Vasanthakumar – January 2016 Epistemic privilege and victims’ duties to resist their oppression ASHWINI VASANTHAKUMAR ∗ ‘It is impossible to characterise victims. They are just people who were in the wrong place and the wrong time in the wrong company. The unjust person has a character, the victim does not even have a role.’ - Judith Shklar1 1. Introduction Victims 2 of oppression are prominent in struggles to defeat the injustices they have endured. They write memoirs, mount legal challenges, build social movements, engage in civil disobedience, and instigate armed resistance. More prosaically, they speak up in the face of casual prejudice, express sympathy with its targets, and intervene to change subtle but damaging dynamics, say in the workplace or the classroom. Victims speak up, and their doing so is instrumental to defeating the injustices they have endured. These efforts are burdensome, at times even dangerous, but they have been instrumental in overcoming oppressive institutions and practices. Historically, then, those who have suffered the worst forms of Department of Politics, University of York. ashwini.vasanthakumar@york.ac.uk. Distant relatives of this paper were presented to audiences at the New Voices in Legal Theory Workshop (St Andrews), the Nuffield Political Theory Workshop (Oxford), and the annual conference of the Association of Social and Legal Philosophy (Leeds). I am grateful to them and to Bob Goodin, John William Devine, Meira Levinson, David Miller, and Eric J Miller for written comments. 1 Judith Shklar, The Faces of Injustice (Yale UP, 1990) at 35. 2 I use victims rather than survivors for two reasons. First, in many of the cases I am considering, individuals continue to be the victims of injustice; this is especially the case with structural injustice but also in cases like torture, where victims continue to suffer long after they are directly subjected to wrongdoing. And second, I take it that a primary motivation for the preference of the term survivor over victim is that the latter implies passivity; the account I advance in this article directly refutes that implication or connotation of the term victim. ∗ 1 Vasanthakumar – January 2016 violence, humiliation and abuse are also those who have borne the burdens of resisting injustice. Victims’ resistance is not by accident, nor always by necessity; often it is done out of a sense of duty. Victims of oppression often charge one another with having duties: of solidarity, of pride, of mutual assistance, and of political resistance. Many certainly see themselves as subject to such duties. They engage one another, often in acrimonious debates, over these duties and what actions they call for. And of course, many victims reject the imputation of any such duty, charging that it perversely burdens those who have already suffered wrongdoing, engages in victim-blaming, or shows an unjustified solicitude for fellow victims over others who are also in need of assistance.3 In short, victims inhabit a complex normative universe that yields a rich and sophisticated political discourse, that has resulted in a transformative politics—and that largely has been ignored by normative theorists. In this article, I argue that victims have a duty to assist fellow victims and to resist the injustices they have experienced. I argue that in virtue of their experience of an injustice, victims are epistemically privileged: they have knowledge that injustice is occurring and knowledge of the harms it inflicts. They are thus uniquely positioned to initiate and motivate resistance efforts, and have a duty to do so. Victims’ duties to resist are an extension of the duty to rescue—they arise precisely because they were “in the wrong place at the wrong time in the wrong company.”4 Victims’ duties of resistance consist primarily in speaking up: in a duty to testify. Testimony is familiarly associated with injustice. Here, I argue that testimony is a necessary tool to resist injustice and rescue those who continue to be victimised. And victims are uniquely positioned to provide such testimony. Ultimately, of course, those who hear this testimony—its audience—may bear more demanding duties to rescue because they are more capable and culpable. But victims have an essential role to play, and a duty to do so. 3 See, e.g., Randall Kennedy, “My Race Problem,” The Atlantic, May 1997. Available at http://www.theatlantic.com/magazine/archive/1997/05/my-raceproblem/376849/ and Stephen L. Carter, Reflections of an Affirmative Action Baby (New York, BasicBooks, 1991). 4 Shklar, The Faces, at 35. This echoes D. Jamieson’s description of the duty to rescue as falling upon those who “are in the wrong place at the wrong time with the right resources.” D. Jamieson, “Rights, Justice, and Duties to Provide Assistance: A Critique of Regan’s Theory of Rights,” Ethics 100(2) (January 1990): 349-362 at 353. 