Vocabulary for the Study of Religion Volume 3 P–Z, Index Edited by Robert A. Segal Kocku von Stuckrad LEIDEN | BOSTON 2015 This is a digital offfprint for restricted use only | © 2015 Koninklijke Brill NV Table of Contents Volume 1 Introduction ................................................................................................................................................................ vii List of Contributors .................................................................................................................................................. viii List of Articles ............................................................................................................................................................ xvii Articles A–E ................................................................................................................................................................ 1 Volume 2 Articles F–O ................................................................................................................................................................ 1 Volume 3 Articles P–Z ................................................................................................................................................................. 1 Index ............................................................................................................................................................................. 619 178 Race / Racism Gilroy, P., Against Race: Imagining Political Culture beyond the Color Line, Cambridge MA, 2000. Goodman, A.H. et al., (eds.) (2003) Genetic Nature/ Culture: Anthropology and Science Beyond the TwoCulture Divide, Berkeley, CA: University of California Press. Gould, S.J., The Mismeasure of Man, New York, 1996 [1981]. Miles, R., Capitalism and Unfree Labour: Anomaly or Necessity? London, 1989. Morning, A., The Nature of Race: How Scientists Think and Teach About Human Diffference, Berkeley, 2011. Myers, K., Racetalk: Racism Hiding in Plain Sight, Boulder, 2005. Omi, M., and H. Winant, Racial Formation in the United States: From the 1960s to the 1990s, New York, 21994. Picca, L., and J. Feagin, Two-Faced Racism: Whites in the Backstage and Frontstage, London, 2007. Amy Ansell Radicalism Radicalism is a familiar concept in academic and popular discourse, a concept that picks out what is generally regarded as a signifijicant socio-political and broader cultural phenomenon. However, it is a concept that is rarely clarifijied. Consequently, much of the discourse concerning radicalism—whether encountered in political science departments or in daily newspapers—is mired in confusion. The initial problem facing the scholar of radicalism is therefore conceptual rather than, say, evaluative. Put simply, the question that faces the scholar in the fijirst instance is the following: What is radicalism? What is it that, for example, supposed political radicalisms like Marxism and fascism have in common? In what sense do the supposed religious radicalisms of Thomas Müntzer and Sayyid Qutb belong to the same family? Meaning of the Term The difffijiculty associated with the conceptual problem in question owes to the largely, though by no means exclusively, negative connotations of the term “radicalism.” The principal connotation—at least, the principal negative connotation—of the term results from its association with extremism. Indeed, the terms “radicalism” and “extremism” are often used interchangeably. But what can we make of extremism as such? Extremism may be taken to denote two things: (1) the holding of marginal or outlandish views (views at the extremes of the relevant spectrum of views) and (2) a willingness to resort to violence in support of these views. The marginal views in question may take any number of forms, but fundamentalist and utopian views are perhaps the most notable examples in this context. The violence to which the extremist is willing to resort may also take various forms, but terrorist and revolutionary forms are arguably the most notable examples here. If the defijinition of extremism above is adequate, then merely (1) holding outlandish views does not make one an extremist (or, generally, the kind of fijigure others need to worry too much about). More contentiously, on this defijinition, merely (2) resorting to violence in support of one’s views does not make one an extremist (though it might make one the kind of fijigure others need to worry about). Resorting to violence in support of, say, mainstream views may be problematic, but it is not an example of extremism. Thus, the mere fundamentalist or utopian is no extremist. Nor is the mere revolutionary or (perhaps counter-intuitively) terrorist an extremist. But are radicals necessarily any of these things, that is, extremists, fundamentalists, utopians, revolutionaries, or terrorists? This remains to be seen. The principal positive connotation of “radicalism” results from its association with the idea of progress or with the progressive tradition. Thus, some think of radicalism as being bound up with the attempt to achieve change (or fundamental change) for the better in some or even every socio-political or cultural domain. Radicals, put crudely, try to make the world a better (or a fundamentally better) place in some or even every respect. What is immediately problematic here, however, is