NATIONAL QUALIFICATIONS CURRICULUM SUPPORT Psychology Cognitive Psychology Staff Resource Pack [ADVANCED HIGHER] Gerard Keegan Kilmarnock College Acknowledgements This document is produced by Learning and Teaching Scotland as part of the National Qualifications support programme for Psychology. Original drawings are acknowledged with thanks to Douglas McConnach. First published 2003 Electronic version 2003 © Learning and Teaching Scotland 2003 This publication may be reproduced in whole or in part for educational purposes by educational establishments in Scotland provided that no profit accrues at any stage. TH E TH EO RY O F P E RF EC T CO M PE T I T IO N CONTENTS Section 1: Section 2: Section 3: Guidance for tutors 1 Introduction Statement of standards Approaches to learning and teaching How to use this pack Recording student attainment Guidance on the content and context for this unit Guidance on learning and teaching approaches for this unit Guidance on approaches to assessment for this unit 1 2 4 6 7 8 Student materials 11 What is cognitive psychology? Setting the scene Outcomes 1 and 2: The concepts Perception Attention 23 72 Student materials (continued) Outcome 3: Issues The use of non-human animals in research Section 4: 8 9 General references 91 101 vi COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 G UI DA N CE FO R TU T O RS SECTION 1 Introduction This is an optional component unit of Advanced Higher Psychology. It has a value of one credit at Advanced Higher. Unit content The unit has three outcomes: 1. 2. 3. Analyse major theories in cognitive psychology. Evaluate research evidence relating to theories in cognitive psychology. Analyse an issue in cognitive psychology. Content of this pack This pack contains resources that will assist the tutor with the delivery of t his unit. It contains material relevant to all of the outcomes. Core skills Details on core skills are obtainable from the Scottish Qualifications Authority (SQA). COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) 1 © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 G UI DA N CE FO R TU T O RS Statement of standards Outcome 1 Analyse major theories in cognitive psychology. Performance criteria (a) Competing theoretical explanations in cognitive psychology are explained accurately and comprehensively. (b) Competing theoretical explanations in cognitive psychology are compared accurately in terms of their main features. (c) Competing theoretical explanations in cognitive psychology are contrasted accurately in terms of their main features. Evidence requirements To demonstrate satisfactory attainment of this outcome, candidates should produce written or oral responses to cover all performance criteria. They are required to do so for two key concepts chosen from the following: perception, attention, memory, language and thinking. Written/oral responses will typically be extended responses of about 1,000 words for each key concept and associated research evidence, integrating Outcomes 1 and 2. Outcome 2 Evaluate research evidence relating to theories in cognitive psychology. Performance criteria (a) Research evidence relating to theories in cognitive psychology is described accurately. (b) Research evidence relating to theories in cognitive psychology is explained clearly and accurately in terms of its strength of support for the theories. (c) Validity of conclusions based on this research evidence is explained clearly and accurately. Evidence requirements To demonstrate satisfactory attainment of this outcome, candidates should produce written or oral responses to cover all performance criteria. They are required to do so for research evidence in two key concepts chosen from the following: perception, attention, memory, language and thinking. 2 COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 G UI DA N CE FO R TU T O RS Written/oral responses will typically be extended responses of about 1,000 words for each key concept and associated research evidence, integrating Outcomes 1 and 2. Outcome 3 Analyse an issue in cognitive psychology. Performance criteria (a) An issue relevant to cognitive psychology is explained clearly and accurately. (b) Essential arguments of this issue are explained accurately and comprehensively in a balanced way. (c) The contribution of this issue to cognitive psychology is explained accurately and comprehensively. Evidence requirements To demonstrate satisfactory attainment of this outcome, candidates should produce written or oral responses to cover all performance criteria. They are required to do so for one issue from the following: science in cognition, animals in research, representations, and computer modelling in cognitive psychology or false memory. Written/oral responses will typically be an extended response of about 1,000 words. COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) 3 © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 G UI DA N CE FO R TU T O RS Approaches to learning and teaching In delivering these units, it is useful if tutors achieve a balance between tutor exposition and experiential learning. It is important to recognise that learners acquire and process information in a number of ways to help them learn. These include visually, aurally, in discussion or exchange with others, during group-based problem solving activities, and during solitary reflection. Students should be encouraged from the beginning to draw on their own experiences, perceptions, and their previous and current learning. Personal experience of interacting with a range of people, and in a number of different situations is an invaluable source of knowledge and is highly relevant to cognitive psychology. The sharing of experiences and insights will promote general awareness that cognitive psychology assists self -understanding and an understanding of humans in a variety of contexts. Students should also be encouraged to gather and use information about different people’s actions, thoughts and feelings and to consider how these affect themselves and others. Relevant quality newspaper and/or magazine articles and video/film productions are useful resources, which bring cognitive psychology to life, so that it can be shared by comparatively large groups of people at any one time. This remains appropriate even when the material is fictional, provided it presents us with a true picture of the human condition and is not deliberately sensationalised. In delivering this unit, it is appropriate that a multicultural approach is taken since the learning needs of individuals vary according to their cultural background. Case studies, role-play and simulations should incorporate characters and elements from different social and cultura l backgrounds wherever possible. Unit induction At the beginning of the unit ‘Cognitive Psychology’, tutors should ensure that students are clear about its nature and purpose. Induction for this unit should last about two hours and should include an intr oduction to the content of the unit, provide a programme of work and explain the arrangements for assessment and reassessment. At this point students can be given the Candidates’ Guide from the Unit Assessment Pack. This helps explain what the unit is about and how it is assessed. 4 COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 G UI DA N CE FO R TU T O RS In order to allow students to make a confident start, reference should be made to links with previous or other current learning with which they are familiar. It is also important to discuss and explore the nature of the course o r group award being undertaken by the group if appropriate. It may be necessary to include induction exercises, particularly if the group is a new one. The type and number of exercises used will, however, depend on the nature of the particular group, their familiarity with each other and with the tutor involved. Learning environment The expertise of the tutor is invaluable in developing skills in, approaches to, and insights about the subject of cognitive psychology. Tutors should aim to create a relaxed and enjoyable learning environment, which is both motivating and supportive. In order that a people perspective is always present the following conditions should be met: • the provision of a learning climate in which students feel supported and able to express their thoughts and ideas; • a teaching style that promotes a supportive learning climate; • learning and teaching methods which draw on students’ past and present learning experience and which enable them to integrate new ideas and skills during their interactions with others. Further guidance can be found in the Psychology Subject Guide. COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) 5 © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 G UI DA N CE FO R TU T O RS How to use this pack Purpose of the pack This pack is designed to provide guidance and support materials to help tutors in the delivery of the unit. The student information and activities are designed to be used by tutors in the way that suits their preferred style of delivery and the needs of their particular student group. This pack has not been designed for open learning purposes. Additional reading, exercises, assignments, etc. and answers to enclosed exercises and worksheets will be provided and facilitated by the tutor. The student activities in the pack will require to be followed up and brought together by the tutor in whatever way is most appropriate. The student activities in this pack cover the three outcomes and their performance criteria at Advanced Higher level. The unit in the learning/teaching situation calls for two key concepts, their features and explanations and one issue to be covered. This Staff Resource Pack endeavours to cover two key concepts, their features and explanations, and one issue. The material is presented in such a way that for each concept covered in these support notes (perception and attention) Outcome 1 (Analyse major theories in cognitive psychology) is discussed first. Outcome 2 (Evaluate research evidence relating to [these 1 ] theories in cognitive psychology) is discussed second and Outcome 3 (Analyse an issue in cognitive psychology) is dealt with last. Section 3 will deal with the issue in relation to cognitive psychology being the use of non-human animals in research. This sequence of delivery is by no means compulsory and may be rearranged at the discretion of the tutor responsible for delivering the unit. 6 COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 G UI DA N CE FO R TU T O RS Using the materials Useful learning materials in this pack include: • Information • Student activities or • Interactives All impinge on essential knowledge required for this unit. They are particularly useful as handout material. They could also be used as the focus of input by the tutor and to develop ideas further as part of question -andanswer sessions and group discussions. These information sheets can be photocopied as a separate pack, should the tutor prefer to use them either as teaching notes or as separate handout materials. Alternatively, the materials could be assembled into smaller topic packs. All worksheets, assignments, exercises and group activities have been covered on those pages that include a Student Activity or Interactive. These general activities have been developed to include exercises for individuals, pairs, triads and small groups to conduct. Tutors may well wish to alter the way in which these activities are carried out according to the needs of their particular group. Recording student attainment A recording proforma for tutors to complete for individual candidate attainment is available in the Unit Assessment pack. • Candidate’s record of progress – for individual candidates to have a record of their attainment. • Internal Assessment Record – to record the internal assessment results of the whole student group. Tutors may devise their own alternative system for recording student attainment. COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) 7 © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 G UI DA N CE FO R TU T O RS Guidance on the content and context for this unit By introducing students to a range of concepts and associated theories, research evidence and issues in cognitive psychology, it is intended to develop knowledge and understanding of cognitive psychology generally and to emphasise the significance of this area to the whole of psychology. A choice of two concepts and one issue is a feature of this unit. This provides flexibility for centres to accommodate different needs and interests in studying cognitive psychology at this level. Fuller information on the content of this unit is provided in the course details. Guidance on learning and teaching approaches for this unit General proposals regarding approaches to learning and teaching are contained in the course details. Learning and teaching approaches should be carefully selected to support the development of knowledge and understanding, investigation and application. The learning experience at this level should be interesting, to encourage enthusiasm for the subject and to stimulate and prepare candidates for independent study. The unit should be approached using a wide range of stimulus materials and teaching approaches. Candidates should be encouraged to draw upon their own experiences and should have access to resources. The material should be up-to-date and relevant to the unit, the level of study and the interests of the candidates. The emphasis throughout should be on active learning, whether as part of a whole class, in small groups or as individuals. The outcomes are interconnected and should be approached as such. Especially at A dvanced Higher it is recommended that, wherever possible, outcomes should be covered in an integrated way. An outcome-by-outcome internal assessment approach, which could lead to a compartmentalised view of psychology, should be avoided. 8 COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 G UI DA N CE FO R TU T O RS Guidance on approaches to assessment for this unit The National Assessment Bank will provide assessment instruments and guidance on implementation. This does not preclude teachers/lecturers from devising their own assessment tasks. Evidence of attainment of the outcomes for this unit may be provided through a variety of methods. However, restricted-response questions are considered to be most appropriate. Where an integrated approach is used for assessment, it will be necessary to identify in the candidate’s response where each outcome has been met. Where assessment evidence is gathered by means of a single assessment towards the end of the unit, care should be taken to ensure that sufficient time is allowed for remediation and reassessment if required. Where a candidat e has failed to achieve one or more of the outcomes, it is only necessary to reassess those outcomes that the candidate has failed to achieve. Where assessments are set which allow candidates to demonstrate performance beyond the minimum standard required , evidence gathered for internal unit assessment might also be used for grade prediction and for appeals for external course assessment. For details of the grade descriptions for external assessment, please refer to the Advanced Higher Psychology course specification. COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) 9 © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 10 COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E S 1 AN D 2 : TH E CO N C EP T S SECTION 2 Perception The Scottish Qualifications Authority (SQA) ask that we consider, in relation to the study of perception: • perceptual processing • theories and research of visual perception – constructivist, direct, interactionist • computer models of visual perception • cultural, social and developmental aspects of perception. By the end of this key concept you will have been introduced to the topic of perception and should be able to understand it in terms of an information, or mediational, process. The important area of visual perception will be explained in terms of related theory and research. Computer models of how psychology suggests we visually process information will be introduced, along with discussion about cultural, social and developmental aspects of perception. Cognitive psychology concerns the study of our cognitive or mediational processes, and is a discipline that emphasises an internal explanation of our behaviour. The word ‘cognitive’ comes from the Latin word cognitio meaning ‘apprehend, understand or know’. Cognitions, then, are those internal mental processes that involve the mind (brain processes). Cognitive processes refer to all the ways in which we obtain, use and process information from our world in order to operate successfully within it. Here we will first explore cognitive psychology generally in an attempt to understand what cognition means. Secondly, we will look at two key concepts that enable us to gain and use knowledge of the world around us. These key concepts are taken from the whole range of cognitive processes that include perception, memory, attention, language and thinking. All of these human abilities or higher-level processes are inferred and cannot be observed directly. This unit will explore two of these different aspects of cognition as key concepts, i.e. perception and attention. Study of other cognitive processes, and their applications, is at the discretion of the tutor and candidates. COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) 11 © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E S 1 AN D 2 : TH E CO N C EP T S But before we look at perception, we need to know what is meant by ‘cognitive psychology’. What is cognitive psychology? Cognitive psychology involves the study of how we take in information from our world, and how we actively process this information to respond to our world. An information processing approach Cognitive psychologists study our higher -level cognitions of perception: attention, language, memory and thinking (or problem-solving). They believe the mind consists of these five information processes, which we individually and co llectively use to operate in, upon, and through our environment. Consequently, the cognitive approach explains human behaviour and mental process from the point of view of information processing. Any dysfunction in our thoughts, feelings and behaviours are due to faulty information processing. What this means is that we might have a problem with one or more of our five mediational processes (identified above). We actively process information The cognitive approach is about how we actively process information using our mediational processes, individually and collectively, to build up our knowledge of the world. It asks how we make meaningful sense of stimuli in our world, and our resulting behaviours in it. The cognitive approach argues that we are no t passive receptors of information, as the behaviourist approach would have us believe. Our mind actively processes what information it receives, and using mediational processes, changes this information into new forms. New information is combined, compared, transformed and integrated with that which is already present. On the basis of our information processes, we build up an increasingly more complex picture of our world, and all the things in it, which affects our feelings and behaviours in our environ ment. 12 COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E S 1 AN D 2 : TH E CO N C EP T S The fall and rise of the cognitive approach From its earliest beginnings psychology has tried to understand the human mind in relation to feelings and behaviours. William Wundt is remembered for his research in 1879 into perception. Freud is r emembered for his work (from 1901) concerning the unconscious. In Perspectives we discovered that the behaviourist approach became popular largely because of its criticisms of the study of such hypothetical constructs. As a consequence, the study of what psychology originally understood itself to be – the study of the mind – became somewhat marginalised for a good part of the twentieth century. A series of events was, however, to occur, aided ironically by a behaviourist, which was to see the cognitive approach overcome its difficulty of generating scientific support for hypothetical constructs. This saw the rebirth of the cognitive approach from about the 1970s onwards, helped in its renaissance by developments in subjects as diverse as computer engineering and cognitive psychotherapy. Tolman and Honzik (1930) Behaviourism emphasises that psychology should study actual observable behaviour, and that we are to be understood in terms of stimulus –response units of behaviour learned via classical and operant conditioning. It was to be a ‘soft’ behaviourist, Edward Tolman, who challenged these assumptions, when in 1930 he suggested that organisms do something with learned S–R units that make them even more efficient and effective in their environment. This was to stimulate the important cognitive idea that we are active processors of information and not passive learners as behaviourism had suggested. In their famous experiment (1930) Tolman and Honzik built a maze environment to investigate latent learning in rats. Latent learning Latent learning is a kind of subliminal learning, which we don’t know we possess, and don’t use until there is some positive reinforcement, or environmental incentive, to do so. An example of latent learning would be where you got a lift to college from a friend every day. You may learn at a latent level the way to get to college, but as a passenger you have no reason to demonstrate your learning by ‘proving’ that you know this. You don’t even think about it. However, when yo ur friend is sick and COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) 13 © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E S 1 AN D 2 : TH E CO N C EP T S you have to drive yourself to college for the first time, if you follow the same route as your friend did, then you have demonstrated latent learning. Rats in mazes Plan of maze 14-Unit T-Alley Maze Fig 1 (From M H Elliott, ‘The effect of change of reward on the maze performance of rats’. Univ. Calif. Publ. Psychol., 1928, 4, p. 20.) In a variety of experiments with different kinds of mazes, Tolman found that, when introduced to his maze, a rat initially sn iffed about, and explored in an erratic fashion. If it eventually discovered food placed in a food box, when it was later put back into the maze the rat searched for the food and did not make as many errors, i.e. go down blind alleys, turn back on itself, etc. – as it did when first introduced to the maze. Cognitive maps Tolman thought that what must have happened is that his rats had formed a primitive cognitive map of the maze in their heads. The cognitive map was formed as a result of their first ex ploration of the maze. Whether they used it to their advantage, as measured by going 14 COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E S 1 AN D 2 : TH E CO N C EP T S more quickly and with fewer errors to the food, depended upon this earlier exploration of the maze, and whether they had been rewarded, or otherwise, when coming across the food box. Purposive behaviourism Tolman and Honzik concluded that cognitive maps allowed the rat to better understand and react to its maze environment. The earlier behaviourists seemed to be wrong in suggesting that organisms were passive learners. Tolman and Honzik (1930) indicated instead that rats are active processors of information about their world. Further, organisms such as rats process what they learn about their world in a very sophisticated fashion in order to obtain some mastery over it. This purposive behaviourism of non-humans, and by behaviourist definition humans, was to stimulate developments in the cognitive approach. Behaviourism’s mechanistic and deterministic view, that we passively learn in response to our environment, was beginning to be questioned from within behaviourism itself. A conundrum solved Tolman and Honzik had gone some way to help solve the conundrum that had plagued cognitive research since Wundt in 1879. That is, how to investigate and generate empirical data about hypothetical constructs; which – remember! – don’t exist in reality, in order to come to a scientific understanding of them. Tolman and Honzik externalised the construct of thinking in rats and studied it indirectly by obtaining empirical data in terms of times and errors made by the rats in the maze. Tolman and Honzik (1930) were then able to confidently infer on the basis of this empirical evidence that rats think in a more sophisticated fashion than earlier behaviourists had believed. They had the essential empirical data. COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) 15 © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E S 1 AN D 2 : TH E CO N C EP T S Neural networks The human equivalent of a cognitive map of our environment is sometimes referred to as a neural network. Saaranin (1973) got American college students to draw maps of their campus. Students tended to enlarge those buildings that were most important to them and shrink the less important. They were often found to be completely wrong when describing campus areas that were not as familiar to them. Similarly, Briggs (1971) discovered, on asking people to judge how far they thought one landmark was from another, that they tended to underestimate the distance between familiar landmark objects and overestimate the distance between unfamiliar landmarks. This research helps to explain the phenomenon of the Irish mile ! 