements rather than gifts. Selective benefits offered by political machines may also be insufficient to generate clientelist support if the obligation they create is not deemed “worth” a vote (or some other demonstration of adhesion). The “going rate” for a vote likely varies across voters with different levels of resources. Second, obligations stemming from reciprocity, do not necessarily propel citizens to become clients when all factors are taken into account (Klosko 1990). A person may feel an obligation to her family to accept groceries from a political party in return for her vote, and this exchange may in turn generate an obligation to vote for that party. However, that new obligation may conflict with some existing obligation, such as the personal conviction that she should to vote her conscience or (where selling one’s vote is illegal) the moral obligation to obey the law. Thus, factors like the intensity of a voter’s attachment to competing parties, the degree to which she has imbibed civic norms, her respect for the law, and support for representative institutions could affect the extent and durability of clientelism. Just as instrumentally motivated clients do not automatically support the machine when they have competing reasons to choose another 8 party,9 voters motivated by feelings of obligation will only become captured clients under specific circumstances, as we detail below. 3. Observable Implications of the Reciprocity and Instrumentalist Approaches Both instrumental and normative motivations for clientelism may be present within a given system, and machine politics will presumably be most durable when both mechanisms operate. In some cases, both approaches make similar predictions. For instance, both predict that clientelism would deteriorate when politicians run out of discretionary resources to distribute. However, the two approaches do yield a number of different predictions, presented in Table 1, which can be used as the basis for more systematic comparison. This comparison helps “locate” our norms-based approach in relation to the now-dominant literature on clientelism and yields testable hypotheses. [Table 1 about here] The key difference between the two approaches concerns the importance of monitoring voters’ actions. If instrumental models are correct, machine politics is limited to contexts in which patrons can credibly threaten to reward or punish their followers for non-compliance (Dal Bó 2007; Kitschelt and Wilkinson 2007b; Nichter 2008; Stokes 2005). By contrast, clientelism based on reciprocity may persist even where voters do not believe that they are monitored. 9 Scholars working in the instrumentalist tradition have long recognized the power of partisan loyalty and policy proximity to moderate the effect of payoffs. For instance, opponents of the machine are considered too costly to buy (Stokes 2005) and supporters are predicted to respond more positively to payoffs (Cox and McCubbins 1993). 9 The two approaches also yield competing predictions about retrospective voting. In the instrumental view, voters care exclusively about prospective costs and benefits (Kitschelt and Wilkinson 2007b: 25, 342; Lyne 2007; Stokes 2005). Although their perceptions of what benefits they may receive in the future are likely informed by what they have received in the past, instrumentally motivated voters care only about how today’s interactions condition their future stream of benefits. Clients motivated by obligation, however, may demonstrate loyalty to leaders who did right by them in the past, regardless of what they stand to gain in the future. That is, their actions today may be motivated by repaying a past favor rather than as part of a calculation about what they expect to receive in the future. They may thus cast their ballots based on purely retrospective considerations (see Kinder and Kiewiet 1979, Fiorina 1981, Cain et al. 1987). Intriguingly, they may even seek to reciprocate perceived injuries and injustices by voting against politicians who failed to deliver when expected to do so. This phenomenon, known as “altruistic punishment,” can even lead citizens to turn against patrons when doing so diminishes the chances of receiving clientelist benefits in the future (Fehr and Gächter 2000, Fehr and Gächter 2002, de Quervain et al. 2004). Political attitudes also play a key role in the reciprocity approach to clientelism. Instrumentalist approaches generally discount citizens’ attitudes because such attitudes do not affect the costs and benefits of supporting the machine. In the norms-based approach, however, civic values create conflicting obligations that should make voters less likely to participate in clientelist arrangements or follow through on a clientelist bargain once it is struck. Civic-minded voters should thus be more likely to see clientelist exchanges as illegitimate, to reject proffered benefits, and to perceive a value conflict between clientelist and civic obligations. Finally, the reciprocity framework predicts that the provision of benefits by politicians induces feelings of indebtedness among recipients to support the politicians in question. As the value of a particular benefit rises in the mind of the recipient, he should become a more reliable 10 client. Instrumentally minded voters clearly also assess the value of a proffered benefit such that voters evaluate whether a given good is “worth” their vote. To the extent that the two perspectives differ on this point, they predict differences in how voters react to two benefits of similar monetary value. For the strictest of instrumentalists, two such benefits should elicit similar responses, whereas in the reciprocity framework, they may elicit widely varying feelings of obligation. For instance, a needed “just in time” service such as a free visit to a doctor for a sick child may elicit more obligation than a cash payment that could purchase such a visit. Instrumentalist arguments are currently better-established in the political science literature, yet as Brusco and colleagues (2004:81) point out, neither framework has been subjected to a systematic test. For this reason, we first summarize supporting evidence for the norms of reciprocity approach from existing studies using a variety of methods. We then present new data from split-sample experiments embedded in two new surveys from Mexico in which registered voters were selected at random from seven precincts (2009, N=545) and four different precincts (2010, N=360) in the Federal District of Mexico City and the State of Mexico.10 We view this combination of observational and experimental methods as a step beyond the observational approach researchers have used to test principal-agent models of clientelism based on instrumentalist micro-foundations (Stokes 2005; Brusco et al. 2007). Clientelist Exchanges Generate Obligation If the provision of selective benefits failed to conjure up feelings of obligation, there would be little reason to think such feelings motivated clientelist exchange. Consistent with our argument, ethnographic accounts of clientelism produced over the last 75 years are drenched in 10 The Supporting Materials provide information on site selection and sampling and show that our procedures effectively randomized the key treatments across respondents. 11 the language of obligation (inter alia, Gosnell 1937, Weinstein et al. 1969, Powell 1970, Scott 1972, Lemarchand and Legg 1972, Lemarchand 1972, Eisenstadt and Lamarchand 1981, Eisenstadt and Roniger 1984, Erie 1988, Roniger 1990, Fukui and Fukai 1996, Gay 1998, Auyero 1999, Auyero 2000, Auyero 2001, Levitsky 2003, Gay 2006). Clients regularly report feeling indebted to the politicians who provide them with benefits and that such obligation compels them to act accordingly (Gosnell 1937, Erie 1988, Auyero 2002, Gay 1998, Gay 2006, Wang 2007). One example of reciprocity from recent fieldwork comes from the so-called “new leaders” (naya netas) in northern India. Although these village notables cannot monitor voters’ behavior, they can count on beneficiaries to support them nonetheless. As one naya neta put it: It is a matter of keeping faith. People can obviously vote as they wish. But most people remember well who has helped them in times of need. And it is only a rare person who is faithless (Krishna 2007: 148). Field reports on electoral politics in other countries, including Benin, Japan, northern Portugal, and the Philippines have uncovered the same dynamic (Schaffer and Schedler 2007: 21). If the approach we propose is correct, not only should benefits generate obligations, but variation in the value of benefits should affect the degree of obligation. Data from existing surveys on Brazil and Mexico suggest that such a relationship does indeed exist. For instance, respondents in the 2002 Brazilian Election Study, which polled over 2,500 adults nationwide, were asked whether voter should accept a particular gift and then vote for the party that provided it in return. In the aggregate, respondents ordered items in a predictable way, reporting the greatest obligation to support a party that provided medical care for a sick child (61%), followed by one that arranged for a spot in school for the voter’s child (52%), provided groceries (46%), and gave the voter a bicycle (30%). (See Supporting Materials.) Likewise, respondents in the nationally representative Mexico 2006 Panel Study reported that providing important 12 public services such as water, sewage, or electricity created more of an obligation than offering a bag of groceries, which in turn was worth more than holding a neighborhood party. Data on self-reported receipt