Generating a simple yet comprehensive theory of public opinion as evaluated through survey response is by no means an easy task. John Zaller and Stanley Feldman hope to do just this while supporting their assumption that respondents to surveys do not have defined preferences but “respond to survey questions on the basis of whatever ideas are at the top of their heads at the moment of answering.” (579) Although Zaller and Feldman’s work may seem plausible and was certainly within the skeptical nature of the public opinion cannon at the time it was written, the authors are too quick to deem their results indicative of personal conflict among attitudes held by the general public. Zaller and Feldman’s results certainly indicate that Americans are ambivalent on some questions that are relatively broad in scope, but the article alone cannot prove much beyond that, also leaves itself susceptible to criticisms of response bias. This is the thesis or topic sentence; it lays out the course the rest of the paper will take, as well as my main argument, that the author’s conclusions are not generalizable, and may be flawed due to response bias (response bias, in a survey, occurs when respondents change their answers to questions in order to please the person who is asking them). The authors begin by questioning interpretations of traditional public opinion research. Particularly Zaller and Feldman tease out the conflict between response instability, which denotes the component of randomness in survey responses, and response effects, which argues that survey questions do not simply shape public opinion but also measure it. Zaller and Feldman conclude that the interplay between these two public opinion phenomenon must be settled by “devis[ing] a theory that accommodates both response instability and response effects.” (583) A series of axioms are then constructed to support their overarching theory. These axioms, that most people are ambivalent about issues, that responses are determined by immediate salient considerations, and that a recent considerations are more likely to influence results, are then verified with data and, in turn, lead the authors to conclude that individuals do not hold true attitudes, but a series of inconsistent and often autonomous reactions that change depending on questions asked. Although Zaller and Feldman’s argument is persuasive, it seems that, at its best, it is only a conditional argument. (This is my thesis or topic sentence for this paragraph. Notice that it supports my thesis in the first paragraph, notably, “Zaller and Feldman’s results certainly indicate that Americans are ambivalent on some questions that are relatively broad in scope, but the article alone cannot prove much beyond that.” This paragraph, therefore, will posit the conditional nature of the study is responsible for its limited scope. It seems logical to assume, for instance, the average American citizen does not hold stable preferences on relatively abstract issues, such as the government making sure every person has a good standard of living. However, it would seem foolish to extend this theory to more individual level preferences, such as weather a citizen likes rap music more than rock or prefers classical music to either one. To extend this simplistic model of public opinion to politics, it may seem perfectly natural that one may hold conflicting opinions about their duty to help the needy, but have very clear ideas about which presidential candidate (Republican or Democrat) they will vote for. Therefore, it is not logical to conclude that the public holds arbitrary opinions about all subjects. This final sentence is a conclusion of this topic. This paragraph claims the authors did not account for the fact that abstract political preferences may be more heavily influenced by response bias than simple political questions. Underscoring the conditionality of Zaller and Felman’s argument is their limited methodology in terms of questions. The topic sentence in the third paragraph indicates this argument will further explain the one presented in the paragraph above. All of the questions asked dealt with social issues that, very often, are seen as racially coded. These questions included inquiries into subjects’ feelings regarding aid to blacks, and their thoughts concerning the government letting each person get ahead on their own. There is nothing uncommon about the assumption that people change the expression of their preferences based on their social situation. It is not uncommon to think that racist whites, for example, would utilize a certain semantic at home or with their white friends at a bar, and a different semantic coding when on the bus with many people of mixed race. Even politicians give different responses to different questions in front of different audiences. Now the paper is beginning to narrow its focus while critically attacking very specific issues within the text. Furthermore, real world examples are being introduced to further illustrate problems with the authors’ theory. Applying this logic to A Simple Theory of the Survey Response, would lead one to conclude that it would be perfectly natural for respondents to change their answers when responding to questions regarding “letting each person get ahead on their own,” or that these responses would change on the heels of other questions pertaining to black issues. It seems natural for respondents to change their answers to be more socially acceptable at the time. Therefore, it seems completely plausible that the ambivalence demonstrated by Zaller and Feldman was generated by a response bias because of the limited nature of the questions. To further investigate this issue, a study could be conducted that utilized the same methodology but broadened the diversity of questions beyond those discussed in the article. The paper does not end with a conclusion about the article, or how I feel about it. Instead, it ends with concrete suggestions of how the study could be improved, or ideas for further research. Works Cited