16 COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E S 1 AN D 2 : TH E CO N C EP T S Interactive Study Tolman, E C and Honzik, C H, Introduction and removal of reward and maze-learning in rats, University of California Publications in Psychology, 4, 257–275, 1930 Aim To investigate latent learning in rats and the relationship betw een reinforcement, learning and performance. Method Experiment. Tolman and Honzik built a complex maze environment (see page 14). They had three groups of rats that underwent seventeen trials in the maze over seventeen days under three conditions. Group 1 rats were never fed in the maze, and when they reached the goal of the food box, were removed. Group 2 rats received the reinforcer of food every time they reached the food box, while on trials 1–10, Group 3 rats got no food but received reinforcement on trials 11–17. Results Group 1 rats always took around the same time to reach the food box and made many errors. They were observed as aimless in the maze. They just wandered around. Group 2 rats learned the intricacies of the maze quickly, and over the seventeen days of trials made progressively fewer and fewer errors. From day 11 Group 3 rats showed a sudden improvement in performance time to reach the food and made as few errors as Group 2 rats by the end of the experiment. COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) 17 © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E S 1 AN D 2 : TH E CO N C EP T S Conclusion Tolman and Honzik (1930) concluded that reinforcement from the environment may not be as important to the learning process as was previously thought. They believed reinforcement was more related to the performance of a learned behaviour. Further, this expe riment helped Tolman infer that organisms such as rats and humans do something with learned units of behaviour to make them more efficient in their environment. Tolman (1946) was to say his rats had formed primitive cognitive maps of the maze environment in their heads. Whether they used this information depended upon a successful outcome to behaving in a particular way. We learn at a latent level that may see us behave in a particular way if there is some incentive from our environment for us to do so. Interactive 18 1. What do you think latent learning means? Give an example in your answer. 2. What was the relationship that behaviourism thought existed between reinforcement and learning before Tolman and Honzik (1930)? 3. What are the three conditions of the independent variable in Tolman and Honzik (1930)? An independent variable is the variable the experimenter manipulates or changes in an experiment. 4. What evidence did the experimenters find that reinforcement is more related to performance of a learned behaviour, rather than to the learning of the behaviour itself? COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E S 1 AN D 2 : TH E CO N C EP T S 1956 – a very good year It is entirely good fortune that the author’s first birthday coincided with 1956 being the landmark year for the cognitive approach! For it would not be inappropriate to say that 1956 precipitated the growth of cognitive psychology, as it exists today. This is because in 1956 the world famous psycholinguist Noam Chomsky presented his paper on the theory of language, Jean Piaget and Bärbel Inhelder wrote about egocentrism in The Child’s Conception of Space, and George Miller’s work on short-term memory was published. In addition, 1956 saw Bruner, Goodnow and Austin debate concept formation, or how we develop different ways of thinking about the environment around us. 1956 was also the year of the Dartmouth Conference in the USA, which saw the beginnings of the AI (artificial intelligence) movement energised by innovations in computer technology. Of importance here is that cognitive psychology gave the emer ging computer technologies their information processing models about how cognitive psychology believed humankind thought and problem -solved. We share a language, in that nowadays in cognitive psychology we often come across words and concepts from information technology such as input, output, storage, retrieval, parallel processing, networking, schema, filters, etc. This is one reason why the approach uses the computer analogy to help explain why it believes we think, feel and behave the way we do. This is as an active processor of information from our world, the outcome of which explains our thoughts, feelings and behaviours. COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) 19 © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E S 1 AN D 2 : TH E CO N C EP T S What is cognitive psychology? Interactive 1. Noam Chomsky published a paper on the properties of language entitled ‘Three models for the description of language’, in I.R.E. Transactions on information theory, 1956. Find out more at http://www.rci.rutgers.edu/~cfs/305_html/Understanding/ LanguageProps.html 2. Read Miller, G A, ‘The magical number seven, plus or minus two: Some limits on our capacity for processing information’, Psychological Review, 63, pp. 81–97, 1956 at http://www.well.com/user/smalin/miller.html For a summary see http://tip.psychology.org/miller.html 20 3. Read Piaget, J and Inhelder, B, The Child’s Conception of Space, Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1956 4. Investigate concept formation by Bruner, Goodnow and Austin (1956) at http://www.cse.unsw.edu.au/~billw/cs9414/notes/ml/01intro/ 01intro.html COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E S 1 AN D 2 : TH E CO N C EP T S The human mind, the cognitive approach and the computer The cognitive approach and computer engineering share the belief that the human mind/brain can be likened to a computer. What a computer tries to do is mirror how the cognitive approach suggests we as human beings problem-solve. The computer analogy assists the cognitive approach to explain the relationship between our information processes and our behaviour in our world. Models like the computer analogy are used throughout psychology to help us understand hypothetical constructs, and nowhere is their use more prevalent than in the study of perception, attention, memory, etc. Models put forward by cognitive psychologists concerning our various cognitions have greatly influenced developments in the computing industry. The more advances that can be made in cognitive psychology the more likely it is that the computer industry will be able to develop the ultimate in inform ation technology – an interactive free-thinking computer that can problem-solve without direction. What the cognitive approach finds out is therefore of great interest to the likes of Bill Gates and Microsoft . The computer analogy Input Processor Output S X R Stimulus Mediational processes Response X = perception, attention, language, memory and thinking In his book, How The Mind Works (1997), Steven Pinker wrote ‘the behaviour of a computer comes from a complex interaction between the p rocessor and input’. This is very much how the cognitive approach understands our behaviour as human beings. The computer analogy is a metaphor, or story, used by the cognitive approach to understand the relationship between our thoughts, feelings, and b ehaviours and our environment. COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) 21 © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E S 1 AN D 2 : TH E CO N C EP T S Input means all the stimuli information that we encounter in our world. Input, or environmental information, about objects, people, events, etc. comes to us via our senses in the form of light energy, sound energy, pressure , etc., or what we ‘see’, ‘hear’ and ‘feel’. All this information ultimately arrives in the brain to be interpreted, understood and acted upon. A good example of this would be the things we see in our world. What we ‘see’, or visually sense, is energy f rom our external environment that first strikes each eye as light waves. This information, alien to our internal biochemistry, is processed by special properties in our eyes into the only type of energy our internal body can understand: electrical energy, which ends up in the visual cortex at the back of the brain as a bundle of electrochemical impulses, or neural signals. We unconsciously match the degree and intensity of these neural signals to what we have stored in our memory concerning the same, or a similar stimulus. Memory helps us recognise and give meaning to what we are visually sensing. This helps us think how best to respond, in terms of our behaviour or output, towards the stimulus object. It is our information processes of perception, attenti on, language, memory and thinking (X) that come between the sensory information ( S) we receive from our world and our response (R) to it. Information processes therefore intercede or come between external stimuli or input from our world, and our behavioural response, or output, to it. Our information processes are like the microprocessors in a computer. Microprocessors come between input in the form of keystrokes, etc., and computer output like printouts and images. The computer analogy helped to confirm behaviourist Edward Tolman’s view that we are more than just S–R units of learned behaviour. It also helps to show that it is our mediational processes that actively do things with the sensory information we receive, which allows us to respond to our world in an enriched fashion. Let us now read about two information processes, perception and attention, aware that the cognitive approach likens our mind to a computer – the most sophisticated evolved. 22 COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E S 1 AN D 2 : TH E CO N C EP T S Perception Introduction In psychology we try first to define the concept we are looking at. ‘Perception is...the process of assembling sensations into a usable mental representation of the world...which...creates faces, melodies, works of art, illusions, etc.’ Coon (1983) ‘Perception is not determined by stimulus patterns, rather it is a dynamic searching for the best interpretation of the available data...perception involves going beyond the immediately given evidence of the senses .’ Gregory (1966) We should be careful however for: ‘To perceive seems effortless... to understand perception is nevertheless a great challenge.’ Dodwell (1995) Here is an attempt at a definition: Perception is the active cognitive information process by which we take in raw sensations from our environment using our sen ses, and interpret these sensations using our past knowledge and understanding of the world in order that the sensation, or what we are sensing, becomes meaningful to us. COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) 23 © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E S 1 AN D 2 : TH E CO N C EP T S Perceptual processing: how do we perceive? An understanding of how we perceive has intrigued cognitive psychologists for decades. As will be discussed later, three explanations have emerged, each enriching our knowledge of perception. 1. The ecological view (Gibson; Gestalt – where we perceive in terms of ‘organised wholes’): where it is said we perceive most clues from our environment directly and without interpretation (we perceive ‘exactly’ what we see, hear, smell, touch and taste). The ecological view is popularly known as bottom-up processing. 2. The constructivist view (Gregory; Bruner): where it is said our perceptual system must often make a reality indirectly out of bits of sensory information due to the absence of other information. The constructivist view is better known as top -down processing. It is perception by hypothesis testing. 3. The interactionist or symbiotic (top-down/bottom-up) view (Neisser): this says we use the most appropriate of the above two processes depending on the situation we find ourselves in. The two processing models work together. When one t ype of perceptual process (or aspect of it) is impaired, the other process (or an aspect of it) ‘fills in’ or compensates to give us, at the end of the day, as much of an understanding of the stimulus as possible. Interactionist processing is best explained in the area of visual perception using Marr’s Computer Analogy, in which he says we first adopt a bottom -up approach to extract visual information from an image/object/event in four stages and put it all together again in the brain in what he calls a sym bolic representation of the stimulus. It is an explanation of visual perception that sees our bottom-up and top-down processes working together. Whether you advocate an ecological (direct bottom -up), constructivist (indirect top-down) or interactionist/symbiotic explanation of perception, it is interesting to note the influence of the nature –nurture debate to your position. While most of the theorists above suggest an empirical basis to our perceptions (that what we perceive or ultimately understand from what our senses are telling us is the result of learning and experience), the influence of Gestalt psychology in the early years of research into this topic does raise the nativist position, that is, that our perceptual ability is innate, and needs little if any ‘learning’ to enhance it. 24 COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E S 1 AN D 2 : TH E CO N C EP T S At the end of the day, we can say that perception is influenced by our innate abilities as human beings, but also by the cognitive apparatus we are born with as used to make meaningful sense of the myriad sensory experi ences we encounter. What we perceive, or understand, we are sensing is also strongly influenced by what we have learned from past experience of the same, or similar, sensations. Perception is further influenced by social, developmental and cultural factors including expectations and motivation. Student Activity 1. Define ‘perception’ in your own words. 2. What aspects of being human processes are involved in perception? 3. What are the three views taken by psychologists as to how we perceive our world? 4. Briefly explain these three views. 5. Which at this stage in your studies do you think best explains perception? Give reasons for your answer. COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) 25 © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E S 1 AN D 2 : TH E CO N C EP T S Processing sensory information Sensation and perception In our original working definition, we said that perception concerns sensing plus our interpretation of this sensation based on meaningful past experience of it. Central to perception must therefore be knowledge of how we receive information from our environment in the first place. This is of course through our senses. We use our traditional five senses, i.e. sight, hearing, touch, taste, smell, to receive information from our external world. Psychology is also able to tell us we have at least one other sense that is called our kinaesthetic sense. This is a sense from within our own bodies that tells us about movement, or the feel of our muscles or joints. Our kinaesthetic sense tells us about balance Our visual sense Our sense of vision is in many respects our key sense. Vision, our visual system and visual perception constitute the most studied information process of all by cognitive psychologists; we look at it in more depth in a later section entitled ‘Our visual system’. Our sense of vision comes to us via our eyes, the structure and location of which allow us to perceive our world in three dimensions; sense colour; sense depth, etc. Our tactile sense Touch is another of our five senses, allowing for our perception of pressure, touch, temperature (principally temperature change), pain and hair movement. We experience touch using sensory cells called receptors that are nerve endings in the skin. Touch receptors are either free ending (in the dermis and around hair follicles) or encapsulated (branched or coiled, enclosed in a capsule). Receptors in our skin respond to a specific type of stimulus and are not evenly distributed over the body. The sensitivity of fingertips, for example, results fr om a large number of touch receptors we have at this extremity. Once a receptor is stimulated, it sends nerve impulses to the brain, which locates and identifies the stimulus involved and assesses its significance. The more intense the stimulus, the greater the frequency of nerve impulses. 26 COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E S 1 AN D 2 : TH E CO N C EP T S The skin’s sensory system is important in alerting the body to changes in its external environment. Potentially harmful stimuli may cause pain that results in either protective reflex actions, such as dropping a hot o bject, or storing a memory to remind you to avoid future similar hazards. The perception of pain is unusual as it is also strongly affected by the emotions and the circumstances in which it is experienced. Our auditory sense The ear is our organ of hearing and balance. It is composed of three parts – external, middle and internal – the greater part of which is enclosed within the temporal bone. The external ear is that portion of the hearing apparatus lateral to our eardrum, or tympanic membrane. The eardrum comprises the auricle, or pinna (the external flap of the ear) and the external auditory canal, which is 3 cm (1.25 in) in length. The middle ear, on the inner side of the eardrum, houses our mechanism for the conduction of sound waves to the interna l ear. It is a narrow passage, or cleft, that extends vertically for about 15 mm (0.6 in) and for about the same distance horizontally. The middle ear is in direct communication with the back of the nose and throat by way of the eustachian tube, which allo ws for passage of air into and out of the middle ear. Traversing, or going across, the middle ear is a chain of three small, movable bones called the ossicles: the malleus, or hammer handle; the incus, or anvil; and the stapes, or stirrup. The ossicles connect the eardrum acoustically to the fluid-filled internal ear. The internal ear, or labyrinth, is the part of the temporal bone containing the organs of hearing and balance to which the filaments of the auditory nerve are distributed. It is separated from the middle ear by the fenestra ovalis, or oval window. The internal ear consists of membranous canals housed in a dense portion of the temporal bone and is divided into the cochlea (Greek for ‘snail shell’), the vestibule and three semicircular canals. A ll these canals communicate with one another and are filled with a gelatinous fluid called endolymph. The disposition and orientation of endolymph also helps us experience our sense of balance. COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) 27 © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E S 1 AN D 2 : TH E CO N C EP T S The ear and balance The semicircular canals and the vestibule are concerned with our sense of equilibrium, or balance. Hairs in these canals, similar to those that form the organ of Corti (the structure responsible for converting sound signals into nerve impulses), respond to changes in the position of the head. The three semicircular canals extend from the vestibule approximately at right angles to each other, providing sensory organs to record movements of the head in each of the three planes of space: up and down, forwards and backwards, and to the left or right. Lying over the hair cells in the vestibule are crystals of calcium carbonate, known technically as otoliths and popularly as ear sand. When the head is tilted, the otoliths shift, and the hairs beneath respond to the change in pressure. The eyes and c ertain sensory cells in the skin and internal tissues also help to maintain equilibrium, but when the labyrinth of the ear is damaged or destroyed, disturbances of equilibrium invariably follow. With eyes closed, a person with a disease or disturbance of the internal ear may be unable to stand without swaying or falling 䪢 How do we hear? Sound waves, which are actually changes in air pressure, are carried through the external auditory canal to the eardrum, causing it to vibrate. These vibrations are communicated by the ossicular chain in the middle ear through the oval window to the fluid in the inner ear. The movement of the endolymph stimulates the movement of a set of fine hair -like projections called hair cells as the cochlea vibrates. Collectively these projections are called the organ of Corti. The hair cells tran smit signals directly to the auditory nerve, which carries information to the brain. The overall pattern of response of the hair cells to vibrations of the cochlea encodes information about sound in a way that is interpretable by the brain’s auditory centr es. The range of hearing, like that of vision, varies from person to person. The maximum range of human hearing includes sound frequencies from about 16 Hz to 28,000 Hz. The frequency at which we can detect sound is measured in Hertz (Hz), or cycles per second. The least noticeable change in tone that can be picked up by the ear varies with pitch and loudness. A change of vibration frequency (pitch) corresponding to about 0.03% of the original frequency can be detected by the most sensitive human ears in the range between 500 and 8,000 vibrations per second. The ear is less sensitive to frequency changes for sounds of low frequency or low intensity. 