of gifts from the same survey also show that the more recipients said that the gifts mattered to them, the greater the obligation they felt to support the party providing it (r = .51, p < .01, N = 79). (See Supporting Materials.) Our own surveys provide a more direct test of this hypothesis using a series of splitsample experiments. Interviewers read third-person vignettes of the following type, in which half the sample was prompted with the smaller sum and half with the larger sum: “Let’s imagine that a candidate for municipal president offers Gabriel/Gabriela [50/500] pesos11 in exchange for his/her vote and Gabriel/Gabriela accepts the money. In your opinion, how much obligation should Gabriel/Gabriela feel to vote for this candidate – a lot, some, a little, or none?” Similar vignettes were read where the benefit in question was a bicycle, several bags of cement, or medical treatment for a sick child. We used hypothetical third-persons to diminish social desirability bias in responses, given that many of the practices discussed were illegal.12 Interviewers matched the gender of the person in the vignettes to that of the respondent in order to enhance identification with the subject of the vignette (King 2004). We also used eight versions of the survey to prevent answers to one question from affecting answers to another (“contamination bias”). The results presented in Table 2 show that respondents, in the aggregate, had a clear 11 The exchange rate at the time was approximately 12 pesos per dollar. 12 When asked directly whether they would accept a payoff in exchange for their vote, just 6% of respondents answered in the affirmative. Yet 32.8% said that they had personally received a good or service from a party representative in a recent election. The strong presence of social desirability bias thus made the use of hypothetical third-persons important. 13 ordering of the degree of obligation that a citizen should feel when he or she accepts a benefit in exchange for political support. (The use of split-sample survey experiments prevents us from examining individual preference orders over the whole range of items in Table 1.) Small monetary payments induced the least amount of obligation to support a candidate, with approximately one quarter of the sample reporting some obligation. Larger monetary payments generated more in the split-sample experiments, but less than other gifts. A gift of a bicycle induced obligation among more than one-third of respondents, and a bag of cement (crucial to people living in poorly constructed homes) raised that proportion to almost two-fifths. As we would expect, the provision of a doctor’s visit for a sick child was the most powerful inducement, with nearly half of respondents saying that such an act should create a sense of obligation in the voter to support the politician providing it. Importantly, both the provision of cement and a doctor’s visit were valued more highly by respondents than receiving 500 pesos, even though this sum would typically be more than enough to purchase either benefit. (These differences were statistically significant at the .01 level.) [Table 2 about here] Evidence from a variety of research methods and across several countries thus shows that clientelist benefits generate feelings of obligation among voters. But do feelings of obligation actually lead people to choose candidates on the basis of clientelist appeals? In our 2009 survey in Mexico, we asked half the respondents whether they would vote for the party with which they sympathized or the party that resolved an important legal issue for them in the past.13 Only 30.2% inclined toward the party with which they sympathized whereas 54.4% chose 13 The other half of the sample was asked the same question, except that voters were told they did not sympathize with the party of either candidate; we use only the first half of the sample 14 the party that gave them a benefit in the past. (Another 15.4% were uncertain which party to choose.) In other words, obligation stemming from past receipt of benefits weighed more heavily on voters than their partisan sympathies. Other research shows that party affiliation powerfully influences vote choices in Mexico (Lawson and McCann 2003, Domínguez and Lawson 2003, Domínguez et al. 2008) and that one component of partisanship concerns issues preferences that underlie prospective programmatic voting (Greene 2007). As another test of the relationship between obligation and voting, we constructed an index of political obligation by adding responses from three questions that were asked of all respondents in our 2010 survey: how much obligation should Gabriel/Gabriela feel to vote for a party that gave him/her a) 500 pesos, b) a paid doctor’s visit for his/her sick child, and c) a rooftop water tank in exchange for his/her vote. A separate item on the survey asked respondents whether a voter who lives in an area that suffers from water shortages should choose a candidate that offers him/her a week’s worth of water before the election in exchange for his/her vote or one who offers nothing before the election but promises to improve the water system in the area if he wins. This question thus asks voters to choose between a pre-electoral selective benefit that we view as a clientelist good and a post-electoral community benefit. In logistic regression models where preference over candidates offering one or the other type of benefit is the dependent variable, the coefficient on the index of political obligation is correctly signed and significant at the .05 level. (See Table 3.) The magnitude of the effect remains virtually unchanged when we control for other variables that could plausibly affect orientations toward clientelism, including family wealth as measured by an inventory of common household items (Kitschelt and Wilkinson 2007; Stokes 2005), education, feelings of political efficacy (as here. Not surprisingly, more respondents in the other half of the sample were even more inclined to support the politicians that had given them a specific benefit. 15 measured by a standard question about whether or not respondents think that politics is too complicated for them to understand), and feeling thermometer ratings of the main political parties. (We return to the effect of civic values, also included in the model, in a subsequent section.) A simulation using the full model (“Model 4” in Table 3) shows that an otherwise average individual who feels the highest level of political obligation is 12% more likely to choose the clientelist candidate. This change more than doubles the likelihood that an individual would support the machine, from 10% to 22%, all else equal.14 [Table 3 about here] Evidence from a variety of sources thus supports the notion that the (1) the provision of selective benefits produces feelings of obligation, (2) subjectively more valuable benefits produce more obligation, and (3) feelings of obligation are associated with clientelist voting. Clientelism Persists Despite Ballot Secrecy Instrumental interpretations of clientelism rest on brokers’ ability to circumvent the secret ballot. In contrast, our norms-based approach implies that voters spontaneously support the machine, even where ballot secrecy is secure. Ample evidence using several research methods supports this view. Field research shows that clientelism persists without policing of voters’ actions in many contexts. For instance, Van de Walle (2007: 64) points out that individualized monitoring is 14 Political obligation as measured by our index is also associated with other aspects of clientelist voting. The 10% of respondents who reported asking a politician for a favor evinced more obligation than those who had never asked for a favor (p < .01). The 6% of the sample that admitted willingness to exchange their vote for a payoff also felt more obligation than those unwilling to enter into a clientelist exchange (p < .1). 16 implausible in countries like Nigeria and Benin, which are not generally regarded as strangers to clientelism. Wang and Kurzman’s (2007: 233) detailed analysis of vote buying in a 1993 contest for county executive in Taiwan reaches the same conclusion: although the ballot was secret, operatives from the Kuomintang documented the purchase of 14,090 votes by relying on networks of trust and obligation. In a number of other countries that lack structured and enduring political parties that could act as clientelist machines, analysts routinely report high levels of clientelism. Peru has been referred to as a case of party system collapse (Seawright 2011; Morgan 2011), yet in the 2010 elections, 24.5% of voters reported involvement in clientelist exchanges (González Ocantos et al. 2011a). More generally, the degree of party institutionalization across Latin American countries is not related to voters’ reported involvement in clientelism. Paraguay, Colombia, Brazil, Bolivia, and Guatemala show lower than average levels of party structuration with higher than average levels of clientelism.15 Nationally representative survey data also show that clientelism extends much further than monitoring. For instance, in São Tomé e Príncipe, 90% of subjects said that brokers attempted to buy their political support in parliamentary elections, yet only 14% reported any attempt at monitoring or sanctioning (Vicente 2008). In a similar vein, survey data from Brazil indicate that many citizens would be willing to carry through on vote-selling transactions, even when the questions asked do not imply any policing of voters’ behavior (see Supporting Materials). In our surveys, Mexican voters also perceived that the parties had a relatively limited capacity (or desire) to monitor votes: just 25.5% said that they saw party representatives inside 15 Party institutionalization data come from Jones (2007: 83). Public opinion data come from Americas Barometer 2010. When unobtrusive measures are used to tap clientelism, rates are substantially higher (González Ocantos et al. 2011b). 