Philosophical Review The Imagery Debate. by Michael Tye Review by: Kathleen A. Akins The Philosophical Review, Vol. 103, No. 1 (Jan., 1994), pp. 172-175 Published by: Duke University Press on behalf of Philosophical Review Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2185886 . Accessed: 18/09/2012 19:08 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp . JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org. . Duke University Press and Philosophical Review are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Philosophical Review. http://www.jstor.org BOOK REVIEWS The Philosophical Review,Vol. 103, No. 1 (January 1994) THE IMAGERYDEBATE. By MICHAEL TYE. Cambridge: MIT Press, Bradford Books, 1991. Pp. xiv, 172. The other day a friendof mine was recountinga dream-a classic traveller's nightmareabout havinga suit made in Hong Kong. Going fromshop to shop, he found himselflost in a maze of alleys and sidestreets,unable to ask directions or, on findinga tailor,to explain what he wanted. "By the way," I said, kiddinghim, "what color of suitdid you finallydecide on?" "Color!?" he said, puzzled. "I don't dream in color; in fact,I don't even dream in black and white. You see, for me, dreaming isn't visual-there aren't any images,any picturesat all." Then he paused and a slysmile came over his face. "Or perhaps I shouldsaythatitdoesn'tseem to me thatI dream in images-at least not after I've woken up!" In The Imagery Debate,Michael Tye attemptsa quick traverseacross the difficult of mental imagery.His organizingprincipleis the current territory dispute in experimental psychology-between those researchers who advocate a "pictorialist" account of mental imagery and those who favor a "linguistic" or "descriptionalist"view. In the firsthalf of the book, the reader is given an admirably clear survey of that landscape. The firsttwo chapters offera short historicalintroductionto the problem of mental images (plus a denunciation of introspection as a reliable means of access to theirnature); the third and fourthchapters explain and evaluate the empiricaladequacy of the leading theoriesfromboth camps, namelyKosslyn's "pictorial" hypothesis and the "linguistic" hypotheses of Pylyshyn and Hinton. In the second half of the volume, Tye presents his own theory of mental imagery (a hybrid account based loosely upon Marr's theory of vision) and then turns to a number of outstanding philosophical issues. Tye's view of mental images is that they are "interpreted symbol-filled arrays"-"functional pictures" thatoccur in a "visual buffer"shared with normal visual processing to which sentential interpretations (for example, "This is an F") have been appended. More specifically,Tye's notion of a functionalpicture turns on three interrelatedideas: a functionalpicture is pictorial,functional,and representational.First,in explaining what makes a neural representationpictorial,Tye improviseson Kosslyn'snotion of a "quasi-picture": a representation of an object, as seen froma particularviewpoint,is pictorialif and number of spatiallyadjacent pointson the object (visible onlyifa sufficient fromthisviewpoint)are representedby partsof the representation(pixellike structurescalled "cells") thatare themselves"adjacent." (Unlike Kosslyn, however, Tye does not require that all parts of the representation correspond to the spatial parts of the object, for his model includes symbols, placed withinthe cells, thatrepresentsurfacepropertiesof objects.) 172 BOOK REVIEWS Here, "adjacency" between the cells of the array-and spatial relations as implying betweensuch image partsin general-is not to be read literally, that the cells themselvesstand side-by-sidein neural space or that they instantiateany other particularspatial relations.Rather,such spatial reladuring image transfortions are said to obtain if the cells are manipulated, mations,as iftheystood in such relations.This is the second characteristic of a functionalpicture.Third, thisrough definitionof a functionalpicture relationin virpresupposes a more primitiveconcept of representation-the tue of which any of the elements of the array,cells or symbols,represent Tye's views on mental representationare a bit thin at all. Unfortunately, on the ground here, but he does brieflyreferto "registration"relations betweensymbolsand externalproperties;additionally,he suggeststhatthe contentof a representationis fixedby those propertiesthatunder normal viewingconditions (relativeto an appropriategroup of individuals)would be causally sufficientto bring about an instance of that representational type.Let us say,then,thatfunctionalpicturesrequire, first,a one-way mapand, second, visiblepartsoftheobjectand cellsoftherepresentation ping between represented a manipulation ofthosecells"in accordancewith"thespatialrelations in thearraystandin a particularkindofregistration and, third,that theelements to bringthemabout.Prima facie, sufficient normally relationto thoseproperties then, the definitionof a functionalpicture contains three verydifferent kinds of criteria-syntactic,"formality,"and semantic constraints.AlthoughTye does not say how these criteriaare interrelated,note here that trouble will arise if an independent notion of syntaxis not forthcoming. If we cannot assume that neural syntacticelements are simply"plain for all to see"-that is, if individuatingneural representationalpartsrequires semanticor formalconsiderations-then therewill be a complex interdependency between the three criteria.Certainly,then, a good deal more needs to be said about these constraintsif the notion of a functionalpicture is to become clear. As I said above, Tye postulates that the functionalpictures of mental arrays"which share the common imageryare "interpretedsymbol-filled machineryof normal visual processing. (In fact,given Tye's view of representationalcontent qua perceptual registration,there seem few other options.) Appealing to Marr's theoryof vision,Tye associates these arrays with representationsat the level of Marr's 2.5-D sketch (albeit a slightly modifiedone), and the visual "buffer"itselfwithwhatevervisual processing site(s) the 2.5-D sketchoccurs. On Marr's theory,recall, there are four levelsof representationin image processing:first,an image thatrepresents lightintensityat points in the retinalimage; second, the primalsketchthat makes explicitintensitychanges and theirspatial organization;third,the 2.5-D sketch that representsedges, depth, and orientationinformation; and fourth,the 3-D model that representsshapes and their spatial orga173 BOOK REVIEWS nization in termsof stickfiguresand volumetricprimitives(for example, generalized cylinders).The visual array,according to Tye, contains Marrlike symbolsfor orientation,depth, the presence of an edge or a ridge, plus some other symbolsof Tye's own making-symbols for color, light and texture,plus one special symbol,'O', thatspecifiesthe presintensity, ence of an object surface.Note thatbecause Marr's 2.5-D sketchdoes not contain any informationabout object segmentationor object identity,Tye "This is an F," mustbe appended to believes thata sententialinterpretation, on his view, either produce a given mental image. Such interpretations, come withthe arrayas generated frommemoryor else are produced "on line," by scanning the arrayand, on that basis, assigninga new interpretation. To see a central problem with Tye's association of visual images with interpreted2.5-D sketches,note that Marr's (unadulterated) theoryof vision makes a fairamount of sense when viewed as a theoryof shape recognition-and this is so even if,at the end of the day, it is not correct.As an explanationof visualphenomenology,however,Marr'stheorypresentsus with a kind of paradox. When we experience visual phenomenology,say,when we look out the windowto the garden below, we do not see littledots and arrowsaffixedto "cartoon" outlines (the primitivesof the 2.5-D sketch), nor do we see stickfiguresor generalized cylinders(the primitivesof shape recognition);on the other hand, we are aware of "pixel by pixel" intensity information,informationthat is no longer explicitlyrepresentedeven in the second stage of processing,the primal sketch. Starting with the photographic image, that is, the moreprocessingsteps taken-each one servingto make fromtheenvironment-theless "like" our visual phenomexplicitmoreinformation seemsto become.How then could such a process posenologytherepresentation siblygive rise to the knownphenomenology?What is the relationshipbetweenthe representationalprimitivesof the variouslevelsof representation and what we see? This is the paradox (call it "Marr's paradox") that arises ifone simplyappropriatesa theoryof shape recognitionforuse as a theory of visual phenomenology.In Tye's case, much the same paradox will arise forthe phenomenologyof imagery.If a mental image is identifiedwithan interpreted2.5-D sketch,how can the representationalprimitivesof the 2.5-D sketchpossiblyaccount for the kind of visual imagerythatwe experience? Tye's response to Marr's paradox-or at least his implicitresponse, for he does not discuss the relation between the vehicles of representation and conscious experience-is to incorporate everyrepresentationaltype that is intuitivelypart and parcel of our conscious phenomenology into the "new and enriched" 2.5-D sketch,while leaving out all those representationalprimitivesthatseem to bear littleobvious relation to our phenomenal experience. Thus, the intuitivepropertiesof visual phenomenol174 BOOK REVIEWS ogy that,on Marr's scheme, are representedexplicitlyonly at levels prior to the 2.5-D sketchnow reappear, representedby symbolsin the individual cells (hence the inclusion of texture,intensity,and color symbols)while the lower-levelrepresentationalprimitivesof intuitively "nonvisual" propertieshave simplybeen omittedfromthe new 2.5-D sketch(Marr's "blobs" or "bars"). Similarly,those intentionalaspectsof images thatare (or would be) discerned furtherupstreamon Marr's theoryare now merelyappended in the formof "sententialinterpretations."In thisway,the embarrassing machineryof shape recognition(forexample, the cylinders)and object segmentation (whateverit might be) are discreetlyhidden behind the scenes. In effect,Tye's answerto Marr's paradox is to collapse togetherthe various levels of visual representationand therebyproduce a representational constructthat, according to our intuitions,bears an intuitive"resemblance" to our visual experience. The paradox of vision is not answered.It is merelyavoided. Recall the epigraph at the beginning of this review.It demonstrated much of what is puzzling about mental imagery-that the phenomenology variesgreatlyfromperson to person; thatthere is no clear inferencefrom "how it seems" to the subject to the formof the underlyingrepresentational structure;thatmental imagery,even when it does seem clearly"visual," has manypeculiar, "un-picture-like"qualities,ones thatare not explained by advertingto the propertiesof ordinarypublic images nor even to the properties of our ordinaryvisual perceptions. Whateverthe true nature of the beast, understandingmental imageryrequires us to address most of the persistentproblems in the philosophyof mind-the problem of intentionality, the natureof consciousnessand itsrelationto the vehicles of mental representationand theircontents,the role of introspection,and so on. In sum, while Tye's book givesa clear and intelligentsurveyof the psychologicalliteratureon mental imagery,it does not providea satisfying philosophical account of the most basic issues surrounding mental imagery. KATHLEEN University ofIllinois,Urbana-Champaign A. AKINS ThePhilosophical Review,Vol. 103, No. 1 (January1994) SPRINGS OF ACTION: UNDERSTANDINGINTENTIONAL BEHAVIOR. By Press, 1992. Pp. ix, 272. ALFRED R. MELE. New York: Oxford University SpringsofActionis a denselyargued, extremelyvaluable essayon the theory of action. In the firstplace, it serves a badly needed function.It brings assesses a range of the best work,done over the togetherand instructively 175