that many radicals resist such a characterization or deny the association between This is a digital offfprint for restricted use only | © 2015 Koninklijke Brill NV Radicalism radicalism and progress. That is to say, a non-progressive form of radicalism is apparent. Radical ecologists and postmoderns, for example, are highly critical of certain supposed commitments within the progressive tradition: commitments to an instrumental conception of reason or an essentialist conception of human nature, for instance. Nevertheless, such radicals still associate radicalism positively with other notions. What these are is a matter of some conjecture, but one possibility is the notion of “adequacy,” especially in circumstances of “crisis.” Thus, non-progressive, ecological radicals think of their brand of radicalism as representing an adequate response to the ecological crisis. Non-radical environmentalists, by contrast, are accused of responding inadequately—of not going far enough (theoretically and practically) in order to escape the crisis situation. If we attempt to trace the etymological and historical development of the term “radicalism”— as opposed to describing its contemporary connotations in ahistorical isolation—we may be in a better position to clarify the concept at hand. Etymologically, “radicalism” derives from the Latin noun radix, meaning “root” (as in the root of a plant). Thus, in strict etymological terms, “radicalism” denotes some kind of interest in or orientation towards “roots.” More contentiously, it denotes an orientation towards “foundations” and “origins” as well as “roots”—at least, insofar as the term has developed historically (if not in strict etymological terms). The word “radicalism” came into use in English in the early nineteenth century. However, the word “radical” had been in use for centuries beforehand. As an adjective, its use is recorded from the end of the fourteenth century. In its early senses, it described that which pertained to the root, essence, basis, or foundation of something or somebody: a vital principle, a defijining attribute, an original cause, and so on. By the seventeenth century, the adjective was used to describe change or action that afffects the foundations or essence of something or somebody: that is, very basic and signifijicant change or action. It was only from the 179 eighteenth century that the adjective was used to describe political or social change or action (and associated beliefs) of the same kind: originally, in the late-eighteenth century and early-nineteenth century, basic and signifijicant political or social reform; somewhat later, especially from the mid-nineteenth century, even more fundamental political or social transformation (or “revolution”). Such change (and its associated beliefs) was originally understood to be of a democratic and/or a socialistic nature. Only in the early-twentieth century did “radical” begin to describe the “right-wing” equivalent as well, though such usage became more prominent later in the century (especially in the post-war period). As a noun, “radical” was fijirst used in a very obscure anatomical sense in the early-fijifteenth century and later used in a much less obscure linguistic sense by the late-sixteenth century. Politically, the noun came into use in the early-nineteenth century to describe supporters of “radical” political and social reform. (It took on its revolutionary sense somewhat later in the nineteenth century and its right-wing sense in the twentieth century, certainly by the 1960s.) The noun “radicalism” was fijirst used—to refer to the beliefs and practices of political “radicals”—at around the same time. Thus, although the meaning of “radical” was not primarily political, the meaning of “radicalism” was. At fijirst, it referred to the beliefs and practices of “radical reformers.” These radical reformers called for substantive political change, procedural or even constitutional. As such, they were distinguished from moderate reformers, who only called for piecemeal procedural or legislative change. But those radical reformers who later became known as “philosophical radicals” were eager to distance themselves from utopian, socialistic, and revolutionary elements in the emerging tradition of political radicalism. Thus, they declared that radicalism was in fact “not dangerous” from the standpoint of the established socio-political order. By the middle of the nineteenth century, however, more “dangerous” forms of radicalism— utopian, socialistic, and revolutionary—did rise to This is a digital offfprint for restricted use only | © 2015 Koninklijke Brill NV 180 radicalism prominence. And these “dangerous” forms were no longer seen as distinctively left-wing in the twentieth century, but also as nationalistic, religious, and even reactionary. Analysis of the Concept In the etymological sense, as we have seen, radicalism denotes an interest in or orientation towards roots. Analysis of the concept of “radicalism” typically begins with this etymological insight and rarely adds anything to it. Thus, Karl Marx, for example, famously wrote that “To be radical is to grasp things by the root” (Tucker ed. 1978: 60). Somewhat more precisely, Zygmunt Bauman recently wrote: Acts, undertakings, means, and measures may be called “radical” when they reach down to the roots: of a problem, a challenge, a task. Note, however, that