Ignorance and Obligation Albert Lenel 2 The topic of my paper stems from an article by H. A. Prichard, ''Duty and Ignorance of Fact." In this article, Prichard raises important questions concerning obligations. The basic question is whether obligations arise from certain characteristics a situation has (i.e. objective characteristics) or whether obligations arise from characteristics a moral agent thinks a situation has (i.e. subjective characteristics). In considering this question, Prichard begins with the following example. Suppose see a man who looks like he has just fainted and I believe that if shout, I might revive him. I might wonder if I have a duty to shout, because I might wonder whether he really has fainted, or whether shouting really would revive him. It seems obvious that my doubt about my duty stems from my doubt about the objective facts (i.e. what really is the case) and not from any doubts about what I think is the case. In such a situation, I might wonder whether shouting really will help and thus whether it is my duty to shout, but something would certainly be wrong if instead l wondered whether I thought shouting would help and then based my duty on what I thought. We would hesitate to say that I did my duty if I ignored the person who fainted because I thought shouting would disturb him, though actually it would have revived him. We might agree that I thought I was doing my duty, but not that I was doing it. This example provides some justification for an objective view of obligations. It leads, however, to further difficulties, as Prichard points out. One problem is that we can never know for certain that the objective facts of a situation are such 3 that a certain moral rule applies. Also, we can never know that our actions will bring about the desired results. This brings us to an undesirable conclusion. We can never know that we have a particular duty, or even that we (or anyone else) has ever had a duty. From this conclusion we can go on to prove that we can never do a duty because it’s a duty - or because we know it's a duty - simply because we can never know what our duties are. Yet another unwanted result of the objective view of duties is shown by the following example. Suppose in the past I performed an action out of malice. Prof. Prichard uses the fainting man example again. In this case, the man faints, but I think he is asleep. Out of malice (this is my sole motive) I shout at him, hoping to disturb his slumber. He had in fact fainted, however. My shouting did not disturb him as intended, but actually revived him. Thus, the case resembles the original example concerning the objective facts: a man faints and I revive him. In the first example, however, I am trying to revive him (i.e. I am trying to do my duty). In the second case, I am trying to disturb him (i.e. I am not trying to do my duty). Yet if the straightforward objective view is held, the two cases must both be examples of my doing my duty (since my duty was to revive the fainting man). It seems clear, however, that the two examples are very different. Doing one's duty accidentally, while trying not to do it (or at least not trying to do it), doesn’t seem nearly as commendable as doing one's duty on purpose. Prichard also considers something similar to the following case. Suppose we are about to enter an expressway from a blind on - ramp. Should we slow down in order to merge with traffic? If there is, in fact, no traffic, the objective view would 4 imply that there was no obligation to slow down. Certainly this is mistaken. Whether there is traffic or not, we should slow down, just in case there is traffic. Here, the subjective view seems much more appropriate. Since we do not know whether there is traffic or not, we should slow down. It is not the objective facts of the case which bring about this obligation (or there wouldn't be one). The obligation arises from what we think the characteristics of the situation are (e.g. that there might be traffic.) Not only are there examples in which an obligation arises from the subjective characteristics of the case (as above), but there are also examples in which an obligation does not arise because of the subjective characteristics of the case. In our ethics class, we considered the following example. 1. There is an obligation to render aid. (This is assumed.) 2. A needs aid. 3. B does hot know that A needs aid. In this example, B is not obligated to help A because he doesn't know that A needs help. Thus, what might have been an obligation (according to the objective view) is not an obligation according to the subjective view. A more concrete example might be more convincing. Suppose A is drowning in his pool. B could easily save A, but because there is a fence around the pool and A is drowning very quietly, B does not know that A is in any distress. Is B obligated to save A in this situation? I hope it seems clear that he is not. The reason B is not obligated is that he is ignorant of a relevant non-moral fact (e.g. that A needs help.) 5 These examples show what Prichard meant by the subjective view. Before continuing with some problems for this view, it should be pointed out that Pilchard is not advocating other forms of subjectivism. Most importantly, Prichard is not advocating a totally subjective view of moral laws (moral facts, or obligations). He is not suggesting that our obligations are only what we think they are. Prichard uses the example of torturing heretics. Though the people who tortured heretics may have believed they were obligated to do so, they were wrong. Nor can they be excused because they thought they were so obligated. The example of the heretic - torturers also involves ignorance. In this case, the torturers