17 polling places trying to determine who voters chose and only 12.1% reported seeing party representatives threaten to sanction voters. Nevertheless, 71.4% believed that parties regularly or sometimes try to buy votes in their neighborhood, and 69.3% think that people in their neighborhood sell their vote (50.4% say that it occurred with frequency and another 18.9% that it happened sometimes). Thus, far more clientelism occurs than the parties’ monitoring capabilities would seem to support. In one particularly clever analysis of heavily clientelist Paraguay, Finan and Schecter (2009: 17) show that individuals who exhibit greater reciprocity in experimental trust games devoid of any political content and with no implication of monitoring, were more likely to report involvement in clientelist exchanges (as measured in separate surveys) than those who evinced less reciprocity. As Vicente concludes, such findings support “the idea that self-enforcement may be the main mechanism by which vote buying works” in settings where such behavior is pandemic (2008: 21). Voters who believe their own choices are monitored could conceivably underreport monitoring or over-report obligation in opinion polls. If so, then voters who believe the vote is not secret should report higher levels of obligation, indicating that our findings are an artifact of voter fear. As a test, we compared the obligation induced by the items that appear in Table 2 with perceptions of monitoring. Respondents who suspected that voting was monitored reported slightly greater obligation for three of the five items; however, these differences were minor and not statistically significant. We also tested whether perceptions of ballot secrecy affected respondents’ beliefs that a voter should choose a party offering discrete material benefits over one offering a broader community benefit. Those who believed that brokers can monitor their vote choices were no more likely to choose the clientelist party. In other words, variation in reported obligation is not a product of beliefs about whether parties can monitor voters’ behavior. 18 Obligation Produces Purely “Retrospective Voting” In instrumentalist models of clientelism, voters care about the future payoffs they will receive from a clientelist party. If voters consider past performance, it is only as an indicator of the likely future stream of clientelist goods that they may receive by supporting the machine (Cox and McCubbins 1986; Dixit and Londregan 1986; Lindbeck and Weibull 1986; Kitschelt and Wilkinson 2007b: 25, 342; Lyne 2007, Stokes 2005). In our norms-based approach, by contrast, voters may make their choices based on purely retrospective considerations because they may feel an obligation to support politicians who have done right by them in the past, regardless of what they stand to gain in the future. The link between the provision of favors or services and retrospective voting is commonplace in developed countries under the name “constituency service”. American congressmen devote enormous attention to this activity – between one quarter and one third of their time – and their efforts appear to pay handsome dividends (Fenno 1978; Fiorina 1981, Yiannakis 1981, Cain et al. 1987, Fiorina and Rohde 1989). The dividing line between such constituency service and clientelism is not always clear. For instance, Japanese politicians maintain massive personal support networks (koenkai) that dole out cash gifts at funerals and furnish constituents with material benefits in times of need (Curtis 1971, Fukui and Fukai 1996, Scheiner 2007). American political machines, as well as constituency service efforts in Ireland (Komito 1984), Italy (Rossetti 1994, Golden 2003), and Mexico (Hilgers 2005) similarly blur the distinction between these activities. Both types of retail politics rely on voters’ obligation to pay back past benefits with political support. Although systematic investigation on this sort of retrospective voting has been limited, the survey data that does exist demonstrates the behavior among voters that we predict. For instance, in a 2002 survey of voters in Argentina conducted by Brusco et al. (2004) and used as 19 evidence in favor of the instrumentalist approach (Stokes 2005), respondents were asked whether they had received a gift from a local representative of a party or organization during the campaign. If they responded “yes,” they were asked whether the gift affected their vote. Respondents who reported being influenced were then asked how the gift affected them in an open-ended question (with verbatim responses recorded). Among those who reported being influenced, 14% said that they felt an obligation to vote for the party that gave them the gift; 21% said they changed their vote because the party “helped” them; 17% said they normally voted for parties who gave them things; and others reported vague positive sentiments based on retrospective rather than prospective considerations. None reported using prospective criteria. Other data cast even more doubt on voters’ use of prospective criteria. If clients think prospectively, then presumably they would only change their vote intentions to candidates that they think will actually win election and thus be in a position to offer benefits in future elections. Testing this hypothesis requires panel survey data that allows observation of respondents’ vote intentions over time as well as whether they receive a clientelist payoff, and their assessments about each candidate’s likelihood of winning. We only found one survey that meets these criteria: the Mexico 2000 Panel Study. In Mexico’s 2000 elections, 24% of voters polled reported that they received some sort of a payoff from one of the parties (Greene 2007: 215) and these payoffs affected vote choices. Those who received payoffs in the crucial period between early June and the July 6 election were more likely to switch their vote intention to a final vote choice for the candidate who doled out the benefit. Models that we report in the appendix show that independent voters who received a gift from the PRI were 6.4% more likely to vote for that party’s candidate (Labastida 7-13.4), Fox 13.6-26.8, CCS 17.1-18.1. Among voters who received a payoff, 30.9% changed their vote intention to the candidate that gave them the benefit, even though they thought that this candidate was unlikely 20 to win the presidency. The most striking finding concerns the candidacy of leftist Cuauhtémoc Cárdenas. As his ill-fated third run for the presidency wore on, voters abandoned him in droves and belief that he would win plummeted. Yet among voters who reported receiving a payoff from Cárdenas’s party in the last month of the campaign season and said that they voted for him in the post-election wave of the panel survey, fully 47.1% thought that he was unlikely to win the presidency when polled less than a month prior to the election. It is highly improbable that voters who received payoffs from Cárdenas’s party came to believe that he could win during the final month of his ill-fated and, by then, flailing campaign. Not only were his prospects dim and getting dimmer in the national media, but most voters (60% to be exact) who received payoffs by the end of April believed Cárdenas was less likely to win when re-interviewed at the beginning of June. These striking findings cannot be accommodated within the instrumentalist framework. Voters motivated by future payoff would be foolish to choose a candidate that they think cannot win office, and therefore cannot leverage the spoils of office to make clientelist payments in future elections. These findings instead imply that voters are motivated by non-prospective criteria. If many clients do not make their vote choices with an eye toward future payoffs, then what motivates their choices? Our 2009 survey investigated this issue further. Half of the sample was asked how much obligation a hypothetical third person would feel to support a party that promised to deliver a particular good or service (e.g., a medical center) in the future; the other half of the sample was asked how much of an obligation the person would feel to support a party that had provided a good or service in the past. If voters ignore or discount past benefits, then they would presumably feel much less inclination to vote for parties that did right by them previously than they would for parties that promise desirable benefits in the future. Yet the data show that this is not the case; respondents reported no greater inclination to support a party that 21 promised to build a medical clinic in the neighborhood if it won the election there than one that reminded them it had built such a clinic in the past. This null result supports our argument, but it is possible that it emerges from the data because voters do not believe that candidate’s promises are credible. The structure of our 2010 survey allows us to investigate this issue further. As above, respondents were asked how much obligation a hypothetical person should feel to vote for a party that promised a medical center in their community if it won and, separately, the obligation created when a party reminded that it improved medical services in the community when last in office.16 Immediately preceding these questions, half of the sample was primed with a question that featured a party that had made good on a prior promise. Even these respondents reported more obligation for the party that reminded of a past benefit than one that promised a future one. If voters are motivated by purely retrospective considerations, then they may also engage in another form of retrospective voting by repaying past insults or injuries. Because clientelism rests on voters’ responses to past favors, failure by politicians to deliver selective benefits will erode the “moral economy” of machine politics, provoking not only detachment from clientelist parties but perhaps even a sense of moral indignation among those who were part of the clientelist network. Erstwhile clients who do feel cheated may then turn against the machine, even if they are still more likely to receive a future payoff from the party they previously supported than from an opposing party.17 16 These questions were asked consecutively rather than as a split sample. 