192 A Sense of Place A sense of place results gradually and unconsciously from inhabiting a landscape over time, becoming familiar with its physical properties, accruing history within its confines. Ken Ryden, Mapping the Invisible Landscape, 38 If sense of place is a metaphorical construct of the relationship between people and place, an exploration into the imaginary world of utopia, dystopia, and cyberspace can be a process of spatial cognition and place-learning. As the preceding chapters have shown, this process is both cognitive and metaphorical in nature, cognitive in that imaginary space and place can be conceptualized, metaphorical in that such conceptualization must rely on representation and analogy. In this process of learning how imaginary space and place are metaphorically related to the lived world, we learn to know the strength of sense of place. In creating the imaginary place of utopia or dystopia, each writer displays his/her own style of organizing space cognitively according to his/her own particular history of place-learning. Likewise, as readers, we return to our own particular history of place-learning to find a mental response to a particular kind of spatial problem. We then tend to develop it as a distinctive cognitive pattern, a template upon which to organize the imaginary world. We form an impression or tentative picture of the imaginary place on the basis of our earlier spatial experiences, and focus our attention on metaphors that fit well within the expectations derived from our experiences. Initial 193 conceptualization of place, as suggested in Lakoff’s idea of conceptual mapping, influences later conceptualization of place by providing a framework into which later information is placed. Imaginary space and place not only have spatial dimension; they also contain place meanings cued in part by cognized spatial form of spatial metaphor. In reading utopian/dystopian narratives or traveling in the world of computer networks, we not only develop sophisticated spatial capabilities, but also develop sophisticated place orientations. We gradually mature into worlds of increasingly complex place relationships. It seems a reasonable assumption that this maturation also progresses by stages. This process can be compared, metaphorically indeed, to the four stages of the development of children’s spatial awareness that psychologist Jean Piaget conjectures.1 In the first stage of spatial maturity, children begin to construct a system of relationships between objects based on the manipulation of objects. Still in their infancy, children associate self-initiated action and related body sensations as isolated events; with the coordination of sight and movement, they learn to relate objects perceived at different times. We are like a newborn infant when we are first confronted with an imaginary place based on a utopian or dystopian text. There is a blur of sensation: a sea of sight, sound, smell and feeling, represented by textual signs. By remembering highly repetitious stimulus patterns, we slowly come to recognize certain states of spatial existence. Islands, dreamlands, and future states are such stimulus 1 The four stages are the sensorimotor (0-2 years), preoperational (2-7 years), concrete operational (7-11 years), and formal operational periods (11 and older). See Jean Piaget and Barbel Inhelder, The Child's Conception of Space, trans. F. J. Langdon and J. L. Lunzer (New York: Norton, 1967), 155-60. 194 patterns. Most importantly, we separate ourselves from the imaginary surroundings as an entity or object of the most profound place significance. By identifying with the major character, we tend to imagine that we are in that place and isolate ourselves in that seemingly enclosed place. Essentially immobile like the infant’s, our self-generated activities are bodily focused in an initial stage of place awareness. Like an infant learning to crawl and thus propel itself in a horizontal plane, spatial metaphors, like objects apart from us, take on meaning through use. The concrete primitive meaning of exploration is supplemented and elaborated by use and function of spatial metaphors. We look for spatial metaphors that can help us transfer our spatial experiences of the lived world into the imaginary world. buildings are usually our targets. Spatial metaphors like cities and Most utopias and dystopias come to us as cities, even though most of them are actually much more extensive than just an urban area. Once we come to the stage when children learn to walk, our world of valuable spatial metaphors expands potentially and exponentially, although like most children, our movements are highly contained within localized territories of utopia or dystopia. We are like children in Piaget’s second period of spatial maturity, who grow to be able to transform the mental construct of their surroundings in very elementary ways. Children in this stage can realize that one arrives at different locations when one goes in different directions, but are still unable to conceptualize the reverse sequence of locations along a given route. In a similar stage, we rely on the narrator, who now plays the role of a parent (and especially the mother)2 and becomes an equal focus of value. An 2 Tuan writes: “Mother may well be the first enduring and independent object in the infant's world of fleeting impressions. Later she is recognized by the child as his essential shelter 195 emerging sense of place appropriateness is tied to the narrator’s availability or accessibility. The narrator may act like an omnipotent god, knowing everything, like the ones in Orwell’s 1984 and Huxley’s Brave New World. The narrator may be a traveler who reports what he has learned on the journey, like Hythloday and Guest. Or like D-503 