28 COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E S 1 AN D 2 : TH E CO N C EP T S The sensitivity of the ear to sound intensity (loudness) also varies with frequency. Sensitivity to change in loudness is greatest between 1,000 and 3,000 cycles, where a change of one decibel can be detected – and becomes less when sound-intensity levels are lowered. The variation in the sensitivity of the ear to loud sounds causes several important phenomena. Extremely loud tones produce in the ear entirely different tones that are not present in the original tone. These subjective tones are probably caused by imperfections in the natural function of the middle ear. The harshness in tonality caused by greatly increasing sound intensities, as when a radio volume control is adjusted to produce excessively loud sounds, results from subjective tones produced in the ear. The loudness of a pure tone also affects its pitch. High tones may increase as much as a whole musical-scale note; low tones tend to become lower as sound intensity increases. This effect is noticeable only for pure tones. Because most musical tones are complex, hearing is usually not affected to an appreciable degree by this phenomenon. In sound masking, the production in the ear of harmonics of lower-pitched sounds may deafen the ear to the perception of higher -pitched sounds. Such considerations make it necessary to raise one’s voice in order to be heard in a noisy place. Our gustatory sense Taste is another of the five senses, effected by the contact of soluble substances on our tongue Although humans can distinguish a wide range of flavours, the sensation of taste is actually a response to a combination of several stimuli, including texture, temperature and smell, as well as taste. In isolation, the sense of taste can only identify four basic flavours: sweet, salt, sour and bitter, with individual taste buds particularly responsive to one of these. The 10,000 or so taste buds found in humans are distributed unevenly over the top of the tongue, creating patches sensitive to specific classes of chemicals which give the taste sensations. Usually sweet and salt are at the tip of the tongue, sour at the edges, and bitter at the base. Chemicals from food are dissolved in the moisture of the mouth and enter the taste buds through pores in the surface of the tongue where they come into contact with sensory cells. When a receptor is stimulated by one of the dissolved substances, it sends nerve impulses t o the brain. The frequency of the repetition of the impulse tells the brain how strong a flavour is and the type of flavour is probably registered by the nerve cells that responded. COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) 29 © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E S 1 AN D 2 : TH E CO N C EP T S Our olfactory sense Smell is the sense by which odours are perceived. The nose, equipped with olfactory nerves, is the special organ of smell. The olfactory nerves also account for differing tastes of substances taken into the mouth, in that most sensations that appear introspectively to us as tastes are in essence really smells! Sensations of smell are difficult to describe and classify, but noting the chemical elements of odorous substances has made useful categorisations. Research has pointed to the existence of seven primary odours – camphor-like, musky, floral, peppermint-like, ethereal (dry-cleaning fluid, for example), pungent (vinegar -like) and putrid – corresponding to the seven types of smell receptors found in the olfactory cell hairs. Olfactory research also indicates that substances with similar odours have molecules of similar shape. Recent studies suggest that the shape of an odour-causing chemical molecule determines the nature of the odour of that molecule or substance. These molecules are believed to combine with specific cells in the nose or with chemicals within those cells. This process is the first step in a complex series that continues with the transmission of impulses by the olfactory nerve and ends with the perception of odour by the brain. How do taste and smell work? Taste and smell are a part of our sensing system much like vision and hearing. Molecules released by substances around us stimulate special nerve cells in the nose, mouth or throat. These special nerve cells transmit electric impulses to special areas of the brain that recognise taste and smell. Olfactory nerve cells are stimulated by odours around us such as flowers, baked goods, perfumes, etc. These olfactory nerve cells are located in a tiny patch high up in the nose. They connect by nerve pathways to areas in the brain. Taste cells react to food and drink, mixed with saliva, and are located in the taste buds of the mouth and throat. Many bumps on the back of the tongue contain taste buds. These taste cells send information along nerve pathways to the brain. Unlike other nerve cells, taste and smell cells are replaced when they become old and damaged. Another set of cells in the nose and mouth have non -specialised nerve endings that are stimulated by strong and irritating sensations such as ammonia, chilli peppers, onions, etc. 30 COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E S 1 AN D 2 : TH E CO N C EP T S As already stated, we can commonly identify four basic taste sensations: sweet, sour, bitter, salt. And there is some evidence that other taste sensations can be appreciated. But the sense of smell is necessary to identify flavours such as chocolate; the sweetness is identified by the nerve cells of the tongue and mouth. The combination of saliva with the chocolate releases odours and molecules. These travel up the nasal passage from the back of the throat. The nasal cells are stimulated and the smell and flavour of chocolate are recognised. This is why people who complain of taste problems really often have a smell disorder that interferes with the ability to identify the flavour of foods. Our internal and external senses interact with each other because we are constantly linking together information got through differing sensory modes, e.g. seeing, hearing, etc. This involves us in what is called cross-modal transfer – where information gained using one mode, e.g. sight, is applied to information from another sensory mode, e.g. hearing. Cross -modal transfer gives rise to a richer array of sensory information upon which we base our interpretation of our own realities (world) – but by that we often become confused. Characteristics of our sensory system Our six modalities (or senses) have certain common characteristics. Before looking at what these are, please list below both the common and scientific name for each: 1. Apparatus Sense Eye Visual 2. 3. 4. 5. 6. Each responds to a particular form of energy or external information, e.g. light waves, sound waves, skin pressure, etc. Each has a sense organ or ‘accessory structure’, which is the first port of call for any incoming information on the road to processing, and full understan ding of the perceived stimuli. Each accessory structure has sense receptors called ‘transducers’. These are specialised cells that are sensitive to particular COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) 31 © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E S 1 AN D 2 : TH E CO N C EP T S kinds of energy. It is as the stimuli impinge on these transducers that the conversion of the stimuli into electrical nerve impulses occurs. This electrical activity is the only kind of energy that can be processed and understood by our brains. Each sensory modality involves a different part of the brain. We are here able to interpret messages received from our sensory receptors, which gives us the experience of conscious awareness of an object, a person, a word, a sound, a taste, etc. A certain minimum stimulation of a sense receptor is needed before we can become consciously aware of the sensory experience that is happening. These minimum requirements are called absolute thresholds, which are based on a value given to a stimulus when we can detect it 50% of the time. The threshold at which we can notice a stimulus differs among and between people, and can be affected by an individual’s physical state; time of day; motivation; the way the stimulus is presented, etc. This is the area of psychophysics within psychology (the interface between the physical stimulus and our subjective experience of it ), which is of great importance to the development of psychology as a subject in its own right (see Wilhelm Wundt, 1879). Student Activity 32 1. What do you understand by our visual sense; our tactile sense; our gustatory sense; our auditory sense; and our olfactory sense? 2. Describe and explain our kinaesthetic sense. 3. How do we first begin to interpret information coming to us from our environment? What is particularly interesting about this from the point of view of psychophysics? 4. What does cross-modal transfer mean? Why is cross-modal transfer important? 5. What do you understand by the term ‘absolute threshold’? Give three examples from your reading. Cite your sources using the Harvard Referencing System. COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E S 1 AN D 2 : TH E CO N C EP T S Our visual system Vision and visual perception is by far the largest area of investigation undertaken by cognitive psychologists. A full understanding needs a little introduction to the eye. The eye, according to Ornstein (1975) is ‘ the most important avenue of personal consciousness ’. We receive around 80% of our information about our world via our visual system. Our visual sense As already noted, sight or our sense of vision is probably the most studied of all our senses thanks to the vast amount of work which has been done in the area of visual perception. A basic understanding of the structure and function of the eye is therefore of relevance – if only to give us a clue as to how and why we receive 2 -D type photographic images on our retinas but interpret these two dimensional images in three dimensions. A knowledge of our visual system is also important to our understanding of how and why it is we can perceive colour and depth in our world – and why it is we can see in the dark, but not as well as cats and other nocturnal animals! Structure and function of the human eye The pupil is the wee black circle at the centre of each of our eyes. The pupil controls the amount of light taken in by the eye. In dark conditions our pupil dilates to its maximum size in order to maximise the amount of light entering the eye and thus our ability to see (not too well) in the dark. In light conditions the pupil constricts, or ‘shrinks’, in response to the intensity of light we experience. Pupil size is controlled by our autonomic nervous system (ANS) which controls organs and glands. The ANS is linked to our central nervous system (CNS), our brain and spine. Interestingly the ANS has two branches: • the parasympathetic branch, which in this instance changes pupil size in response to illumination, and, • the sympathetic branch which in this instance dilates the pupil under conditions of strong emotional arousal. COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) 33 © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E S 1 AN D 2 : TH E CO N C EP T S The two branches of the ANS are self-regulating rather than under our conscious control. Regulatory control of the ANS is directed by the hypothalamus, found in the brain. Both branches of the ANS are what psychologists call antagonistic to one another. As one branch moves us to action in one direction, the other counters this. Vitreous humour is the clear, jelly-like substance that fills the middle of the eye. Dilation of the pupil is controlled by the ciliary muscles found in the iris. The lens of the eye is held in place by suspensory ligaments. Much like a camera, the lens focuses light on the retina as an inverted or upside -down image. Ciliary muscles control the shape the lens forms as it focuses light energy on the retina. The lens thickens and increases in curvature when focusing on nearby objects and becomes flatter when we are focusing on objects far away. Muscles around the eye adjust the shape of the lens to focus on an object either nearby or far away. The lens gets thicker when focusing for near objects, and thinner for distant objects. The size of the image reflected on the retina also changes. The retina, which is found at the back of the eye, is where images we see are thrown. The macula, which is a small area found on the retina, has three layers of specialised light-sensitive cells. Each of the layers helps explain certain human visual abilities, and consequently per ception. The three layers of the retina The first layer of the retina contains what are called rods and cones. Rods and cones are photosensitive transducer cells that convert light energy into electrical nerve impulses. Our 120M rods help us see in ever decreasing light. Our 7M cones allow us to experience chromatic vision (colour). Different cone types respond to the three primary colours of red, green and blue. This is because each of these colours has different wavelengths. Mixtures of red, gree n and blue allow us to experience all the colours found in the colour spectrum. A deficiency in one or more of these cone types is the reason for colour blindness. Bipolar cells, a second layer in the retina, are connected to our rods and cones and help relay information to ganglion cells found at the third layer of the retina. 34 COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E S 1 AN D 2 : TH E CO N C EP T S Finally, in the retina we find a third layer called ganglion cells. Ganglion cell fibres (axons) help form the beginnings of the optic nerve. Three types of ganglion cell ‘fire’ in response to the contours and movement of objects in our visual array or field of vision – simple cells have been found to respond to simple features of a stimulus, i.e. straight lines, edges, slits, etc., when found in a particular orientation, or way -up, in our visual field. Complex cells, which are direction sensitive, have been found to respond to lines of particular orientation wherever found in our visual field, and hypercomplex cells deal with the length of visual stimuli, or where a stimulus begins and ends. The visual pathway The visual pathway from each eye to the visual cortex in our brain is called the optic nerve. Each optic nerve converges and crosses over at the optic chiasm or chiasma, thus information from our right eye goes to the lef t visual cortex and information from our left eye goes to the right visual cortex. Let’s take a journey along the visual pathway. Light rays from sources either artificial or natural are reflected off distant objects in our surroundings. These light rays first enter into the eye by passing through a clear tissue called the cornea. From the cornea, light then passes through a clear fluid termed the aqueous humour and then through the pupil opening of the iris in order to reach the crystalline lens. Using its two muscle bands in bright situations, the iris constricts to protect the retina from too much damaging light, while during dim light situations, the iris dilates to let in as much light as possible. The pupil, COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) 35 © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E S 1 AN D 2 : TH E CO N C EP T S which appears as a black dot in the middle of the coloured iris, is actually not a structure but an aperture, a controlled opening or hole! Through the pupil, light reaches the crystalline lens. The lens – in conjunction with the cornea – acts to bend or ‘refract’ the light in order to focus the rays on to the retina. From its name you might believe the crystalline lens does most of the refracting of the eye but this is not the case. It is the cornea that is the primary refractive surface of the eye. Eighty -five percent of the job of bending light is performed by the cornea, while the remaining fifteen percent is done by the lens. The crystalline lens does have one advantage over the cornea. The power of the cornea to bend light is fixed, whereas the crystalline lens can flex to provide more power in order to see near objects. The lens is held in place behind the pupil by hundreds of fibrils termed zonules. When we focus on near objects, these fibres relax allowing the lens to curve outward, thus increasing its power to refract light. When looking at distant objects, the zonules pull tight and the lens flattens. The process of lens flexure in order to see near objects is termed accommodation (which should not to be confused with Jean Piaget’s notion of accommodati on of schema). From the crystalline lens, light rays travel through another clear medium termed the vitreous humour until it reaches the retina. When light enters through this whole optical system, it is actually inverted by the process. An image in the outside world is actually upside-down and backwards when reaching the retina. It is the brain that later processes the image the correct way. The retina is the central mechanism for collecting light rays and converting light energy into electrical impuls es that the brain can ultimately understand. The retina contains millions of nerve cells with photoreceptors attached to each one. There are two major photoreceptors located in the retina. Rods are long, slender receptors that occupy the peripheral retina. Rods are responsible for detection of movements, detection of shapes and night-time vision. Our fine detail and colour vision is provided by the cone receptors. These cone-shaped cells occupy only a small portion of the retina and are found huddled together in what is called the macula. The portion of vision responsible for the most detail actually takes up the least amount of room on the retina. Cones are divided into three subtypes – red, blue and green. When light hits these red, green and blue photoreceptors, a light-activated chemical reaction occurs within the cells converting a photon of light into an electro-chemical impulse. Visible light is a spectrum like that of a rainbow. Each colour of the rainbow has a particular frequency in that spectrum. The complex process of colour vision occurs when 36 COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E S 1 AN D 2 : TH E CO N C EP T S light of a particular frequency stimulates either the red, blue or green cone that is most sensitive to that given frequency. The quantity of photoreceptors, as well as the type of receptor s stimulated, is later interpreted by the brain as a stimulus intensity and colour. From stimulation, light energy is transformed into an electric current for the body. This current then flows along each individual nerve until it reaches the optic nerve of the eye. The optic nerve is termed a nerve but it is actually a collection of about a million nerves rolled into one. We have two optic nerves: one for each eye. The optic nerve extends from the back of each eye. They then enter into the skull thro ugh a small opening in the back of the bony orbit that protects the eye. From here the optic nerves travel a short distance before they meet up with each other at a structure known as the optic chiasma/chiasm. At the optic chiasma, some of the nerve fibres from the right optic nerve cross over to the left side and vice versa. This crossing of optic nerve fibres causes everything we see off to the right in each eye to be processed by the left brain and everything off to the left in our surroundings to be processed by the right brain. After parts of each optic nerve cross at the chiasma, they continue on into what is called the optic tract. This is where the optic nerves travel around the brainstem, one nerve to the right hemisphere and the other to the left hemisphere of the brain. From here everything mentioned occurs on both the right and left sides of the brain. The optic tract carries impulses to another processing area in the brain called the lateral geniculate nucleus (LGN). This structure is like a switching station. Before the impulses even reach the LGN, a small amount of fibres from the optic tract split off to other areas of the brain that control dilation and constriction of the pupils. After the LGN, each nerve ‘fans’ out into what is called the optic radiations. Some of the nerve travels over the parietal lobe of the brain while others travel the low road over the temporal lobe. The nerves continue on until they reach the back portion of the brain called the occipital lobe. At the occipital lobes all the impulses from the right and left eyes are processed into what we perceive as our visual reality. The information between the two eyes is also compared to create our three dimensional world. Discussion point What do you understand by the term ‘sensation’? How does a sensation differ from a perception, properly known as a percept? COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) 37 © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E S 1 AN D 2 : TH E CO N C EP T S Where all sensory information ends up to be processed and understood This is of course in our brain, the organ concerned with consciousness. Consciousness is our awareness (plus perception; attention; language; thinking and memory) and the overall control of the body. The human brain is a relatively small structure, weighing about 1.4 kg (3.1 lb) and making up about 2% of total body weight. It is contained w ithin the skull, which acts as a protective casing. Although the brain is only a small proportion of overall body weight, information received about the outside world and from the rest of the body converges at the brain to be processed. Sensations arrive h ere and are processed. We first begin to perceive what a particular sensation is (and therefore what it is we are experiencing) on the basis of how good, bad or indifferent our various senses are individually and collectively. How we reach individual understanding of what particular sensations mean for us is further based on some innate abilities, plus any previous experiences we have had in connection with them. Processing sensory information Cortical area Function Prefrontal Cortex Motor Association Cortex Problem-solving, emotion, complex thought Co-ordination of complex movement Primary Motor Cortex Initiation of voluntary movement Primary Somatosensory Cortex Receives tactile information from the body Sensory Association Area Processing of multisensory information Visual Association Area Complex processing of visual information Visual Cortex Detection of simple visual stimuli Wernicke’s Area Language comprehension Auditory Association Area Auditory Cortex Complex processing of auditory information Detection of sound quality (loudness, tone) Speech Centre (Broca’s Area) Speech production and articulation 38 COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E S 1 AN D 2 : TH E CO N C EP T S Conclusion: sensation and perception What we see is more than just light focusing on the retina of the eye. Vision is an enormously complex process. That which is seen must be captured by the optical system, transmitted and processed by the retina, and then passed along to the brain for even more detailed processing. Areas of the brain must extract and interpret the essence of all that we see. It must recognise colour, contour, shape, texture, movement and perspective, then compare all this information to our ‘internal database’ (or meaningful similar or same previous experiences). A tiny, two-dimensional image hitting the retina must be transformed into a three-dimensional world all – pardon the expression – in the blink of an eye! Vision is defined by two components: sensation and perception. The concepts of sensation and perception are difficult to separate but sensation is the detection and encoding of visual stimuli, whereas perception is the higher-level cognitive process that processes, organises and interpretes this visual sensation. Perception should thus be seen as an active cognitive process influenced by our internal and external world. These aspects of perception will now be addressed. COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) 39 © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E S 1 AN D 2 : TH E CO N C EP T S Student Activity Interactive First experiment Steadily fixate on the black light bulb for thirty seconds or more. Try not to avert your gaze. Then immediately turn your gaze to the white region on the right next to the bulb (or a blank white sheet of paper). You should see a glowing light bulb! So what’s going on? The glowing white light bulb you see on the white background after staring at the black light bulb figure is c alled an after-image. When you focus on the black light bulb, light sensitive photoreceptors (whose job is to convert light into electrical activity) in your retina respond to the incoming light. Other neurons that receive input from these photoreceptors respond as well. As you continue to stare at the black light bulb your photoreceptors become desensitised (or fatigued). Your photo pigment is ‘bleached’ by this constant stimulation. The desensitisation is strongest for cells viewing the brightest part o f the figure, but weaker for cells viewing the darkest part of the figure. Then, when the screen becomes white, the least depleted cells respond more strongly than their neighbours, producing the brightest part of the after image: the glowing light bulb. This is a negative after-image, in which bright areas of the figure turn dark and vice versa. Positive after -images also exist. Most after-images last only a few seconds to a minute because, in the absence of strong stimulation, most nerve cells quickly readjust. Desensitisation of the retina can be important for survival. A constant stimulus is usually ignored by the brain in favour of a changing one, because a changing stimulus is usually more important. But desensitisation also leads to after-images. After-images are constantly with us. When we view a bright flash of light, briefly look at the sun, or are blinded by the headlights of an approaching car at night, we see both positive and negative after images. To