17 Instrumentalist models that employ a standard punishment path strategy such as grim trigger (Stokes 2005) yield similar hypotheses; however, instrumentally motivated (and thus futureoriented) voters should not rationally turn against patrons who spurn them in any one election cycle if such a party might still provide them with benefits in the future. 22 To test for the possibility that voters practice such “altruistic punishment” (Arnold 2001, Fehr and Gächter 2002), we compare responses to two separate items from our 2010 survey. The first asked whether a hypothetical voter should feel obliged to vote for a party from which she normally receives foodstuffs in exchange for support but which did not deliver anything this year. The second asked respondents whether they agreed with the statement “when someone takes advantage of me, I get them back” (which was asked without reference to politics). Those who strongly agreed with the second statement – thus demonstrating a willingness to practice altruistic punishment in general – were much more likely to think that the spurned voter should choose a rival party rather than abstain after benefits were withdrawn (chi-squared = 4.14 for three degrees of freedom, p < .05). Civic Attitudes Discourage Clientelism The extent of political clientelism clearly varies across different political contexts and a viable theory of clientelism must account for such differences. As noted above, even if feelings of obligation are activated, other feelings might diminish potential clients’ likelihood of following through on the bargain. We specifically focus on civic attitudes that prompt citizens to see clientelist exchanges as illegitimate. We present evidence from experiments that prime civic and anti-civic primes attitudes as well as mass surveys that measure the likelihood that citizens with different levels of civic values will enter into clientelist exchanges. Clever field experiments show that civic attitudes influence the effectiveness of clientelist appeals across sub-national units. For instance, Vicente (2008) demonstrated that exposure to anti-vote-buying literature in São Tomé e Príncipe increased perceptions that other people in the neighborhood were voting their conscience and reduced the extent of vote buying. In the same vein, Wantchekon (2003: fn 20) showed that Beninese villages that were randomly selected to receive nationally oriented, “programmatic” appeals were more critical of vote-buying 23 than villages that received parochial (regionally-oriented), clientelist appeals. Surveys that include adequate questions on civic attitudes and clientelism suggest a strong relationship between the two across individuals. For instance, in the 2002 Brazilian Election Study, respondents who more strongly favored democracy as a system of government were significantly more likely to believe that voters should not accept selective benefits in return for their vote (p < .01). Likewise, respondents in the Mexico 2006 Panel Study who expressed support for democracy as a system of government were more likely to reject the notion that a hypothetical third person should be willing to trade his vote for groceries (p <.01).18 In both cases, these relationships survive controls for potential confounding factors like income, education and age. (See Supporting Materials for details.) Our 2009 Mexico survey employed a split-sample experiment to test hypotheses about civic attitudes more directly. Half of respondents were asked whether they believed that it is important to live in a democracy (the civic prime) and the other half were asked whether they agreed that people did not get ahead unless they took advantage of others (the anti-civic prime). All respondents were then asked whether it would be acceptable or unacceptable for a person to give his or her vote in exchange for a job for a relative, followed by the question that the other half of the sample had received first. Thus, all respondents received the same questions, just in a different order. Despite the subtle nature of the experimental manipulation, differences between the two groups were large and significant. Whereas 36% of respondents who received 18 A separate survey in Argentina (see Stokes 2005) shows that the correlation between clientelism and civic attitudes does not reach statistical significance. This null result is the only finding that does not support our argument from any available survey that contains the requisite questions; it may be a product of the small number of respondents who believed clientelism to be legitimate (approximately 13%). 24 the anti-civic prime first were willing to accept the clientelist exchange, only 25% of those who answered the question on democracy first were similarly inclined (p < .05). As a further test, we examined both the partial effect of civic attitudes on clientelist voting and the joint effect of civic attitudes and the index of political obligation presented above on voting for a clientelist party. These results appear in Table 3 (above). We measured civic attitudes with a simple additive index of responses to items on how disappointed the respondent would be in a friend who did not pay his household electric bill, stole a soft drink from a store, did not pay bus fare, or earned money by selling marijuana.19 In logistic regression models that also control for feelings of political obligation and efficacy, household income, education, and partisan identification, the coefficient on the index of civic attitudes was correctly signed and always significant at the .1 level or better. In simulations based on this model, a voter who is typical in every way but highly civically minded would be 16% less likely to cast her lot with a clientelist party than a non-civic voter, cutting in half support for the machine. A voter who reports the highest levels of political obligation to patrons and the lowest levels of civic obligation would be more than 33% more likely to support the machine than voters who are least civic-minded and most clientelist in orientation.20 Thus, whereas feelings of obligation encourage voters to support a clientelist party, feelings of civic duty discourage them from doing so. 19 This battery has been used in a number of other surveys sponsored by the Latin American Public Opinion Project (see http://www.vanderbilt.edu/lapop/). 20 Across all models, first differences for political obligation and the joint effect of political obligation and civic duty are statistically significant at the 95% level. The effect of civic duty alone is significant at the 90% level. 25 4. Conclusion: Durable and Self-Enforcing Clientelism Scholars in the instrumentalist tradition have occasionally acknowledged that clientelist linkages can involve strong feelings of affect and duty. As Kitschelt and Wilkinson write: Continued interaction and exchange between patrons and clients over time – for example, at local celebrations – may eventually make regular monitoring of voting unnecessary because…the interaction may be sufficient to induce cultural expectations of reciprocity inherent in any gift-giving situation (2007: 15). However, instrumentalist accounts treat such examples as isolated exceptions or aberrations, rather than as manifestations of a separate, solid basis for clientelism. We argue that the obligation to reciprocate is the basis for a theoretically and empirically well-supported alternative mechanism for machine politics in a range of settings. We do not argue that instrumental calculation is unimportant for clientelism; the credible threat of sanctions and rewards is surely a fundamental feature of machine politics in many places. Rather, we suspect that there is substantial variation in the foundation of clientelism across countries (or regions within the same country). In other words, there may be places where the absence of spontaneous support necessitates close monitoring of voters by the machine, places where politicians can rely on norms of obligation to garner votes, and places where brokers find recourse to both mechanisms. The role of obligation has broad ramifications for relationships between candidates and voters. Although we have focused on voters, our argument need not be limited to the base of the machine. Precinct captains, too, may be motivated by feelings of obligation to the parties and politicians on whose behalf they operate and thus require less monitoring from their bosses. It is even possible that some types of patrons – e.g., local notables or religious figures who control discretionary resources – may take obligations to their clients seriously. Ironically, such a moral