the Latin noun “radix,” to which the metaphorical uses of “radical” trace their pedigree, refers not only to roots, but also to foundations and to origins. (Pugh ed. 2009: 25) According to Bauman, then, radicalism denotes a practical or theoretical orientation towards the roots, foundations, or origins of something. However, there is an immediate problem with this defijinition and with etymologically-based defijinitions in general: they are partial, inadequate, and in need of refijinement. The emphasis of such defijinitions is on radicalism as a mere orientation— any kind of orientation—towards roots or fundamental objects. This raises the possibility of a non-fundamental orientation towards fundamental objects—of, as it were, a “non-radical radicalism”—such that one might (as a supposed radical) take a rather superfijicial interest in fundamental matters. (Nevertheless, Marx’s sense of “grasping” and Bauman’s sense of “reaching down” may be intended to counter this possibility; a possibility which could, incidentally, dissolve the distinction between fundamentalism and radicalism.) Of course, an over-emphasis on the fundamental orientation of radicalism would result in a similarly partial or inadequate defijinition of radicalism as a fundamental orientation towards some kind—indeed any kind—of object. This raises the possibility of a fundamental orientation towards non-fundamental objects—of, as it were, a “radical non-radicalism”—such that one might (as a supposed radical) take a fundamental interest in some rather superfijicial matter. Moving beyond mere etymology, then, our analysis suggests that there are two seemingly necessary conditions for the application of the term “radicalism”: fundamentality of object and fundamentality of orientation. Radicalism as such might therefore be said to consist in a fundamental practical or theoretical orientation towards a fundamental object. This is a highly abstract defijinition that will only be concretized (to a degree) when we turn to the specifijic forms of radicalism. But, even at this level of abstraction, some may wish to build some more contentious conditions into the defijinition of radicalism, a defijinition that they might claim to be too thin as it stands. One such condition is the motivation condition: some contend that radicalism is necessarily motivated by the sense that something is amiss with existing practice or theory. Another contentious condition is the conclusion condition: some contend that radicalism—even in its theoretical form—is necessarily productive of new or at least unorthodox results. A third contentious condition is the action conclusion: some contend that radicalism—even in its theoretical form—necessarily gives rise to action. A fijinal contentious condition (at least for present purposes) is the ideology condition: some contend that radicalism is necessarily identifijiable with a particular ideology or family of ideologies. We may grant—as a matter of fact—(1) that radicals are often motivated by the sense that existing practices are unjust or that existing theory is on the wrong track, (2) that radical theory often generates unorthodox conclusions, and (3) that radical theory is often tied up with some attempt to change the world. However, these are contingent This is a digital offfprint for restricted use only | © 2015 Koninklijke Brill NV 181 Radicalism facts about radicalism which should not be built into its defijinition. There is no reason, in principle, why radicals should not (1) be motivated by simple curiosity about existing practices or existing theory (such that they experiment with or inquire into these in a “radical” fashion), (2) arrive at conventional conclusions (albeit by “radical means”), or (3) engage in abstract theorizing only. By contrast with the fijirst three contentious conditions, the attempt to build the ideology condition into a defijinition of radicalism is not a case of building contingent facts in, but of defijining radicalism to ideological taste. This is most (though not solely) apparent when those who situate themselves on the ideological left claim a monopoly on radicalism, such that radicalism is seen as a left-wing phenomenon only. However, there is no reason in principle why ideological outlook should preclude the possibility of fundamentally orienting oneself towards a fundamental object. Even conservatives (of certain varieties, at least) exhibit radical tendencies in our sense, to say nothing of fascists and others on the extreme right. If we return to the connotations of “radicalism” discussed in the previous section, and question the justifijication for (as opposed to the explanation of) the association between radicalism and extremism or the idea of progress, it becomes readily apparent that both associations are tenuous. There is nothing about radicalism as such (on our defijinition) that ties it to either (1) the holding of outlandish views and willingness to resort to violence in support of these views or (2) the attempt to make the world a better place in some or even every respect. Radicals may, of course, hold outlandish views and be willing to resort to violence in support of these views: that is to say, radicalism may be extremist. And radicals may attempt to make the world a better (or a fundamentally better) place in at least some respect: that is to say, radicalism may be progressive. In