THURGOOD MARSHALL LAW REVIEW VOLUME 17 FALL 1991 NUMBER 1 CAPITAL SENTENCING EVIDENCE AFTER PENRY AND PAYNE BY DANIEL I. H. BENSON* INTRODUCTION In Penry v. Lynaugh 1 the Supreme Court of the United States reversed in part and remanded a Texas capital case in which the jury "was not provided with a vehicle for expressing its 'reasoned moral response' to [mitigating evidence introduced by the defendant] ... in rendering its sentencing decision."2 In 1982 I had predicted this result3 on the basis of the Court's decisions in Eddings v. Oklahomcr and Lockett v. Ohio,S when considered in light of the obvious defects in the Texas capital sentencing scheme preventing the jury from making a meaningful response to mitigating evidence falling outside the scope of Texas' I narrowly limited special issues on punishment. 6 Other * Professor of Law, Texas Tech University; B.A., University of Texas at Austin, 1958; J.D., University of Texas at Austin, 1961; M.A., Texas Tech University, 1974. 1. 492 U.S. 302 (1989). 2. 492 U.S. at 328 (1989). 3. Benson, Texas Capital Sentencing Procedure After Eddings:Some Questions Regarding Constitutional Validity, 23 So. Tex. L. J. 315, 331 (1982). 4. 455 U.S. 104 (1982). 5. 438 U.S. 586 (1978). 6. When the Penry case was tried, Texas law provided for the submission of three special issues to the sentencing jury: (1) whether the conduct of the defendant that caused the death of the deceased was committed deliberately and with the reasonable expectation that the death of the deceased or another would result; (2) whether there is a probability that the defendant would commit criminal acts of violence that would constitute a continuing threat to society; and (3) if raised by the evidence, whether the conduct of the defendant in killing the deceased was unreasonable in response to the provocation, if any, by the deceased. Tex. Code Crim. Proc. Ann. art. 37.071(b) (Vernon 1981) (amended 1991). Jurors were required HeinOnline -- 17 T. Marshall L. Rev. 1 1991-1992 2 THURGOOD MARSHALL LA W REVIEW [Vol. 17:1 commentators had raised this or closely related issues concerning the constitutional inadequacy of the Texas scheme.7 Indeed, the Court of Appeals, in its decision in Penry, 8 duly noted some of our scholarly qualms, 9 and clearly understood the problem, stating it in a very compelling manner, 10 but denied relief "because prior Fifth Circuit decisions have rejected claims similar to Penry's."ll So much for the interaction of the legal academic community and the courts; in this instance our proffered scholarship was apparently of little value. 12 In response to Penry, the Texas capital sentencing scheme has been revised,13 but significant problems remain, so that some further "critical academic analysis"14 seems justified. Seen in 'perspective, the problems are not confined to the Texas sentencing system, but are present in the sentencing schemes of all states still using the death penalty, so that the issues addressed by the Supreme Court in Penry have ramifications beyond the single jurisdiction involved in that case. to return answers of "yes" or "no" as to each issue submitted, or to report their inability to agree on one or more issues. Unanimous answers of "yes" on each issue submitted resulted in the death sentence being pronounced by the trial judge; answers of "no" or inability to agree on the answer to one or more issues resulted in imposition of a life sentence by the judge. Tex. Code Crim. Proc. Ann. art 37.071(a) (Vernon 1981) (amended 1991). The defendant was allowed to present evidence "as to any matter that the ~ourt deems relevant to sentence," Tex. Code Crim. Proc. Ann. art. 37.071(a) (Vernon 1981) (limended 1991), but if the evidence presented did not come within one or more of the three special issues, the jury had no way to respond to it under the system in effect at the time of Penry. 7. E.g., Green, Capital Punishment, Psychiatric Experts and Predictions ofDangerousness, 13 Capital U. L. Rev. 533, 553 (1984); Dix, Constitutional Validity of the Texas Capital Murder Scheme: A Continuing Question, 43 Tex. B. J. 627, 630, 633 (1980); Black, Due Process for Death: Jurek v. Texas and Companion Cases, 26 Cath. U. L. Rev. 1 (1976). 8. 832 F.2d 915 (5th Cir. 1987), afFd in part and rev'd in part, 492 U.S. 302 (1989). 9. 832 F.2d at 924 n. 5. 10. 832 F.2d at 925-26. 11. 832 F.2d at 926. 12. Former Chief Judge John R. Brown of the Court of Appeals for the Fifth Circuit has argued that the proper role of law professors in our legal system is to provide "critical academic analysis in an objective nonpartisan way." John R. Brown, Is the Corpus (Juris) Terminally Ill?, 12 Tex. Tech L. Rev. 13, 20 (1981). Judge Brown asserted that "it is a disruptive confusion of roles for law professors to participate actively as counsel in actual cases, trial or appellate." Id. at 19. Perhaps so, but to date my participation as appellate defense counsel in capital case litigation has been more effective than my "critical academic analysis." See e.g., Warren v. State, 562 S.W.2d 474 (Tex.' Crim. App. 1978); United States v. Wimberley, CM 409,334 (Army B.R. Feb. 25, 1965), afjd. 16 C.M.A. 3 (1966). Even as counsel for the United States, in at least one case I have been successful in urging that death sentences be set aside, where that was clearly appropriate. See Frady v. United States, 348 F.2d 84 (D.C. Cir. 1965). I regard Judge Brown's admonitions to law professors to stay out of the courts as interesting rhetoric but bad advice, at least in my own case. I realize that this may indicate something about whether I am presently in the, right branch of the profession, a point on which my faculty colleagues and law students might like to be heard. 13. The new sentencing scheme is set forth in Tex. Cqde Crim. Proc. Ann. art. 37.071 (Vernon 1991), and will be discussed in the course of this article. 14. Brown, supra note 12, at 20. HeinOnline -- 17 T. Marshall L. Rev. 2 1991-1992 CAPITAL SENTENCING 1991] 3 The problem common to Lockett. ls Eddings l6 and Penryl7 was the matter of how to insure that the sentencing agent. whether judge or jury. would be able to consider and respond meaningfully to evidence of any mitigating circumstances tendered by the defendant. when limitations in the various statutory schemes precluded such consideration and response. In Payne v. Tennessee. ls decided June 27. 1991. the problem confronting the Court arose from sentencing evidence introduced by the prosection: victim impact testimony. The Court had decided in Booth v. Maryland l9 that the Eighth Amendment bars the admission of victim impact evidence during the punishment phase of a capital case. and had expanded that holding to include prohibition of improper argument by the prosecutor regarding religious and personal qualities of a murder victim in South Carolina v. Gathers. 20 In Payne the Court concluded that both Booth and Gathers were wrongly decided. overruled them. and held that "if the State chooses to permit the admission of victim impact evidence and prosecutorial argument on that subject, the Eighth Amendment erects no per se bar."21 Payne. like Penry, involved issues that have ramifications beyond the single jurisdiction involved in the case. Under Payne, the prosecution can apparently now bring before the sentencing judge or jury a virtually unlimited array of evidence pertaining to the victim of a homicide, the victim's family and the impact the homicide has had upon them. and perhaps even the impact of the homicide upon the community at large or groups within the community (church, civic club, lodge. and like organizations). To be sure. the Court indicated in Payne that such evidence must be relevant, observing that "there is no reason to treat such evidence differently than other relevant evidence is treated."22 But there are no guidelines. no standards, to define and set the limits of victim impact evidence. The Court's capital case jurisprudence now permits a defendant to introduce relevant mitigating evidence beyond the scope of a state's statutory scheme for structuring the punishment decision. and requires that the sentencing judge or jury be capable of making a meaningful response to that kind of mitigating evidence. From the prosecution 15. 16. 17. 18. 19. 20. 21. 22. 438 u.s. 586 (1978). 455 u.s. 104 (1982). 492 u.s. 302 (1989). 111 S.Ct. 2597 (1991). 482 u.s. 496 (1987). 490 u.s. 805 (1989). 111 S.Ct. at 2609. ld. HeinOnline -- 17 T. Marshall L. Rev. 3 1991-1992 THURGOOD MARSHALL LA W REVIEW 4 [Vol. 17:1 side, the Court's capital case jurisprudence now permits the introduction of relevant victim impact evidence and argument based on such evidence. Presumably rebuttal evidence can be presented by the prosecution in response to mitigating evidence, and by the defendant in response to victim impact evidence. In his dissent in Penry,23 Justice Antonin Scalia complained that: The Court today demands [that the Texas scheme] ... be replaced . .. with a scheme that simply dumps before the jury all sympathetic factors bearing upon the defendant's background and character, and the circumstances of the offense, so that the jury may decide without further guidance whether he "lacked the moral culpability to be sentenced to death," ... "did not deserve to be sentenced to death," . . . or "was not sufficiently culpable to I deserve the death penalty". . . . The Court seeks to dignify this by calling it a process that calls for a "reasoned moral response," . . . but reason has nothing to do with it, the Court having eliminated the structure that required reason. It is an unguided, emotional "moral response" that the Court demands be allowed an outpouring of personal reaction to all the circumstances of a defendant's life and personality, an unfocused sympathy. Justice Scalia insisted that "the Court has come full circle, not only permitting but requiring what Furman once condemned."24 Apparently it would not trouble Justice Scalia if the Court's capital case jurisprudence excluded some relevant mitigating evidence, but admitted all relevant aggravating evidence. In his concurring opinion in Payne, Justice Scalia repeated his belief that the admission of all relevant mitigating evidence as required by Eddings'-5 and LockettU is wrong, and even if the requirement should be abandoned he would still affirm the judgment in Payne admitting victim impact evidence and argument. 