sense on the part of intermediaries and patrons would actually strengthen clientelism, 26 because brokers motivated in this fashion would be less likely to steal the funds they were to distribute (and thus have more resources to distribute) and promises made by politicians who were perceived to care about their constituents might be viewed as more credible (and thus more likely to inspire compliance on Election Day). Another implication of our findings is that the distinction between clientelist exchange and constituency service is not as clear-cut as observers might assume. Both types of interactions between politicians and constituents create a sense of obligation toward politicians who provide selective benefits. The electoral rewards of such personal exchanges make retail politics a durable element of all democracies. Self-enforcing clientelism also affects party structures. If voters spontaneously comply out of obligation, then clientelism may not require the highly organized and deeply rooted political machines that most analysts now argue is necessary (Kitschelt 2000; Kitschelt and Wilkinson 2007b; Gyrzmala-Busse 2005). For instance, Stokes (2005: 317) argues that “The typical political machine (or clientelist party) is bottom-heavy, decentralized, and relies on an army of grassroots militants.” Such elaborate structures may be useful to would-be patrons, but they may not be necessary. Personalist politicians who distribute benefits may be able to build clientelist relationships without building full-fledged monitoring apparatuses. This possibility may help explain the persistence of clientelist politics in democracies around the globe in a period when economic austerity and media-centered campaigning has diminished party density (Mair and Van Biezen 2001), transformed mass parties into “electoral-professional” ones with far fewer local activists (Panebianco 1988), and undermined traditional political machines in many countries (Levitsky 2003; Greene 2007; Weyland 1996). Finally, our conclusions have important implications for efforts to curb machine politics. One obvious strategy – with which instrumentalist approaches to clientelism would presumably agree – is to eliminate the discretionary resources available to political parties and candidates. 27 Not only would restricting the flow of selective benefits prevent politicians from generating new obligations, the withdrawal of resources could also lead voters who had come to rely on such selective benefits to rebel against the party that suddenly failed to hold up its end of the traditional bargain between patrons and clients. As long as such resources remain available, public policies designed to reinforce the secret ballot may prove insufficient to break up political machines. Rather, efforts to instill civic values also have a role to play. Where norms of obligation underwrite clientelism, machine politics faces a serious challenge if citizens come to view clientelist transactions as illegitimate, feel obligated to vote their conscience, or come to view their patrons’ largesse as a right rather than an obligation that must be repaid with political loyalty (Rossetti 1994). These shifts in mindset constitute a key part of the “difficult transition from clientelism to citizenship” (Fox 1994, Gay 2006) – a transition that is difficult precisely because it requires not only institutional reform but also attitudinal change. 28 Table 1. Observable Implications of the Reciprocity and Instrumentalist Frameworks Issue Feelings of obligation Monitoring Retrospective clientelist voting Civic attitudes Reciprocity Predictions Citizens feel an obligation to support politicians that provide them with selective benefits Greater benefits cause greater feelings of obligation Clientelism can exist despite ballot secrecy Purely retrospective voting based on previous provision of benefits Possible “altruistic” punishment for cessation of benefits Civic values undermine clientelism Instrumentalist Predictions Feelings of obligation should not affect vote choices Surveillance/lack of ballot secrecy required for clientelism to persist Retrospective considerations only matter as an indicator of future payoffs Attitudes about clientelism and civic life do not affect clientelist exchanges 29 Table 2. Degree of Felt Obligation for Benefits Offered, Mexico 2009 50 pesos Percent who felt “a lot” or “some” obligation to support politician providing gift 24.6 Mean obligation 0.78 Percent of respondents who thought it correct to accept the gift 23.9 500 pesos 28.2 0.89 24.9 Bicycle 33.8 1.00 30.2 Cement 39.7 1.15 32.4 Doctor visit 49.9 1.48 71.8 Benefit offered Note: The mean value is calculated on a scale of 0 to 3 where 0 is no obligation, 1 is little, 2 is some, and 3 is a lot. The differences between adjacent benefits in the table are not statistically significant except cement versus medical treatment for which p<.01. Differences between all other paired comparisons are statistically significant at the .01 level. 30 Table 3. Logistic Regression Models of Support for a Clientelist Party Variable Political Obligation Index Civic Attitudes Index Political efficacy SES Education PAN feeling thermometer PRD feeling thermometer PRI feeling thermometer Constant Number of cases Model 1 B SE Sig 0.10 0.04 ** -2.07 0.25 *** 314 Model 2 B SE Sig 0.09 0.04 ** -0.09 0.05 * -0.13 0.33 Model 3 B SE Sig 0.10 0.05 ** -0.08 0.05 * -0.15 0.34 -0.07 0.13 0.10 0.08 -1.12 -1.48 0.55 ** 295 0.81 * 294 Model 4 B SE 0.10 0.05 -0.10 0.05 -0.38 0.36 -0.01 0.13 0.14 0.08 -0.08 0.07 -0.03 0.06 0.05 0.06 -1.50 0.92 284 Sig ** * * Note: Dependent Variable is coded as 1 for voting for a clientelist party and 0 otherwise. * p<.1, ** p<.05, *** p<.01, two tailed tests. 31 References Allswang, John M. 1977. Bosses, Machines, and Urban Voters: An American Symbiosis. Port Washington, NY: Kennikat. Aragon, Lorraine V. 1996. “Twisting the Gift: Translating Precolonial into Colonial Exchanges in Central Sulawesi, Indonesia”, American Ethnologist, 23 (1): 43-60. Auyero, Javier. 1999. “‘From the client’s point(s) of view’: How poor people perceive and evaluate political clientelism”, Theory and Society, 28 (2): 297-334. Auyero, Javier. 2000. “The Logic of Clientelism in Argentina: An Ethnographic Account”, Latin American Research Review, 35 (3): 55-82. Auyero, Javier. 2001. Poor People’s Politics: Peronist Survival Networks and the Legacy of Evita. Durham: North Carolina: Duke University Press. Bartlett, Peggy F. 1980. “Reciprocity and the San Juan Fiesta”, Journal of Anthropological Research, 36 (1): 116-130. Berg, Joyce, John Dickhaut, and Kevin McCabe. 1995. “Trust, Reciprocity, and Social History”, Games and Economic Behavior, 10 (1): 122-142. Bienenstock, Elisa Jayne and Alison J. Bianchi. 2004. “Activating Performance Expectations and Status Differences through Gift Exchange: Experimental Results”, Social Psychology Quarterly, 67 (3): 310-18. Birch, Leann Lipps and Jane Billman. 1986. “Preschool Children's Food Sharing with Friends and Acquaintances”, Child Development, 57 (2): 387-395. Boissevain, Jeremy. 1966. “Patronage in Sicily”, Man, 1 (1): 18-33. Brusco, Valeria, Marcelo Nazareno, and Susan Stokes. 2004. “Vote Buying in Argentina”, Latin American Research Review, 39(2):66-88. Cain, Bruce, John Ferejohn, and Morris P. Fiorina. 1987. The Personal Vote: Constituency Service and Electoral Independence. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. 32 Calvo, Ernesto and María Victoria Murillo. 2004. “Who Delivers? Partisan Clients in the Argentine Electoral Market”, American Journal of Political Science, 48(4):742-757. Cambanis, Thanassis. 2006. “With Speed, Hezbollah Picks up the Shovel: Group’s Engineers, Funds Pour into War Torn Lebanon”, Boston Globe, August 19, 2006. Caplow, Theodore. 1984. “Rule Enforcement without Visible Means: Christmas Gift Giving in Middletown”, American Journal of Sociology, 89 (6): 1306-23. Carmichael, H. Lorne and W. Bentley MacLeod. 1997. “Gift Giving and the Evolution of Cooperation”, International Economic Review, 38 (3): 485-509. Centeno, Miguel Angel. 1997. Democracy within Reason: Technocratic Revolution in Mexico. 2nd Edition. University Park, PA: Penn State Press. Cesarini, David, Christopher T. Dawes, James H. Fowler, Magnus Johannesson, Paul Lichtenstein, and Björn Wallace. 2008. “Heritability of Cooperative Behavior in a Trust Game”, Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 10.1073/pnas.0710069105 (published online 3 March). Chanrda, Kanchan. 2007. “Counting Heads: A Theory of Voter and Elite Behavior in Patronage Democracies” in Patrons, Clients, and Policies: Patterns of Democratic Accountability and Political Competition. New York: Cambridge University Press, pp. 80-109. Chubb, Judith. 1982. Patronage, Power, and Poverty in Southern Italy. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press. Clapham, Christopher, ed. 1982. Private Patronage and Public Power : Political Clientelism in the Modern State. London : Frances Pinter. Cornelius, Wayne. 1975. Politics and the Migrant Poor in Mexico City. Stanford: Stanford University Press. Cox, G. W. and J. M. Kousser. 1981. “Turnout and Rural Corruption: New York as a Test Case”, American Journal of Political Science 25 (4): 646-63. 33 Dal Bó, Ernesto. 2007. “Bribing Voters”, American Journal of Political Science, 51 (4), 789–803. de Quervain, Dominique J.-F., Urs Fischbacher, Valerie Treyer, Melanie Schellhammer, Ulrich Schnyder, Alfred Buck, and Ernst Fehr. 2004. “The Neural Basis of Altruistic Punishment”, Science, 305 (5688): 1254-58. Jorge I. Domínguez, Chappell Lawson, and Alejandro Moreno, eds. 2008. Consolidating Mexico’s Democracy: The 2006 Presidential Campaign in Comparative Perspective. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press. Domínguez, Jorge I. and Chappell Lawson, eds. 2003. Mexico’s Pivotal Democratic Election: Candidates, Voters, and the Presidential Campaign of 2000. Stanford and La Jolla, CA: Stanford University Press and Center for U.S.-Mexican Studies, University of California at San Diego). Dreman, S. B. and Charles W. Greenbaum. 1973. “Altruism or Reciprocity? Sharing Behavior in Israeli Kindergarten Children”, Child Development, 44 (1): 61-8 Eisenstadt, S. N. and R. Lamarchand, eds. 1981. Political Clientelism, Patronage, and Development. Beverly Hills, CA; Sage. Eisenstadt, S. N. and Luis Roniger. 1984. Patrons, Clients, and Friends: Interpersonal Relations and the Structure of Trust in Society. New York: Cambridge University Press. Elster, Jon. 1989. The Cement of Society: A Study of Social Order. New York: Cambridge University Press. Erie, Steven P. 1988. Rainbow’s End: Irish-Americans and the Dilemmas of Urban Machine Politics. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press. Fehr, Ernst and Urs Fischbacher. 2002. “Why Social Preferences Matter: The Impact of NonSelfish Motives on Competition, Cooperation, and Incentives”, The Economic Journal, 112 (478): C1-C33. Fehr, Ernst and Simon Gächter. 2000. “Fairness and Retaliation: The Economics of 34 Reciprocity”, Journal of Economic Perspectives, 14 (3): 159-81. Fehr, Ernst and Simon Gächter. 2002. “Alturistic Punishment in Humans”, Nature, 415: 137-40. Fenno, Jr., Rochard. 1978. Home Style: House Members in their Districts. 1978. New York: Little, Brown. Finan, Federico and Laura Schechter. 2009. “Vote-Buying and Reciprocity”. Typescript, accessed March 9, 2009, http://www.econ.ucla.edu/ffinan/Finan_Votebuying.pdf,. Fiorina, Morris P. 1981. Retrospective Voting in American National Elections. New Haven: Yale University Press. Fiorina, Morris P. and David Rohde, eds. 1989. Home Style and Washington Work. Ann Arbor, MI: University of Michigan Press. Fowler, James H., Laura A Baker, and Christopher T. Dawes. 2008. “Genetic Variation in Political Participation”, Scientific American, in process. Fox, Jonathan. 1994. “The Difficult Transition from Clientelism to Citizenship: Lessons from Mexico”, World Politics, 46: 151-84. Fukui, Haruhiro and Shigeko N. Fukai. 1996. “Pork Barrel Politics, Networks, and Local Economic Development in Contemporary Japan”, Asian Survey, 36 (3): 268-286. Gächter, Simon and Benedikt Herrmann. 2008. "Reciprocity, culture, and human cooperation: Previous insights and a new cross-cultural experiment," Discussion Papers 2008-14, The Centre for Decision Research and Experimental Economics, School of Economics, University of Nottingham. Gay, Robert. 1994. Popular Organization and Democracy in Rio de Janeiro. Philadelphia: Temple University Press. Gay, Robert. 1998. “Rethinking Clientelism: Demands, Discourses, and Practices in Contemporary Brazil” European Review of Latin American and Caribbean Studies 65: 724. 35 Gay, Robert. 2006. “The Even More Difficult Transition from Clientelism to Citizenship: Lessons from Brazil”, in Patricia Fernández-Kelly and Jon Shefner, eds., Out of the Shadows: Political Action and the Informal Economy in Latin America. State College, PA: Pennsylvania State University Press, pp. 195-217. Gintis, Herbert, Samuel Bowles, Robert Boyd, and Ernest Fehr. 2003. “Explaining Altruistic Behavior in Humans”, Evolution and Human Behavior, 24 (3): 153-72. Golden, Miriam A. 2003. “Electoral Connections: The Effects of the Personal Vote on Political Patronage, Bureaucracy and Legislation in Postwar Italy”, British Journal of Political Science, 33: 189-212. Gosnell, Harold F. 1937. Machine Politics: The Chicago Model. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Greene, Kenneth F. 2007. Why Dominant Parties Lose: Mexico’s Democratization in Comparative Perspective. New York: Cambridge University Press. Grohol, J.M. (Feb 1999). Detecting deception: A quick review of the psychological research. [Online]. http://psychcentral.com/archives/deception.htm. Hammerstein, Peter, ed. 2003. Genetic and Cultural Evolution of Cooperation. Cambridge, MA: M.I.T. Press. Harik, Judith Palmer. 2004. Hezbollah: The Changing Face of Terrorism. New York: I. B. Tauris. Harris, Mary B. 1970. “Reciprocity and Generosity: Some Determinants of Sharing in Children”, Child Development, 41 (2): 313-328. Heinrich, Joseph, et al. 2005. “Economic Man in Cross-Cultural Perspective: Behavioral Experiments in 15 Small-Scale Societies”, Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 28; 795-815. Herrmann, Benedikt, Christian Thöni, and Simon Gächter. 2008. “Antisocial Punishment Across Societies”, Science, 319 (5868): 1362-7. Johnson, Colleen Leahy. 1974. “Gift Giving and Reciprocity among the Japanese Americans in 36 Honolulu”, American Ethnologist, 1 (2): 295-308. Kinder, Donald R., and D. Roderick Kiewiet. 1979. “Economic Discontent and Political Behavior: The Role of Personal Grievances and Collective Judgments in Congressional Voting”, American Journal of Political Science, 23 (2): 495-527. King, Gary, Christopher Murray, Joshua Salomon, and Ajay Tandon. 2004. “Enhancing the Validity and Cross-Cultural Comparability of Measurement in Survey Research” American Political Science Review 98, 1: 191-207. Kitschelt, Herbert and Arturas Rozenas. 2011. “Contingent exchange and Contractual Opportunism: Making Clientelistic Relationships Work”. Manuscript presented at the “Workshop on democratic Accountability Strategies”, May 18-19, Duke University, Durham, NC. Accessed online at http://duke.edu/~kkk4/2011_clientelism/Rozenas_2_4_Contingent_Exchange.pdf, August 17, 2011. Kitschelt, Herbert and Steven Wilkinson, eds. 2007a. Patrons, Clients, and Policies: Patterns of Democratic Accountability and Political Competition. New York: Cambridge University Press. Kitschelt, Herbert and Steven I. Wilkinson. 2007b. “Citizen-politician linkages: an introduction,” in Herbert Kitschelt and Steven I. Wilkinson, eds., Patrons, Clients, and Policies. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 1-49. Klosko, George. 1990. “The Moral Force of Political Obligations”, American Political Science Review, 84 (4): 1235-50. Kohnken, G. (1987). Training police officers to detect deceptive eye witness statements: Does it work? Social Behavior, 2, 1-17. Komito, Lee. 1984. “Irish Clientelism: A Reappraisal” Economic and Social Review 15 (3):17394. 37 Kraut, R.E., & Poe, D. (1980). Behavioral roots of person perception: The deception judgments of customs inspectors and laymen. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 39, 784-798. Krishna, A. 2007. “Politics in the Middle: Mediating Relationships between the Citizens and the State in Rural North India,” in Herbert Kitschelt and Steven I. Wilkinson, eds., Patrons, Clients, and Policies. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. pp. 141-158. Latinobarómetro. 2007. Informe Latinobarómetro (November). Accessed March 9, 2009 http://www.latinobarometro.org/. Lawson, Chappell and James McCann. 2003. “An Electorate Adrift? Public Opinion and the Quality of Democracy in Mexico”, Latin American Research Review, 38 (3): 60-81. Lawson, Chappell, et al. 2007. The Mexico 2006 Panel Study. http://web.mit.edu/polisci/research/mexico06. Lemarchand, René. 1972. “Political Clientelism and Ethnicity in Tropical Africa: Competing Solidarities in Nation-Building”, American Political Science Review, 66 (2): 68-90. Lemarchand, René and Keith Legg. 1972. “Political Clientelism and Development: A Preliminary Analysis”, Comparative Politics, 4 (2): 149-178. Levitsky, Steven. 2003. “From Labor Politics to Machine Politics: The Transformation of PartyUnion Linkages in Argentine Peronism, 1983-1999”, Latin American Research Review, 38 (3): 3-36. Lomnitz, Larissa Adler. 1982. “Horizontal and Vertical Relations and the Structure of Urban Mexico”, Latin American Research Review, 16 (2): 51-74. Lomnitz, Larissa Adler. 1988. “Informal Exchange Networks in Formal Systems: A Theoretical Model”, American Anthropologist, 90: 42-55. Mair, Peter and Ingrid Van Biezen. 2001. “Party Membership in Twenty European Democracies, 1980-2000” Party Politics 7 (1), 5-21. 38 Mauss, M. 1990. The Gift. New York: W. W. Norton. McCabe, Kevin A., Daniel Houser, Lee Ryan, Vernon Smith, and Theodore Trouard. 2001. “A Functional Imaging Study of Cooperation in Two-Person Reciprocal Exchange,” Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 98: 11832-11835. McCabe, Kevin A., Mary L. Rigdon, and Vernon L. Smith. 1996. “Game theory and reciprocity in some extensive form experimental games”, Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 93(23): 13421–13428. McCabe, Kevin A., Mary L. Rigdon, and Vernon L. Smith. 2003. “Positive reciprocity and intentions in trust games” Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization 52 (2):267-75. Nichter, Simeon. 2008. “Vote Buying or Turnout Buying? Machine Politics and the Secret Ballot”, American Political Science Review 102 (February): 19-31. Ostrogorski, Moisei. 1910. Democracy and the Party System in the United States: A Study in Extra-Constitutional Government. New York: Macmillan. Panebianco, Angelo. 1988. Political Parties: Organization and Power. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Pfeiffer, Silke, Frederic C. Schaffer, Claudio Weber Abramo, and Leslie Busby. 2004. “Vote buying” in Global Corruption Report 2004. London: Transparency International. Ch. 5. Powell, John Duncan. 1970. “Peasant Society and Clientelist Politics”, American Political Science Review, 64(2): 411-425. Radnitz, Scott. 