were not ignorant of the non-moral facts. They knew that they were causing intense suffering in others, and they did it intentionally. They were ignorant of the fact that they were doing something wrong, however. The ignorance is of a moral fact. They knew what the non-moral facts were, but yet were ignorant of a moral fact. Prichard refutes such a subjective view. Certainly he is right in this case. Some Nazis thought they were doing their duty by killing Jews. But, though they thought this was their duty, they were wrong. In this sense, duties (obligations and moral facts) are objective. Now Prichard is involved in dichotomy. His subjective view must allow that ignorance of a non-moral fact excuses one from an obligation (or even prevents the obligation from arising). The objective nature of his view on moral facts 6 (obligations, etc.), however, must allow that ignorance of a moral fact does not excuse one from an obligation. To make matters clearer, I will expand upon the example used from class. 1. There is an obligation to render aid. (This is an assumption.) 2. A needs aid. 3. B does not know that A needs aid. 4. C does know that A needs aid, but 5. C does not know that there is an obligation to render aid. Therefore, B has no obligation to help A because B is ignorant of a relevant nonmoral fact. C, however, is obligated to help A (though he doesn't know it) because ignorance of moral fact is no excuse. In this example, Prichard’s position seems intuitively correct. I'm not sure it will work so well with more complicated cases. Suppose the correct moral fact on abortion, for example, is that it is murder and should be regarded as such. Next, suppose Judith Thompson (who argues very effectively for the position that a woman has a stronger right over her body than the fetus, and thus should be allowed to have an abortion if she freely chooses to do so) chooses to have an abortion. She is not ignorant of any non-moral fact. She may even regard the fetus as a person, and she knows she is going to have it killed. She also has a mistaken belief that her right over her body is stronger than the fetus' right to life (i.e. she believes a false moral proposition). Prichard would have to maintain that if she has an abortion, she is as morally blameworthy as any other murderer, since ignorance of a moral law is no excuse. 7 Perhaps this example is not as clear as I'd like, but something appears to be wrong here. It’s not as if she refused to think about the relevant moral facts. Thompson worked very hard at arriving at what she believed is a correct moral principle, and then she lived by it. Though she is ignorant of a moral fact (by hypothesis), she did her best to find out what the correct moral facts were. In this case, I find Prichard’s position somewhat unfair. As Reid says, “When a man must act . . . he ought surely to use all the means in his power to be rightly informed. When he has done so, he may still be in error; but it is an invincible error, and cannot justly be imputed to him as a fault”1 There are clearer examples which show that Prichard's position must be modified. Consider again the example with subjects A, B, and C. C was said to be obligated to help A, whether C knew the moral fact, “There is an obligation to render aid,'' or not. But what if C is a seven year child? Perhaps C hasn't been given a chance to learn this obligation yet. What if C was brought up by psychotic parents and never received any moral education? Or perhaps C is braindamaged or severely retarded. In these cases, it seems clear that C’s ignorance, even of a moral fact, excuses him from his obligation. Prichard’s view seemed very attractive at first, but what can be done about these 1. Human Acts, Eric D'Arcy, p. 113. 8 apparent difficulties? If these examples really are counter-examples to Prichard’s view, what is it about them that make them exceptional cases? Prichard does allow that ignorance of a non-moral fact can be an excuse, as seen by the example with A, B, and C. B is excused from an obligation to help A (who's in need of aid) because he is ignorant of A's situation (i.e. ignorant of a non-moral fact). Before considering the problems encountered with examples of ignorance of a moral fact, consider which cases of ignorance of a non-moral fact excuse someone from an obligation (or prevent the obligation from even arising). Is ignorance of a non-moral fact always an excuse? Eric D’Arcy, in his book, Human Acts, brings up the example of a motorist again. Earlier I argued for a subjective view of obligation because it is obvious that, for example, when entering an expressway from a blind on-ramp, one should slow down to merge with traffic, whether there actually is any traffic or not. D'Arcy uses the same type of example to point out an entirely different fact. Suppose a motorist entire an expressway from a blind on-ramp without bothering to check for traffic or slow down. In D'Arcy's example, he makes it clear that the motorist realizes the need to check for traffic and slow down. Despite this realization, the motorist feels like risking it, zooms onto the expressway, and runs a V. W. Beetle off the road. Would Prichard argue that the motorist's ignorance of the non-moral fact that there was a V.W. in the way precluded him from having any obligation toward the V.W.? If it is only the agent’s thoughts about the situation that matter, and the 9 agent wasn't aware of the V.W., how could he be under any obligation? Surely Prichard would not say that. Prichard’s argument for allowing ignorance of a non-moral f act as an excuse only applies in certain cases. D’Arcy also gives an example of a case of omission in which ignorance of a non-moral fact is no excuse. A surgeon begins