27 Justice Stevens, on the other hand, dissenting in Payne, rejected the notion that since the defendant has a right to introduce all relevant mitigating evidence, the prosecution should be allowed to respond with similar evidence about the victim as a matter of faimess. 28 "This argument is a classic non sequitur . .." insisted Justice Stevens, because "[t]he victim is not on trial; her character, whether good or bad, cannot 23. 24. 25. 26. 27. 28. 492 u.s. at 359 (citations omitted). Id. The reference is to Furman v. Georgia, 408 U.S. 238 (1972). 455 U.S. 104 (1982). 438 U.S. 586 (1978). _ U.S. at _ , III S.Ct. at 2613. _ U.S. at _ , 111 S.Ct. at 2627. HeinOnline -- 17 T. Marshall L. Rev. 4 1991-1992 1991] CAPITAL SENTENCING 5 therefore constitute either an aggravating or mitigating circumstance."29 Justice Stevens elaborated his point: Even if introduction of evidence about the victim could be equated with introduction of evidence about the defendant, the argument would remain flawed in both its premise and its conclusion. The conclusion that exclusion of victim impact evidence results in a significantly imbalanced sentencing procedure is simply inaccurate. Just as the defendant is entitled to introduce any relevant mitigating evidence, so the State may rebut that evidence and may designate any relevant conduct to be"an aggravating factor provided that the factor is sufficiently well defined and consistently applied to cabin the sentencer's discretion. 3o Justice Stevens believes that the approach taken in Payne will, in some cases, cause defendants to be "sentenced arbitrarily to death on the basis of evidence that would not otherwise be admissible because it is irrelevant to the defendants' moral culpability."3! The present situation, then, is one in which some members of the Court believe that too much mitigating evidence is being allowed from the defendant,32 and other members of the Court believe that too much aggravating evidence is being allowed from the prosecution. Suggestions are made from both viewpOInts that the way is now open for the imposition of death sentences "freakishly" and "wantonlY,"33 and as the result of "wholly arbitrary and capricious action,"34 the very thing condemned in Furman and its progeny.35 The present disorder in the Court's capital case jurisprudence on sentencing raises the question of whether it is really possible to devise and implement systems which provide guided discretion and avoid arbitrary and capricious imposition of the death penalty. It may well be that the decision of whether or not to execute another human being is so fraught with deep-seated emotional, psychological, religious and highly individual personal value judgments on the part of the sentencer, whether judge or jury, that it is beyond the capacity of the legal system to confme the discretion of the sentencer with lists of aggravating and 29.ld. 30.ld. 31. _ u.s. at _ , III S.Ct. at 2630. 32. 492 U.S. at 359. 33. Furman v. Georgia, 408 U.S. 238, 310 (1972) (Stewart, J., concurring). 34. Gregg v. Georgia, 428 U.S. 153, 189 (1976). 35. See, e.g., the dissenting opinion of Justice Scalia, joined by Chief Justice Rehnquist, Justice White and Justice Kennedy, in Penry v. Lynaugh, 492 U.,S. 302, 359 (1989), and the dissenting opinion of Justice Stevens, joined by Justice Blackmun, in Payne v. Tennessee, _ U.S. _ , _ , 111 S.Ct. 2597, 2630 (1991). HeinOnline -- 17 T. Marshall L. Rev. 5 1991-1992 THURGOOD MARSHALL LA W REVIEW 6 [Vol. 17:1 mitigating factors. The Court's capital case jurisprudence on sentencing may be little more than an elaborate illusion which provides the appearance of carefully guided discretion, but which actually delivers the same kind of arbitrary and capricious infliction of the death penalty that was denounced in Furman. It seems td me that this is the case. I want to discuss that illusion, the reasons for it, and its characteristics, rather than do the standard case analysis of the Court's capital punishment jurisprudence. The kind of analysis I propose will tell us more, in my view, about where we are and what we are doing with capital punishment at this point in our national life, than legal analysis of case law. In point of fact, the case law has very little to do with what is actually taking place, and can evep. be misleading, since it conveys the impression that the Court is continuing to develop a wellreasoned body of law in a consistent, organic manner. II. SHAM QUANITIFICATION OF NONSCALAR QUALITATIVE DATA It may prove helpful to provide some qackground regarding the uses and misuses of quantitative data in sociology and other behavioral sciences. What is happening in the Court's capital case jurisprudence closely resembles misuse of quantitative data in the social sciences, although the situation is not precisely the s~e. The similarities are close enough, however, to justify a compatison. In 1956 sociologist Pitirim A. Sorokin wrote a book entitled Fads and Foibles in Modern Sociology and Related Sciences,36 in which he discussed at some length a phenomenon he called quantophrenia. 37 Sorokin raised no objections to the appropriate use of mathematical analysis and statistical techniques in social science; it was misuse that he opposed: So long as the method is genuinely mathematical and is applied to those psychosocial facts which lend themselves to quantitative analysis, it proves fruitful and deserves ever-increasing cultivation. But when the true quantitative method is replaced by pseudomathematical imitations; when the method is misused and abused in various ways; when it is applied to phenomena which, so far, do not lend themselves to quantification; and when it consists in the manipulation of mathematical symbols in a vacuum or in the mere transcription of mathematical formulae on paper 1 36. PITIRIM A. SOROKIN, FADS AND FOIBLES IN MODERN SOCIOLOGY AND RELATED SCIENCES (1956). 37. Id. at 102-73. HeinOnline -- 17 T. Marshall L. Rev. 6 1991-1992 1991] CAPITAL SENTENCING 7 without tying them to the relevant psychosocial units-then the approach misfires. Under these conditions, use of mathematical method becomes a mere quantophrenic preoccupation having nothing in common with mathematics and giving no cognition of the psychosocial world. 38 Sorokin asserted that the "tidal wave" of misuse of mathematical methods was "so high that the contemporary stage of the psychosocial sciences can be properly called the age of quantophrenia and numerology. "39 Elaborating, Sorokin explained that "[tlhis disease manifests itself in many forms and in every region of sociology, psychology, psychiatry, and anthropology. . . . "40 He described several elements of quantophrenia in the social sciences. First, there are "[elver-increasing numbers of quanto- or metrophrenic studies . . . published in the journals.... "41 Similarly, books in the field "become increasingly numerological and metromanic. "42 Researchers come to believe that "quantitative research is the only truly scientific investigation of psychosocial phenomena, and that all nonquantitative studies are either merely 'arm chair philosophy,' or 'subjective speculation,' or at best 'an inexact, superficial and unverifiable literary exercise' . "43 Research grants are increasingly available only for quantitative studies, and there is "[al similar trend ... under way among journalists, reviewers, and even ministers and the public at large."44 Sorokin concludes that quantophrenia results in the social science disciplines becoming "territories dominated by an occupational army of statisticians, bookkeepers, accountants, numerologists, and metromanics. "45 In the larger context of his unhappiness with "the age of quantophrenia," Sorokin complained specifically of sham quantification of nonscalar data, observing that "one of the most notable manifestations of metrophrenia is the increasing trend toward unrestrained quantification of all qualitative data, no matter whether or not they lend themselves to such an operation.' '46 It is here that Sorokin gets close to what is happening in the capital punishment jurisprudence of the Supreme Court, as I view the situation, and it 38. 39. 40. 41. 42. 43. 44. 45. 