2010. Weapons of the Wealthy: Predatory regimes and Elite-Led Protests in Central Asia. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press. Rao, Vijayendra. 2001. “Poverty and Public Celebration in Rural India”, Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science. Culture and Development: International Perspectives, 573: 85-104 Roniger, Luis. 1990. Hierarchy and Trust in Modern Mexico and Brazil. New York: Praeger. 39 Roniger, Luis and A. Günes-Ayata, eds. 1994. Democracy, Clientelism, and Civil Society. Boulder, Colorado: Lynne Rienner. Rossetti, Carlo. 1994. “Constitutionalism and Clientelism in Italy”, in Luis Roniger and A. GünesAyata, eds., Democracy, Clientelism, and Civil Society. Boulder, CO: Lynne Rienner. Sanfey, Alan G., James K. Rilling, Jessica A. Aronson, Leigh E. Nystrom, and Jonathan D. Cohen. 2003. “The neural basis of economic decision making in the ultimatum game”, Science, 300: 1755-1757. Schaffer, Frederic and Andreas Schedler. 2007. “What is Vote Buying?” in F. Schaffer, ed. Elections for Sale: The Causes and Consequences of Vote Buying. Boulder, CO: Lynne Rienner, pp. 17-30. Schaffer, Frederic, ed. 2007. Elections for Sale: The Causes and Consequences of Vote Buying. Boulder, CO: Lynne Rienner. Scheiner, E. 2007. “Clientelism in Japan: The Importance and Limits of Institutional Explanations,” in Herbert Kitschelt and Steven I. Wilkinson, eds., Patrons, Clients, and Policies. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 276-297. Scott, James C. 1972. “Patron-Client Politics and Political Change in Southeast Asia,” American Political Science Review, 66: 91-113. Scott, James C. 1976. The Moral Economy of the Peasant; Rebellion and Subsidence in Southeast Asia. New Haven: Yale University Press. Simmel, Georg and Kurt H. Wolff. 1950. The Sociology of Georg Simmel. Glencoe: Free Press. Stokes, Susan 2005. “Perverse Accountability: A Formal Model of Machine Politics with Evidence from Argentina” American Political Science Review, 99(3):315-325. Stokes, Susan. 2007. “Political Clientelism.” In C. Boix and S. Stokes (ed.) Oxford Handbook of Comparative Politics. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Trivers, Robert L. 1971. “The Evolution of Reciprocal Altruism”, Quarterly Review of Biology, 46 40 (1): 35-57. Wang, Chin-Shou. 2007. “Dilemmas of Electoral Clientelism: Taiwan, 1993”, International Political Science Review, 28(2): 225-245. Wantchekon, Leonard. 2003. “Clientelism and Voting Behavior: Evidence from a Field Experiment in Benin”, World Politics, 55 (3): 399-422. Weinstein, Eugene A., William L. DeVaughan, and Mary Glenn Wiley. 1969. “Obligation and the Flow of Deference in Exchange”, Sociometry, 32 (1): 1-12. Yan, Yunxiang. 1996. The Flow of Gifts: Reciprocity and Social Networks in a Chinese Village. Stanford: Stanford University Press. Yiannakis, Diane Evans. 1981. “The Grateful Electorate: Casework and Congressional Elections”, American Journal of Political Science, 25 (3): 568-80. Van de Walle, N. 2007. “Meet the new boss, same as the old boss? The evolution of political clientelism in Africa,” in H. Kitschelt and S. Wilkinson, eds., Patrons, Clients, and Policies. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 50-67. Vicente, Pedro C. 2008. “Is Vote Buying Effective? Evidence from a Field Experiment in West Africa”. Unpublished manuscript, accessed March 4, 2009 http://faculty.ucr.edu/~jorgea/econ261/africa.pdf. Vicente, Pedro and Leonard Wantchekon. 2009. “Clientelism and Vote Buying: Lessons From Field Experiments in African Elections” Oxford Review of Economic Policy 25, 2: 292– 305. 41 Supporting Materials In these supporting materials, we present details on the Mexico 2009 and Mexico 2010 Clientelism surveys as well as supplemental analyses that are referred to in the main text. 1. Mexico Clientelism surveys 2009 Mexico Clientelism Survey The 2009 survey consists of 545 completed interviews with Spanish-speaking Mexican adults, in six purposively selected sites in the Federal District (Mexico City) and Mexico State (including areas within the greater Mexico City metropolitan area). Areas were selected for high levels of electoral competition between different parties (PRI-PAN, PAN-PRD, PRD-PRI, and PRI-PANPRD). Interviews were conducted during September 5-11, 2009 and September 19-21, 2009 by the firm Data Opinión Pública y Mercados. Eighty percent of interviews were supervised (70% at the time of the interview, 10% afterward). 2010 Mexico Clientelism Survey The 2010 survey consisted of 352 completed interviews with adult, Spanish-speaking Mexicans at four purposively chosen points in the Mexico City metropolitan area. Areas were selected for high levels of electoral competition between different parties (PRI-PAN, PAN-PRD, PRD-PRI), with a focus on lower-middle class or poor neighborhoods where some vote-buying is likely. Interviews were conducted during August 2010 by the firm Data Opinión Pública y Mercados. Items in the 2010 survey were similar to those in 2009, with the exception that certain experimental questions that failed to generate an adequate response (e.g., a “blank ballot question asking respondents to name the price they would charge for their vote) or were judged confusing by interviewers in 2009 were excluded. As in 2009, 80% of interviews were supervised (75% at the time and 5% afterwards); to avoid frightening residents in high-crime 42 zones, in some cases the supervisor was stationed in site of the interview but was not physically next to the interviewer during the interview. Typical polling sites for both are shown below: 43 2. Comparison of treatment groups on variables of interest Because the surveys were paper-and-pencil, automated random assignment of interviewees to treatment groups was not possible. Randomization was accomplished by interspersing the survey forms that were then used by interviewers. Because a small number of interviews were not completed and because interviewers could have inadvertently reordered the questionnaires, we performed the following ex post checks to verify that randomization “worked” on the spit-sample items referred to in the text (all from the 2009 survey). Table A1. Treatment versus Control Groups I Candidate offers Gabriel/a 50 pesos vs. 500 pesos for his/her vote Variable Group A Group B Mean Std Dev Mean Std Dev Age 44.7 16.3 43.8 17.1 Self-reported insufficiency of household income 2.83 .89 2.71 .82 Percent female 57% -58% -Skin color (interviewer-coded); higher = darker 2.43 .78 2.42 .80 Education 5.28 2.44 5.06 2.36 Social class (interviewer-coded, inverse) 3.90 .85 3.94 .87 Percent with refrigerator in home 38% 34% Percent voted in July 2009 midterm elections 71% 71% Efficacy (% saying politics not too complicated) 53% 53% Believes vote is secret 76% 79% Attends church once per week or more .39 .49 .43 .50 Note: N = 545. No differences significant at p < .1 except income (p = .09). In this split-sample experiment, Group B (in which Gabriel received the 500 peso offer) scored slightly higher self-reported insufficiency scale (meaning they felt more financially squeezed). If income affects willingness to accept a clientelist payoff, this disparity in income would tend to increase the differences between the two group (however slightly). Group B did not score significantly lower on measures of social class or household item ownership. Because income insufficiency was asked later in the questionnaire and was subjectively self-reported, a treatment effect on income (i.e., asking about a higher peso amount subsequently affected respondents’ views of their own income insufficiency) cannot be ruled out. 44 Table A2. Treatment versus Control Groups II Retrospective voting: Will construct medical clinic vs. did construct medical clinic Variable Group A Group B Mean Std Dev Mean Std Dev Age 45 16.8 43 16.6 Self-reported insufficiency of household income 2.75 .82 2.79 .89 Percent female 58% 58% Skin color (interviewer-coded); higher = darker 2.41 .78 2.44 .80 Education 5.01 2.37 5.33 2.43 Social class (interviewer-coded) 3.89 .87 3.9 .84 Percent with refrigerator in home 37% 32% Percent voted in July 2009 midterm elections 71% 71% Efficacy (% saying politics not too complicated) 52% 54% Believes vote is secret 79% 76% Attends church once per week or more 42% 40% Note: N = 545. No differences significant at p < .1. Table A3. Treatment versus Control Groups III Civic values experiment: receives civic prime first vs. anti-civic prime first Variable Group A Mean Std Dev Age 45.1 16.5 Self-reported insufficiency of household income 2.83 .86 Percent female 57% Skin color (interviewer-coded); higher = darker 2.45 .76 Education 5.03 2.40 Social class (interviewer-coded) 3.92 .83 Percent with refrigerator in home 35% Percent voted in July 2009 midterm elections 72% Efficacy (% saying politics not too complicated) 51% Believes vote is secret 79% Attends church once per week or more 42% How disappointed R would be in friend who sold his 1.53 1.45 vote (inverse scale) Percent who would be very disappointed in a friend 79% who sold his vote Note: N = 545. No differences significant at p < .1. Group B Mean Std Dev 43.4 16.9 2.71 .85 59% 2.40 .82 5.31 2.40 3.92 .88 34% 70% 55% 77% 42% 1.58 1.54 81% 45 3. Supplemental Analyses Obligation On page 16 in the main text, we argued that “survey data from Brazil show that citizens are willing to carry through on vote-selling transactions, even when the questions asked do not imply any policing of voters’ behavior.” In the 2002 Brazil Election Study, the relevant question read: I am going to read you various scenarios and would like you to say what a person SHOULD do something and what a person WOULD do. i. A candidate offers a handicapped person a wheelchair a. Accept the wheelchair and vote for the candidate, OR b. Not accept the wheelchair and vote for another candidate ii. A candidate offers a bag of groceries to a very poor and hungry family… iii. A mother cannot get a place for her child in school. A candidate obtains a place for the child… iv. A candidate offers a mother with a sick son money for his medical treatment… v. A candidate offers a truckload of bricks for several families to finish building their homes… vi. A candidate offers to remodel a soccer field for a group of friends who get together to play soccer each week… vii. A candidate offers a bicycle for a child… Respondents were asked whether the person should (or would) accept the gift and vote for the politician in question. They were thus not given the option of accepting the gift and not supporting the party who gave it, nor were they allowed to assume that the politician might renege on giving the gift if the prospective voter accepted. The results are reported in Table A1. 