to operate without first making sure of the patient’s heart condition. If this results in injury to the patient, the surgeon is morally blameworthy even though he was ignorant of the non-moral fact (e.g. the patient's heart condition). One minor difficulty concerns D'Arcy's distinction between deeds and omissions. D’Arcy claims the driving example and the example of a hunter shooting without checking carefully what's moving are deeds in which ignorance is no excuse. The surgeon example and the example of a lighthouse keeper who finishes a card game though he cannot remember if he is due back are given as examples of omissions in which ignorance is no excuse. But in all four examples, something is omitted (e.g. checking traffic, checking what's moving, checking the patient's heart, and checking what time one is due back) and something is done (in ignorance) (e.g. entering a road, shooting at some movement, operating on the patient, and playing cards). All these examples do point to the fact that ignorance of a non-moral fact is not always an excuse. But all four examples seem to be both omissions (omitting getting the facts) and deeds (proceeding without important relevant facts despite the knowledge of their importance). At any rate, this minor objection doesn't change the overall picture. 10 What is it about these four examples that nullifies the excuse (i.e. why isn’t ignorance an excuse in these examples?). All of these examples are examples of negligence. The agent knows his act might be harmful, yet he doesn’t bother to get all the relevant information. D’Arcy argues that in these examples, the agent’s ignorance is his own fault. The agent is culpable for his ignorance. In the example with A, B, and C, B’s ignorance of A’s need for aid, if it is in no way B’s fault that he is ignorant, excuses him from his obligation to A. But suppose B knew A couldn't swim, knew A was near the pool, an: knew A was irresponsible enough to fall in. B also notices that A is not making any noise any more. B first wonders if A is all right, but decides he would rather not know if A is in need of his help. (B is busy playing cards with the lighthouse-keeper.) Now it seems that B is obligated to check on (and, if necessary, save) A because B's ignorance in this case is his own fault. B is culpable for his ignorance. It might be pointed out that in these cases of culpable ignorance; it doesn't seem that the agent has incurred the original obligation. For example, if A needs help and B knows it, B is obligated to help A. If B doesn't know A needs help through no fault of his own, then B has no obligation to A. But if B's ignorance is his fault, then it seems that B has an obligation to find out whether A needs help (but not necessarily an obligation to help A, for example, if A doesn't need help). Thus it seems that when the ignorance is culpable, the agent has an obligation to find out the relevant facts. I'm not sure what else D'Arcy could mean by calling an agent's ignorance culpable unless it means the agent has an obligation not to be ignorant. 11 Prichard considers the possibility of an obligation to consider the circumstances fully. He argues that the obligation (or duty) to consider the circumstances fully cannot arise from the possibility of there being another duty. For, if Prichard's view is correct, if the ''duty'' to consider the circumstances fully comes from a possible duty once we have considered the circumstances fully, then by not considering the circumstances fully, we can absolve ourselves from all duties. Without considering the circumstances fully, the second duty never arises (due to ignorance). If the duty to consider the circumstances fully is based on this second duty, then this second duty never arises, the duty to consider the circumstances fully has no basis, and thus no longer exists either. Prichard says: “For plainly the duty of doing one action cannot possibly depend on the possibility of the duty of doing another the duty of doing which cannot arise unless the former action has actually been done.... the truth is that our having a duty to consider the circumstances cannot be based on the possibility of our having a future duty of another kind if we were to consider them. Rather, to vindicate such a duty, we must represent the two so-called duties as respectively an element and a possible element in a single duty, viz. to consider the circumstances, and then if, but only if, as a result, we reach a certain opinion, to do a certain action.”2 2. H.H. Richard, Moral Obligation, p.27. 12 Prichard has a point here. If he is correct, then the duty to consider the circumstances fully is not a separate duty, but part of a more complex duty (i.e., The duty to check the expressway traffic and then to yield the right of way if the situation demands it, is a single, complex duty). Nevertheless, Prichard does obviously allow for cases in which ignorance of a non-moral fact is no excuse. The reason is that there are cases in which part of the duty is to consider the relevant facts. These cases are comparable to D’Arcy’s cases of culpable ignorance due to negligence. Both Prichard and D’Arcy also allow for cases in which ignorance of a nonmoral fact is an excuse. Prichard can allow this by claiming that not all duties include considering the circumstances fully. For example, we may have a duty to help those in need, but this duty does not include as part of itself a requirement that we check up on everyone to see if they are in need. This is comparable to D’Arcy’s examples of non-culpable ignorance in which the agent is ignorant through no fault of his own. Now that we have examined the similarities and differences between Prichard and D’Arcy concerning ignorance of