fact, radicals may hold outlandish views, be willing to resort to violence in support of these views, and thereby attempt to make the world a better place: that is to say, radicalism may be simultaneously extremist and progressive. But there are cases of non-progressive radicalism (as we noted above). And abstract theoretical radicalism, at the very least, is clearly not extremist in itself (since it does not commit the radical to any kind of practice, let alone violent practice). Forms of Radicalism If we attempt to develop a taxonomy of radicalism(s), we need to begin by clarifying a basic distinction that has been employed above: that is, the distinction between practical radicalism (or radicalism as a mode of action, a specifijic way of acting on a specifijic kind of thing) and theoretical radicalism (or radicalism as a mode of thought, a specifijic way of thinking about a specifijic kind of thing). We may then further develop our taxonomy by distinguishing the cultural domains within which radicalism—whether practical or theoretical (or, indeed, both)—is evident. The principal domains in question are seemingly the political, the religious, and the aesthetic, though there is no reason to suppose that radicalism must be limited to these domains. Radicalism as a mode of action may be defijined as a fundamental practical orientation towards (or fundamental action on) a fundamental object in a given domain. The fundamental object in question is a defijining feature of the relevant domain: that is to say, in the absence of this feature, the domain would be fundamentally diffferent and would have to be redefijined. The fundamental orientation in question represents a practical challenge to that domain or, rather, a practical challenge to the same fundamental object (or defijining feature) within it. The (radical) practical challenge is such that it may lead to the abolition of this object or the transformation of the relevant domain. Radicalism as a mode of thought may be defijined as a fundamental theoretical orientation towards (or fundamental inquiry into) a fundamental object in a given domain. The fundamental object in question is, once again, a defijining feature of the relevant domain. The fundamental orientation in question represents a theoretical challenge This is a digital offfprint for restricted use only | © 2015 Koninklijke Brill NV 182 to that domain or, rather, a theoretical challenge to the same fundamental object (or defijining feature) within it. The (radical) theoretical challenge is such that it may undermine this object or destabilize the relevant domain. Fundamental objects vary across cultural domains. Indeed, these defijining objects distinguish the diffferent cultural domains. Fundamental approaches, by contrast, may be less domain-specifijic; they may not distinguish cultural domains to the same extent. But what are the fundamental objects in the principal domains in which radicalism is apparent? In the political domain, they include fundamental socio-political norms, practices, relations, and institutions. At the institutional level, then, political radicals are fundamentally oriented—both practically and theoretically— towards the polity and/or the socio-economic order. Modern political radicals (of the institutional variety) therefore present a fundamental challenge to the state and/or capitalism, which most take to be the defijining institutions of modernity. (In their absence, modernity would have to be socio-politically redefijined.) In the religious domain, the fundamental objects include defijining objects of belief and veneration, whether these are characterized as divine, spiritual, transcendental, sacred, or supernatural. Gods and religious institutions such as churches are both examples of such objects. Religious radicals present a fundamental practical or theoretical challenge to objects of this kind, efffectively challenging us to redefijine the religious domain. In the aesthetic domain, fijinally, the fundamental objects may be seen to include works of art, artifacts in general, that which is sensible, or only that which is beautiful. Aesthetic radicals present a fundamental challenge to such objects, either theoretically challenging our very conception of the beautiful or practically challenging existing modes of creation, for example. We have spoken of radicals of the political, religious, and aesthetic varieties as presenting fundamental challenges to fundamental objects in their respective domains. But the question remains: What constitutes a fundamental challenge? What radicalism constitutes a fundamental approach? In answering this question, we can generalize to some extent across cultural domains. While fundamental objects difffer in diffferent domains, fundamental approaches are similar (or similarly characterizable) in these domains. In the case of radicalism as a mode of action (whether political, religious, or aesthetic), fundamental approaches may be reformist or revolutionary. In either case, they constitute practical attempts to transform the fundamental object(s) of the relevant domain (and thus to redefijine that domain)—gradually, in the reformist case, or immediately, in the revolutionary case. The historical notion of “radical reform” is therefore coherent on the account offfered here. In the case of radicalism as a mode of thought (whether political, religious, or