46 Table A4: Feelings of Obligation in Brazil Should accept the gift and vote for candidate Hypothetical Benefit offered Don’t recipient is.. is… Yes No know Would accept the gift and vote for candidate Don’t Yes No know Handicapped person Wheelchair 40% 54% 6% 76% 17% 7% Poor family Groceries 47% 48% 5% 81% 13% 6% Mother Spot in school for her child 52% 43% 5% 82% 13% 5% 61% 35% 4% 86% 10% 5% 46% 50% 5% 80% 15% 6% 39% 56% 5% -- -- -- 30% 65% 5% -- -- -- Mother Family Group of friends Parents Medical care for her child Truckload of bricks for homes Refurbish a soccer field Bicycle for their child In Table A4, all differences are significant at the 1% level for whether recipients should accept the gift and vote for the candidate, except the differences between “Groceries” and “Truckload of bricks” and “Wheelchair” and “Refurbish a soccer field”, which are significant at the 5% level. For whether recipients would accept the gift, all differences are significant at the 1% level except the difference between “Groceries” and “Spot in school” (p = .97). All differences between “would” and “should” answers are significant for each question at the 1% level. (N = 2,513.) A similar battery of questions, mentioned on p. 11 of the text, was asked in the Mexico 2006 Panel Study (Lawson et al. 2007). The question (from Wave 3 of the panel survey) read: (INTERVIEWER: USE “Gabriel” IF MALE INTERVIEWEE AND “Gabriela” IF FEMALE INTERVIEWEE) Let’s imagine that there is a person named Gabriel/Gabriela who is a person like you and lives in a community like yours. A representative of a political party ... (READ OUT SCENARIOS) In your opinion, how much of an obligation should Gabriel/Gabriela feel to vote for this political party – a lot, some, a little, or none? a. throws a party for Gabriel(a)’s community 47 b. gives money to Gabriel(a) to buy a week’s groceries c. promises to build a sewage system in Gabriel(a)’s community if he wins the election in that neighborhood Because the panel structure of the sample was complex, and some questions were only included in some waves, we report separately the results for different subsamples. Table A5: Feelings of Obligation in Mexico Cross-section that accompanied Wave 2 (N = 305) Obligation induced by… A lot Some Neighborhood party 23.6 17.4 Money for groceries 28.5 16.7 Paving streets (retrospective) 28.9 18.7 Sewage (prospective) 31.8 18.7 Employment (prospective) 32.8 19.9 Little 10.8 8.5 12.1 13.1 9.2 None 40.3 39.3 33.4 29.5 32.5 Don’t know 7.9 6.9 6.9 6.9 6.2 Mean 1.3 1.4 1.5 1.6 1.6 Panel Wave 3, all respondents including Mexico City and rural oversamples (N = 1,594) Obligation induced by… A lot Some Little None Don’t know Mean Neighborhood party 17.5 14.7 10.9 50.8 6.1 1.0 Money for groceries 24.0 12.6 8.6 48.7 6.1 1.1 Sewage (prospective) 25.5 18.4 10.8 39.6 5.7 1.3 Panel Wave 3, national sample only (N = 1,067) Obligation induced by… A lot Some Neighborhood party 17.4 15.1 Money for groceries 24.1 13.0 Sewage (prospective) 25.5 19.5 Little 11.5 8.9 11.0 None 51.7 49.1 39.9 Don’t know 4.2 4.9 4.1 Mean 1.0 1.1 1.3 In Table A5, means are a weighted average of the responses, excluding “don’t know” answers, where “a lot” = 3 and “none” = 0. Differences in means within each sample in the third wave are statistically significant at the 1% level. For the Cross-Section in Wave 2 (first set of rows), all differences are significant at the 5% level or better and three are not significant (“Neighborhood party” and “Money for groceries”, “Money for groceries” and “Paving streets”, and “Sewage” and “Employment”). Aside from the surveys mentioned in the text, we are unaware of any surveys from other countries that contain items which could be used for this sort of analysis. In p. 11 of the text, we report that: “ the more recipients said that the gifts mattered to them, the greater the obligation they felt to support the party providing it (r = .51, p < .01, N = 48 79).” Data are taken from the third wave of the Mexico 2006 Panel Study, in which the following series of questions was included: Over the last weeks, has a representative of a political party or candidate given you a gift, money, food, subsidy or any other type of help? Which party or candidate was it? (INTERVIEWER: AFTER EACH, ASK) What did they give you? (INTERVIEWER: MARK ALL MENTIONS) Would you say this gift or assistance from the party or candidate mattered a lot to you, mattered somewhat to you, or didn’t matter to you? In appreciation of the gift or assistance, how obliged would you say you felt to vote for the candidate who gave it -- very, somewhat, a little, or not at all? The full results from the panel, which includes the national sample plus the rural and Mexico City oversamples (N = 1594), are shown in Table A6 (below). Rows do not necessarily sum to the total because four respondents received more than one type of gift from a party. Table A6: Gifts from parties and candidates in Mexico 2006 Panel Study Number of Number saying Number feeling “some” respondents gift mattered or “a lot” of an obligation receiving “some” or “a to support the party gifts lot” giving the gift Money 6 2 1 Meals (alimentos) 1 0 0 Bag of groceries (despensa) 25 13 5 Token gift (obsequio) 43 7 5 Other good or service 10 3 2 Don’t remember / Didn’t answer 3 3 1 Total number of respondents 84 28 14 receiving at least one gift Effect of civic values On p. 20-21 of the text, we argued that respondents in Brazil “who more strongly favored democracy as a system of government were significantly more likely to believe that voters should not accept selective benefits in return for their vote.” To test this claim, we used data 49 from the above items for Brazil (from the 2002 Brazil Election Study); the dependent variable is an additive index of responses to whether people should accept the following benefits in exchange for their vote; it is measured on an eight-point scale. The statistical model includes a series of explanatory variables: education; age; income as measured by the log of the quantity total monthly household income divided by the number of people in the household (the scale ranges approximately from .6 to 10); opinion of democracy as measured by how much the respondent agreed or disagreed with the following statement (on a five-point scale): “Democracy may have its problems, but it is better than other forms of government”; and an index of “Rouba-mais-faz” which is an additive sum of responses to a series of items on how much corruption the respondent appeared willing to accept in public life (Q105a-k); it ranged from 1 to 45. The second column of Table A7 shows the results of OLS regressions with p-values in parentheses. The results hold when the “Rouba-mais-faz” index is excluded. [Data not shown.] Table A7: Voters’ Orientations toward Clientelism in Brazil and Mexico Variable Brazil 2002 Mexico 2006 Education level .24 .11 (.01) (.00) Income .18 .01 (.01) (.45) Age range -.13 -.04 (.01) (.05) Support for democracy .46 .20 (.00) (.00) “Rouba-mais-faz” index .07 -(.00) N 1,882 1,326 R-squared .13 .08 Second, we argued that “respondents in the Mexico 2006 Panel Study who expressed support for democracy as a system of government were more likely to reject the notion that a third person (“Gabriel”) should be willing to trade his vote for groceries.” To test this claim, we used data from the Mexico 2006 Panel Study (Lawson et al., 2007) 50 described above. Specifically, we constructed an index using a four-point scale of responses to the question about how much obligation a third person should feel to vote for a party that had provided him or her with groceries for the week. That is, only answers to the second item (b) in the battery were used; however, the results are similar for an additive index of responses to all three questions. [Results not shown.] The explanatory variables are similar to those used in the Brazil model and include education, age, income (measured by in a ten-point scale),21 and opinion of democracy as measured by how much respondents agreed or disagreed with the statement: “For me it is very important to live in a democracy” (also on a five-point scale). The third column of Table A4 shows the results of OLS regressions with p-values in parentheses. Aside from the surveys mentioned in the text, we are unaware of any surveys from any other countries that contain items which could be used for this sort of analysis. 21 The non-effect of income in Mexico persists in a range of specifications and with different proxies for living standards. [Data not shown.] 51