Consciousness Introduction Though consciousness is central to human experience, it has been little studied in psychology. It was an important part of psychological inquiry in the 19 th century, but languished for most of the 20th century with the insistence on quantitative methods and replicability. In the United States, the influential behaviorist movement explicitly rejected study of internal states, basing its psychology on relating stimulus to response. New methods in both neurophysiology and cognitive psychology have reopened the study of consciousness, however, relating it to essential functions of human cognition. If we assume that consciousness is a complex enough phenemonon that genes are required to support it, we can conclude from evolutionary theory that consciousness has a function. Since it is universal to all people, like eyes or hearts, the neurological machinery that supports it must rely on genes that are selected for. In contrast, a genetically supported trait that is not useful tends to disappear. Fish trapped in dark caves, for instance, lose their eyes over many generations because mutations in the genes supporting eyes are no longer selected against. If the still-unknown array of genes supporting consciousness is maintained, there must be some essential capabilities that consciousness bestows. Evolutionary theory does not tell us what those capabilities are, however. That is the subject of recent and current research. General Introductions There are no general college-level textbooks devoted exclusively to consciousness. The closest approximation is a brief book by Friedenberg ((2013), though it emphasizes consciousness and attention as applied to vision. Several books, however, include good introductions to a wide variety of approaches. Uncovering the mechanisms of consciousness has been identified as one of the most important problems in science (Crick, 1995), yet consciousness has proved paradoxically difficult to define. The common definition invokes awareness, which merely adds a near-synonym without defining either term. Baars & Gage (2010) prominently include consciousness among the core issues in cognitive neuroscience. Banks et al. (2009) provide a definitive group of chapters by leading scholars on their approaches to consciousness. Block (2004) defines several levels or kinds of consciousness. Another approach is through language; if one can talk about a perception or experience, or at least attempt to do so, then that event is couscious; otherwise it is not. This approach is related to memory, where consciousness is defined as that which can be recalled. David Eagleman (2011) covers it all, basing his approach not on the conscious but on the unconscious that defines most of what the brain does. The sense of agency, that we are in conscious control of our actions, is tested to the extreme by Wegner (2002). Many of these sources also address the so-called mind/brain problem, the relationship between a mind that seems personal and a brain that operates by the biological principles of neurophysiology. Mind, though, is what the brain does, just as digestion is what the stomach does. Opening up the stomach does not reveal digestion any more than opening up the brain reveals mind. Mind is a verb, something the brain does. It won’t be found sitting in some brain module. Baars, B. & Gage, N. (Eds.), 2010. Cognition, Brain and Consciousness, 3rd Ed. New York: Elsevier. Written primarily as an introduction to cognitive neuroscience, the book reflects the authors’ expertise in consciousness but does not require a neuroscience background. Banks, W., Baars, B., Banaji, M., Bridgeman, B., Gallagher, S., Rees, G., Schooler, J. and Wegner, D. 2009. (Eds.), Encyclopedia of Consciousness. Amsterdam: Elsevier. A collection of articles by leading scholars on what consciousness is and what functions it might fulfill. Block, N. 2004. "Consciousness" in R. Gregory ed. Oxford Companion to the Mind, 2nd edition. Block, a philosopher, reviews what consciousness means in several schools of thought, including the ideas of modern philosophers of mind. Crick, F. 1995. The astonishing hypothesis: The scientific search for the soul. New York: Touchstone. In one of the contributions that revived the scientific study of consciousness, Crick’s Nobel prize gave the field legitimacy. Eagleman, D. 2011. Incognito: The Secret Lives of the Brain. New York: Pantheon Books. The brain is conceived as a cluster of semi-autonomous agents, most of them operating unconsciously, each with a specialized job. It asks among other things whether we are responsible for our actions if those actions are largely driven by unconscious brain mechanisms. A compelling read, with lot of surprises. Highly recommended. Friedenberg, J. 2013. Visual attention and consciousness. New York: Psychology Press. The first two chapters treat general problems of consciousness, and the last chapter reviews some of the major theories. The remainder of the book applies these ideas to the visual system. Wegner, D. 2002. The Illusion of Conscious Will. Cambridge, Ma.: MIT Press. This is a terriifying book. In the laboratory Wegner and colleagues can