prevent permanent damage to your eyes, never look at any bright light source, in particular the sun. The British psychologist Kenneth Craik burned a tiny hole in his right retina and 40 COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E S 1 AN D 2 : TH E CO N C EP T S permanently scarred his eye at that spot, when he stared directly into the sun for two minutes. Don’t try this at home! For the first few days following his experiment – in which he wanted to find out whether such a lesion in the eye is visible – he saw a dim orange disk with closed eyes (positive after-image) and a black after-image with open eyes. Fortunately, after a year or so, Craik’s vision at that location in his eye appeared to return to normal. His brain cleverly filled in information at this damaged piece of his retina. Second experiment Notice that if the after-image is viewed on the screen or on a nearby sheet of white paper, it appears relatively small. If it is viewed on a distant wall, however, it appears much larger, even though the size and shape of the retinal image remains the same. The perceived size of the after-image varies directly with the distance of the surface on which it is viewed. This relation is an instance of a more general perceptual relation known as Emmert’s law: The perceived size of a particular visual angle is directly proportional to its perceived distance . The illusion of after-images appearing to vary in size despite a constant retinal image is precisely what one would predict if perceived size is governed not only by visual angle but also by distance. The two seemingly different facts, that images of the same si ze lead to perceptions of different size (Emmert’s law), and that images of different size lead to perceptions of the same size (size constancy), actually illustrate the same principle: distance is taken into account in computing the size of a perceived object from the size of the image falling on to the retina, which is another example illustrating that we don’t just see what our eye tells us. Third experiment When you close your left eye and adapt to the figure with your right eye, only your right eye will see an after-image when looking at a white region. The after-image does not transfer between eyes. This helps scientists determine where in the visual system this effect arises. This type of after-effect is caused by cells in the retina fatiguing, rath er than by cells in the visual cortex, where information from the two eyes is combined. COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) 41 © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E S 1 AN D 2 : TH E CO N C EP T S The active nature of perception Factors that further explain perception and our perceptual world are embodied in what are called ‘The principles of perceptual or ganisation’ which include: • Gestalten; figure and ground • perceptual constancies; for example, depth perception Gestalt psychology and Gestalten One way of looking at perception is from the point of view of Gestalt psychology (Kohler, Koffka and Wertheimer); see p. 24. It is easily understood. Gestalt psychology, which was in vogue in Germany in the early part of the twentieth century, postulates that we have an innate disposition to perceive objects using our inbuilt principles of grouping, or Gestalten. What Gestalten means is our innate ability to construct our world in terms of organised ‘wholes’. It is as if we have a natural ability to ‘tidy up’ stimuli as we sense them. Their Laws of Pragnänz capture the principles behind our Gestalten, which are our innate way of perceiving things in terms of symmetry, uniformity and stability. Individual Gestalten are: Proximity Objects that are close together are perceived by us as a ‘whole’, e.g. a) b) . . . . ....................... . . How do you perceive a) and b) above? Similarity Similar objects are normally perceived by us as belonging to the same group. Above, what similar sets of objects do you perceive as a group and what other one do you see – or think you see – which does not exist in reality? Storm the reality studios! 42 COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E S 1 AN D 2 : TH E CO N C EP T S Continuity Sensations appearing to create a continuous form are perceived by us as belonging together, e.g. a fence with slats missing is still perceived as a fence. We organise sensations appearing together to form a continuous whole, e.g. x x x x x x x x x x Do you perceive the above as a square shape made up of Xs, or ten separate and individual Xs? Closure Where, at an unconscious level, we fill in contours/gaps in stimul i to form a complete whole in order to make perceptual sense of it, we need to bear in mind the importance of past experience and perception. This is illustrated below. What do you make of these stimuli? Your tutor should explain the significance of this simple demonstration. The whole is greater than the sum of its parts COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) 43 © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E S 1 AN D 2 : TH E CO N C EP T S Texture Texture is another principle of Gestalten where objects of the same texture are perceived as belonging to the same group, e.g. grains of sand and pebbles at the seaside form for us a ‘beach’. You are unlikely to perceive the scene above as made up of individual grains of sand. Simplicity We have a tendency to group together stimulus features in a way that provides the simplest interpretation of the world (e.g. houses as opposed to their make-up – windows, doors, roofs, walls, ceilings, etc.). The notion of simplicity does have a link with the social psychological phenomenon of stereotyping and attribution theory. Common fate This strange term describes the principle where individual objects moving together at the same rate are perceived by us as a group. We group, by common fate, flocks of seagulls and swarms of wasps. We do not perceive each individual in the flock or swarm. We innately organise the stimuli int o a ‘whole’ in order to perceive and understand it. Innate principles behind Gestalten and Gestalt psychology, which are biological in origin, go some way to explain perception. Perception is therefore more than mere ‘seeing’. We often find in psychology that such innate abilities have survival value for us. 44 COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E S 1 AN D 2 : TH E CO N C EP T S Student Activity Figure and ground What do you make of the visual stimuli below? This stimulus is known in psychology as Rubin’s vase and is often used to demonstrate illusions. Danish psychologist Edgar Rubin made the vase/profile illusion famous in 1915. As you might be able to ‘see’ from Rubin’s vase, our visual perceptual process puts some aspect of the 2 -D stimuli to the ‘front’ or foreground (figure) and another aspect to the meaningless background (ground). Some part of the image always stands out as ‘figure’ and some other part ‘ground’. With Rubin’s vase the principle is reversible. What is meant here is that you will either perceive a vase to the front or two faces squaring up to ea ch other! Often what we perceive (as above either a vase or faces) is related to our: • • • • • expectations culture experience of the stimuli motivation social world. All of these influences on perception are collectively called our ‘perceptual set’. The work of the Dutch artist M C Escher is famous for its ability to trick the eye. Please answer the questions that follow. COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) 45 © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E S 1 AN D 2 : TH E CO N C EP T S Perceptual set? Keep off the the grass E A D 13 A 16 15 14 B 12 The cat sat on the map and licked its whiskers 1. Look at three stimuli above. Explain each from the point of view of perceptual set. 2. Below are what might appear as blobs when you first look at them. Your impression of the blobs provides an example of awareness at a sensory level. If you continue to look at the blobs, four words will emerge. You needn’t try to organise the blobs. The organisation process will occur without any overt striving on your part. These blobs have been created to slow the perceptual process so that you can experience what typically occurs speedil y in subjective time. After you have perceived what they are, use the explanatory thumbnail to help you explain what you have just done. Your first and seemingly immediate awareness, which more or less corresponds to the energy stimulation patterns, is referred to as ‘sensation’. ‘Perception’ can be distinguished from sensation in that it refers to a process that requires more organisation than sensation, is more heavily dependent on learning than sensation, and requires more time for completion than sensation. Explain the difference between a sensation and a percept. 46 COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E S 1 AN D 2 : TH E CO N C EP T S 3. Below is the famous illusion in psychology attributed to Boring. From the point of view of your perception, what do you first perceive? Can you perceive anything else? Explain this illusion in the light of factors that influence perception. COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) 47 © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E S 1 AN D 2 : TH E CO N C EP T S Development and perception Do we have innate, or inborn, perceptual abilities, and as a result can we discover whose is the more correct viewpoint as regards our perceptions: the direct/ecological viewpoint or the indirect/constructivist viewpoint? Bower (1966) is, amongst other things, famous for his peek -a-boo experiment into our perception of size constancy, otherwise known as relative size. He set out to discover if size constancy in babies was a consequence of experience or was innate. He conditioned young babies (neonates) of two months to turn their heads on the presentation of a 30 -centimetre cube at a distance of 1 metre away from them. They were then presented with three further conditions of the independent variable: • a 30-centimetre cube at 3 metres • a 90-centimetre cube at 1 metre and • a 90-centimetre cube at 3 metres (which produces the same size of retinal image as the 30-centimetre cube at 1 metre). He recorded the number of times each stimulus produced the conditioned response (head turning) and his results showed: • • • • Condition Condition Condition Condition 1 2 3 4 (30 (30 (90 (90 cms cms cms cms 1 3 1 3 metre): metres): metre): metres): 98 58 54 22 head head head head turns turns turns turns The finding that most head turns occurred in response to the first stimulus showed that the babies were responding to the actual size of the cube irrespective of distance. This supports the ecological and Gestalt position of size constancy being innate. Further research by Slater (1989) supports Bower’s findings, and suggests that size constancy (our ability to perceive the true size of an object) is actively and provably present in babies as young as eighteen weeks. 48 COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E S 1 AN D 2 : TH E CO N C EP T S A further study by Bower investigated the innate Gestalt principle of closure. He conditioned neonates to respond to triangle number 1 and then presented them with 2, 3, 4 and 5. Number 1 Number 2 Number 4 Number 5 Number 3 Bower found that the conditioned response was generalised more by the babies to the complete triangle (number 2). It is suggested that with number 1 the young babies initially perceived an unbroken triangle to lie behind the black bar and that this indicates that the Gestalt principle of closure is innate in all of us. These innate Gestalt principles are the basis for further and more complex perceptual organisation. R L Gregory is a cognitive psychologist who takes a constructivist approach to perception. He says that we often (have to) go beyond the evidence of sensory information alone to understand and behave appropriately in our world. He believes experience in our environment has a part to play here. He used visual illusions in an attempt to prove his point. Visual illusions see us interpreting them as more than just sensory input alone. This was demonstrated earlier. With the old woman/young woman illusion did you first/always see a young or an old woman? Which is the more correct interpretation of the stimuli? We often use knowledge of visual illusions to our advantage. DIY programmes are about altering perceptions to make rooms more appealing. If you have a small bathroom or kitchen and want to create an illusion of size, DIY programme presenters often use the MullerLyer illusion and paint horizontal lines on alternate rows of tiles giving an impression of depth, or use vertical lines to create height – where none in reality exists. By using the natural contours of the room, like corners, they work on our environmental experiences of cues to depth, i.e. two COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) 49 © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E S 1 AN D 2 : TH E CO N C EP T S railway lines that appear to converge into the distance are used as an external clue to depth in our world. This is illustrated at (b) below. (a) (b) On the other hand there are psychologists such as Gibson and Walk (1960) who believe more in an ecological or bottom-up approach in their understanding of our perceptual processes – at least as far as depth perception is concerned. As can be seen on page 51, in their famous visual cliff experiment, they discovered in their work with kittens and neonates that depth perception is probably innate in humans as it is in kittens. This suggests that the application of our innate perceptual abilities are important from the point of view of personal survival. They have come about as a result of evolution. It would appear in the application of perception that we benefit from both theoretical positions. Some abilities that influence perception appear innate – but experience of our environment and what we learn in it is important as well. 50 COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E S 1 AN D 2 : TH E CO N C EP T S Perception study Source: Gibson, E J and Walk, R D, ‘The visual cliff’, Scientific American, 202, pp. 64–71, 1960 Aim: To discover if depth perception is innate or learnt. Participants/subjects: Children aged 6–14 months Animals aged 24 hours Method: Laboratory experiment Independent variable: age of participants Dependent variable: whether baby crawled to deep side of visual cliff. Procedure: Visual cliff constructed of glass over a box with black and white squares positioned to show depth at one end. Infants were placed in the middle and encouraged to move towards their mothers who waited at the opposite end. COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) 51 © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E S 1 AN D 2 : TH E CO N C EP T S Animals, e.g. rats, chickens, turtles and lambs were also tested by placing them in the middle and observing to which end they went. The reason why Gibson and Walk used both animals and humans in their study is that babies could not take part until they can crawl (around 6 months) by which time the learning of depth perception may have occurred. Non human animals were used at an earlier age (as young as one day) where it was fairly certain no learning of depth perception could have occurred. Conclusion: Gibson and Walk (1960) suggest non-human animals are born with innate ability to perceive depth and that babies as young as 6 months could perceive depth, though there is no indication if this is innate or learned. Neither the direct ecological view nor the indirect constructivist view is entirely supported. Perceptual constancy So far we have established that perception depends upon bodily structures and processes; our innate principles of Gestalten, and us imposing 3 dimensional meaning on 2-dimensional visual experience on the basis of expectations, culture, experience, motivation and our social world – sometimes wrongly! Perception is actively influenced by all these factors working individually and together. Where this all ultimately happens is within the human brain, centring on the hypothalamus in particular. We also have a perceptual ability, collectively called perceptual constancies, which helps us to perceive our world. Where our perceptual constancies of size, shape, brightness and depth come from is not fully understood. Cognitive psychologists disagree as to whether they come about as a consequence of our biology and genetic inheritance (nature) or as the result of learning and experience (nurture). It should be said, however, that as far as depth constancy is concerned, there is good psychological evidence to suggest that depth perception is innate. Perceptual constancy is our ability to perceive sameness of visual stimuli even when the sensory evidence is to the contrary. We have a perceptual constancy in the four areas below that also help us make sense of our perceptual world. • size • shape 52 COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E S 1 AN D 2 : TH E CO N C EP T S • brightness • depth Perceptual constancies occur when our brains correct or modify our rapidly changing sensory inputs to give us a more constant perception of the world. For example, size constancy ensures that as we watch a friend walk off into the distance, although the image of the person projected on to our retina is rapidly decreasing in size, we do not perceive that our friend is actually shrinking! The knowledge that as the proximal stimulus (the internal sensory image) changes, the distal stimulus (the external object being perceived) does not, allows us to correct our sensations and maintain constant perceptions. Cognitive psychology has over the years offered three theories about perception. It is in the area of perceptual constanc ies that much supporting evidence to which theory is the more correct has emerged. These theories are summarised as follows. Three theories of perception: direct, constructivist, and interactionist 1. Bottom-up (ecological view): (Gibson; Gestalt – ‘organised wholes’) where it is said we perceive most clues from our environment directly and without interpretation (we perceive ‘exactly’ what we see/hear/smell/touch and taste). The ecological or direct view explains perception as being ‘bottom-up’ – our world impinges on our senses which process the information to the brain where it is directly interpreted, understood and acted upon. Bottom-up theory cannot explain illusions. Discussion point Why do you think the bottom-up theory of perception cannot explain illusions? Why can’t bottom-up theory be dismissed altogether? Give reasons for your deliberations. 2. Top-down (constructivist view): (Gregory; Bruner) who say our perceptual system must often make a reality indirectly out of bits of sensory information due to the absence of other information. They are top-down in their explanation of perception. Higher -level cognitive functions play a part. We often perceive things in the absence of bits of sensory information by hypothesis testing or ‘best gues sing’ on the basis of our previous (in)experience of what it is we sense. COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) 53 © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E S 1 AN D 2 : TH E CO N C EP T S Discussion point What is the key to a top-down theory of perception? What other influences would operate on a top-down perceptual understanding of our world? 3. Top-down/bottom-up (interactionist/symbiotic view): (Neisser; Marr) who say we use both top-down and bottom-up information processes in the perception of our reality. Nature and nurture both play a part. Both enhance perception individually and collectively. When one pe rceptual process, or aspect of it, is impaired, the other process, or an aspect of it, ‘fills in’ or compensates to give us at the end of the day as good an individual understanding of the image/object/event as possible. Symbiotic processing is best explained in the area of visual perception using Marr’s computer analogy where he says we extract visual information from an image/object/event in four stages and put all this together again in the brain in what he calls a symbolic representation of the stimulus. Marr’s computational model as an explanation of visual perception is illuminating in that it helps emphasise the role of both bottom-up and top-down processing independently, collectively and integratively. For an overview of Marr’s computer analogy s ee overleaf. Interactive Read Theories of Visual Perception: Problems and Perspectives at http://www.psychol.ucl.ac.uk/alan.johnston/Theories.html and Two Visual Systems and Two Theories of Perception: An Attempt to Reconcile the Constructivist and Ecological Approaches by Joel Norman of the University of Haifa, Israel at http://psy.haifa.ac.il/~maga/tvs&ttp.pdf For next day read Chapter 2 of Cognitive Psychology by Richard Gross and Rob McIlveen (Hodder & Stoughton). Summarise each of the three theories/approaches to our understanding of perception. In your opinion, which appears the most correct? Give reasons for your answers. It is to be hoped that good students will refer to psychological and everyday examples in their deliberations. 54 COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E S 1 AN D 2 : TH E CO N C EP T S An interactionist view David Marr (1945–80) was a British psychologist who made important contributions to the study of visual processing. In doing so, he integrated results from psychology, AI, and neurophysiology. His classic book, Vision: A computational investigation into the human representation and processing of visual information, is considered one of the most important works in cognitive science. In addition to his work on vision, Marr developed a general account of information-processing systems in terms of three levels of analysis: (1) the level of computational theory of the system, (2) the level of algorithm and representation, which are used to make computations, and (3) the level of implementation: the underlying hardware or ‘machinery’ on which the computations are carried out. Algorithm An algorithm is a mechanical and completely reliable procedure or set of instructions for completing an operation in a finite number of steps. For example, ‘To unlock a door with an unfamiliar set of keys, try each one until one of them does unlock the door’. Another example, from logic, is truth tables, which determine whether a formula is a tautology. In mathematical contexts, an algorithm is a mechanical procedure for computing a result or outcome. Use of an algorithm always provides a solution to a problem, unlike a heuristic. In an attempt to understand the complex make -up of our visual perception David Marr – in ‘Marr, D (1980), Visual information processing: the structure and creation of visual representation s. Phil.Trans.R.Soc.Lond.B, 290, 199–218’ – argues that neural activity transforms sensory (essentially visual) stimulation into our experience of reality. This is done gradually, by our extracting and deconstructing specific information from the object we ‘see’, in four stages and then putting all this information together again in our attempt to recognise and understand what is we are (visually) perceiving. Marr calls this a symbolic representation. Representation ‘Representation’ can refer to a symbol or thing, which represents (‘refers to’, ‘stands for’) something else, or it can refer to the relation between a representation (in the sense just described) and what it represents. In either case, there are many kinds of representation. For instance, there are linguistic forms of representation (as exemplified by the words in this sentence) and non-linguistic forms of representation (as exemplified by maps and models). General questions about COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) 55 © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E S 1 AN D 2 : TH E CO N C EP T S representation focus on the nature of the relation between a representation and what it represents, features which distinguish representations from other, non-representational items and features which distinguish different kinds of representation. Questions about representations, which arise in connection with mental states and cognition, involve the representational nature of imagery (is it more picture-like or language-like?), the creative use of representational systems, and the relationship between language and thought. These questions are of particular concern for computational models of mind, which require that mental representation be in a form suitable for computation. Marr’s (1982) 4 module computational theory of vision 1. The image or grey-level description Represented by the intensity of light at eac h point in the retinal image, this allows us to discover the boundaries of and regions in the image. Marr suggests our ability to identify boundaries and regions on this basis is the beginning of visual perception. 