aesthetic), fundamental approaches are more difffijicult to specify. What does it mean to fundamentally inquire into fundamental objects like states, churches, and artworks? We might say—with Charles Fourier (1996: 8)—that it entails employing (or attempting to employ) a method of “absolute doubt” and “absolute separation.” The former essentially involves calling (or being willing to call) the “necessity, excellence, and permanence” of the fundamental object(s) into question. The latter involves taking (or attempting to take) nothing for granted with respect to the object(s), especially on the basis of received wisdom. Thus, the theoretical radical adopts (or attempts to adopt) a position of what we might call non-presumptive criticism with respect to a fundamental object in some cultural domain. Bibliography Baylor, M.G. (ed.), The Radical Reformation, Cambridge UK, 1991. Edwards, J., The Radical Attitude and Modern Political Theory, Basingstoke, 2007. Egbert, D.D., Social Radicalism and the Arts: Western Europe, London, 1970. Fourier, C., The Theory of the Four Movements, eds, G. Stedman Jones and I. Patterson, Cambridge UK, 1996. This is a digital offfprint for restricted use only | © 2015 Koninklijke Brill NV 183 Rapture Gottlieb, R.S. (ed.), Radical Philosophy: Tradition, Counter-Tradition, Politics, Philadelphia, 1993. McLaughlin, P., Radicalism: A Philosophical Study, Basingstoke, 2012. Pugh, J. (ed.), What is Radical Politics Today? Basingstoke, 2009. Tucker, R.C. (ed.), The Marx-Engels Reader, New York, 1978. Paul McLaughlin Rapture The “rapture” is an eschatological concept, paralleling the Christian doctrine of resurrection, that has evolved from its origins in the established churches of early nineteenth-century Britain and Ireland to dominate large and influential sections of contemporary American evangelicalism. Toward the end of the twentieth century, the theology of the rapture found frequent iteration in popular culture, providing critical narrative background in Michael Tolkin’s controversial fijilm The Rapture (1991), being parodied in the Simpsons cartoon series (2005), and being sympathetically expounded in the Left Behind novels (1995–2007), which sold over 65 million copies and repeatedly topped the New York Times bestseller list. By the end of the twentieth century, the doctrine of the rapture had moved from its sectarian origins into the American cultural mainstream. This movement of the cultural position of the rapture has impacted upon its articulation while confijirming its connotation of cultural and political despair—a despair made all the more ironic by the rising political influence of a number of its key advocates and by the extraordinary sales of the Left Behind novels. The etymology of “rapture” derives from rapere, a term used in the Vulgate translation of 1 Thessalonians 4:17 to describe the “catching away” of Christians at the parousia of Jesus Christ. Although it is difffijicult to trace the fijirst modern usage of the term, it is possible to identify its circulation in English and American Protestant discourse from the late seventeenth century. Until the mid- nineteenth century, the term functioned as a broadly equivalent descriptor of the resurrection of the dead, which, in traditional orthodoxy, was believed to occur simultaneously with the second coming of Jesus Christ. Throughout this period, “rapture” tended to be used as a verb, describing the experience of resurrection, rather than as a noun, describing the resurrection as an event. This shift toward the usage of “rapture” as a noun occurred as the term was invested with specifijic meaning in the 1820s and 1830s, when the members of a Protestant, conservative and socially elite circle initially associated with Trinity College Dublin and the University of Oxford read 1 Thessalonians 4:17 and similar passages to suggest that true Christians would be suddenly and could be imminently taken to heaven by Jesus Christ (“the rapture”). These believers came to argue that this event would be followed by seven years of tribulation, in which the Antichrist would rise to power and wield his formidable resources to efffect the extinction of Jews and those Gentiles who would convert to authentic Christianity after the rapture; and that this tribulation would be followed by the second coming, a series of fijinal judgements, the millennium and the inauguration of the new heavens and earth. This emerging eschatological system, later described as “dispensational premillennialism,” reflected the particular cultural and political anxieties of its early adopters, narrating an historiography of despair in which the future of the established churches looked bleak and the developing democratic impulse of post-revolution Europe looked menacing. One of the system’s best advocates was an Anglican priest named John Nelson Darby (1800–1882), who in the late 1820s seceded from the Church of Ireland to lead the “Plymouth Brethren,” and whose influence on the eschatological thought of evangelicals was “both profound and pivotal, more so perhaps than any other Christian leader for the last 200 years” (Sizer 2004: 96). Darby’s frequent travels in North America helped to facilitate the widespread circulation of the new theology and its elevation to near-creedal status through the influence of This is a digital offfprint for restricted use only | © 2015 Koninklijke Brill NV