46. ld. ld. ld. ld. ld. ld. ld. ld. ld. at 103. at 103-04. at 104. at 105. at 122. HeinOnline -- 17 T. Marshall L. Rev. 7 1991-1992 8 THURGOOD MARSHALL LA W REVIEW [Vol. 17:1 is this aspect of his observations about misuse of mathematical techniques that I want to compare with the Court's capital case jurisprudence. Sorokin notes that: The passion for quantifying all sorts of qualitative data has manifested itself in many fields: in measuring the intensities and qualities of beliefs, emotions, intelligence, ideologies, attitudes and public opinion; in the quantitative theories of "factor-analysis"; in the construction of "mathematical models"; and in exploring general methods for correctly translating nonmetric qualities into scalable ones.47 The point to see is that "if the quantified 9ualities have units, they can be measured or scaled and the measurements expressed in numbers," but the converse is also true: "If the scaled quantities do not have units, they cannot be adequately ~caled and measured."48 Accordingly, Sorokin argues, "[i]f, in spite of this, the 'unitIess qualities' are quantified, the resultant measurements are bound to be fictitious rather than real, arbitrarily superimposed upon the phenomena rather than giving objective measurements of them. "49 Sorokin's conclusion was that "[i]t is high time to cease these pseudoscientific preoccupations.' 'so Sorokin's book did not end the preoccupation of the social sciences with mathematics and statistics. Statistical analysis continues to be an important research tool, even though there are situations where measurement may be out of place. Indeed, it has been argued that there is also sometimes a preoccupation with qualitative aspects of research: I Possibly more widespread than the mystique of quantity, and certainly more pernicious in its effect, especially on behavioral science, is a corresponding mystique ofquality. This mystique, like its counterpart, also subscribes to the magic of numbers, only it views their occult powers as a kind of black magic, effective only for evil ends, and seducing us into giving up our souls for what, after all, is nothing but dross. 51 The mystique of quality insists that to a significant extent it is not possible to express important conclusions about human behavior solely 47. Id. 48. Id. 49. Id. 50. Id. at 130. 51. ABRAHAM KAPLAN, THE CONDUCT OF INQUIRY: METHODOLOGY FOR BEHA VIORAL SCIENCE 206 (1964). HeinOnline -- 17 T. Marshall L. Rev. 8 1991-1992 1991] CAPITAL SENTENCING 9 by the use of numbers. Methodologist Abraham Kaplan explains, "As my friends at the University of Michigan have sometimes formulated this view, 'If you can measure it, that ain't it!"'52 Kaplan observes: "The point is that both quality and quantity are misconceived when they are taken to be antithetical or even alternative."53 There is a place for both approaches to analysis of human behavior and human problems. Even so, the kind of sham quantification of truly nonscalar, qualitative data denounced by Sorokin would seem to lead to error. There is a point beyond which it is not possible to convert inherently subjective matters into objective data of the kind that can be measured and thereafter dealt with as objective phenomena. III. SHAM OBJECTIVITY IN CAPITAL SENTENCING Although statistical methodology and mathematics do not play a large role in the Supreme Court's capital case jurisprudence,54 it can be argued that the Court is making a mistake quite similar to that criticized by Sorokin: the Court is trying to impose an objectivity impossible of attainment upon the process of capital sentencing, a process so inherently subjective that it is not susceptible to effective control by lists of aggravating and mitigating "factors" that can be added up and compared in an effort to determine which list "outweighs" the other. Indeed, such lists of aggravating and mitigating factors are not generally used in any other kind of criminal cases. The United States Sentencing Commission's sentencing guidelines can be thought of as something like a compilation of aggravating and mitigating factors, 55 and those guidelines apply in non-capital cases. But the federal sentencing guidelines represent an attempt to consider the ep.tire relevant background of a convicted offender, and to arrive at a sentence that takes into account everything about the individual to be sentenced. Further, the purposes of the federal sentencing guidelines include the goal of rehabilitating the offender56 as well as incapacitating him or her and providing just punishment. 52. Id. 53. Id. at 207. 54. No doubt this is matter of keen disappointment for many. Consider the Court's refusal to be guided by the available statistical data presented in McCleskey v. Kemp, 481 U.S. 279, 312-13 (1987), concluding that while there was "a discrepancy [in capital sentencing] thai appears to correlate with race," that discrepancy does not "demonstrate a constitutionally significant risk of racial bias affecting the Georgia capital sentencing process." 55. See United States Sentencing Commission, FEDERAL SENTENCING GUIDELINE MANUAL (1987). 56. Id. at 1. HeinOnline -- 17 T. Marshall L. Rev. 9 1991-1992 10 THURGOOD MARSHALL LA W REVIEW [Vol. 17:1 The same cannot be said, of course, for capital case sentencing schemes. There is certainly no question of rehabilitation of the offender, and the states' capital sentencing sche~es reflect an intense preoccupation with the task of excluding things from consideration, rather than broadly including everything of relevance. One would have thought that in formulating a procedure for deciding who is to be killed and who is to be spared, each state would have approached the task by seeking to include everything that could have a bearing on the issue. One might have supposed that the states wou),d have followed the path recommended by Karl Llewellyn when he refused to attempt a defInition of law itself: A definition both excludes and includes. It marks out a field. It makes some matters fall inside the field; it makes some fall outside. And the exclusion is almost always rather arbitrary. I have no desire to exclude anything from matters legal. In one aspect law is as broad as life, and for some purposes one will have to follow life pretty far to get the bearings of the legal matters one is examining. I say again, therefore, that I shall not attempt a definition. I shall not describe a periphery, a stopping place, a barrierY Instead, what the states did, in practice, had, the effect of making the "rather arbitrary"58 kinds of exclusions about which Llewellyn complained. And the Supreme Court found it necessary to devote an inordinate amount of time and effort to the process of deciding which exclusions were acceptable and which would not pass constitutional muster. Again, such lists of aggravating arid mitigating factors are unique to capital case sentencing, for the most part.59 Regulating the exercise of discretion on the part of the sentencer is not unique to capital cases. As Barry Nakell and Kenneth A. Hardy pointed out in their 1987 study of the arbitrariness of the death penalty: 57. Llewellyn, A Realistic Jurisprudence-The Next Step, 30 Colum. L. Rev. 431, 432 (1930). 58. [d. 59. It is true that aggravating factors can be considered in non-capital cases, and that such factors can increase the severity of the punishment. For example, in Texas the use or exhibition of a deadly weapon during the commission of a felony offense can result in the unavailability of probation for the offender. Tex. Code Crim. Proc. Ann. art. 42.12, § 3g(a)(2) (Vernon 1989). Similarly, the use or exhibition of a deadly weapon during the commission of a felony can result in an offender having to serve more time in prison before he or she becomes eligible for parole. Tex. Code Crim. Proc. Ann. a~. 42.18, § 8 (Vernon 1989). But even though such aggravating factors play a role in sentencing and the punishment to be imposed on the offender, they are not employed in the same way that aggravating and mitigating factors are used in capital cases. There is no attempt, in the use of such factors in non-capital cases, to eliminate other kinds of evidence, as in the capital case jurisprudence. HeinOnline -- 17 T. Marshall L. Rev. 10 1991-1992 1991] CAPITAL SENTENCING 11 The problem of controlling discretion is not unique to capital punishment; it is a characteristic of the criminal justice system in general. Any arbitrariness in sentencing, to the extent that it exists, is probably a product of processes common to capital and noncapital cases. That arbitrariness may not be the unique feature; the severity of the penalty is. The overarching question is whether that makes any difference. 6O And the further overarching question, for purposes of the present discussion, is whether the capital sentencing procedures approved by the Supreme Court, including the lists of aggravating and mitigating factors and the treatment of sentencing evidence mandated by those lists, eliminates significant arbitrariness. Lawyers and judges tend to rely perhaps too heavily upon procedure itself. Nakell and Hardy commented: Ordinarily, a judicial decision about whether a decision-making process is arbitrary is based on a determination of whether the system lacks necessary procedures. Therefore, the standard constitutional remedy for arbitrariness is simply the erection of procedural safeguards. Confidence in the efficacy of procedure as the instrument for the protection of liberty is a hallmark of our due process jurisprudence. Once the procedures are in place, the Court customarily assumes they will work and does not generally inspect their performance. 