2. Primal sketch Here Marr says we go on to identify surface markings, object boundaries and markings using the Gestalt principles of grouping. 3. 2½-D sketch A third stage where in the deconstruction of an image we give it depth and orientation. It is not yet 3-D. Object recognition needs the input matched against memory so that non-visible points are accounted for (perceptual constancy). 4. 3-D model representation Where the nature and construction of the object is at this final stage confirmed/denied using higher level top -down processing functions and abilities. This gives rise to a symbolic representation of our visual reality and is for Marr true object recognition. 56 COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E S 1 AN D 2 : TH E CO N C EP T S Our three theories of perception and their explanations of constancies Size constancy As previously explained, size constancy refers to the fact that, although retinal images of objects get smaller as the object recedes into the distance, we perceive that the object does not change in size. Taking size constancy into account, the constructivist view of perception maint ains that size constancy develops because we learn through experience that objects do not actually shrink as they move away from us. Some cross -cultural evidence is consistent with this view, in that sometimes people from the dense jungle or heavily wooded regions, who are not accustomed to viewing objects at a distance, mistakenly perceive distant objects as being very small. Ecological direct-perception theory on the other hand maintains that size constancy occurs as a direct result of the information taken in by our senses and that failure to conserve size results only when the situation does not provide us with enough direct sensory information. Shape constancy Shape constancy is our ability, innate or learned, to perceive the shape of an object as being constant even though our retinal image of the object is changing. An example of this would be the chalkboard at the front of your class. Regardless of where we are sitting, we all perceive the chalkboard as a rectangular shape despite the fact that we all have different retinal images of it depending upon where we are sitting. Constructivists, or top -down theorists, see shape constancy coming about as a product of learning in our environment whereas bottom-up theorists see shape constancy as being somehow innate and part of the experience of sensation. Brightness constancy Lightness, or brightness constancy, refers to our perceptual ability to adapt to the situation where the illumination (brightness) of an object changes, but we continue to perceive its brightness and colour as the same or constant. A white sheet of paper first perceived in bright sunlight will still appear white and of approximately the same shade when later perceived by us under the shade of a tree. Constructivists (top-down theory) explain brightness constancy in our learnt knowledge that objects do not change their ‘brightness’ as lighting conditions change. Ecological theory takes a bottom up explanation of brightness constancy. They say that enough information is present in the sensory experience itself to allow us to maintain a constant (lightness) perception of the object. COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) 57 © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E S 1 AN D 2 : TH E CO N C EP T S Which is the more correct is very difficult to ascertain. Because babies cannot communicate very well when first born, we have little way of knowing if these constancies are present from birth, or learnt (however quickly), as the result of experience. We may find a more accurate explanation to the origins of perceptual constancies in an examination of depth perception. Student Activity Depth perception An awareness of depth perception will help us understand why it is we visually sense the world in two dimensions (like a photograph) but perceive what we see in three dimensions! This is demonstrated below: Above (left) is a Swedish stamp based on the original diagram on the right by the British physicist Roger Penrose (1954) called an Impossible Triangle. They are each obviously two-dimensional. Are you currently experiencing both in three dimensions? Shut one eye. Do you still experience both in 3D? If you are this definitely contradicts direct perception bottom-up theory as an explanation of perception. Now the hard bit: why is this the case? Without depth perception we would find walking, reaching, driving and playing games (among other things) difficult. We see depth in our visual world because of • monocular depth cues, and • binocular depth cues. 58 COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E S 1 AN D 2 : TH E CO N C EP T S Monocular depth cues Monocular depth cues come about from seeing the world with one eye; or our two individual eyes singularly...think about it!! Monocular depth cues, or cues to depth, come to us from our external world. Put simply, what things are and where things are in our external world gives us cues or clues to depth. Even if we visually experience our world with one eye, and the image which is striking our retina is definitely two -dimensional, where things are in our visual field allows us understand or perceive our world in three dimensions. Monocular depth cues include, inter alia, interposition, linear perspective and relative size. Interposition/superposition One monocular depth cue we call interposition or overlapping. Interposition is the monocular cue we use to perceive depth when we see a scene in which one object is partially obscuring another. The object we can fully see we perceive as nearer than the partially obscured object – which we perceive as behind. If your tutor sits down behind their desk we can adjudge that the desk is nearer you than they are: you can fully see the desk and only the top half of their body. The interposition of the desk and the tutor is here a monocular depth cue. A B C Interactive Explain interposition, with reference to the above three figures. COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) 59 © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E S 1 AN D 2 : TH E CO N C EP T S Shades and shadows When we know the location of a light source and see objects casting shadows on other objects, we learn that the object shadowing the other is closer to the light source. As most illumination comes downward, we tend to resolve ambiguities using this information. Shadows in 2 -D images are used by the advertising industry and sign writers to attract our attention to the ‘fact’ that the words seem to stand out from their background, giving the impression that the background is farther away from the letters. Why? We notice it more! GK Another monocular depth cue is: Linear perspective Linear perspective is another monocular depth cue. If we see two parallel lines converge into one another in the distance, this tells us about depth. It is easily demonstrated in a railway station. When it is safe (!) look down at the railway lines. They are parallel to one another. Now look up the track and you will see the rails converge (come in on one another). This is linear perspective. If we see this happening, it is a monocular cue to depth or distance. Linear perspective can even work in two dimensions, i.e. Which of the two horizontal lines above is longer, the one at the top, or the one at the bottom? Measure them. What do you find? From the point of view of perceptual theory why did you perceive what you di d? 60 COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E S 1 AN D 2 : TH E CO N C EP T S Relative size Relative size is another monocular depth cue. Relative size occurs when we see two objects, like two houses, against their backgrounds in our visual field. We see in two dimensions that one house is smaller than the other. Indeed the 2-D visual information we receive about the smaller of the two houses would appear to suggest it is the size of a match -box! This is not the case. We perceive on the basis of relative size that the visually smaller house is farther away from us. The larger of the two we perceive as nearer. The human visual system interprets depth in sensed images using both physiological and psychological cues. Some physiological cues require both eyes to be open (binocular); others are available also when looking at image s with only one open eye (monocular). All psychological cues are monocular. In the real world the human visual system automatically uses all available depth cues to determine distances between objects. Binocular depth cues Binocular physiological depth cues are easy to understand. They come about because we have two eyes. Binocular cues to depth in our visual field result because of the fact that each of our eyes receives a slightly different picture of the same scene; our noses see to that. COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) 61 © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E S 1 AN D 2 : TH E CO N C EP T S The dual and overlapping picture we get as a result is called stereopsis. Stereopsis gives us binocular cues to depth because most of us enjoy binocular (two-eye) vision. We can lose the ability for binocular depth cues to our visual world due to a blow to the head (that gives us double vision) or damage to the eye due to strabismus (squints), etc. Sports people generally have excellent binocular vision. You will find that professional sports people whose game involves a ball of some description are usually excellent at other ball sports they play as a ‘hobby’. Stephen Hendry, the world -famous snooker player, is an excellent golfer. The goalkeeper Andy Goram has Scottish caps for both football and cricket. Ian Botham played both professional cricket and professional football – though not at the same time of year. If we have two eyes, when objects get closer to us, each eye turns inwards. As objects, or percepts, move farther away, each eye turns outwards. The brain interprets this as a binocular cue to how near or ho w far the percept (image/object) is from us. This inward and outward movement of our eyes in response to how near or how far a percept is from us is called binocular convergence. Because each eye has a slightly different view of the same visual world, thi s similar, but different information is also used to help us judge depth. The closer each retinal image (or picture) is to the other, the nearer our brain interprets an object being to us. This is called binocular disparity. We therefore achieve depth perception due to monocular and binocular depth cues. Monocular depth cues come from our visual environment. Binocular depth cues arise because we have two eyes. The biology of the human body gives rise to binocular depth cues. Our external environment gives us monocular depth cues. Student Activity Describe and explain how we perceive depth in our world. 62 COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E S 1 AN D 2 : TH E CO N C EP T S Motivation In psychology, motivation concerns what prompts us to action or to behave in a particular way. Motivation can affect our perception of o bjects, events, people stimuli, etc. Motivation in psychology is a study all in itself. Cognitive psychology understands that our motivation to react, act and behave in a particular way is affected by two things. These are our • internal biology; and • external environment. Sometimes our internal biology and external environment come together to make us think, feel and behave in a particular way. The interaction of our biology and our environment as they motivate us to be more perceptually aware produces interesting – and expensive – results. When our body needs fuel, i.e. food, it tells us so when we experience hunger pangs. This is our body’s internal signal or cue to us to eat. Our biology affects our perception in that when we are hungry and experi ence hunger pangs, we perceive food much more vividly. It is fatal to go food shopping in a modern supermarket if you are hungry. The fruit appears more appealing, the home baking more delicious, the meat and fish more tasty looking! We perceive the colour of food more intensely. We are more aware of the smell of food. Perception of food is heightened by internal bodily factors. External factors like the clever use of lighting to illuminate fruit colouring more, and the bakery in the supermarket constantly baking bread and cakes, also influence and motivate us to perceive food more intensely when hungry. The internal and external factors of motivation strongly influence our perception of food and in this situation we may end up buying and spending much more than we needed! Supermarkets of course are aware of this. A knowledge of cognitive psychology can affect your waistline, wallet and purse. Cultural variations on perception In 1966 Mundy-Castle investigated the interpretation Ghanaian children of between 5 and 10 put on their line drawings. They were presented with a series of drawings each of which used only a limited number of depth cues. These were height in plane, interposition and relative size. Each picture showed a man and a deer at the front and an elephant at the back in different combinations, i.e. Mundy-Castle discovered that the COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) 63 © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E S 1 AN D 2 : TH E CO N C EP T S children’s interpretations were significantly different from those made by a similar sample of European children. The Ghanaian children were unable to use such depth cues as the road to interpret the picture. Their culture did not give them experiences of roads (and deer – they called these goats or similar) and thus influenced their perception. Similar findings into (faulty) depth perception have been found when people are transposed out of their own environment into an alien one. Social and emotional influences on perception Culture is bound up in our social world which itself provides the circumstances within which we feel and express emotions. When New Lab our came to power in the late 1990s, Lord Irvine became the Lord Chancellor and speaker of the House of Lords, head of the English legal system and a member of the Cabinet. He set about refurbishing his official residence at taxpayers’ expense and could not understand the public reaction to his spending tens of thousands of pounds on wallpaper, chairs and curtains. Because of the affluent and privileged social world he lived in, his perception of what was spent on what was entirely different from that of th e vast majority of the population. Allport (1955) reports on a study concerning the influence of our social world regarding prejudice and perception. Prejudices arise from the social world we find ourselves in. Prejudice is thus learnt – formally and informally. Prejudice influences perception. Using a stereoscope (a device for presenting a separate picture to each eye simultaneously), the experimenters showed participants mixed-race pairs of individuals; one member of each pair shown to each eye. Generally people were better and more definite when picking out and categorising members of their own race. They were more unsure and cagey when categorising people of other ethnic groups. Afrikaaners, long noted for their prejudice against black people, different iated far more quickly and definitively between the different ethnic peoples presented via the stereoscope. They had a very definite perception and raised emotional awareness regarding differing racial groupings. Allport interpreted this as showing that the strongly racist views held by Afrikaaners had influenced their perception. In 1948 Postman, Bruner and McGinnies discovered using a tachiscope that sexual and other taboo words had a higher recognition level than ordinary language. Participants took longer to process these types of words than neutral ones. Postman et al suggest that this longer processing time is a type of perceptual defence – to defend us from the unacceptable. However, Bitterman and Kniffin (1953) found that the 64 COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E S 1 AN D 2 : TH E CO N C EP T S time difference disappeared if participants were allowed to write down these taboo words. They said that Postman’s earlier work suffered from a methodological response bias. Participants were simply less willing to say swear words aloud than neutral words. So who is the mor e correct? Worthington (1969) subliminally presented participants with taboo words – so subliminally that participants were completely unaware of their presentation. They were cleverly embedded at the centre of a dot of light projected on to a screen. Dots were presented in pairs and the participants had to say which dot was brighter, dimmer or were they both the same? Dots with taboo words embedded on them were consistently rated as being dimmer than those with neutral words. The perceptual defence argume nt therefore has some merit. Carpenter, Weiner and Carpenter (1956) engaged participants in the completion of sensitive topics such as personal inadequacy, sex, hostility, etc. They categorised participants as either ‘sensitive’ or ‘repressed’ as a result . Sensitive participants perceived taboo or disturbing words more easily; repressed participants perceived such words less readily and quickly. Personal differences in values and attitudes can thus greatly influence perception. These we get from our social world. Solley and Haigh (1958) reported on a study to show the influence emotion has on perception. Children were asked to draw pictures of Santa Claus in December and January. Representations were larger and included more presents in the month of December in comparison to January. In January the drawings shrank and the presents got fewer! Solley and Haigh (1958) imply that emotions such as excitement and anticipation can influence perception. In 1951 Lazarus and McCleary conducted an experiment that had them give mild electric shocks to participants when presented with a nonsense syllable. This provoked an avoidance response to them in the future! Interestingly they also found an avoidance response when participants came across the nonsense words subliminally. This implies that the perceptual system works at both a conscious and an unconscious level and that consciously and unconsciously our perception of our world can be influenced by previous experiences. COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) 65 © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E S 1 AN D 2 : TH E CO N C EP T S Perception and advertising Advertising makes its money by attracting our attention to products their clients want us to buy. Very often there is in reality very little to differentiate between similar products. One need only consider soap powder to appreciate this point. So what makes us choose between one brand and another? Whether we notice it in the first place is the first step in the process. Getting our attention and then changing our perception is what advertising is all about. You cannot perceive something without attending to it. You cannot attend to something without perceiving it. Please read the two extracts from the BBC website and answer the questions that follow. Monday 29 March 1999 published at 12:42 GMT Ads make French Connection Fashion retailer French Connection has announ ced a 27% jump in profits on the back of its controversial ‘FCUK’ advertising campaign. The company, which owns the Nicole Farhi brand, said pre -tax profits for the year to January rose to £10.4m ($16.3m) from £8.2m a year ago, well up on market expectations. Sales grew 25.2% to £117.3m, assisted by the opening of 10 new stores. Like -for-like sales, excluding the effects of the new store space, were 11% higher. The company said its decision two years ago to abbreviate its full name, French Connection UK; to FCUK has had an impact on customers. Its recent Christmas advertising campaign, FCUK Christmas – Take Me Away, further ‘created attention and provoked discussion’, the company said. ‘Great optimism’ Chief executive Stephen Marks, said: ‘At the core of our recent success have been the advertising campaigns for both French Connection and Nicole Farhi. Overall we enter the new year with great optimism.’ He added that sponsorship of boxer Lennox Lewis in his recent world heavyweight bout with Evander Ho lyfield, which saw Lewis wear the FCUK logo on his shorts, had seen its sales of similarly branded T-shirts soar. In Britain the company says its businesses are ‘performing well in what continues to be very difficult market conditions’, Mr Marks said, whi le the US retail 66 COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E S 1 AN D 2 : TH E CO N C EP T S business ‘is well ahead of last year at this stage’. The group has 88 stores in the UK and US and aims to have 109 open by January next year. New shops have been opened in London, across the UK and in Washington. Four outlets are set to open in New York. September 1999 Warning to advertisers over ‘f-word’ The Advertising Standards Authority is urging magazines and poster companies not to run advertisements for a clothing firm, French Connection, which make a play on the ‘f-word’. The ASA has upheld 26 complaints about the campaign, which uses the slogan ‘f.c.u.k. advertising’. The authority says it has brought advertising into disrepute. The company says it has registered ‘fcuk’ as the trademark of French Connection UK and claims that means it must be acceptable. It told the authority that it had responded to previous complaints about its posters by putting dots between the initials and separating the words ‘fcuk’ and ‘advertising’ with a picture. But in its magazine advertisement, which appeared in style titles such as Vogue, Marie Claire and FHM, no alterations were made. The company said it saw no need because these magazines often contained strong language in their editorial features. The ASA said without the use of dots, most rea ders would mistake the advertisers’ initials for the f-word – and it considered the campaign brought advertising into disrepute. It has now urged media companies not to accept the advertisements in future. ASA spokesman Chris Reed said: ‘It’s very unusual for us to take this action on the grounds of taste and decency. Our research shows 77% of the public do not believe the f-word should be used on advertising. We are sending out a message to advertisers to be careful.’ Lilli Anderson, French Connection spokeswoman, criticised the ruling as ‘undemocratic’ and said she thought it would have little impact on their ability to run their next adverts, which were already being placed in magazines for the spring. ‘We’ve sold 85,000 T-shirts with “fcuk fashion” on them. If that many people want to wear it across their T -shirts, to uphold a complaint by 26 people is not very democratic,’ she said. COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) 67 © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E S 1 AN D 2 : TH E CO N C EP T S Student Activity 1. What material success did French Connection UK have as a result of their name change? 2. What did the company put this success down to? 3. What criticisms did the Advertising Standards Authority make of the company name change? 4. Despite these criticisms, psychologically what must have happened from the perspective of the potential consumer? 5. When confronted for the first, second or even third time with the stimuli, what cognitively happened for the unaware consumer? 6. What happened to their buying behaviour? 7. Using your knowledge of perception explain the success of this campaign. Discussion point Think about something you looked forward to for a long time. What mental representations did you have in anticipation of it? What emotions did you feel? Was the event as brilliant as you first perceived it to be? Student Activity Describe and explain cultural, social and developmental influences on perception. 