make people produce actions without being aware that they are producing them, or experience actions that they think they are producing although they are not. Unconscious processing dominates the work of the brain, and people have little knowledge of what is happening there. Phenomenology What distinguishes consciousness? What are the phenomena to be explained? The sources in this section are the work of philosophers of mind endeavoring to explain what consciousness is like and how it affects mental life. Churchland (2002) gives a philosopher’s introduction to the approaches of a number of schools of thought. A lot of these, though, rely on introspection, thinking about one’s own thinking, which has proved to be disappointing as a source of information about brain function precisely because so much of that function is unconscious. The technique has proved notoriously unreliable in psychology, where ideas that seemed obvious have been proved to be wrong, and vice versa, but it is still occasionally invoked in nonexperimental contexts. Nagel’s (1974) classic paper introduces the feeling of ‘what it is like’, which has been influential in subsequent philosophical studies. Chalmers (1996) points out the distinctiveness of the problem of accounting for consciousness, not measurable by normal behavioral methods. Blackmore (2011) goes a little further by including some neurological insights. Blackmore, S. 2011. Consciousness: An Introduction. New York: Oxford University Press. An engagingly well-written exploration of where cosciousness comes from and what it might do for us. Chalmers, D. J. 1996. The Conscious Mind: In Search of a fundamental Theory. New York: Oxford University Press. Chalmers, a philosopher, introduces study of the physiology of behavior and action as the ‘easy problem’, while consciousness is the ‘hard problem’. The distinction frames much subsequent work, though if the ‘easy’ problem were really easy it would have been solved it long ago, and that solution will go a long way toward addressing the ‘hard’ problem. Churchland, P. S. 2002. Brain-Wise: Studies in Neurophilosophy. Cambridge, Ma.: MIT Press. Churchland distinguishes several aspects of consciousness, each with a distinct phenomenology and function. Several distinct approaches to the mind/brain relationship are also discussed. Nagel, T. 1974. What is it like to be a bat? Philosophical Review, 83, 435 – 450. Nagel asks what it is like to be a bat, for example, using ‘what it is like’ to begin identifying what distinguishes consciousness from other mental functions. Methods of Research Because there are no obvious objective tests of the private experience of consciousness, as there are for instance for perception, many indirect methods have been employed. Since introspection, thinking about one’s own mental processes, has not proved adequate, an array of other approaches has been employed, each with its strengths and limitations. Brain Pathology Since humans cannot be used in invasive neurophysiological studies, brain damage from strokes or trauma presents natural experiments that provide much of what we know about human brain organization. Milner and Goodale (1995), a neurologist and a cognitive psychologist, examine the famous case of a patient who lost her ability to perceive with vision, but retained the ability to perform some tasks requiring visually guided action. Weiskrantz (1997) coined the term ‘blindsight’, the ability of humans and monkeys to perform some visual tasks in visual fields rendered blind by removal of the primary visual cortex. In many cases the deficit is restricted to one part of the visual field, so that the subject can serve as his/her own control. In his 1998 book he describes generalizations that can be drawn from this line of research. Kentridge et al. (2004) show that attention can alter properties of blindsight, helping to distinguish attention from consciousness. Damasio, a leading neurologist and neurological theorist, uses data from braindamaged patients to examine the relation of self to mind. Damasio, A. R. 1999. The Feeling of What Happens: Body and Emotion in the Making of Consciousness. New York: Harcourt Brace. Examines neurological cases to show relationships of body sense and emotional capability in forming the conscious mind. Damasio, A. R. 2010. Self Comes to Mind: Constructing the Conscious Brain. New York: Pantheon Books. Consciousness in this analysis arises from the mind applying thought processes to its own existence. Kentridge, R. W., Heywood, C. A. & Weiskrantz, L. 2004. Spatial attention speeds discrimination without awareness in blindsight. Neuropsychologia, 42, 831-835. The effect of attention on reaction time, even for stimuli picked up without awareness, shows attentional effects in unconscious processing and demonstrates the distinction between attention and consciousness. Milner, A. D. & Goodale, M. A. 1995. The Visual Brain in Action. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. Thorough description of a neurological patient who has lost the ability to perceive, but can still control visually guided behavior. The patient nearly died in a case of carbon monoxide poisining, and awoke perceptually blind, with no conscious vision but retaining some motor-oriented visual abilities. The book is the most thorough source for the two-visual-systems theory that separates perception from action. Weiskrantz, L. 1998. Blindsight: A Case Study and Implications. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. The case of a patient who after loss of part of the visual system loses the ability to experience vision, but not the ability to perform some visual tasks. Weiskrantz, L. 1997. Consciousness lost and found. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. Reviews several decades of research on monkeys and humans, demonstrating that monkeys retain some visual capabiities after removal of part or all of the primary visual cortex. Humans who have had strokes in the same area are shown to be even more reliant on the cortex. Neural Correlates One method seeks changes in the brain that occur at the transition from unconscious to conscious processing. Bird, C. M., Castelli, F., Malik, O., Frith, U. & Husain, M. 2004. The impact of extensive medial frontal lobe damage on “theory of mind” and cognition. Brain, 127, 914-928. Identifies the medial region of the frontal lobe as key in interpreting the mental states of others, and in turn the mental states of the self. Koch, C. 2004. The Quest for Consciousness. Englewood, Co.: Roberts & Company. The book concentrates on neural mechanisms of perception and attention, and includes a wide range of physiological information relevant to consciousness. A wide-ranging general introduction. Godwin, C. A., Gazzaley, A., & Morsella, E. in press. Homing in on the brain mechanisms linked to consciousness: The buffer of the perception-and-action interface. In A. Pereira and D. Lehmann (Eds.), The unity of mind, brain and world: Current perspectives on a science of consciousness. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. A theory is introduced with neural evidence basing conscious states on preparation for motor action. In the process a function for consciousness is proposed. Morsella, E., Krieger, S. C., & Bargh, J. A. 2010. Minimal neuroanatomy for a conscious brain: Homing in on the networks constituting consciousness. Neural Networks, 23, 14 – 15. Contrasts brain areas that function without consciousness and those that affect conscious awareness. Pollen, D. A. 1995. Cortical areas in visual awareness. Nature, 377, 293-294. Contrasts responses of visual system neurons with awareness of visual events. Many areas of the visual brain function in a mode inaccessible to consciousness. Carlson, T., Rauschenberger, R., & Verstraten, F.A.J. 2007. No representation without awareness in the lateral occipital complex. Psychological Science, 18, 298-302. Proposes the lateral occipital complex, a part of the visual system, as a seat of visual awareness. Method of Contrasts This approach aims to contrast conscious and unconscious brain functions in contexts that are otherwise as similar as possible, thereby revealing the extra neurological contribution of conscious processing. Baars, B. 1988. A Cognitive theory of Consciousness. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. One of the first books treating consciousness with modern scientific methods, it contrasts conscious and unconscious brain functions in the in the context of the ‘global workspace’ theory. Consciousness in this view serves to allow brain modules access to one another and to behavior. Baars, B. 1997. In the Theater of Consciousness. New York: Oxford university Press. Elaborates the global workspace theory, one of the most influential approaches to the neural substrate of consciousness, with data and thinking produced since the appearance of the earlier Baars book. Sleep As the only sustained unconscious period in normal individuals, sleep presents a natural experiment in the functions of consciousness. Dement (1974), the founder of the Stanford sleep laboratory, describes significant discoveries in sleep research. Jouvet (2001) reviews work on dreaming as a distinct mode of consciousness. Dement, W. 1974. Some Must Watch While Some Must Sleep. San Francisco: Freeman and Company. A popular-level classic of sleep research, describing the discovery of rapid-eye-movement (REM) sleep among other phenomena such as the stages of sleep. It helped to establish sleep as a significant area of scientific inquiry. Jouvet, M. 2001. The Paradox of Sleep: The Story of Dreaming. Cambridge, Ma.: MIT Press. The author coined the term ‘paradoxical sleep’ to describe REM sleep, the paradox being an EEG that looks like the intense brain activity of alert waking. He discusses possible functions of sleep and dreaming, which remain uncertain. Attention Attention and consciousness were once thought to be two sides of the same coin, but recent research has shown them to be distinguishable, as Kanai et al. (2006) demonstrate. Libet et al. (1983) caused a sensation when he demonstrated neurological events preceding a ‘free-will’ intention to move. Later, Libet (1985) reviews implications of that study and the reactions to it. Haggard & Cole (2007) elaborate on his result, analyzing components of the response. Haggard et al. (2002) extend the method to analysis of action. Haggard, P., Aschersleben, G., Gehrke, J. & Prinz, W. 2002. Action, binding and awareness. In B. hommel & W. Prinz (Eds.), Attention and Performance XIX: Common Mechanisms in Perception and Action. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. An international team examines the relationship between action and awareness, concluding among other things that the planning of action is conscious, while its execution often is not. Haggard, P. & Cole, J. 2007. Intention, attention and the temporal experience of action. Consciousness and Cognition, 16, 211-220. Following up on the Libet et al. (1983) study, psychophysical methods are used to examine the relationships of stimulus event, the intention to respond, and the actual response (pressing a key). The experiment controls for attention to the stimulus. Kanai, R., Tsuchiya, N., & Verstraten, F. A. J. 2006. The scope and limits of top-down attention in unconscious visual processing. Current Biology, 16, 2332-2336. Psychophysical methods show that considerable processing, even for attention, can occur without consciousness. Libet, B. 1985. Unconscious cerebral initiative and the role of conscious will in voluntary action. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 8, 529-566. Libet reviews the reactions to his finding that what seem like willed actions are preceded by unconscious but measurable brain events. The article is accompanied by comments from leading researchers and Libet’s reply to them. Libet, B., Gleason, C., Wright, W. & Pearl, D. 1983. Time of conscious intention to act in relation to onset of cerebral activities (readiness potential: the unconscious initiation of a freely voluntary act. Brain, 106, 623-642. Describes a groundbreaking study in which a cortical potential begins to appear up to half a second before a person is aware of the intention to move. What seemed conscious and willed is preceded by unconscious neurological processes. The study has spawned a small industry of follow-up studies amplifying on the surprising result. Perception One of the hallmarks of consciousness is that it underlies perception. We are conscious of what we perceive, but some sensory processing can proceed without consciousness. Breitmeyer’s definitive book (1984) reviews conditions in which large, prominent targets can be rendered invisible by masking with other stimuli. Bridgeman (1992) defines the conditions under which vision is accompanied by consciousness and conditions not requiring consciousness. Lathrop & Bridgeman (2011) give a dramatic example of that contrast. Breitmeyer, B. 1984. Visual Masking: an Integrative approach. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. The authoritative examination of visual stimuli that reach the retina but are not consciously perceived. Those masked stimuli can still affect behavior, though. Bridgeman, B. 1992. Conscious vs. unconscious processes: The case of vision. Theory & Psychology, 2, 73-88. Shows that most eye movements are generated and controlled unconsciously; also differentiates two functions of vision, perception on one hand and controlling visually guided behavior on the other. Lathrop, B. & Bridgeman, B. 2011. Perception in the Absence of Attention: Evidence of Perceptual Processing in the Roelofs Effect During Inattentional Blindness. Perception, 40, 1104-19. An empirical demonstration that visual processing of position information can take place without awareness. The perceived location of a target is changed without perception of the frame that induces the change. Subjects can still point accurately to the target, however, despite its illusory perceived position, demonstrating a mismatch between consciously reported position and motororiented action. Language There seems to be a privileged relationship between language and consciousness, because we are always aware of what we are saying. The systems that generate speech, however, remain unconscious and somewhat obscure, linking a lexicon and grammatical conventions to thoughts quickly and effortlessly. Psycholinguist Wim Levelt (1989) examines this process. Bridgeman (1992) proposes a role for recursive processing as a key human innovation that makes human thinking much more powerful than that of other animals. Vygotskii (1962) and Luria (1981) represent the Russian tradition of exploiting natural experiments in child development and neurological cases respectively. Bridgeman, B. 1992. On the origin of consciousness and language. Psycoloquy (refereed electronic journal) psycoloquy.92.consciousness.1.bridgeman. Shows how hearing one’s own speech allows ideas to take a second pass through the brain, amplifying the power of human thinking. Consciousness allows a person to act on the world, rather than waiting to respond to external stimuli. The paper is followed by comments from a number of experts. Levelt, W. J. M. 1989. Speaking: From intention to articulation. Cambridge, Ma.: MIT Press. One of the world’s leading psycholinguists demonstrates the special relationship between awareness and speech, with all of the steps in between. Luria, A. R. (1981) Language