61 Nakell and Hardy acknowledged that Furman was different, holding "that because the death penalty is different, the traditional procedural remedies were not sufficient. "62 But that means, as they also pointed 60. BARRY NAKELL & KENNETH A. HARDY, THE ARBITRARINESS OF THE DEATH PENALTY 29-30 (1987) (footnote omitted). Nakel1 and Hardy carried out an empirical study which examined "the relationship between the death penalty on the statute books and the death penalty in practice," conducting their study "on homicide cases that arose in North Carolina during the first year of that state's death penalty statute containing the new procedures." Id. at xiii. They col1ected information about the defendants, the victims, and circumstances of the offenses, and the processing of the cases through the judicial system, subjecting all of the data to statistical analysis. They found that "although the legal standards were the most consistently significant factor in the outcomes at al1 stages of the capital punishment process, considerable variation in the results cannot be explained by the legal standards alone and therefore represents arbitrariness." Id. at xii-xiv. They identified several extralegal factors that affected the outcome of the cases involved. See text accompanying note 67, infra. 61. Id. at 38 (citing Kent v. United States, 363 U.S. 541, 555 (1966); Leeper v. Texas, 139 U.S. 462, 468 (1891); and Hurtado v. California, 110 U.S. 516, 536-37 (1884». 62.Id. HeinOnline -- 17 T. Marshall L. Rev. 11 1991-1992 12 THURGOOD MARSHALL LA W REVIEW [Vol. 17:1 out, that since the Supreme Court in its 1976 decisions 63 "upheld the new procedures on their face, as McGautha did for the former procedures, the 'death is different' doctrine should require the Court to reexamine them in practice, as Furman did for the former procedures."64 Certainly the Court has examined those procedures "in practice" since Furman, although as noted earlier the Court refused to be guided by the available statistical data regarding racial discrimination in the imposition of the death penalty in the McCleskey6S case. The Court's examination of the procedures "in practice," however, has been significantly limited to evaluation of things like the kinds of evidence that will or will not be considered during the penalty phase of a case. That sort of limitation, with its heavy and misguided emphasis on what Sorokin called "quantophrenic preoccupation,"66 has contributed to the elaborate, but mistaken, illusion that the Court's capital case jurisprudence has fostered schemes which provide carefully guided discretion in capital sentencing. The notion seems to be that if the right kinds of lists can be compiled, and the states compelled to adhere to them in the sentencing stage of capital cases, then all will be well: the jury will hear only the right kind of evidence, the decision making process will be properly guided, and there will therefore be no arbitrariness in death sentences resulting from the process. Trial judges, prosecutors and defense lawyers know that the most critical sort of decision making in capital cases takes place before trial. Nakell and Hardy, for example, concluded in their study of North Carolina cases under the new death penalty statutes that there were "extralegal factors that had strong relationships with the outcome at several discretionary stages. "67 They found that: Those extralegal factors are, in the pretrial stages, the judicial district in which the case was processed and the race of the defendant; at the verdict stage, an extralegal factor is the race of the victim. Obviously, the jury was an important discretionary decision maker for the cases that went to trial. Nevertheless, the prosecutor exercised far greater discretionary influence over the course of the process through control over the charging and guilty 63. In Gregg v. Georgia, 428 U.S. 153 (1976); Proffitt v. Florida, 428 U.S. 242 (1976), and Jurek v. Texas, 428 U.S. 262 (1976). In Woodson v. North Carolina, 428 U.S. 280 (1976), and Roberts v. Louisiana, 428 U.S. 325 (1976), the Court struck down the mandatory death penalty schemes involved. 64. NakeIl & Hardy, supra note 60, at 38 (the references are to McGautha v. California, 402 U.S. 183 (1971), and Furman v. Georgia, 408 U.S. 238 (1972». 65. McCleskey v. Kemp, 481 U.S. 279 (1987). 66. Sorokin, supra note 36, at 103. 67. NAKELL & HARDY, supra note 60, at xiv. HeinOnline -- 17 T. Marshall L. Rev. 12 1991-1992 CAPITAL SENTENCING 1991] 13 plea negotiation decisions that determined whether a case went to trial at all. 68 Elaborating on this aspect of capital cases, Nakell and Hardy reported that "[t]he indictment stage is only the first opportunity that the prosecutor has to exercise discretion in the processing of homicide cases,' '69 pointing out that even after indictment the prosecutor has control over whether to reduce or dismiss first degree murder charges, and that this can be done on the prosecutor's own initiative, or after negotiation with defense counsepo Significantly, they found that "[a]lthough the evidence was ... a very strong predictor of whether a defendant was brought to trial for first degree murder . . . there was still considerable' variation in the decisions unaccounted for by the evidence."71 Their final conclusion on this aspect of their study was: The prosecutor's discretionary decisions had a significant effect on whether a case was brought to trial for first degree murder without regard to the quality of the evidence or the seriousness of the case. That discretion was exercised in connection with the charging, dismissal, and plea bargaining decisions. If the prosecutor took the case to trial, the trial and sentencing juries, the trial judge, the appellate court, and the governor might make impo.rtant discretionary decisions. The prosecutor's earlier discretion, however, may fairly be singled out as the one with the widest practical impact.72 Nakell and Hardy determined that "the chances of defendants in cases ,vith the same quality of evidence being brought to trial on a first degree murder charge, and therefore at risk of a death sentence, depended to a significant extent . . . on what judicial district processed the case.''73 They found that most of the districts brought between 5 percent to 15 percent of their cases to trial as first degree murder prosecutions, but that "at least two districts had aberrantly high rates, one of 42 percent and the other of 40 percent,"74 so that "Controlling for the quality of the evidence in the cases, at least three districts operated outside the norms established by the rese'75 Expressed in 68.ld. 69. ld. at 130. 70.ld. 71. ld. at 131. 72. ld. at 152. 73.ld. 74.ld. 75.ld. HeinOnline -- 17 T. Marshall L. Rev. 13 1991-1992 14 THURGOOD MARSHALL LA W REVIEW [Vol. 17:1 terms of the chances of a defendant going to trial as a capital defendant, they reported that in one of the aberrant districts studied, "the odds of a defendant being brought to trial on first degree murder were 158 times those of a similarly situated defendant in a control group; in a second [aberrant district], 18 times grater; and in a third [aberrant district], 9 times greater."76 This hardly comes as news to experienced trial judges, prosecutors and defense lawyers. They know from their own direct experience that the results of studies like that done by NakeU and Hardy are providing accurate data on what actually goes on in processing defendants through the capital trial and sentencing systems of our states. This aspect of the capital sentencing process in the United States should not come as a surprise to interested legal and other scholars. It has been discussed frequently enough in the literature to make it almost a matter of common knowledge. Welsh S. White, in his thorough examination of the procedural safeguards employed in capital cases, noted "the prosecutor's ability to manipulate the system"77 and the fact that such ability affects the operation of the system. White also commented on the quality of defense counsel as a factor of great signifIcance in the process of determining which capital defendants are actually sentenced to death, concluding that variations in the quality of representation given by defense counsel are not likely to change, so that "the objective of securing the evenhanded application of capital punishment is likely to remain an illusory goal."78 In a subsequent book on the death penalty, White discussed Justice Byron White's evalu;ation for the plurality in Gregg v. Georgia79 of the effect that the pl~a bargaining process has in the-determination of which defendants will stand trial facing a death sentence. Justice White found "untenable" the argument that prosecutorial discretion is standardless and therefore would result in wanton and freakish imposition of the death penalty.80 Regarding Justice White's conclusion, Welsh White commented: Justice White's premise, of course, is that i~ determining whether the death penalty will be charged, prosecutors will be influenced by the same factors as the jury will be in determining whether the death penalty will be imposed. In the context of plea bargaining, 76.Id. 77. WHITE. LIFE IN THE BALANCE: PROCEDURAL SAFEGUARDS IN CAPITAL CASES 14 (1984). 78.Id. 79. 428 U.S. 153 (1976). 80. 428 U.S. at 225. HeinOnline -- 17 T. Marshall L. Rev. 14 1991-1992 1991] CAPITAL SENTENCING 15 however, this premise is very dubious. The vast empirical literature relating to plea bargaining indicates that it operates pursuant to dynamics that are totally different from those that apply in criminal trials. This literature has not focused specifically on plea bargaining with capital defendants. Over the past two years I have conducted numerous interviews with defense counsel who specialize in capital cases. These interviews indicate that the likelihood of a plea bargain in a capital case will be dramatically affected by factors that have nothing to do with the nature of the crime or the strength of the evidence against the defendant. 