68 COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E S 1 AN D 2 : TH E CO N C EP T S Student Activity: Interactive What is this picture? As you search for meaning in it, your brain strives to make sense of the seemingly meaningless spots. If, after a while, you still see no meaning in the picture read the answer below. Once you ‘see’ the solution, it will never again be meaningless to you. So what’s going on? This experiment shows that past experience can affect your perception of such properties as form or depth. Consider what happens when you view this illustration. At first most people cannot tell what it depicts, but with continued inspection or a hint, the fragments suddenly are perceptually reorganised and recognised, in this case, as a Dalmatian dog. A recognisable image emerges that had no perceptual reality before. Hence, there is some sort of perceptual change among the neurons in your brain. This also leads to a change in the way in which you perceive the shape and depth of the scene. Perhaps mos t importantly, the figure now looks like the object it was supposed to represent – it now has the shape and depth relations of a Dalmatian dog. Sometimes being told that a Dalmatian hides in this scene can provide the visual system with enough of a hint t o recognise the dog. This is a case in which a high-level brain area underlying language comprehension tells a lower-level area, in this case the cortical areas dedicated to visual scene analysis, what might be going on. This is another example of why the study of cognitive psychology should be seen holistically. COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) 69 © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E S 1 AN D 2 : TH E CO N C EP T S If this dog were animated, it would be immediately apparent. Common motion of a group of otherwise unrecognisable blobs is a very powerful cue for our visual system. It enables our visual system to realise that it’s dealing with a single object. This effect is termed grouping. It is important that an animal can do this well, otherwise it might not easily spot a predator, prey or other food. Animals must be able to separate the figure from the ground. What we call camouflage is an attempt to deceive these processes. A stalking cat moves cautiously and freezes from time to time to avoid giving motion clues to its prey. It has even been suggested that our good colour vision evolved to enable our primate ancestors to spot coloured fruit against a confusing background of green leaves. What gives us so much visual pleasure may originate as a device to spot our food and to break camouflage. In most illustrations, we tend to perceive a figure that stands out from the background. In printed material, the figure is usually darker than its background. Figures also tend to be smaller and more regular than backgrounds. Sometimes these principles do not hold, and we have difficulty distinguishing figures from their backgrounds. However, this difficulty disappears when our brain somehow organises these difficult visual images into a meaningful and recognisable pattern. When this is done, only the figure and background can be seen, and whatever was seen before is gone forever! Once you understand what is being presented, your perception changes, and you will be fixed on the ‘correct’ interpretation forever. Since these types of figure/ground figures do not lead to immediate identification, the mental recognition of the ‘correct’ figure must be perceptual in character. After all, the image does not change on your retina. Thus we can assume that some mental process that precedes or accompanies the moment of recognition entails a perceptual reorganisation. Second experiment Now that you have recognised the Dalmatian dog, try perceiving the image in its original meaningless way. You will find it almost impossible to do. The picture becomes permanently meaningful. This is in contrast to an ambiguous figure that ha s two equally likely interpretations. The ambiguous figure will ‘flip’ between two states, because your brain cannot decide which one is more meaningfully biased than the other one. In the case of the Dalmatian dog, however, once your brain perceives t he ‘correct’ 70 COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E S 1 AN D 2 : TH E CO N C EP T S image and ascribes meaning to the picture, your brain will not be able to perceive a meaningless image again, because the meaningless interpretation is no longer equally biased with that of your past experience with Dalmatian dogs. During al l the time you were staring at the picture, the image on your retina did not change. Rather, your brain worked to construct a correct interpretation of the image, trying out different interpretations, until your brain ‘recognised’ something. This emphasises that perception is an active process of constructing a scene description. Student activity Conduct an experiment using the Dalmatian dog stimuli to test the hypothesis H1: ‘That previous past experience influences perception.’ Revise how to write up a psychological research investigation and visit http://www.uwsp.edu/psych/apa4b.htm COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) 71 © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E S 1 AN D 2 : TH E CO N C EP T S Attention In consideration of the key concept of attention, the Scottish Qualifications Authority say that for Psychology at Advanced Higher level we cons ider: • an information processing approach to the study of attention • models of focused and divided attention • theories and research regarding focused auditory and visual attention – visual search, schemas • performance deficits in everyday attention. By the end of this key concept you should be aware that attention is an important information process, closely related to perception. Our natural state of attention is divided attention. This is where we are able to attend to, and deal with, lots of information in our world at one and the same time. On the other hand, we also have an ability to focus on, or selectively attend to, particular stimuli, while ignoring all others – at least at a conscious level. This implies that sometimes even that to which we do not attend directly can still be attended to indirectly. What we attend to, and what we do not attend to, is influenced a great deal by just how meaningful a particular stimulus is for us. Attention is also affected by our motivation, expectations, emo tion and culture. The close relationship between perception and attention will be explored in the context of active information processing. Different theories and models of visual and auditory attention will be looked at to give us a greater understanding of our various states of attention, which we use interchangeably on an everyday basis. What is attention? Our definition of attention is perhaps entirely appropriate. Attention is ‘… the taking possession by the mind in clear and vivid form, of one o f what seems several simultaneously possible objects or trains of thought. Focalisation, (and the) concentration of consciousness are of its essence. It implies withdrawal from some things in order to deal effectively with others.’ William James (1890) A study of the information process of attention first involves us in considering four areas: selected or focused attention; divided attention; and (as a consequence) the objective and subjective factors associated with why we attend to some stimuli to the exclusion of others. It must 72 COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E S 1 AN D 2 : TH E CO N C EP T S be emphasised that attention is closely related to perception in the family of cognitive processes in that ‘The topics of perception and attention merge into each other since both are concerned with the question of what we become aware of in our environment. We can only perceive things we are attending to and attend to things we perceive.’ Greene and Hick (1984) As hopefully you are aware by now, cognitive psychology is dominated by what is called an ‘information-processing paradigm’. We study information processes like perception, attention, language, memory and thinking from the point of view of the information processes involved, in terms of models of what we think is involved. The study of attention therefore sees psychologists looking at two main areas: • focused or selective attention, where attention is seen in terms of the mechanisms by which certain information is registered by us, while other information is disregarded (and whether or not it enters our consciousness); • divided or capacity attention, where the study of attention concentrates on the upper limit to the amount of processing that we can perform on incoming stimuli at any one time. How do we study attention? Cognitive psychology almost exclusively adopts the experimental method as its prime research methodology. In their laboratory research into attention, cognitive psychologists utilise a number of interesting strategies: • shadowing: where in the study of attention participants are presented with a message into one ear, and almost immediately repeat it back; • dichotic listening tasks: where a message is simultaneously presented to the left ear, and a different message to the right. Participants are asked, for example, to attend to and repeat back one message only; COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) 73 © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E S 1 AN D 2 : TH E CO N C EP T S • the dual-tasking technique: used to study divided attention where subjects are presented with a variety of incoming stimuli and are asked to respond to one, some or all of them. Task performance is fou nd here to be affected by task, similarity, task practice and task difficulty. A deficit in our performance, sometimes called a performance deficit, may be evident as a result. Theories of focused or selective attention Attention, like all our cognitive processes, is a hypothetical construct. This is the name given to things we study in psychology that don’t actually exist in a physical, or real, form. Thus in order to study the hypothetical construct of attention we use models of what we think is happening when we attend to stimuli. Theories on focused attention (how we seem to attend to some stimuli to the exclusion of others) have traditionally argued in their models that somewhere along the attention information-processing pipeline there is a ‘bottle neck’, where we have to filter out unwanted messages (or deal with them to only a limited degree), in order to allow the passing through of more important messages to our higher-level processing system. Indeed, the absence of this probably innate neurological ability would make life impossible. We would be bombarded with stimuli and unable to work out what ones need dealing with first in order for us to operate successfully in our world. The aptly named single-channel theories of attention put forward by the likes of Broadbent, Deutsch and Deutsch, Treisman and Norman primarily differ over where this filter is, and how much and what it is we process of any non-attended stimuli. Focused auditory attention Broadbent’s filter model (1958) The study of attention began in earnest for cognitive psychology in 1958 with the publication of Broadbent’s paper ‘Perception and Communication’. Felt by many to be a cornerstone theory in cognitive psychology, Broadbent attempted to answer in part Cherry’s earlier 1953 c ocktail-party phenomenon, with a theory about how he thought we could focus our attention on one conversation, whilst ignoring other conversations going on around us at the same time. The conversation we have attended to may be taking place on the other side of the room! Broadbent (1958) suggests that we focus on, or selectively attend to, stimuli on the basis of their physical properties. 74 COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E S 1 AN D 2 : TH E CO N C EP T S Interactive Starting off at http://xenia.media.mit.edu/~barons/cocktail.html write a report on Cherry (1953) under the following headings: name, date, title of original research, method/procedure, results and conclusions. Broadbent said our world has too many stimuli in it for us to handle at any one time. To deal with this, we utilise a filter mechanism to process s ome – and block out other – incoming information. As a consequence, a bottle neck of data (attracted to us in the first place on the basis of their physical properties) occurs early on. What this means is that Broadbent believes we first attend to objects, etc. on the basis of certain objective physical properties that they have. Essentially these physical characteristics ‘grab’ our attention and help us notice one stimulus more than another. Physical characteristics important to focused or selective attent ion include such things as volume, brightness, intensity and novelty. These factors are well used in the world of advertising and marketing. In order to perceive a stimulus – in this case a product – our attention to it must somehow first be triggered. Using a split-span procedure of focused auditory attention, Broadbent postulated that each ear acts as a separate channel of communication and deals with incoming aural stimuli singularly and selectively. Later work suggested his filter model was too simplistic. Indeed, there is some evidence to suggest that he did not satisfactorily account for the fact that some aspects of the unattended-to message during his split-span procedures could be recalled by participants later. This is related to one of the major subjective reasons for us paying particular attention to some things, e.g. how much a certain stimulus means to us. The split-span procedure Using headphones, this is where Broadbent would present three numbers 7, 1, 3 to one ear, at the rate of one number per second. At the same time, the other ear receives another three numbers 6, 2, 4. The participants listen to both sets of numbers, and then write down as many as they can recall. Interactive Using the same initial source as the previous Interactive, summarise Broadbent’s (1958) research conclusions into auditory attention. COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) 75 © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E S 1 AN D 2 : TH E CO N C EP T S Treisman’s attenuator model (1964) This holds with much of Broadbent’s initial single channel model of attention but sees the bottle neck as being much more flexible. Treisman’s theory agrees that initial screening of a stimulus occurs on th e basis of its physical characteristics, but instead of ‘irrelevant’ messages being disregarded, the perceptual filter or attenuator turns down their volume, so to speak. They are still available for higher-level processing. ‘The channel filter attenuates irrelevant messages rather than blocks them completely.’ Treisman (1964) What is particularly interesting is that Treisman’s attenuator model also brings to our (individual) attention that further analysis is based upon individual words, grammatical structure and word meaning. It aptly deals with an explanation for the cocktail-party phenomenon in that we can hear something without attending to it and do ‘attend’ to it when it ‘means’ something to us. We seem to be able to pay attention (consciously an d unconsciously) more on the basis of personal meaning than the physical characteristics of the message itself. Treisman (1964), ‘Verbal cues, language and meaning in selective attention’, American Journal of Psychology, 77: pp. 206–19 British psychologist Anne Treisman, now Professor of Cognitive Psychology at Princeton University, revolutionised cognitive psychology with her doctoral attenuator model of attention in the 1960s – which she has revised, refined and progressed ever since. Attenuator theory says we can attend to particular stimuli even although we are not aware of them. It built on Cherry’s ‘cocktail-party’ phenomenon, influenced by criticisms of Broadbent’s earlier theory that we consciously attend to stimuli solely on the basis of physical properties and that we can only attend to stimuli one at a time. Aim: To investigate our ability to selectively attend to a stimulus when it depends solely on the identification of verbal or linguistic features of the message. 76 COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E S 1 AN D 2 : TH E CO N C EP T S Participants: Undergraduates and research students at Oxford University. Method: Laboratory experiment. Independent variable: content: type and direction of messages to each ear (the message to be attended to was sometimes switched ear -to-ear). The content of the message, to be selectively attended to, was a 150-word passage of prose taken from the novel Lord Jim by Joseph Conrad. The contents (differing verbal characteristics) of the irrelevant messages were: I. II. III. IV. V. VI. VII. VIII. IX. X. Prose from the same book in a man’s voice Prose from the same book in a woman’s voice Prose with an insertion of Latin in a woman’s voice Prose on a technical discussion on biochemistry in a woman’s voice French prose from a novel in the same voice as IV German prose from a novel in the same voice as IV Italian prose from a novel in the same voice as IV ‘Pigeon’ Czech in an English accent in the same voice as IV Backwards English in the same voice as IV French translation of the Lord Jim shadowed message in the same voice as IV. Procedure: Participants were engaged in a dichotic listening task that involves asking participants to listen to different information in each ear. Using a technique called shadowing, the Lord Jim message was presented, as were the ten irrelevant messages listed above with the participant being told to attend to Lord Jim only and repeat it out loud. Dependent variable: Interference on ability to recall Lord Jim message/recall of attenuated messages. COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) 77 © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E S 1 AN D 2 : TH E CO N C EP T S Conclusion: That when we are in a state of focused attention we selectively attend to stimuli using what is called a filter. This filter does not work entirely on the taxi rank principle as previously thought. Treisman’s attenuator model (1964) suggests that early selection/attention is based on physical properties of the stimulus such as pitch, loudness, etc; that attention is directed toward information that reaches a threshold of recognition; but most crucially of all that during selective attention several inputs can be processed at the same time. We pay attention to unattended-to messages on the basis of thresholds we set for attending to stimuli. Important stimuli have a low threshold while less important stimuli have a high threshold. The inputs we can still attend to at the weak (attenuated) level are those that are most meaningful to us, i.e. our name and gossip about ourselves!! Treisman’s work then and since has demonstrated that unattended -to messages are more thoroughly processed than previously thought. She found that unknown foreign languages produced less interference on selective recall than known foreign languages, that we do seem to identify what we are attending to, and that during the attentional process we discard irrelevant stimuli more quickly than more meaningful information, which is then processed/not processed at a deeper, focused level depending on the task on hand. Personal meaning is once again emphasised in the study of our information processes. From Treisman (1960) 78 COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E S 1 AN D 2 : TH E CO N C EP T S Deutsch and Deutsch (1963); Norman (1969, 1976). Late selection filter theory Later single-channel theories of why we attend to certain things in particular emphasise this is done on the basis of what is deemed pertinent to the individual. This simply means that we attend to and percei ve stimuli on the basis of what is subjectively valid (meaning something), or important, to ourselves. Put another way, attention/perception is influenced by selfishness! Pertinence model theorists put the bottle neck in our ‘single channel’ of attention much nearer the response end of the auditory processing system. They say, rejecting Broadbent, that we fully analyse all signals and pass them on to the attenuator, which passes on the signal to be further processed but in a more toned-down form. We attend to certain things more than others because something about them is more relevant for us. The pertinence model suggestion that we analyse everything has been criticised by Solso and Professor Michael Eysenck as too rigid and inflexible. In general terms, criticisms of the Pertinence Model are worries about a single all -purpose, limited capacity, central processor. Single -channel theory seems too allinclusive a theory to account for the complexities involved in the unique human experience of attention. Interactive Read Chapter 5 of Cognitive Psychology by Richard Gross and Rob McIlveen (Hodder & Stoughton). Discuss and evaluate single-channel theory in the light of focused auditory attention. Focused visual attention Investigation into focused visual attention has looked primarily at three main areas: • unilateral neglect • extinction; and • Balint’s syndrome. COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) 79 © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E S 1 AN D 2 : TH E CO N C EP T S Unilateral neglect Unilateral neglect (UN) occurs as a result of brain damage to the right parietal lobe. It manifests itself where victims, for example when copying a drawing, leave out everything on its left-hand side. They cannot account for stimuli in their left visual field. Unilateral neglect patients show a similar behaviour when asked to perform tasks involving visual imagery (Bis iach and Luzzatti, 1978). Lately it has been discovered that some processing of neglected stimuli does actually occur. Marshall and Halligan (1988) presented a UN patient with a drawing of two identical houses side by side. The only difference was that the one on the left-hand side had flames coming out of the windows. The patient could not report any difference between the two drawings, but did say that she would prefer to live in the house on the right hand side! Why this phenomenon occurs is still a bit of a mystery. Parkin (1996) reports, ‘… the idea that a single theory of neglect will emerge is highly unlikely because of the diversity of defects being discovered.’ Interactive Read a review of Unilateral Neglect: Clinical and Experimental Stud ies, edited by Robertson and Marshall at http://psyche.cs.monash.edu.au/v1/psyche-1-08-walker.html 80 COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E S 1 AN D 2 : TH E CO N C EP T S Extinction Extinction is a symptom found in some unilateral neglect patients. These patients can attend to stimuli when presented normally to either their left or right visual field. But when the two stimuli are presented side by side, the one nearer the side of the visual field that is neglected goes undetected. Balint’s syndrome Balint’s syndrome comes about due to damage in both cerebral hemispheres involving the posterior parietal lobe or parietal -occipital junction. Balint’s syndrome patients exhibit a variety of attentional difficulties including fixed gazing, over-extending for objects and simultagnosia. Simultagnosia is when only one object at a time can be seen (Humphreys and Riddoch, 1993). In this research, when Balint’s syndrome participants were shown a number of red and green circles, they were generally unable to see both coloured circles simultaneously. They could, however, identify them w hen they became one ‘whole’ object joined together by lines. Simultagnosia Red Green Red Green Humphreys and Riddoch (1993) While there is no one agreed theory as to the cause of simultagnosia, Driver (1998) suggests that the main problem for Balint’s patients is their inability to disengage covert attention from an object. Covert attention is when our attention moves without the eyes, often as a precursor to a saccade, which can be either endogenously or exogenously controlled. Some expl anations: Endogenous (controlled) attention – this is usually a movement of covert attention that isn’t elicited by something in the environment (such as a sudden flash) but by the individual who knows where they need to look next. For example, when reading we know that we have to move our eyes along a line of text from left to right. Because we have knowledge about a predictable environment, our attention can be COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) 81 © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E S 1 AN D 2 : TH E CO N C EP T S directed to the right of fixation (up to fourteen letters) to help guide our reading. Exogenous (automatic) attention – an abrupt onset (e.g. a flash of light in peripheral vision can capture covert attention. This usually results in a saccade to the flash area to have a look what is there). Saccade – a movement of the eye. When the eye mo ves, no information is taken in until it lands and a new fixation is started. Source: http://www.psychology.nottingham.ac.uk/staff/dec/c8cllc/l13 16glossary.doc Elements to visual attention In an attempt to discover the components of visual attention, P osner and Pederson (1990) reviewed findings from such attentional disordered patients. They argue that our ability to visually attend involves three separate processes. • we have an ability to disengage our attention from one stimulus to another. This component of visual attention is called disengagement; • we also use shifting, which is our ability to move our attention from one stimulus to another; • we use the process of engaging, or ‘locking’ on to new visual stimuli. A ‘spotlight’ model of visual attention The spotlight model of visual attention is considered by the likes of Driver (1996) and LaBerge (1983). It is a model that holds that we adopt a broader attentional beam, depending on the visual task; that when we visually attend to stimuli, our visual attention can be likened to an internal mental spotlight that mostly concentrates on the centre of whatever it is we are visually attending to. We visually attend less to what might be going on at the periphery of our visual scene. When we have to process this peripheral visual information, we have to shift the spotlight. The idea that no processing occurs beyond the periphery of the spotlight has been confirmed by, amongst others, Johnston and Dark (1986). 82 COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E S 1 AN D 2 : TH E CO N C EP T S The ‘zoom-lens’ model of visual attention The ‘spotlight’ model precipitated the development of the zoom -lens model of visual attention. Erikson (1990) accepts the existence of the idea of an internal mental spotlight, but believes its ‘beam’ can be adjusted like the zoom-lens of a camera depending upon the width of the visual stimulus to be considered. The zoom-lens model cannot account for the earlier results of Neisser and Becklen (1975), and latterly Juola et al (1991), where both studies suggest that, contrary to zoom-lens theory, some stimuli within our visual environment can be attended to and others ignored. This is probably because zoom-lens theory gives the impression of visual attention concentrating in upon a given area of visual space, rather than stimuli within a given area. Neisser and Becklen (1975), in superimposing two visual scenes on top of each other, found participants could easily attend to one scene while ignoring the other. Contrary to zoom-lens theory, this suggests that objects within a visual environment can be the main focus of our attention. Visual search Visual search is the way we use focused visual attention in our everyday lives. It is our searching out of a target stimulus in a busy visual environment, such as looking for a friend in a crowd, or finding a parti cular topic in a book, etc. Visual search has been investigated by way of visual search tasks. This is where a participant is shown a visual display, and has to decide, as quickly as possible, if the target is within the display. In 50% of randomly presented trials, it will not be. What influences the speed and accuracy of such a visual search is considered in feature integration theory. A C S G L M W J O P S Z H 6 C Q P D F N W P K Y B A visual search task. Please locate the number 6 within th e above visual array. COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) 83 © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E S 1 AN D 2 : TH E CO N C EP T S Feature integration theory Feature integration theory is attributed to Treisman and Gelade (1980), and Treisman (1988). The crux of the theory is that visually our attention must be focused on an object or stimulus before its features can be synthesised into a pattern that allows us ultimately to make some sense of it. Treisman and Gelade (1980) asked participants to try to detect the letter T in among Is and Ys. They predicted that because a T has a distinguishing feature, the horizontal bar at the top, and Is and Ys do not, participants would detect the target stimulus easily. This they found to be the case. Participants took on average 800 milliseconds to detect a T within their arrays. They also discovered that detection was not influenced by the size of the stimulus array. In another experiment, Treisman and Gelade embedded the T in an array of Is and Zs. This is a bit more difficult for us to detect as Z also has a horizontal bar at its top. Because of this similarity, participants had to search for more complex features of T, which is where its vertical and horizontal bars conjoin with each other at the top. Here, participants took 1,200 milliseconds to detect Ts. In this more complex attentional task, Treisman and Gelade fou nd that the size of the stimulus array did influence processing time. Treisman concludes that within the more complex visual arrays (e.g. Ts within Is and Zs), we first need to apply focused attention to begin to detect targets. A second stage of processing then occurs, where we search for the target based upon its features. In simpler visual tasks (T in among Is and Ys) we do not use focused attention, and as a result the size of the array does not have an adverse affect on detection time – as it does in the more complex visual search task. Interactive Read pp. 62–4 of Cognitive Psychology by Richard Gross and Rob McIlveen (Hodder & Stoughton), and pp. 126 –8 of Principles of Cognitive Psychology (2nd ed) by Michael Eysenck (Psychology Press). Discuss and evaluate Treisman’s feature-integration model of visual attention. 84 COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E S 1 AN D 2 : TH E CO N C EP T S Divided attention Divided attention is our ability to attend to lots of things at one and the same time. Inherent in divided attention is the previously introduced concept of focused attention. Focused attention is our sometimes super -ordinate ability to concentrate on one task. However, focused and divided attention have more in common with each other than one might initially think, as ‘….anything which minimises interference between processes, or keeps them further apart, will allow them to be dealt with more readily either selectively or together.’ Hampson (1969) Shaffer (1975) well illustrates the effect interference has on a dual-process task. He got a skilled audio-typist and, using headphones, presented her with information into one ear, which she had to type. The two concurrent independent variables were: • a shadowing task where a shadow message was sent to her other ear; and • a reading-aloud task of visually presented material. In both conditions of the independent variable, a performance deficit was evident compared with when she performed the interfering tasks separately from the audio-typing task. Shaffer’s experiment neatly captures what divided attention is really all about. Quite simply we are at our best performing a variety of tasks that are both different and well known to us. Task similarity, task practice and task difficulty all have a part to play in our ability to maintain vigilance/attention to more than one thing at a time. Performance affecting variables such as task similarity, task practice and task difficulty come into their own in the consideration of what is called automaticity. Automatic processing or (automaticity) ability This is easily demonstrated when we think about driving a car. Initially we exercise focused attention on the mastering of all the individual ‘S -R’ units of driving. The task difficulty here is immense, especially when you have to put all the learning units together in a fl uid action and pay attention to everything that is happening around you (including the disapproving driving instructor beside you). Stress is thus a factor in the effort involved in focused attention. Confidence follows with task practice, culminating in the rather gallus automatic processing ability of being able to drive while simultaneously exercising divided attention by COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) 85 © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E S 1 AN D 2 : TH E CO N C EP T S having a conversation with someone on your mobile, changing tapes, lighting a cigarette and using your mirror to put on your make -up. We must be able to go through a series of ‘states of attention’ depending upon changing situational variables such as task similarity, task practice and task difficulty. Interactive Go to http://psychclassics.yorku.ca/Stroop/ and read Stroop (1935) ‘Interference in serial verbal reactions’, Journal of Experimental Psychology, 18, pp. 643–61. Write a report on this under the following headings: Name, Date, Title, Aim, Method/Procedure, Results and Conclusions. Action slips and schemas When we are in a state of divided attention, an action slip is the performance of something by us that we did not intend to do (Reason, 1979, 1992). Reason asked thirty-five participants to keep a diary of their action slips over a two week period. A total of 433 action slips were recorded. He then put 94% of them into five categories – giving us some clues about the basis of action slips. • Storage failures (40%): forgotten or incorrectly recalled actions, such as trying to lock one’s door twice. • Test failures (20%): exchanged actions, such as getting changed for bed instead of for the intended party! • Sub-routine failures (18%): re-orderings, insertions or omissions of parts of actions, such as having forgotten to pour water into the teapot before serving. • Discrimination failures (11%): attentional failures such as mistaking yoghurt for milk. • Programme assembly failures (5%): such as erasing the wrong letter from a wrongly spelled word. Strangely, action slips occur more frequently in the area of actions that are highly practised and over-learned. At first, when we have to learn how to behave in a particular way towards a particular stimulus, we are in a state of focused attention. Here, when we first learn to perform something, our central processor or attentional system is subject to closed-loop control. This type of control is slow and involves effort, but 86 COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E S 1 AN D 2 : TH E CO N C EP T S is less prone to error. Once we become skilled at the desired behaviour, and now being in a state of divided attention, the attentional system uses openloop control to guide our actions. This is much faster and effortless, but more prone to error. Open-loop attentional control also allows us to deal with lots of things at one and the same time. In the study of divided attention, and thus open -loop control, it is suggested that we utilise schemas, a schema meaning here an ‘organised plan’ or mental representation of everything we understand about a stimulus, based on our previous experience of it. Sellen and Norman (1992) believe schemas determine our attentional performance. Their theory distinguishes between two types of schema. Parent schemas are the highest -level schemas and equate with an overall behavioural intention, like going to college for a lecture. Child schemas are lower-order schemas which address the behaviours involved in reaching the desired intended behaviour, like getting up, getting dressed, having breakfast, leaving the house, etc. Each schema has a particular activation level, and the behaviour is forthcoming once that activation level is reached. Sellen and Norman argue that errors can be made in a number of ways. One might be where an error has been made in the formation of an intention and consequently an incorrect schema is activated. As a result, activation of the correct intended schema is lost. Another is where faulty triggering of an action schema happens, probably influenced by past experience of a particular context or situation. COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) 87 © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E S 1 AN D 2 : TH E CO N C EP T S Interactive Discuss with reference to Reason the concept of action slips, and evaluate them with reference to Sellen and Norman. Usef ul ref erences Reason, J T, ‘Actions Not as Planned: The Price of Automatisation’, in G Underwood and R Stevens (eds), Aspects of Consciousness. Volume 1, Psychological Issues, London: Academic Press, 1979 Reason, J T, ‘Cognitive Underspecification: Its Variety and Consequences’, in B J Baars (ed.), Experimental Slips and Human Error: Exploring the Architecture of Volition, New York: Plenum Press, 1992 Reason, J T and Mycielska, K, Absentmindedness: The Psychology of Mental Lapses and Everyday Errors, Englewood Cliffs, NJ: PrenticeHall, 1982 Sellen, A J and Norman, D A, ‘The psychology of slips’, in B J Baars (ed.), Experimental Slips and Human Error: Exploring the Architecture of Volition, New York: Plenum Press, 1992 Sustained attention, vigilance and performance decrement This must have relevance to those working in tedious jobs where inattentiveness could lead to health and safety problems. In Johnnie Walker’s distillery in Kilmarnock, whisky is bo ttled on an assembly line. It comes in one end in huge vats and goes out the other, bottled, labelled and boxed to be sent all over the world. Each individual bottle undergoes microscopic scrutiny for flaws. Each worker on the line spends a maximum of twenty minutes, at any one time, concentrating on looking through a large eyepiece at each bottle as it passes along the line to be boxed. Millions of gallons of whisky are bottled in Kilmarnock every year. Johnnie Walker’s have no doubt found out to their cos t the price of sustained attention, vigilance and performance deficit in their workers. Put simply, if not addressed, it affects profits! Mackworth (1950) researched sustained attention, vigilance and performance deficit by getting subjects to concentra te on very boring tasks. He wanted to investigate how long someone could sustain a boring task and still keep alert. He set up a number of signal -detection tasks where subjects had to press a key on hearing/seeing a particular auditory/visual signal. Every now and again, a tone would sound, or a signal appear, that was louder or larger than the rest. Participants had to 88 COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E S 1 AN D 2 : TH E CO N C EP T S press the key on detection of this. Mackworth compared the signals given with the number reported and the errors made (this is anoth er indication of externalising a cognitive process). As a result, Mackworth put forward a number of factors which influence vigilance, which he calls performance decrement. At a general level, the longer the task the greater the performance decrement. We can sustain concentration longer and reduce performance decrement by looking at the factors that influence our ability to attend to stimuli. These factors depend upon • the task itself • the person • the situation. Mackworth found that in the light of the task itself the brighter and longer a signal the greater the performance decrement. As regards the person, he discovered feedback on performance; moderate stimulants and the personality of the person could aid sustained attention while in the situation o ccasional interruptions and irritants like phones ringing in the background and bosses lurking nearby saw an increased ability to concentrate on the task in hand – a task we might have performed a million times before. COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) 89 © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 90 COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E 3 : I S SU E S SECTION 3 Issue: the use of non-human animals in research Please read the following: Richard Gross; Rob McIlveen; Hugh Coolican; Alan Clamp and Julia Russell, Psychology: A New Introduction (2nd ed), Hodder & Stoughton, Chapter 63, pp. 773–85. Julia Russell and Craig Roberts, Angles on Psychological Research, Nelson Thornes, Chapter 13, pp. 212–43. Two major concerns are raised by the use of animals in psychological research. They are: • ethical questions relating to the pain or suffering which may be inflicted on laboratory animals; • ecological validity. There is a wide-ranging debate about what animal studies can, in theory, reveal about human behaviour. The early behaviourists believed that the basic principles of learning operated in the same way in many species. Behaviourist ‘laws’ of learning could be demonstrated just as well in rats as in man. This belief is no longer accepted and generalisations from animal to human behaviour have come to be regarded with some suspicion. Ethics and non-human animal research in psychology Jones, Gross and McIlveen (1999) presciently introduce the topic of ethical considerations and psychological research by stating: ‘Just as Orne (1962) regards the psychological experiment as a social situation, so every psychological investigation is an ethical situation.’ To this end, the British Psychological Society (BPS) lays down codes of conduct to which members in their research of human and non -human participants should adhere. In the UK, this would see practitioners using, among other points of reference: • The Code of Conduct for Psychologists (BPS, 1983) COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) 91 © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E 3 : I S SU E S • The Ethical Principles for Conducting Research with Human Participants (BPS, 1990, 1993) – see below – and • The Guidelines for the Use of Animals in Research (BPS and Committee of the Experimental Psychological Society, 1985) Conducting research with human participants Based on the British Psychological Society (BPS) Ethical Guidelines and Code of Conduct 1985. 92 1. General considerations: especially as much developmental psychology investigates children and young people, always ensure that the research you do is done from the standpoint of the participants taking part. Research should never be offensive to anyone. This means that you should do nothing which threatens a person’s health, well-being or dignity. You should also be aware that we live in a multi-cultural country of diverse ethnic communities. Research should be considered from a socially inclusive, non-sexist, anti-racist and non-ageist perspective. 2. Consent: wherever possible, consent should always be got from participants. 3. Deception: deception is not allowed if participants would be unlikely to co-operate in its absence. If in doubt, the researcher should seek advice from a tutor, etc. 4. Debriefing: any research should provide participants with an opportunity to discuss the outcomes of it. This is called debriefing, and allows discussion of the specific purpose of the research; interpretation of the participants’ particular performance scores, answers, etc., and gives them an opportunity to ask questions. 5. Withdrawal from the investigation: all participants should give their permission to take part in your research. They should also be allowed to withdraw at any time if they so wish. COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E 3 : I S SU E S 6. Confidentiality: unless subject to Scots law and UK statute, e.g. the Data Protection Act, confidentiality between participant and researcher should be observed at all times. If in doubt, seek advice from your tutor, etc. 7. Protection of participants: all participants in a piece of research should be protected from any physical or mental harm. 8. Observational research: any observation should observe the privacy and psychological well-being of those studied. If consent to be observed is not possible, observations sho uld only occur where it would be normal that those observed would/could be seen by others. If in doubt, consult your tutor. 9. Giving psychological advice: sometimes during research, the researcher will be asked for their advice concerning a psychological matter which is of concern to a participant. The golden rule is not to give advice if not qualified to do so. If in any doubt you should seek advice from your tutor. 10. Colleagues: all of us who study psychology share the above set of ethical principles. It is our duty to encourage others who do psychological research to observe these ethical guidelines at all times. Look up: BPS Code of Conduct http://www.bps.org.uk/about/rules5.cfm and http://www.bps/org.uk.charter/codofcon.htm COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) 93 © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E 3 : I S SU E S Why use animals in psychological research? In summary, animals are used in psychological research because of: • the ‘behavioural continuity’ between animals and humans • their simpler biological form • fewer emotive implications of non-human research, hence enhancing objective academic debate • their ability to give clearer cause–effect relationships. Cross-comparative species–species research has its origins in Darwin’s Origin of Species (1859) research in that the study of simpler life forms from our evolutionary history gives us a greater insight into why we think, feel and behave as we do. In 1992 Brehm wrote: ‘In our necessary concern with treating subjects well and protecting them from any harmful effects, we must not overlook the other side of the ethica l issue: the ethical imperative to gain more understanding of important areas of human behaviour. Intimate relationships can be a source of the grandest, most glorious pleasure we human beings experience; they can also be a source of terrible suffering and appalling destructiveness. It is, I believe, an inherently ethical response to try to learn how the joy might be increased and the misery reduced.’ What she means is that ethical and practical considerations are related, in that while psychologists have a duty to protect the welfare of individual participants (and implicitly non-human participants), there remains the overriding duty to do socially relevant research: this is the stuff of psychology. Put more bluntly, animal research allows for experimen tation into aspects of thinking, feeling and behaving that would be ethically difficult, if not impossible, to conduct on human beings. These ethically sensitive areas include severe sensory deprivation (Reisen, 1947; Blakemore and Cooper, 1970); complete social isolation (Harlow and Zimmerman, 1959); extreme stress (Brady, 1958; Seligman, 1974); surgical procedures (Olds and Milner, 1954). In a clinical sense, such procedures and investigations with animals also allow for greater control of variables in such experimentation, e.g. the Skinner Box, whose environment is completely under the control of the experimenter. Further, the use of non-human animals in research allows the claim of evolutionary 94 COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E 3 : I S SU E S continuity to be made. What this implies is that dif ferences between humans and non-humans are quantitative rather than qualitative. We share the same basic evolutionary adaptations. Mammals such as rats, cats, dogs, monkeys, apes and humans have all developed similar brain structure. It is size, number of neurons and the interconnections between these nerve cells that make the inherent differences. It is said that ‘at the level of its basic units, evolution has been highly conservative’, and as a result parallels can be made via experimentation with non-human animals concerning cognitive, conative and affective behaviours (Green, 1994). From a practical point of view – i.e. size, manipulation, shorter life-span, shorter gestation period, etc. – the use of animals in a laboratory experiment is more easily managed than the use of humans. Study of animals also gives rise to the generation of hypotheses and later testing of humans. Examples of this from within developmental psychology would include Bowlby’s theory of attachment (see later), which was greatly i nfluenced by the earlier work of the ethologist Lorenz into imprinting. From a scientific point of view, due to easier manipulations, animal experimentation gives rise to data about cause –effect relationships between variables, as opposed to correlations between co-variants when using humans. The obvious example here, however distasteful from an animal perspective, would be the study of variables influencing cancers. With humans we can only make correlations between smoking and lung cancer. With animals, smoking can be induced (the independent variable) and cancer observed and measured (the dependent variable). Finally Coolican (1994) affirms that species–species comparisons across the phylogenic (evolutionary) scale can indicate what we as humans have lost or gained in our evolutionary history when compared to animals, i.e. the discovery of a redundant structure in the human nervous system, when found active in animals today may suggest its previous purpose and function for human beings. Why use animals at all? The rationale behind animal experimentation is twofold: • the pursuit of scientific knowledge; and • the advancement of science. As a result of animal research in medicine, we have made inroads into cause, diagnosis, prognosis and treatments in the form of vaccines for infectious diseases, the development of antibacterial and antibiotic COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) 95 © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E 3 : I S SU E S drugs, heart surgery, organ transplants, kidney failure, diabetes, malignant hypertension, gastric ulcers, etc. The price is any distress and suffering caused to any animal used in experimentation. Codes of practice ensure that such distress and suffering are minimised as far as possible. The decision to use, or not to use, animals is taken using a cost –benefit analysis of animal pain, distress and suffering as measured against the developments of new scientific knowledge to alleviate human misery and suffering. The medical and scientific justification of animal experimentation is strong in that ‘Gray (1991) argues that not only is it not wrong to give preference to the interests of one’s own species, one has a duty to do so’ (Shackleton Jones; Gross and McIlveen, 1999). This speciesism is countered by opponents who say that medical advances have been delayed due to misleading results from animal experimentation , and that in the early stages of such investigation little in the way of scientific advancement for human beings is forthcoming because scientific understanding of the issue is still developing. It can be many years before any cost –benefit can be seen, tempered by the cost to the animal in terms of pain and suffering, as against the scientific and medical benefit achieved for humans as a result. Whether or not to use animals in experimentation can be decided upon using the Bateson (1986, 1992) Decision Cube. The three dimensions upon which the researcher’s decision is made are: • the quality of research • the certainty of benefit • the degree of animal suffering. Bateson believes that his third dimension should only be pursued if the quality of research and medical benefit is deemed high. Experimentation on animals should not be undertaken for its own sake. Consider the following. Jose Delgado (1969) used observation in a laboratory setting to investigate localisation of physical and motor functions in the brain – using electrical stimulation of the brains of monkey. He wanted to know what particular parts of the brain were responsible for particular physical and motor behaviours. Stimulation of some brain points he found produced normal co-ordinated walking, walking in circles or running. Simulation of other areas produced yawning, falling asleep, loss of appetite, etc. In the most spectacular example, a 5 -second stimulation of a brain area elicited a sequence of behaviour which lasted 96 COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E 3 : I S SU E S 10–14 seconds: the monkey stopped whatever it was doing, changed its facial expressions, turned its head to the right, stood up on two feet, circled to the right, walked on two feet to a pole in the centre of the room, climbed up the pole and came down, growled, threatened, and sometimes attacked another monkey, then approached the group in a friendly manner and resumed its normal behaviour. This stimulation was repeated 20,000 times and the monkey was observed going through exactly the same sequence of behaviou r every time. This suggests that the cause of particular observable behaviours is mere electrical activity in particular parts of the brain. What is true for animal brains such as those of monkeys may also be true for human brains. It is, of course, unethical to experiment on human brains without some legitimate medical purpose. Why then, one might ask, is it not also unethical to do these experiments with laboratory animals? Another example of research using animals in an experiment in biological psychology is Olds and Milner (1954). They wanted to discover the brain’s pleasure centre. They attached an electrode to a rat’s hypothalamus which it could self-stimulate. One area in particular when stimulated would see the rat forgo water and food in favour of constant self-stimulation often up to 100 times a minute and 190 times an hour. By placing the electrode in another part of the hypothalamus, they also discovered a pain centre. The rat never went near the control mechanism to self-stimulate the electrode again! Ethical issues involved here are serious and complex. Some experimenters suggest that if they did no experiments that caused suffering to animals, then there would be very little progress in any field related to biology, medicine or psychology – and in the long run the resultant human suffering might be greater than the animal suffering caused by any experiment now. The ethics of experimentation raises a classic question – does the end justify the means? There is no single, all-purpose answer to such questions. The answer must depend on how good one expects the end to be, how bad one expects the means to be, and how sure one is that this means will lead to that end. Sometimes the end justifies the means, and sometimes it does not. Sometimes experiments produce significant knowledge at a modest price in animal suffering, and sometimes the result is not worth the investment. Unfortunately, it is often difficult to predict how valuable the results of an experiment will be. COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) 97 © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E 3 : I S SU E S Look up: Animals (Scientific Procedures) Act 1986 and go to http://www.homeoffice.gov.uk/animact/aspag5.htm http://www.frame-uk.demon.co.uk/legislat.htm Teaching sign language to a chimpanzee Aim: The aim of this Gardner and Gardner study (1969) was to investigate if a young chimpanzee could be taught to communicate with humans using Ameslan, which is American whole-body sign language. Earlier attempts by Hayes and Hayes (1951) to teach the chimpanzee Vicky to talk had failed. Hayes and Hayes discovered this was because c himpanzees cannot vocalise as humans can. Vocalisation is our ability to talk by forming sounds to make words and phrases, and is biological in origin. Gardner and Gardner had, using natural observation earlier, discovered that chimpanzees communicate by gesture. They felt that this was a good basis upon which to teach a chim panzee to communicate by signing. Method: A longitudinal case study, which is still running today. Subject: Washoe, a female chimpanzee brought into captivity at around 11 months o ld. Procedure: Researchers spent all their time with Washoe and communicated with her, and each other, using Ameslan. Ameslan uses particular gestures to represent objects, events, people, etc. in our world. To get Washoe to use Ameslan they initially held her hands and fingers to make the shape of the word or phrase required. To encourage this, they used behavioural learning techniques based on classical and operant conditioning. Washoe came to associate particular things with the particular gestures she made. If she got the sign correct, she was rewarded by being tickled. Social learning theory was also applied, in that Washoe observed, imitated, and modelled her signing and language behaviours on the humans around her. Results: Detailed records of Washoe’s signing behaviours were kept on a daily basis for the first two months of the project. This stopped because her 98 COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E 3 : I S SU E S signing became just too rapid. Thereafter observation checklists, filled in by three researchers at the same time, were kept to record new signs. A new sign was recorded as being acquired when Washoe used it for fifteen consecutive days without being prompted. By 20 months she was forming her own two -word sentences. By age 4 she was able to sign 132 different words that included nouns, pronouns, adjectives and verbs. To confirm Washoe’s ability, Gardner and Gardner used a double-blind technique. Pictures were shown to Washoe who had to respond by making the appropriate sign. Two independent observers, only one of whom could see the picture Washoe was shown, and the other who could only see the sign that Washoe made, confirmed that Washoe got the ‘picture -sign’ right in 72% of occasions. Conclusion: Gardner and Gardner concluded that Washoe was an active information processor of language. She had developed an exceptional ability to use (sign) language to communicate her needs, wishes and intentions. In comparison with a human, who acquires around 4,000+ words by age 4, Washoe’s ability was not too impressive. In comparison with other chimpanzees, however, Washoe was a superstar! Washoe went on to become the matriarch of five signing chimpanzees at the Chimpanzee and Human Communication Institute of the University of Central Washington. COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) 99 © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 O U TCO M E 3 : I S SU E S Interactive Research other investigations of language acquisition in animals by reporting the aim, method/procedure, results and conclusions of the following studies: Kellogg and Kellogg (1933) and Gua the chimpanzee Hayes and Hayes (1950) and Vicky the chimpanzee Patterson (1978) and Koko the gorilla. Useful starting points: http://www.psypress.co.uk/harley/pdf/P052 -053.pdf http://www.fortunecity.com/greenfield/twyford/73/gua.html http://www.psychology.iastate.edu/faculty/rhpeters/psychology101/pres entations/rhp-language.ppt http://www.koko.org/ http://www.infres.enst.fr/confs/evolang/actes/_actes24.html In around 1,000 words, analyse the use of non -human animals in research in cognitive psychology. • First you must tell the reader what it is you intend to do and how you are going to tackle it. • Then discuss in a non-emotive way the issue, why it developed and its relative importance to cognitive psychology. • Identify and give arguments for the ‘issue’ with relevant theorists/research. • Identify and give arguments against the ‘issue’ with relevant theorists/research. • Identify giving arguments relevant ‘solutions’ to the difficulties/problems posed by the issue. • Identify and give example(s) from at least one appropriate concept of the issue. • Identify and give relevant research indicating the importance of the issue in relation to the appropriate concept(s). • Finally, consider relevant conclusions related to the importance of the issue for cognitive psychology. 100 COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 G E N ER AL R EF E R EN CE S SECTION 4 References Allport, D A, ‘Attention and performance’, in G C laxton (ed.), Cognitive Psychology: New Directions, London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1980 Allport, D A, ‘Visual attention’, in M Posner (ed.), Foundation in Cognitive Science, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1989 Allport, D A, ‘Attention and control. Have we been asking the wrong questions? A critical review of twenty-five years’, in D E Meyer and S M Kornblum (eds), Attention and Performance (Volume 14), London: MIT Press, 1989 Allport, D A; Antonis, B and Reynolds, P, ‘On the division of attention: A disproof of the single channel hypothesis’, Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 24, 225–35, 1972 Attneave, F, ‘Some informational aspects of visual perception’, Psychology Review, 61:183–93, 1954 Atwell, M, ‘The evolution of text: the interrelationship of reading and writing in the composing process’, paper presented at the annual meeting of the National Council of Teachers of English, Boston, MA, 1981 Baron, R A, Psychology: The Essential Science, London: Allyn & Bacon, 1989 Berry, J W; Poortinga, Y H; Segall, M H and Dasen, P R, Cross-cultural psychology: Research and Applications, New York: Cambridge University Press Blakemore, C, The Mind Machine, London: BBC Publications, 1988 Blakemore, C and Cooper, G F, ‘Development of the brain depends on the visual environment’, Nature, 228, 477–8, 1970 Broadbent, D E, ‘The role of auditory localization in attention and memory span’, Journal of Experimental Psychology, 47, 191–6, 1954 Broadbent, D E, Perception and communication, Oxford: Pergamon Press, 1958 Broadbent, D E, ‘Task combination and selective intake of information’, Acta Psychologica, 50, 253–90, 1982 Bruce, V and Green, P R, Visual Perception (2nd ed.), Hove: Erlbaum, 1990 Bruner, J S, ‘On perceptual readiness’, Psychology Review, 64, 123–52, 1957 Bruner, Jerome S and Postman, Leo, ‘On the Perception of Incongruity: A Paradigm’, Journal of Personality, 18, 206–23, 1949 COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) 101 © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 G E N ER AL R EF E R EN CE S Cherry, E C, ‘Some experiments in the recognition of speech, with one and two ears’, Journal of the Acoustical Society of America, 25: 975–9, 1953 Cherry E C and Taylor W K, ‘Some further experiments on the recognition of speech, with one and two ears’, Journal of the Acoustical Society of America, 26:554–9, 1954 Chomsky, N, Syntactic Structures, The Hague: Mouton & Co, 1957 Coren, S and Girgus, J S, Seeing is Deceiving: The Psychology of Visual Illusions, Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, Inc., 1978 Craik, F M and Lockhart, R S, ‘Levels of Processing: A Framework for Memory Research’, Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behaviour, 11: 671–84, 1972 Crider A B; Goethals G R; Kavanaugh R D and Solomon P R, Psychology, (3rd ed.), London: Scott, Foremans & Company, 1989 Deutsch, J and Deutsch, D, ‘Attention: Some theoretical considerations’, Psychological Review, 70: 80–90, 1963 Deutsch, J and Deutsch, D, ‘Comments on selective attention: Perception or response’, Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology , 19: 362–7, 1967 Dodwell, P C, ‘Fundamental processes in vision’, in R L Gregory and A M Coleman (eds), Sensation and Perception. London: Longman, 1995 Eriksen, C W, ‘Attentional search of the visual field’, in D Brogan (ed.), Visual Search, London: Taylor & Francis, 1990 Eriksen, C W and Yeh, Y Y, ‘Allocation of attention in the visual field’, Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performances, 11: 583–97, 1985 Eysenck, M W, Principles of Cognitive Psychology, Hove: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, 1993 Eysenck, M W, ‘Attention’, in C C French and A M Coleman (eds), Cognitive Psychology, London: Longman, 1994 Eysenck, M W and Keane, M T, Cognitive Psychology: A Student’s Handbook, Hove: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, 1990 Fantz, R L, ‘The origin of form perception’, Scientific American, 204: 66–72, 1961 Fodor, J A and Pylyshyn Z, ‘How direct is visual perc eption? Some reflection on Gibson’s “ecological approach”’, Cognition, 9: 139–96, 1981 Gardner, R A and Gardner, B T, ‘Teaching sign language to a chimpanzee’, Science, 165: 664–72, 1969 Gardner, R A and Gardner, B T, ‘Comparative Psychology and language acquisition’, in K Salzinger and R Denmark (eds), Psychology: The State of the Art, New York: Annals of the New York Academy of Science, 1977 102 COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 G E N ER AL R EF E R EN CE S Gardner, R A and Gardner, B T, ‘Comparative Psychology and language acquisition’, Annals of the New York Academy of Science, 309: 37-76, 1978 Gibson, E J and Walk, R D, ‘The “visual cliff”’, Scientific American 202: 64– 71, 1960 Gibson, J J, The Perception of the Visual World, Boston, MA: Houghton Mifflin, 1950 Gibson, J J, The Ecological Approach to Visual Percept ion, Boston, MA: Houghton Mifflin, 1979 Gordon, I E, Theories of Visual Perception, Chichester: Wiley, 1989 Gregory, R L, Eye and Brain: The Psychology of Seeing (5th edition), Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1997 Gregory, R L, The Intelligent Eye, London: Weidenfeld & Nicolson, 1970 Gregory, R L and Wallace, J, Recovery from early blindness, Cambridge: Heffer, 1963 Gross, R D, Key Studies in Psychology (2nd edition), London: Hodder & Stoughton, 1994 Gross, R, Psychology: The Science of Mind and Behaviour (4th edition), London: Hodder & Stoughton, 2001 Hayes, K H and Hayes, C, ‘Intellectual development of a house -raised chimpanzee’, Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society , 95: 105– 9, 1951 Hubel, D H and Wiesel, T N, ‘Receptive fields, bi nocular interaction and functional architecture in the cat’s visual cortex’, Journal of Physiology, 160: 106–54, 1962 Hubel, D H and Wiesel, T N, ‘Receptive fields, binocular interaction, and functional architecture of monkey striate cortex’, Journal of Physiology, 195: 215–43, 1968 Johansson, G, ‘Visual motion perception’, Scientific American, 14: 76–89, 1975 Johnston, W A and Dark, V J, ‘Selective Attention’, Annual Review of Psychology, 37: 43–75, 1986 Johnston, W A and Heinz, S P, ‘Flexibility and capacity demands of attention’, Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 107: 420–35, 1978 Johnston, W A and Heinz, S P, ‘Depth of non -target processing in an attention task’, Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 5: 168–75, 1979 Juola, J F; Bowhuis, D G; Cooper, E F and Warner, C B, ‘Control of attention around the fovea’, Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 15: 315–30 Kahneman, D, Attention and Effort, Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall, 1973 COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) 103 © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 G E N ER AL R EF E R EN CE S Kahneman, D and Tversky, A, ‘Changing views of attention and automaticity’ in R Parasuraman; D R Davies and J Beatty (eds), Varieties of Attention, New York: Academic Press, 1984 Keegan, G, ‘Delirium on helium’, Psychology Review, Vol 9, Phillip Allen Updates, 2002 Keegan, G, Developmental Psychology: Staff Resource Pack (Advanced Higher), Dundee: Learning and Teaching Scotland, 2002 Keegan, G, Higher Psychology: Approaches and Methods , London: Hodder & Stoughton, 2002 Kellogg, W N, ‘Communication and language in the home-raised chimpanzee’, Science, 162: 423–7, 1968 Kellogg, W N and Kellogg, L A, The ape and the child: a study of environmental influence upon early behaviour , New York: McGraw Hill, 1968 Koffka, K, The Principles of Gestalt Psychology, London: Lund Humphries, 1935 Kohler, W, Gestalt Psychology, New York: Liveright, 1947 Krebs, D and Blackman, R, Psychology: A First Encounter, London: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, 1988 LaBerge, D, ‘Spatial extent of attention to letters and words’ , Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance , 9: 371–9, 1983 Locke, J, An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, New York: Mendon (original 1690; reprinted, 1964) Loftus, E S and Palmer, J C, ‘Reconstruction of automobile destructi on, an example of the interaction between language and memory’, Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behaviour, 13: 585–9, 1974 Loftus, E S and Zanni, G, ‘Eyewitness testimony. The influence of wording on a question’, Bulletin of the Psychonomic Society, 5: 86–8, 1975 Marr, D, Vision: A computational investigation into the human representation and processing of visual information, San Francisco, CA: W H Freeman, 1982 Miller, G A, ‘The magical number seven, plus or minus two. Some limits on our capacity for information processing’, Psychological Review, 63: 81– 97, 1956 Miller, G A, ‘The acquisition of word meaning’, Child Development, 49: 999–1004, 1978 Milner, B, ‘Interhemispheric differences in the localization of psychological processes in man’, British Medical Bulletin, 27: 272–7, 1971 Neisser, U, Cognition and Reality, San Francisco, CA: W H Freeman, 1976 Olds, J, ‘Pleasure centers in the brain’, Scientific American, October, 105–6, 1956 104 COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 G E N ER AL R EF E R EN CE S Olds, J, ‘Self-stimulation of the brain’, Science. 127: 315–23, 1958 Olds, J and Milner, P, ‘Positive reinforcement produced by electrical stimulation of the septal area and other regions of a rat brain’, Journal of Comparative and Physiological Psychology, 47: 419–27, 1954 Ornstein, R, The Psychology of Consciousness (2nd edition), Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1986 Pavlov, I P, Conditioned Reflexes, Oxford: OUP, 1927 Piaget, J, The Psychology of Intelligence, London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1950 Piaget, J, The Child’s Conception of Number, London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1952 Piaget, J, The Origins of Intelligence in Children, New York: Norton, 1963 Piaget, J, The Child’s Conception of the World, London: Paladin, 1973 Piaget, J and Inhelder, B, The Child’s Conception of Space, London: RKP, 1956 Piaget, J and Inhelder, B, The Psychology of the Child, London: RKP, 1969 Pinker, S, How The Mind Works, New York: Norton, 1997 Plomin, Robert and DeFries, John C, ‘The genetics of cognitive abilities and disabilities’, Scientific American, 278 (5): 62–9, 1998 Plutchik, R, The Psychology and Biology of Emotion, London: Harper Collins, 1994 Popper, K, Conjecture and Refutations: The Growth of Scientific Knowledge , New York: Harper & Row, 1968 Postman, L; Bruner, J S and McGinnies, E, ‘Personal values as selective factors in perception’, Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology , 43: 142–54, 1948 Rubin, E, Synsoplevede Figurer, Kobenhavn: Gyldendalske, 1915 Rubin, Z and McNeil E B, The Psychology of Being Human (3rd edition), London: Harper and Row, 1983 Schacter, S and Singer, J E, ‘Cognitive, social, and physiological determinants of emotional states’, Psychological Review, 69: 379–99, 1962 Scottish Qualifications Authority, Arrangements for Psychology (1st edition, 1997, 4th edition, 2000, 5th edition 2001), Glasgow Segall, M H; Dasen, P R; Berry, J W and Poortinga, Y H, Human behavior in global perspective (2nd edition), Boston, MA: Allyn & Bacon, 1999 Thorndike, E L, Animal Intelligence: An Experimental Study of the Associative Processes in Animals (Psychological Review, Monograph Supplements, No. 8), New York: Macmillan, 1898 Thorndike, E L, Animal Intelligence, New York: Macmillan, 1911 (Reprinted Bristol: Thoemmes, 1999), COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) 105 © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3 G E N ER AL R EF E R EN CE S Tolman, E C and Honzik, C H, ‘Introduction and removal of reward and maze-learning in rats’, University of California Publications in Psychology, 4: 257–75, Philadelphia, PA: Lippincott, 1930 Treisman, A M, ‘Contextual cues in selective listening’, Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 12, 242–8, 1960 Treisman, A M, ‘Verbal clues, language and meaning in selective attention’, American Journal of Psychology, 77: 215–16, 1964 Treisman, A M and Gelade, G A, ‘A feature integration theory of attention’, Cognitive Psychology, 12: 97–136, 1980 Wundt, W, Outlines of Psychology, Wilhelm Engelmann, 1897 106 COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY (AH) © Le a r n i n g a n d T e a c h i n g S c o t l a n d 2 0 0 3