in Zamyatin’s We, the narrator is the one who comes from the imaginary world to report everything he has experienced. To know more about the imaginary place and its utopian value or dystopian principle, we have to follow the narrator, moving along the paths he has been through and seeing whatever he sees or allows us to see. The third stage that Piaget conjectures is marked by increased sophistication of image transformation. For children, what takes place in one direction can also take place in the opposite. Children can look at objects in space from a multiplicity of viewpoints and can express these experiences using abstract language. By the end of this period, children have grasped the following spatial concepts: first, proximity—the nearness of one object one to another; second, separation—the disassociation of objects; third, order—the spatial succession of objects; fourth, enclosure—the surrounding of objects by other objects; and fifth, continuity—the totality of objects seen as a complete distribution in space (Piaget and Inhelder, 1967: 3). Likewise, the third stage of our place awareness involves a bounded territory where we become attached not only to significant persons and other significant metaphors, but also to localities of interest that contain various persons, objects, and activities. We learn to pay attention to King Utopus and and dependable source of physical and psychological comfort.” The Perspective of Experience, 29. See his Space and Place: 196 the myth of his creation of utopia, to Old Hammond and the history of revolution leading to his era, and to I-330 and her subversive activities with Mephis against the One State. Moreover, like young boys or girls, we consider an imaginary place to be a large and somewhat immobile type of metaphor that represents a locus of some recognized (utopian) satisfaction or (dystopian) dissatisfaction. At first, such a large metaphor has less meaning than small metaphors in the imaginary place because, unlike portable toys or security blankets for boys and girls, it cannot be handled and moved easily (Piaget and Inhelder, 1967: 3). It is true that the imaginary place of utopia or dystopia, though a spatial metaphor, cannot be as easily dealt with as a simple analogy. Below the surface of being a territory, utopia or dystopia is a multi-facet construct that encompasses territoriality and many other elements concerning geopolitics and terrritorializatoin. Nonetheless, we do come to value imaginary places as spaces to be occupied bodily rather than possessed merely through handling. At this stage, we become concerned with the name of place and to develop a sense of territoriality or possession relative to close-by places or to places used frequently or intimately. Again, like children of this stage, we begin to apply a single idea of place to different kinds of imaginary places. Panopticon is such an idea that may be employed to utopia or dystopia, due to its place-bound structure and control-oriented mechanism. In Piaget’s last period of spatial maturity, children are liberated from concrete reality in that they are able to pose truly abstract hypotheses. They can use spatial images that entail unreal transformations from apparent reality. These transformations are topological, projective, and geometrical. Topological transformations involve rules of proximity, separation, sequence, 197 and closure, which remain invariant under continuous deformation. Projective transformations involve spatial relations constructed according to various points of view, as when the surface of a sphere is reproduced on a flat surface in different ways. Geometrical transformations involve metrical relationships that coordinate space with respect to a system of outside reference points (Piaget and Inhelder, 1967: 3). This stage holds true of the process of our place learning. especially visual ones, loom over the horizon of our perception. Spatial images, They may be manipulated for the purpose of distorting reality and producing politically correct messages, or they may be utilized as a means to create hyperreality that can or potentially substitute reality. On the other hand, our bounded range is expanded by disjointed route/destination combinations. Acting as a traveler in the imaginary world, like children who regularly sit in the family automobile, we develop a clear sense of “here” and “there.” But in cyberspace, we still need to develop a complete notion of the intervening linkages between such places. We are like children, “caught up in the excitement of people, things, and events; going from one place to another is not their responsibility” (Tuan, 1977: 29). Our geographic horizon of the imaginary place expands, but not necessarily step-by-step, toward the larger scale. Our interest and knowledge may focus first on a small community on the web and then, skipping the neighborhood, shift to the city before jumping to foreign territories (like frontiers) without ever anchoring on the region. In this process, we develop an ability to categorize settings according to generic “place-types”— architectural or territorial. The global space is seen to differ from the architectural and territorial ones, which, in turn, are seen to differ from the 198 global one. Our recognition that different kinds of behavior are often appropriate in these varied places grows in sophistication. Having attained the last stage of our learning process of place awareness, we are like children who have learned to function effectively in a fully integrated activity space. is contemplated. We retain the viewpoint from which the lived world Although we have escaped, in large measure, the confines of imaginary place as a bounded space, the narrator of utopian/dystopian narratives (who has once