81 White then discussed such factors as the place where the crime was committed, the widespread practice of offering most capital offenders an opportunity to plead guilty, the fact that prosecutors in small counties are more likely than prosecutors in larger counties to offer a plea bargain in capital cases, and the experience and ability of the defense lawyer h.andling the case. 82 White concludes: These observations show that the prosecutor's decision to plea bargain is certainly not based exclusively on his assessment of the nature of the alleged capital offense or the strength of the government's case. Indeed, the existing literature suggests that these factors are of secondary importance. Prosecutors have offered plea bargains even in cases where the defendant's crime seems especially heinous and the evidence of his guilt is strong. 83 81. WHITE, THE DEATH PENALTY IN THE EIGHTIES: AN EXAMINATION OF THE MODERN SYSTEM OF CAPITAL PUNISHMENT 32 (1987) (citation to general plea bargaining literature omitted). 82. ld. at 32-35. 83. Id. at 35. Regarding the latter point, about a plea bargain in a case where the crime was especially heinous and the evidence of guilt was strong, I was involved as defense counsel in a case originally charged and indicted as capital, but which was reduced to a non-capital murder charge prior to trial for the sole reason that the prosecutor was a candidate in a race for the state senate, and did not have time to try the case as a capital case, particularly in view of the lengthy voir dire examination of prospective jurors that would have been required. The trial of the case as a capital case would have seriously disrupted the campaign schedule. It was expressly negotiated and agreed between the prosecutor, defense counsel, and the capital defendant, that if the defense would seek a continuance and thus enable the prosecutor to meet the obligations of the various campaign trips that had been scheduled, the charge would be reduced from capital murder to non-capital murder. That was done, the trial was held as a non-capital case, and the defendant was convicted of murder by a jury and sentenced to the state penitentiary. Perhaps understandably, I am not at liberty to provide a citation to that case, and indeed I would not want to do so, since an appropriate result was obtained in the case (from the standpoint of the prosecution and society) even in the absence of a capital sentence, and the prosecutor in question won election to the state senate and has been an able and effective public servant in that capacity over the years. But the case does serve to illustrate the point: plea bargains, reduction of charges to non-capital murder, and similar decisions by prosecutors in capital cases, quite often have little or nothing at all to do with the kinds of issues sentencing judges or juries consider at the penalty phase of a capital trial. HeinOnline -- 17 T. Marshall L. Rev. 15 1991-1992 16 THURGOOD MARSHALL LA W REVIEW [Vol. 17:1 White argued that Justice White's assumption about prosecutorial discretion in capital cases is incorrect, and "[t]hus the Court's conclusion that the death penalty will not be arbitrarily applied is suspect," with this conclusion suggesting "serious questions about the constitutionality of our present system of capital punishment."84 Charles L. Black, Jr., made the same points in discussing how the charging decision is made: The rough answer (not subject to sufficient qualification to make analysis of the qualifications here worthwhile) is that the prosecutor makes this decision, and that his decision is within large limits "discretionary"-subject to no clearly statable rule, but formed, even by the most conscientious of prosecutors, on the basis of an open-ended series of factors, such as an estimate of difficulties of proof or a belief that a charge of the maxim,um offense that might be proved would result in an unduly severe punishment given the circumstances, and so on. It is the "and so on" that is most important, for there is no rule to bar entry of any noncorrupt consideration-and the occasional entry of a corrupt consideration is exceedingly hard to establish. 85 Significantly, Black insists that there is not "any practicable way to reduce this process to rule."86 Accordingly" "within any foreseeable future, one of the absolutely crucial decisions for life or death-the decision whether to offer the defendant a chance to plead guilty to a noncapital offense-will be made administratively, on the basis of administrative discretion, without clear stanpards in law. "87 Another excellent study demonstrating the same aspects of the prosecutor's unguided discretion is that of William J. Bowers, who reached conclusions similar to those of the ~tudies already cited, and who observed: Perhaps, indeed, it is inevitable that capital punishment will be used in an arbitrary and discriminatory manner. Because death is the supreme punishment, it will be reserved for the crimes people find most shocking and abhorrent-those that most provoke anger, inflame emotions, and incite fear and apprehension. In other words, this form of punishment, which, according ~o the Supreme Court, must be held most strictly to the standards of just retribution 84.Id. 85. CHARLES L. BLACK, JR., Capital Punishment: The Inevitability of Caprice and Mistake 46-47 (1978). 86. Id. at 51. 87.Id. HeinOnline -- 17 T. Marshall L. Rev. 16 1991-1992 1991] CAPITAL SENTENCING 17 because it is "different in kind" from other forms of punishment, may at the same time be the one most subject to the deeply rooted passions and prejudices that will cause its application to depart from the retributive justice model. 88 And while dealing with this aspect of prosecutorial discretion, Bowers asserts, as I do in this article, that capital punishment, can serve to draw distinctions among crime and criminals that are not, and cannot be, reflected in the law, but that do reflect social realities-such as who the victims and offenders are. In effect, the symbolic and defInitive character of death as punishment may make its use peculiarly sensitive to social forces beyond the realm of law and justice. 89 It seems to me that Bowers is correct in this. In any event, the death penalty selection process is clearly not susceptible to effective control by lists of aggravating and mitigating factors, although the Supreme Court's capital case jurisprudence plainly assumes that such lists, along with other procedural protections, are adequate to control the process so as to eliminate arbitrariness of an unconstitutional dimension. It is for this reason that I suggest the Court's objectivity is a sham objectivity. With respect to the aggravating and mitigating factors, Bowers states that the Court has made the following basic assumptions: 1. That sentencing guidelines within the context of a separate sentencing phase of the trial will effectively focus the attention and concern of sentencing authorities on selected legally salient characteristics of the crime and the convicted defendant, and thus effectively remove legally irrelevant factors from consideration in the sentencing decision. 2. That automatic appellate review of all death sentences will serve as a check on findings of fact with respect to aggravating and mitigating circumstances and, by application of the similarity standard, will detect and correct any tendency of sentencing authorities to use the remaining discretionary powers in an arbitrary or discriminatory manner. 3. That the sentencing and review procedures under these statutes will counteract any tendency toward the displacement of arbitrariness or discrimination to other (earlier) points in the handling of potentially capital cases, in part because the sentencing guidelines will also influence the exercise of discretion at other decision points. 88. WILLIAM J. BOWERS, LEGAL HOMICIDE: DEATH AS PUNISHMENT IN AMERICA, 1864-1982 205 (1984). 