non-moral facts, it’s time to consider examples concerning ignorance of moral facts. As previously stated, Prichard does not allow for any excuses due to ignorance of a moral fact. In the original example of A, B, and C, both B and C were ignorant of an obligation to A. According to D’Arcy, B has no obligation if he is not culpable for his ignorance of a non-moral fact (A's needing help), but B does have an obligation if he is culpable for his ignorance of this non-moral fact. 13 According to Prichard, B has no obligation if no part of the obligation includes finding out the relevant facts, but B does have an obligation if part of the obligation is to find out the relevant facts. D’Arcy wants to expand his view to include moral facts as well. That is, D’Arcy argues that nonculpable ignorance of a moral fact excuses just as nonculpable ignorance of a non-moral fact does. At first glance, the approach seems very appealing. Consider again all the difficulties raised with Prichard’s position on ignorance of moral facts. If an agent is incapable of knowing a moral fact, D’Arcy calls it inculpable ignorance of a moral fact. Now there is some way to deal with seven year olds, brain damaged people, and the severely retarded. If, for some reason beyond the agent’s control, the agent does not know of an obligation, the agent is not culpable for his ignorance, and therefore is excused from the obligation. D’Arcy says, “In the ordinary language of day-to-day moral evaluations, we speak as if ignorance... excuses or fails to excuse, not according as it bears upon matters of moral rule, law, or principle, or upon matters of relevant fact: but according as the ignorance itself is or is not culpable. It is true that, in order to reject an excuse put forward on grounds of ignorance, one might argue that the ignorance in question was a case of ignorance of moral principle, and invoke an 14 ethical theory which held that such ignorance is always culpable; but the point in making such moves would be to show that the ignorance in question was itself culpable.''3 Prichard, in refusing to allow ignorance of moral fact as an excuse, would be claiming that all cases of ignorance of a moral fact are cases of culpable ignorance, according to D’Arcy. Prichard would, I am sure, allow that seven year olds, brain damaged people, (etc.) who are unable to know a moral law should be excused. If this is true, how do Prichard and D’Arcy differ concerning ignorance of moral facts? When is ignorance of a moral fact inculpable for D’Arcy and when is it an excuse for Prichard? D'Arcy claims that the conditions needed to consider ignorance of a moral fact culpable can be stated in general terms, ''...one need not claim to be able to draw up one list of moral principles of which inculpable ignorance is possible, and another of which it is not. The conditions necessary for holding ignorance or error to be culpable can be stated only in general terms: A's ignorance or error about X is culpable if and only if X is something which A is (1) obliged, and (2) able, to know. Now by hypothesis the disputed point is something which he is obliged to know; we are obliged to know what is 3. E. D’Arcy, Human Acts, p. 107. 15 morally required of us.''4 Thus, D’Arcy’s view could be made to resemble Prichard’s, if we agree that we have an obligation to know our obligations. Then, all cases of ignorance of a moral fact would fall into D’Arcy’s category, culpable ignorance. This follows from condition (1) of D’Arcy’s necessary conditions of culpability (i.e., if X is an obligation and we are obligated to know our obligations, then ignorance of an obligation is culpable). Though D’Arcy’s view had considerable appeal initially, on closer inspection it appears to be less plausible. Consider the notion of having an obligation to know your obligations. My initial objection involves ignorance of the obligation to know your obligations. But if there is an obligation to know your obligations, then there is an obligation to know your obligation to know your obligations. This will continue ad infinitum. Perhaps D’Arcy would admit that we do all have an obligation to know our obligation to know our obligation... to know our obligations, but this certainly seems awkward. Consider a concrete example. Suppose we have an obligation to help those in need. We may not know of this obligation. What is it of which we are guilty? If no one is in need, then I would hesitate to say that I was violating my obligation to know that I'm obligated to help those in need. If I know A is in need, but I don't know that I have an obligation to help him, what obligation do I violate? Obviously I violate my obligation to help others in need, if I don't help A. But do I also violate my obligation to know I have an obligation to A? Don’t I violate only 4. Ibid p. 112. 16 one obligation by not helping A (namely, the obligation to help those in need)? Ultimately, it seems that my obligation to know my obligation to help others just collapses into my obligation to help others. If I don't know of this obligation, I may violate it by not helping someone I know is in need. But if no one is in need, I haven't violated any obligation. And if I do fail to help someone I know is in need, the only obligation I violate is the obligation to help those in need. One further objection concerns the possibility of being obligated to know something. Usually we speak of an obligation to do a certain action. It is understandable, then, to speak of an obligation to find out or learn the facts of a situation. But in what sense can we be obligated to know some fact (moral or otherwise)? Though what we know depends in part on some intentional action we perform (e.g. going to Ethics