and Cognition. translated by J. V. Wertsch (Ed.). New York: Wiley. A neurologist’s view of the close relationship of language to cognition, gained largely from study of a large group of brain-damaged patients. Vygotskii, L. S. (1962) Thought and language. translated by E.Hanfmann and G. Vakar (Eds.). Cambridge, Ma.: MIT Press. In this classic written several decades earlier in Russian, Vygotskii (there are other transliterations of his name from the Cyrilic) shows with ingenious experiments how language comes to dominate thinking in the course of child development. The Split-Brain Preparation For several decades neurosurgeons have occasionally severed the corpus callosum, the bundle of fibers that connects the left and right halves of the brain, to relieve otherwise intractable epilepsy. The side effects seemed to be minimal until Sperry (1966) discovered that the patients were aware only of stimuli that entered one hemisphere. The brain split also affected motor activity, for instance where the hand controlled by the reading hemisphere picks up a book while the hand controlled by the other hemisphere tries to put it down. Sperry’s seminal discovery spawned a research specialty investigating split brains in animals and humans. Gazzaniga (1970; 1995), a student of Sperry’s, summarizes subsequent work defining the deficit and its origins. To study the effects of a severed corpus callosum more closely, researchers began investigating monkeys whose hemispheres had been isolated surgically. Gazzaniga, M. 1970. The Bisected Brain. New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts. Interprets classical studies by Sperry, Gazzaniga and others in humans and monkeys defining the different specializations of left and right cortical hemispheres. Consciousness is located in the ‘dominant’ hemisphere, the left in most people. The test, though, is that the dominant hemisphere controls speech, so we hear only from that hemisphere in split-brain patients. In normal people, te two hemispheres are tightly and intimately connected. Gazzaniga, M. 1995. Principles of human brain organization derived from split-brain studies. Neuron, 14, 217-228. Reviews further work on the specializations of the two brain hemispheres derived from studies of animals and split-brain patients, finding a conscious hemisphere that emphasizes language and sequential organization, and an unconscious non-dominant hemisphere that does more holistic processing. The differences appear in only a few cortical areas. Sperry, R. 1966. Brain bisection and consciousness. In J. Eccles (Ed.), Brain and Conscious Experience. New York: Springer-Verlag. Nobel laureate Roger Sperry describes experiments that restrict stimulation to one side of the brain or the other in split-brain patients, finding consciousness in only one hemisphere, termed the dominant hemisphere. The work revolutionized study of the neurological basis of consciousness. Memory In one dominant interpretation, consciousness is nothing more or less than the operation of a particular kind of working memory. The test for conscious awareness is often a memory test, asking whether a person remembers what has just transpired. Grossberg (1999) reviews these links with an eye to the contrast between consciousness of sensory stimulation and lack of consciousness of the mechanisms of motor execution. A motor learning system probably centered in the cerebellum handles unconscious learning for instance of how to ride a bicycle. Milner et al. (1998) describe the role of episodic memory, mostly from intensive study of a patient who lost the ability to form new long-term memories due to an operation that removed his hippocampus on both sides. Baddeley (2007) reviews his influential discoveries during a lifetime of work on memory, differentiating a number of memory systems, their functions, and their interactions. In another memory-related line of research, Reber (1967) discovered that learning without awareness was possible even for verbal learning. This paper founded a line of research by many workers, investigating possible complications in the design and interpretation of the work. Recent research (Moore et al., 2012) takes advantage of this tradition, using a similar method to investigate the sense of agency, the sense that an action is purposeful. Baddeley, A.D. 2007. Working Memory, Thought and Action. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Baddeley describes the episodic buffer, the phonological loop, and other components of working memory that were previously lumped together as short-term memory. A ‘central executive’ manages the whole system. Grossberg, S. 1999. The link between brain learning, attention, and consciousness. Consciousness and Cognition, 8, 1 – 44. Learning and memory are seen as keys to consciousness, driving attention and motivating behavior. Milner, B., Squire, L. R. & Kandel, E. R. 1998. Cognitive neuroscience and the study of memory. Neuron, 20, 445-468. Demonstrates with data from neurological patients that ability to form new long-term memories is not essential for consciousness. Moore, J. W., Middleton, D., Haggard, P. & Fletcher, P. C. 2012. Exploring implicit and explicit aspects of sense of agency. Consciousness and Cognition, 21, 1748-1753. This brief paper directly pits explicit and implicit learning against one another, finding separate mechanisms for the two kinds of learning that interact with one another in the short term. Reber, A. 1967. Implicit learning of artificial grammars. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 6, 855-863. Subjects could learn grammatical rules of an artificial grammar from examples, and use them to judge whether new strings of symbols fit the rules, all without reaizing that they had learned the rules. They were also unable to desctibe the rules when asked. Sperling, G. 1960. The information available in brief presentation. Psychological Monographs, 74, Whole No. 498. The discovery of a high-capacity sensory memory that lasts less than half a second and operates unconsciously, but feeds longer-term memory systems. It is tightly connected to a particular sense modality and preserves information without interpreting it. Neurophysiological Models The global workspace theory of Baars (2005) was one of the first and still one of the most influential theories of the brain mechanisms of consciousness. Functions of consciousness are examined by Pribram (1990) and by Morsella (2005), both taking a modular approach. Gazzaniga and Miller (2009) take the extreme view of the limited role of consciousness in the brain. Finally, Pereira et al. (2010) put it all together by summarizing and comparing various theories. Baars, B. J. 2005. Global workspace theory of consciousness: Toward a cognitive neuroscience of human experience. Progress in Brain Research, 150, 45 – 53. Describes recent work on one of the leading theories of consciousness, as allowing access to wide regions of the brain with varying functions. Gazzaniga, M. & Miller, M. B. 2009. The left hemisphere does not miss the right hemisphere. In S. Saureys & G. Tononi (Eds.), The Neurobiology of consciousness Pp. 261-270. Amsterdam: Elsevier. This chapter represents the most extreme view of the limitations of consciousness. The only conscious part of the brain is an area in the left prefrontal cortex whose job is to observe the unconsciously directed behavior of the owner of the brain, as though by a third party, and tell a story about that behavior. The story is then used by unconscious parts of the brain to plan future behavior. Everything else is unconscious. Morsella, E. 2005. The function of phenomenal states: Supramodular interaction theory. Psychological Review, 112, 1000 – 1021. A neurologically based analysis of a modular structure of the brain, and modular interactions in the brain. Pereira, J. R. A., Edwards, J. C. W., Lehmann, D., Nunn, C., Trehub, A. & Velmans, M. 2010. Understanding consciousness: A collaborative attempt to elucidate contemporary theories. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 17, 213-19. An even-handed review of both conceptual and scientific theories, illustrating lack of consensus among those studying consciousness. Pribram, K. H. 1990. Introduction: Brain and consciousness. In E. R. John (Ed.), Machinery of the Mind. Cambridge, Ma.: Birkhaeuser. Consciousness is related to planning, resulting in reflective self-awareness that is traced back through von Uexkull in the early 20th century to Brentano in the 19th. Consciousness allows the organism to operate in the world despite the immediate demands of the environment, rather than because of those demands. Social Models An important set of approaches consider cnsciousness to arise from the evolutionary pressure for humans and other organisms to understand the intentions of others and to anticipate their actions. The resulting capability is turned back on the self, resulting in self-awareness. Baumeister and Masicampo (2010) propose a function of consciousness in social interactions; Graziano and Kastner (2011) take the idea further, proposing that the same mental machinery is used in detecting the mental states and intentions of others (‘theory of mind’) and in detecting our own mental states and intentions (consciousness). Minsky (1985), a computer scientist, independently proposes a mind made up of a cluster of specialized modules. Baumeister, R. F. & Masicampo, E. J. 2010. Conscious thought is for facilitating social and cultural interactions: How mental simulations serve the animal-culture interface. Psychological Review, 117, 945-971. Anticipates the theory of Graziano & Kastner, below, proposing a practical function for consciousness. Graziano, M. S. A. and Kastner, S. 2011. Human consciousness and its relationship to social neuroscience: A novel hypothesis. Cognitive Neuroscience, 2, 98-113. A brilliant analysis starting with awareness as a perceptual reconstruction of attention. The mental machinery that evolved to resolve other people’s awareness is turned back on ourselves to compute information about our own awareness. Minsky, M. 1985. The Society of Mind. New York: Simon and Schuster. Demonstrates how the mind can be analyzed as a large group of semi-independent modules, most of them operating unconsciously. Society is used as a metaphor for brain organization.