89. Id. HeinOnline -- 17 T. Marshall L. Rev. 17 1991-1992 18 THURGOOD MARSHALL LA W REVIEW [Vol. 17:1 4. That variations among these statutes in the restrictiveness of sentencing guidelines and the particular rules. and procedures governing the sentencing decision, providing they do not eliminate individualized treatment, will not impair their effectiveness in removing arbitrariness and discrimination from the administration of capital punishment.90 And Bowers asserts that "[w]hether, in fact, these reforms will remove arbitrariness and discrimination from the administration of capital punishment is ultimately an empirical question. "91 Bowers concludes, with the other studies I have cited, that there is abundant empirical evidence of continuing arbitrariness and discrimination in the administration of the death penalty, notwithstanding the lists of aggravating and mitigating factors, and the Supreme Court's jurisprudence dealing with the formulation and use of those lists. Bowers explains: The evidence of arbitrariness and discrimination presented here is qualitatively more than a statistical demonstration that certain states' sentencing practices have failed to meet the Furman standard. Beyond this, we have seen that the arbitrariness is manifold in its links to race, location witb;in the state, and other personal, situational, and social influencesr that it is pervasive in its presence at various decision-making points in the handling of capital cases; that it is intractable under different kinds of statutes in different states; and that it is replicated in different kinds of studies using different kinds of data. These findings represent an extension of our perspective on arbitrarines~ in capital punishment in the sense that they explicate some of the ways in which extralegal influences operate even in the presence of post-Furman statutory reforms-how prosecutors, defense attorneys, and judges, as well as jurors, become the agents of both systematic and unsystematic arbitrariness.92 Examples of other books and studies establishing the continuing arbitrariness of the death penalty process could be set forth here, but perhaps the material cited is adequate to establish that a significant body of literature exists on this issue, and that, as Bowers put it, the findings are "replicated in different kinds of studies using different kinds of data, "93 obtaining each time subst~tially the same findings and reaching basically the same conclusions. And so I believe it is a fair judgment, well supported by the available evidence in the literature, 90. Id. at 91. Id. at 92. Id. at 93. Id. at 201-02. 202. 372-73. 373. HeinOnline -- 17 T. Marshall L. Rev. 18 1991-1992 1991] CAPITAL SENTENCING 19 that the Supreme Court's efforts to impose objectivity in capital sentencing have been unsuccessful, and that any resulting apparent "objectivity" is merely a sham. Robert Weisberg has noted Justice Thurgood Marshall's angry complaint "that the Court has asked virtually nothing of the states that they were not doing before Furman, and essentially he is right. "94 Weisberg states: "It is as if the constitutional strictures on the death penalty are merely a matter of legal aesthetics. The state will satisfy the Court if it can describe its penalty scheme according to some rational-looking form-indeed some metaphor of rational form. "95 Expanding on this theme, Weisberg insists that: The Court's experiment in reducing the death penalty to the rule of law has devolved to a merely aesthetic requirement: the states must have some sort of penalty trial law on their books to fill the embarrassing gap created by Furman. The law must somehow identify a .class of death-eligible murderers smaller than the class of all murderers, must give some sentencer some discretion about choosing which of the eligibles to execute, and must grant defendants a fairly broad opportunity to make a case for mitigation. Beyond that, the rule may be of any kind, and the Court will not monitor its enforcement.96 Weisberg's assessment of the situation seems to me to be fair and accurate. That is, in fact, where the Court's capital case jurisprudence has led to date: instead of true objectivity, and the elimination of arbitrariness in response to the command of Furman, the actual requirement is a mere aesthetic one, which can be met easily by "some metaphor of rational form."97 IV. REASONS FOR THE PRESENT SITUATION The reasons for the present situation are as disturbing as the situation itself. I am persuaded that the basic reason why the Supreme Court has allowed its capital case jurisprudence to deteriorate to the condition it is now in can be found in the simple fact that apparently most of the citizens of the United States support the death penalty. Indeed, apparently even most lawyers in the United States support 94. Weisberg, Deregulating Death, in 1983 Sup. Ct. Rev. 305,354 (1984) (citation omitted to zant v. Stephens, 462 U.S. 862, 906-11 (1983) (Marshall, J., dissenting». 95. [d. 96. [d. at 358. 97. [d. at 354. HeinOnline -- 17 T. Marshall L. Rev. 19 1991-1992 20 THURGOOD MARSHALL LA W REVIEW [Vol. 17:1 capital punishment, with the American Bar Association Journal reporting in 1985 that 68 percent of lawyers "favor the carrying out of capital punishment sentences already imposed by the courts. "98 The same article reported that support by the general public for the death penalty had risen to 72 percent, "the highest favorable percentage since 1936."99 Further, opinion polls show that the majority of our people believe that the death penalty is a deterrent. 1oo Walter Berns, in arguing for the death penalty, acknowledged that the Court's response to public opinion was a significant part of the reason for the Court's decision in Furman. Berns said, "judges are not immune to popular opinion or able to isolate themselves completely from the trend of the times, and the trend [in 1972] was clearly in the direction of abolition."101 In the same way, "polls on public support for the death penalty have been heeded by the Supreme Court as indicating that 'evolving standards of decency' do not preclude use of capital punishment,"102 in the years following the Furman decision. "Judicial interpretation ofthe Eighth Amendment's prohibition of cruel and unusual punishment has relied, in part at least, on public opinion regarding the bounds of appropriate penalty." 103 Apparently the shift in opinion from opposition to support took place around 1966: In 1966, Gallup and Harris polls showed the American public to be, by a scant majority, in opposition to capital punishment-a trend toward declining support extending ftom early measures in the 1930s. However, with 1966 began a shift in opinion: In 1969, the level of support for the death penalty had risen to 51 percent, and by 1976, according to a survey carried out by the National Opinion Research Center, over 65 percent of Americans supported capital punishment for the crime of murder. 104 In any event, I am persuaded that Weisberg's analysis is correct with respect to the present death penalty schemes being "a merely aesthetic requirement"IOS insofar as the present Supreme Court is concerned. While it is true that "[t]he law of Western society 98. Reskin, Law Poll: Majority of Lawyers Support Capital Punishment, A.B.A.J. Apr. 1985, at 44. 99.Id. 100. ROGER HOOD, THE DEATH PENALTY: A WORLD-WIDE PERSPECTIVE 153 (1989). 101. WALTER BERNS, FOR CAPITAL PUNISHMENT: CRIME AND THE MORALITY OF THE DEATH PENALTY 4 (1979). 102. SARAH T. DIKE, CAPITAL PUNISHMENT IN THE UNITED STATES 60 (1982). 103. Id. at 60-61. 104. Id. at 61 (citations to the relevant studies omitted). 105. Weisberg, supra note 94, at 358. HeinOnline -- 17 T. Marshall L. Rev. 20 1991-1992 1991] CAPITAL SENTENCING 21 traditionally is analyzed as an autonomous, logically consistent legal system in which the various rules are derived from more abstract norms,"I06 it is also true that the Supreme Court follows the election returns (and one might also insist that the Supreme Court, in the sense of the source of its justices, follows from the election returns). In following the election returns, the current Supreme Court seems driven to allow capital punishment into the indefinite future, provided only that each state seeking to use it will first implement a scheme of punishment that comports with Weisberg's criteria: the law must "somehow identify a class of death-eligible murderers smaller than the class of all murderers, must give some sentencer some discretion about choosing which of the eligibles to execute, and must grant defendants a fairly broad opportunity to make a: case for mitigation."107 A very convincing argument has been made by Franklin E. Zimring and Gordon Hawkins to the effect that our nation's present use of capital punishment is related to the death penalty's symbolic character, and to "the ritual or ceremonial function of . .. capital punishment. . . ." 108 They explain that: The extensive ethnographic literature on ritual and symbolism focuses mainly on "primitive" societies, tending to overlook the collective ceremonials and focal rituals of large and complex modem societies. Our own twentieth-century institutions and practices, in which what Durkheim called the "collective consciousness" is expressed, have been largely ignored. But it seems likely that the symbolic significance of death penalty legislation, the ritual nature of the murder trial, and the incantatory power of the death sentence constitute a large part of the appeal for supporters of the death penalty. 109 Zimring and Hawkins point out that this symbolic and ceremonial function of capital punishment "may suggest an explanation for the curious ambivalence in contemporary societies that want to preserve death penalty legislation and murder trials yet appear to feel no need for executions."llo The reason for this is that: In a simple, homogeneous tribal society a human sacrifice performed with the intention of influencing or manipulating the 106. LEOPOLD 275 (1971). POSPISIL, ANTHROPOLOGY OF LA W: A COMPARATIVE THEORY 107. Weisberg, supra note 94, at 358. 108. FRANKLIN E. ZIMRING & GORDON HAWKINS, CAPITAL PUNISHMENT AND THE AMERICAN AGENDA 11 (1986). 109. Id. (footnote omitted). 