class), it is not possible for us intentionally to know something. It’s not as if we choose to know fact A, but decide not to know fact B. Thus talk about an obligation to know what is morally required of us, though it seems plausible at first, is actually quite impossible. D’Arcy might want to change this to something like, we have an obligation to find out what our obligations are, but I don't think this will avoid the earlier objections. D’Arcy’s position had much initial plausibility. It does seem that we separate cases of culpable ignorance and inculpable ignorance when figuring out blameworthiness (especially in cases of negligence). However, the duty to find out the relevant facts of a situation cannot be derived from any possible duty discovered this way. (Or else, as Prichard says, failing to do your duty to find out the relevant facts would excuse you from any duty; thus there would be no 17 ground for the duty to find out the relevant facts, either. Hence, failing to do your duty to find out the relevant facts would also excuse you from this duty itself.) Unless some other ground for a duty to find out the relevant facts can be found, we should stick to Prichard’s notion of a complex duty. Thus all D’Arcy’s examples of negligence are examples of a complex duty for Prichard (e.g. the hunter has a duty : (a) to find out what’s moving in the bushes and (b) not to shoot it if it is a person.) D’Arcy’s position on ignorance of moral facts is even less plausible on close inspection. To be culpable for your ignorance of a moral fact, D’Arcy requires that you be both obliged and able to know this moral fact. As pointed out, the notion of an obligation to know moral facts is very problematic. Though D’Arcy’s position looks very neat and simple, it falls prey to many objections. Prichard’s view might not be as symmetrical as D’Arcy’s, but it is superior nonetheless. Instead of being culpable for being ignorant of the facts in certain situations (which seems to create a problematic obligation to find out the facts in a situation), Prichard uses the notion of complex duties. Thus there isn’t a duty to find out the facts of a situation apart from the duty to act on those facts. In this way, Prichard escapes the problem of justifying a duty to find out the relevant facts. Instead of being culpable for being ignorant of any moral fact (which involves D’Arcy in the impossible notion of an obligation to know your obligations) Prichard claims that ignorance of a moral fact is no excuse. The only problem left for Prichard concerns cases in which the agent cannot see an obligation. 18 In answering this objection, Prichard could, perhaps, borrow one bit of D’Arcy’s position. If someone is unable to see a moral fact, this might be some grounds for an exculpatory plea. This would help Prichard in handling cases involving seven year olds and brain damaged people, without involving him in the paradox of an obligation to know your obligations. Another way of handling the problem of seven year olds and brain damaged people might also be feasible. When discussing obligations we have, we are assuming that these obligations apply to moral agents. It might be possible to rule out problematic cases involving children or defective people by claiming that they are not really moral agents. If this tack is taken, however, moral agents cannot be defined in terms of the ability to see moral facts, without becoming circular. There is one other reason for accepting D’Arcy’s view on ignorance of moral facts when due to the person’s inability to see the moral fact. Consider the objection concerning J. Thompson and abortion. Prichard's unmodified view would lead to the fact that Thompson is as blameworthy as any murderer. If we add D'Arcy's idea that someone's inability to know a moral fact may excuse them from an obligation, there may be a solution to this problem. If Thompson really did her best to figure out what her obligations were, and she still could not see that she was wrong in believing that her right to her body was a stronger right than the fetus’ right to life, then perhaps she can be excused (at least in part) because she is unable (in some sense) to know the correct moral facts. As 19 D’Arcy points out, however, this is not to say Thompson didn't act wrongly, only that she is not to be blamed for it. The same could be said of the seven year old and the brain damaged people. Yet we would not want to apply this to anyone who had some crazy notion about their obligations. Cases involving the violation of clear-cut moral principles (unlike the abortion issue) should not be pardoned just because the person really believes his crazy notions about obligations are correct. He may not choose not to know some clear-cut obligation; but if his lack of knowledge is not the fault of anyone else, but is his fault (in some sense), then even if he didn't choose to be ignorant he is not exonerated by his ignorance. The only difference between this case and the abortion case seems to be the clarity of the obligations in question. Thus the most precise we can make the position on exculpation due to ignorance of a moral fact would be something like the following: “If the obligation in question is one that a normal adult could reasonably be expected to see, then a normal adult can not be exculpated if he fails to see it.''5 Though this rule is very general (containing phrases like “normal adult'' and ''reasonably be expected to see”) it does fit my intuitions about children and defects (being restricted to normal adults) as well as my intuitions about less clear-cut obligations like abortion (being restricted to obligations that could reasonably be expected to be seen). 5. R. Lemos, Notes from Phi 623, 3/21/79