played the role of parent) remains a primary focus for support. The narrator’s effective world stretches beyond fictional, local place to global space. At this point, the meaningful behavior settings of our lived world, fostered by a sense of place, are effectively related across differences of scale. Like an experienced traveler, we know how different settings are linked, and we can negotiate effectively between them, even in the world of computer networks. We have developed our own style of being in places differently defined by spatial metaphors. It enables us to travel from place to place, comparing each imaginary place with our own and learning how its spatial formation influences our perception of the place. We have learned the behaviors appropriate to different kinds of imaginary places, to our own satisfaction. It brings us a sophisticated sense of how different meanings of imaginary place are cued. We recognize sophisticated nuances of imaginary place meanings as they are encoded in landscape and townscape created by literary text or hypertext. As a result, we carry a sophisticated cognitive map of the imaginary world comprised of linked sets of place expectations. While our learning of imaginary space and place has more to do with conceptualizing the positioning of spatial metaphors defined as places, this spatial learning has more to do with conceptualizing the content of localities 199 thus metaphorized. Our place learning goes well beyond the mere spatial dimension to embrace the full spectrum of meaning by which imaginary places are anticipated and used. Nonetheless, we are still vulnerable to the confusion that exists in geography and other disciplines as to the relationship between the concept of space and that of place. Many scholars use the two terms synonymously. This happens so often that even the concept of sense of place is usually made to stand as a convenient alternative for the concept of spatial sense. For many geographers, the concept of place is firmly rooted in notions of location variously expressed. “Place,” for Donald Meinig, “commonly refers to a definite area, a fixed location” (Meinig, 1979: 3); while for Edward Relph, location is only incidental, with space providing a mere context for place (Relph, 1976: 8). So critical of abstract space is Lefebvre that he hardly discusses the difference between the two concepts. Yet, he reminds us that abstract space “serves those forces which make a tabula rasa of whatever stands in their way, of whatever threatens them—in short, of differences” (Lefebvre, 1991: 285). His idea is particularly right about the disappearance of “we” when he continues: “These forces seem to grind down and crush everything before them, with space performing the function of a plane, a bulldozer, or a tank” (Lefebvre, 1991: 285). the homogenizing power of abstract space. Indeed, everything surrenders to We—people—are no exception. The involvement of people is usually ignored when the relationship between place and space becomes a focus. It should be noted that place and space are linked together only when we3 are involved. In defining the place and space as complementary ideas, Tuan 3 To emphasize the involvement of human factor in the relationship between place and space, “we” and “our” are italicized in the following passages of this paragraph. 200 writes: “In experience the meaning of space often merges with that of place” (Tuan, 1977: 29). He explains: From security of place we are aware of the openness, freedom, and threat of space, and vice versa. Furthermore, if we think of space as that which allows movement, then place is pause; each pause in movement makes it possible for location to be transformed into place. (1977: 29) For Tuan, space is given by our ability to move. Our movements are directed toward, or repulsed by places as objects. Space can be variously experienced by us as the relative location of places, as well as the distances that separate or link places. The way Tuan defines space and place appears to derive from our need to define relationships among different spatial elements. He equates the idea of space with wide-open vistas or panoramas implying unhindered movement. By contrast, he equates the idea of place with enclosure: “Enclosed and humanized space is place” (Tuan, 1977: 6). To emphasize his point, he continues: “Compared to space, place is a calm center of established values.”(Tuan, 1977: 12). Thus place is shelter and space is venture, the former attachment and the latter freedom. The “boundedness of place” is seen to contrast with the “exposure of space” (Tuan, 1977: 54). Sense of place is embedded in the concept of place. It is an imperative that architects deal with sense of place when they design a living space. Unlike geographers, architects see space in three rather than two dimensions. For them, space is a three-dimensional enclosure, as opposed to the two-dimensional configuration geographers conceptualize. Such space is designated to enclose or encompass. Such space surrounds, or potentially surrounds, in an all-encompassing sense 201 Space is something that gives form to place as one aspect of place-meaning. Christian Norberg-Schultz writes: “Whereas ‘space’ denotes the three-dimensional organization of the elements which make up a place, ‘character’ denotes the general ‘atmosphere’ which is the most comprehensive property of any place.” Places, he notes, are designated by nouns as they are considered “real things that exist” (Norberg-Schultz, 1980: 11). system of relations, is denoted instead by prepositions. Space, as a He writes: “In our daily life we hardly talk about ‘space,’ but about things that are ‘over’ or ‘under,’ ‘before’ or ‘behind’ each other, or we use prepositions such as ‘at,’ ‘in,’ ‘within,’ ‘on,’ ‘upon,’ ‘to,’ ‘from,’ ‘along,’ ‘next’”(Norberg-Schultz, 1980: 16). Prepositions denote topological relations that represent the abstract essence of space. The other characteristics of place are denoted by adjectives. Space, he concludes, is a problem of orientation and place a problem of expectation: When man dwells, he is simultaneously located in space and exposed to a certain environmental character. The two psychological functions involved may be called ‘orientation’ and ‘identification.’ To gain an existential foothold, man has to be able to orientate himself; he has to know where he is. But he also has to identify himself with the environment, that is, he has to know how he is in a certain place. (Norberg-Schultz, 1980: 19) It is in this latter sense of place as identification that spatial metaphors move beyond the realm of spatial preoccupation. Spatial metaphors turn a place into an object or entity conceptualized in two-dimensional geographical space but retaining a three-dimensional spatial form. Above all, it is a focus of meaning, character, and identity for an imaginary place. It is in the 202 recognition of this identity, even when such recognition can vaguely reveal spatial implications, that the concept of imaginary place has real value. This is the same recognition that Tuan emphasizes for places with physical reality: “Places are centers of value,” Tuan writes. “They attract or repel in finely shaded degrees. To attend them even momentarily is to acknowledge their reality and value” (Tuan, 1977: 18). Spatial metaphor is the carrier of sense of place. It appeals to a sense of three-dimensional spatial form when we are situated in a two-dimensional context. Imaginary space provides only the background for spatial metaphors. What makes an imaginary city impressive is not so much the bulk of the buildings grouped in it, but its spatial, metaphorical meaning that is linked to our lived world. Imaginary space is less tangible than the spatial metaphors it contains. Imaginary space is what remains between spatial metaphors, because imaginary space is derived from its metaphorical boundaries. But it is spatial metaphor, not imaginary space, that usually attracts attention. This can be understood the way Robert Yudell deals with the relationship between forms and space: It is not surprising that forms are more often the focus of our attention than space or movement in space. Space is typically thought of as a void or as the absence of solid, and movement thought of as a domain separate from its existence in space.4 Space stands as a useful concept to be imposed on the imaginary world to help make our experience coherent. 4 Space by itself, however, is an insufficient The passages of Robert J. Yudell are cited in Kent C. Bloomer and Charles W. Moore, Body, Memory, and Architecture (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1977), 57. 203 schemata to comprehend how writers structure and use spatial metaphors. Rather, it is the concept of place, a schemata of focused meaning cued in part by spatial form, that deserves attention. Yudell’s idea can further help us better understand the role of imaginary place. An imaginary place is the sum of all spatial metaphors that combine to give a sense of behavioral focus through expectation. It comes with its identity or character through the satisfactions or dissatisfactions anticipated as variously cued by spatial metaphors both animate and inanimate. Identity is a unique configuration of all the spatial metaphors that amount to make up a place. Implicit in these spatial metaphors are behavioral expectations. Accordingly, the role of utopian writers is to recognize and exploit different identities of utopian place in such a manner as to match the human needs implicit in the lived world. This matching is a problem of recognizing these identities, of giving them appropriate spatial metaphors, and of identifying their spatial meanings with textual articulation. The way to an expressive and exciting imaginary place is through the creation of separate identities—a good place, an island, a state, etc.—each forming an essential part of the whole. A utopian writer creates these identities through a sense of place that spatial metaphors mold as they form spatial sequences. Cyberspace is an ensemble of spatial sequences molded by spatial metaphors. It is imagined as a construct much bigger than a traditional city. Yet, it can be articulated only when we are involved. and we map. We move, we memorize, When we move, we create more alternative trajectories; when we memorize, we learn by heart each spatial metaphor; and when we map, we regain the sense of place lost to its image-laden hyperreality. In fact, we act more like a traveler in cyberspace, and on our journey we experience a variety 204 of spatial identities attributable to the imaginary space. As we travel through spatial sequences in cyberspace, there gradually arises in us a territorial identity that matches the one we have in the lived world. It is the same territorial identity that has help position us in any other imaginary space or place. It builds in us not only a capability of being oriented by the surrounding metaphors, but also a set of tacit knowledge of the imaginary place. With this territorial identity, we can understand an imaginary place without needing an articulated system or systematic structure. Finally, our spatial experiences are integrated into a mental model called sense of place. Such a mental model helps us situate ourselves in an imaginary place, thereby producing our spatial relationship with the imaginary place, whether it is utopia, dystopia, or cyberspace. We carry it with us, transfer it to other places, and employ it to decode whatever spatial messages that may come to us.