110.Id. HeinOnline -- 17 T. Marshall L. Rev. 21 1991-1992 22 THURGOOD MARSHALL LA W REVIEW [Vol. 17:1 course of human events is required. In larger, more complex societies the same psychological need is fulfilled, without an actual sacrifice, by the performance of the preliminary rituals. The latent social function is the same. 111 Elaborating on the theme of our desire to preserve death penalty statutes notwithstanding our actual reluctance to carry out large numbers of executions at a swift pace, Zimring and Hawkins comment upon the astonishing backlog of condemned prisoners now being held in American penitentiaries: The circumstances of capital punishment in the United States of the 1980s are unprecedented. At the midpQint of the decade some 1,700 prisoners were held by state authorities under "active sentences of death," cases where no outstanding court order or executive decision has reversed a death sentence following a murder conviction. The american megaprison now has, increasingly, a mega-death row as its seventh circle. Either we are on the verge of a momentous change in American execution policy, or we are engaged in a gruesome charade. 112 The statistical reality of the present backlog of prisoners who have been condemned to death in the states using capital punishment is unique in American history. "This is by far the largest collection of the condemned in American history. It exceeds by a factor of five the total number of executions in the United States and Western Europe in the previous twenty-five years."113 Indeed, "if present trends in both death sentences and executions continue for a very few years, the number of those awaiting execution will equal the number executed in the past half-century."114 As of 1986, the date of Zimring and Hawkins' book, "[t]o keep pace with the number of death sentences issued annually under state penal schemes approved by the U.S. Supreme Court is to live in a nation that executes about 300 people per year, and perhaps one for each day of the year."lIS The ritual and symbolic nature of the death penalty is further indicated by the fact that the most consistent commitment to retention and use of capital punishment has been in the South. In fact, "[a]t first sight, so striking is the contrast between the South and the other regions [of the nation] that the South appears to be 'another 111. 112. 113. 114. 115. [d. [d. at 95. [d. [d. [d. at 96. HeinOnline -- 17 T. Marshall L. Rev. 22 1991-1992 CAPITAL SENTENCING 1991] 23 country'. "116 In the South, the backlash following the Furman decision was particularly excessive: Some of the initial reaction to this seeming abolition of the death penalty bordered on hysteria. Michael Meltsner gave some characteristic examples: Georgia's Lieutenant Governor Lester Maddox described the decision as a "license for anarchy, rape, murder." Alabama's Lieutenant Governor Jere Beasley claimed that "a majority of this nation's highest court has lost contact with the real world." Atlanta Police Chief John Inman spoke of the loss of "a definite deterrent to major crimes." Memphis Police Chief Bill Price asserted that those who had "hesitated to pull the trigger before just might go ahead now."117 Zimring and Hawkins suggest that "the most plausible explanations of the political reaction in those states responding to Furman with new death penalty legislation are from the literature of social psychology, either the so-called frustration-aggression hypothesis or the theory of psychological reactance." 118 The frustration-aggression hypothesis states that aggression is always a consequence of frustration. 119 The psychological reactance theory is "[e]ven more descriptive of legislative response [to Furman]."120 Furman was perceived as a loss of freedom to legislate about capital punishment, and "[t]he loss of freedom to legislate on the death penalty triggers a strong desire to reassert the legislative power to act." 121 What happened in the South after Furman seems to confirm this kind of interpretation: Almost without exception the states that started executing most promptly after Gregg v. Georgia were those whose capital punishment laws Furman had avoided. Far from being representative of national public opinion, they were drawn from the same Southern constituency that provided the bulk of executions over the past half-century. Rather than a resurgent national perception of capital punishment as the solution to the problem of criminal homicide, what this pattern illustrates is a state response to a federal slight that was seen as arbitrary and unwarranted. III 116. 117. 118. 119. Id. Id. Id. Id. 120. Id. 121. Id. 122. Id. at 31. at 38 (footnote omitted). at 41. (footnote omitted). at 42. (footnote omitted). at 44. HeinOnline -- 17 T. Marshall L. Rev. 23 1991-1992 24 THURGOOD MARSHALL LA W REVIEW [Vol. 17:1 Death sentences in the South doubled in reaction to Furman: Before 1972, when that decision [Furman] was announced, the number of new death sentences each year in the Southern states averaged about fifty, with the trend, if any, downward. ·After a year of rapid legislative adjustment in 1973, the number of new death sentences each year more than doubl~d, and there is no year after 1973 in which the number of new death sentences in the South did not substantially exceed the number of such sentences issued in any year prior to Furman. 123 That enormous increase in death sentences in the South speaks volumes about the symbolic nature of capital punishment, particularly in that part of the nation. Zimring and Hawkins explain: The doubling of the number of death sentences in the South in reaction to Furman . . . can be seen as the use of death penalty policy to express hostility toward the nation~ government's power. Moreover, the persistence of a higher level of death sentences since Gregg, and the continued clustering of actual executions in states of the old Confederacy, provide additional evidence that executions represent a manifestation of state autonomy that continues to influence state and local decision makers even when federal restraints on the freedom to execute have been removed.J24 The symbolic nature of the death penalty is further illustrated, in the context of the unique role played by the South in this situation, by the fact that for all practical purposes, capital punishment is not used in the federal criminal justice system. "Barring a catastrophic skyjacking incident or presidential assassination, there is no likelihood of an execution under federal jurisdiction in the next decade."J2S The United States Department of Justice has not made the active use of capital punishment in the federal criminal' justice system a "policy priority." 126 The federal government allows the states to take the lead (overwhelmingly in the South) in carrying out the symbolic functions of the death penalty, and for reasons that are reasonably clear: The reasons go beyond the national government's respect for state sovereignty. The federal administration can support state capital punishment provisions, approve from a distance the execution 123. 124. 125. 126. [d. at 102. [d. at 152-53. [d. at 14I. [d. HeinOnline -- 17 T. Marshall L. Rev. 24 1991-1992 CAPITAL SENTENCING 1991] 25 activities of the states, and collect whatever political dividends attach to that position without itself incurring any execution backlash. In effect they send surrogates to battle in the war on crime. 127 The present situation, then, is one in which only the states have any significant role to play in the utilization of the death penalty, and among the states those in the South lead the rest of the nation in the use of capital punishment. The federal government stays out of the picture almost entirely, with its role being limited to official approval of capital punishment, while the southern states accomplish implementation of the penalty as surrogates of the federal government. There are more condemned persons on death row than can be executed under the pace of the system now in use. And nothing is changing. The heart of the matter is that capital punishment is no longer an instrument of public policy in America, but a symbolic ritual, utilized to provide assurance that some appropriate response is being made to violent crime. The present disorder in the Supreme Court's capital case jurisprudence is symptomatic of the symbolic nature of the death penalty in modern America. This is not the jurisprudence of a nation that utilizes the death penalty to rid itself quickly, efficiently and fairly of those citizens in its midst who commit murder. This is jurisprudence about a symbol, a ritual, an outmoded practice that bears little relationship to the reality of our modern national life. Zimring and Hawkins, it seems to me, make this very clear in discussing the instruments used to kill the condemned: gas chambers, electric chairs, the gallows, and recently lethal injection: By inidcentury, the means of execution employed in the United States were already regarded as atavistic. Two decades of disuse since then had rendered chambers and chairs the stuff of wax museum exhibits rather than the instruments of public policy. Thus to maintain an active execution policy required a means of killing less obviously discordant with today's institutions and values. It is fair to call the search for modern means of executions a public relations gesture only if it is acknowledged that this sort of "public relations" is of central importance. Capital punishment could seem appropriate only if a technique for taking life could be devised that appeared to be an authentic part of modern America. 128 This explains the move to lethal injection as a more humane, modern means of killing condemned persons. In the discussions about adopting 127. Id. 128. Id. at 122. HeinOnline -- 17 T. Marshall L. Rev. 25 1991-1992 26 THURGOOD MARSHALL LA W REVIEW [Vol. 17:1 lethal injection as the modern way of executing criminals, there was little discussion of what was not humane about electric chairs, gas chambers and the gallows. Instead, "[t]he use of therapeutic drugs rather than nontherapeutic poisons, as a means of killing and the attempt to link death with science and medicine, make sense only if proponents of lethal injections are seen as pursuing a modern way to inflict death."!29 The selection oftherapeutic drugs, to be administered by medically qualified technicians, "was n0t fortuitous; the need was to define the enterprise of executing people in a way that was consistent with scientific progress and medical values."!30 Killing people as a response to the problem of murder in our society is not consistent with scientific progress. At best, capital punishment is a relic from the dark past, and at worst it is an unfortunate regression, a capitulation to that past and the more primitive instincts and passions. While giving in to the public demand for capital punishment, the Supreme Court is still unwilling to acknowl~dge the data showing that unfettered pre-trial discretion is what plays the most important role with regard to who will become a candidate for execution. It is an odd situation: prosecutors, defense lawyers and trial judges all know how the system actually makes its pre-trial selections of capital case defendants, but the Supreme Court stands aloof from reality and contents itself in case after case with examining the minutiae of the various state schemes of allowing and prohibiting capital sentencing evidence. Indeed, the sentencing scheme in Texas as recently revised will undoubtedly be subjected to the scrutiny of the Supreme Court as this curious charade is continued. V. THE TEXAS RESPONSE TO PENRY Texas responded to Penry by making some modifications in its capital sentencing scheme. The scheme, as modified, is instructive as a further example of the "merely aesthetic requirement"!3! of the Supreme Court's current capital case jurisprudence for a system of selecting the death-eligible murderers. The former scheme allowed three special issues to be submitted to the sentencing jury:!32 one on whether the act of the defendant that caused the death of the deceased was deliberate; one on whether there is a probability that the defendant will commit criminal acts of violence 129. 130. 131. 132. Id. Id. Weisberg, supra note 94, at 358. See Note 6, supra. HeinOnline -- 17 T. Marshall L. Rev. 26 1991-1992 CAPITAL SENTENCING 1991] 27 in the future; and one, if raised by the evidence, on whether the conduct of the defendant in killing the deceased was unreasonable in response to provocation, if any, by the deceased. The new scheme eliminates the first and third questions, but retains the second question regarding the probability of future violence. 133 There is a new question covering the situation in which the jury finds ·the defendant guilty as a party under the applicable sections of the Texas Penal Code134 after appropriate instructions by the trial court on that matter. The new provision requires the trial court to submit the following issue: (2) in cases in which the jury charge at the guilt or innocence stage permitted the jury to find the defendant guilty as a party under Sections 7.01 and 7.02, Penal Code, whether the defendant actually caused the death of the deceased or did not actually cause the death of the deceased but intended to kill the deceased or another or anticipated that a human life would be taken. I3S The state has the burden of proving the issues submitted under the questions inquiring about future violence and guilt as a party. 136 The standard is that of beyond a reasonable doubt. 137 Responding to Penry, Texas added the following language to the instructions to be given the jury in death penalty cases: (1) in deliberating on the issues submitted under Subsection (b) of this article, it [the jury] shall consider all evidence admitted at the guilt or innocence stage and the punishment stage, including evidence of the defendant's background or character or the circumstances of the offense that militates [sic] for or mitigates [sic] against the imposition of the death penalty,138 Under the new, modified scheme, if the jury returns an affirmative finding to each issue submitted under Subsection (b),139 then it must answer the follmving issue: Whether, taking into consideration all of the evidence, including the circumstances of the offense, the defendant's character and background, and the personal moral culpability of the defendant, 133. 134. 135. 136. 137. 138. 139. Tex. Tex. Tex. Tex. [d. Tex. Tex. Code Crim. Proe. Ann. art. 37.071(b) (Vernon: 1991). Penal Code Ann. §§ 7.01, 7.02 (West 1974). Code Crim. Proe. Ann. art. 37.071(b)(2) (Vernon 1991). Code Crim. Proe. Ann. art. 37.071(e) (Vernon 1991). Code Crim. Proe. Ann. art. 37.071(d)(I) (Vernon 1991). Code Crim. Proe. Ann. art. 37.071(b) (Vernon 1991). HeinOnline -- 17 T. Marshall L. Rev. 27 1991-1992 28 THURGOOD MARSHALL LA W REVIEW [Vol. 17:1 there is a sufficient mitigating circumstance or circumstances to warrant that a sentence of life imprisonment rather than a death sentence be imposed.140 The statute does not state which party has the burden or proof on that issue, nor does it state what the standard of proof is to be on that issue. Presumably those matters will have to be determined through litigation. The jury is to answer this new special issue "yes" or "no," and it cannot answer the issue "no" unless it agrees unanimously and cannot answer the issue "yes" unless 10 or more jurors agree. 141 The jury need not agree on what particular evidence supports an affirmative finding on the issue. 142 If the jury is unable to agree on an answer to the issue, then the court must sentence the defendant to life imprisonment rather than death. 143 If the jury returns an answer of "yes" on the issue, the court must sentence the defendant to life imprisonment rather than death. l44 It is only if the jury returns an answer of "no" on that issue, and an answer of "yes" on each issue submitted under Subsection (b), that the court is authorized (and required) to sentence the defendant to death. 145 The jury is to be instructed, under the new scheme, that it "shall consider mitigating evidence to be evidence that a juror might regard as reducing the defendant's moral blameworthiness." 146 Given the composition of the present Supreme Court, and the existing capital case jurisprudence of the Court, it seems reasonably probable that the Court will put its blessing on this modified Texas capital sentencing scheme. The matters of which party has the burden of proof on the new question regarding mitigating circumstances and what the burden is, will have to be decided through litigation, but once that has been done the new scheme should pass muster without difficulty at the Supreme Court of the United States. But even the modified Texas sentencing scheme is little more than the "merely aesthetic requirement" described by Weisberg. 147 It does not reach, or even attempt to reach, the matter of unlimited, unfettered pre-trial discretion discussed above,148 which infects the capital punishment systems of the states using the death penalty. 140. 141. 142. 143. 144. 145. 146. 147. 148. Tex. Code Crim. Proe. Ann. art. 37.071(e) (Vernon 1991). Tex. Code Crim. Proe. Ann. art. 37.071(f)(2) (Vernon 1991). Tex. Code Crim. Proe. Ann. art. 37.071(f)(3) (Vernon 1991). Tex. Code Crim. Proe. Ann. art. 37.071(g) (Vernon 1991). [d. [d. Tex. Code Crim. Proe. Ann. art. 37.071(f)(4) (Vernon 1991). Weisberg, supra note 94, at 358. See notes 67-93 and accompanying text. HeinOnline -- 17 T. Marshall L. Rev. 28 1991-1992 CAPITAL SENTENCING 1991] VI. 29 CONCLUSION Capital sentencing evidence after Penry and Payne will, of course, include more matters than such evidence included before those decisions. The defendant can bring in more evidence now, and so can the prosecution. Probably that result is as it should be. In deciding the terrible question of whether to kill another human being, the sentencing agency, whether judge or jury, should have available all relevant evidence bearing upon the issues involved. In that sense, the Penry and Payne decisions represent some appropriate and desirable progress. But the real problem remains untouched: the matter of unlimited pre-trial discretion on the part of the police, the prosecutor and the grand jury. Even though the Supreme Court of the United States will neither recognize nor address this aspect of the problem, it has been thoroughly demonstrated and is understood by all experienced counsel who have handled capital cases, whether for the defense or the prosecution. Until that central problem' has been addressed and dealt with, if possible, the various state schemes for regulating the presentation of evidence in death penalty cases will continue to be merely aesthetic requirements, by and large, as some states, mainly in the South, continue the use of their "chambers and chairs" and lethal injections and hangings and shootings, the "stuff of wax museum exhibits rather than the instruments of public policy." 149 In the meantime, capital punishment in our nation will continue on its present bizarre course, perhaps meeting symbolic and ritualistic needs in our society, but better explained by anthropologylso than by law. 149. ZIMRING & HAWKINS, supra note 108, at 122. 150. See generally POSPISIT., supra note 106, at 14-16, 20-31. HeinOnline -- 17 T. Marshall L. Rev. 29 1991-1992 HeinOnline -- 17 T. Marshall L. Rev. 30 1991-1992