2 Vasanthakumar – January 2016 Victims’ efforts may seem obvious, readily explained as a function of collective interests and identities.5 Others have cast the duty to resist as a duty to oneself—to protecting one’s rational capacities, selfrespect, or wellbeing.6 The account I develop here is compatible with these arguments and reflects many of the insights they express. It is distinct, however, in a few key respects. First, the duties I identify are other-regarding: they are duties that victims owe to other victims who remain subject to oppression. Victims ought to engage in resistance because it assists other victims, and any benefit to their own wellbeing or self-respect is incidental. Resisting injustice is not an exercise in self-perfection,7 then, but an enterprise dedicated to the assistance of others. Similarly, the duty is not directed towards realising justice except insofar as this best assists victims. And finally, I therefore conceive of resistance as an attempt to rescue or assist,8 and derive victims’ duties from the duty to rescue rather than from any special relationship between victims.9 Because victims’ duties are instrumental, Tommie Shelby, “Foundations of Black Solidarity: Collective Identity of Common Oppression,” Ethics (2002) explores identities and interests as bases for collective anti-racism action. Interests and identities have, however, limited explanatory and justificatory reach. Neither account can make sense of victims’ resistance when their interests and identities are not at stake. And neither account captures the sense in which these efforts are obligatory rather than merely contingent or supererogatory. To survivors who no longer countenance injustice or who do not share the bonds of community, by this account, no special reasons accrue; to individuals who do not judge it to be in their self-interest to make common cause with fellow survivors, or who do not identify with these survivors, reprimands, expressions of disappointment, or accusations of betrayal are misplaced. For such a powerful politics, to which many advances in the realization of justice are owed, these normative bases are surprisingly flimsy. 6 See, e.g. Daniel Silvermint, “Resistance and Well-being,” Journal of Political Philosophy (2013); Jean Harvey, “Victims, Resistance, and Civilized Oppression,” Journal of Social Philosophy (2010); Bernard Boxhill, ‘Self-respect and Protest,” Philosophy & Public Affairs (1976) and “The Responsibility of the Oppressed to Resist Their Own Oppression,” Journal of Social Philosophy (2010); Thomas E. Hill, Jr., “Servility and Self-Respect,” The Monist (1973) and “Moral Responsibility of Bystanders,” Journal of Social Philosophy (2010) and Carol Hay, “The Obligation to Resist Oppression,” Journal of Social Philosophy (2010). Ann Cudd is a notable exception here, arguing that women’s acquiescence to sexist institutions strengthens these institutions and harms other women. It is not clear, however, whether she attributes an obligation to resist or treats such resistance as supererogatory. Ann Cudd, Analyzing Oppression (OUP 2006). 7 Shklar, The Faces, at 31. While it is certainly true that victims who do not speak out against injustice often are accused of lacking self-respect, self-respect cannot account for the extent of victims’ efforts to resist injustice, particularly when their self-respect or wellbeing is not obviously implicated. 8 I address the distinction between these two later. 9 Any such relationship, say of shared identity, is relevant to this account only insofar as it makes victims more effective in providing a rescue. 5 3 Vasanthakumar – January 2016 they do not call for any particular attitude on the part of the victim; victims need not care especially about resisting oppression or about other victims.10 Victims may well be subject to duties of justice and to special obligations deriving from particular relationships, identities and commitments—I am interested here in making the case that they also bear duties to rescue. Attributing duties of resistance to victims and in virtue of their victimhood might seem perverse. And yet, victims of oppression regularly take it for granted that they bear duties of resistance: they feel compelled to seek the defeat of the injustices they survived, to speak out against those that continue to plague others, and they remonstrate with fellow survivors who fail to join their efforts. Torture victims provide testimony to human rights bodies about the abuse they have endured, hoping that doing so will bring a halt to these practices.11 African-American professors point out ongoing forms of prejudice within the academy even when doing so detracts from their career advancement.12 And women share their daily experiences of sexual violence and aggression, illustrating to others the prevalence and harm of everyday sexism at the risk of inviting further aggression.13 2. Preliminary Clarifications a. Injustice I focus on institutional injustices, such as torture, police brutality, systemic discrimination, and grave poverty. I therefore use injustice 10 Whether or not this is psychologically feasible, it is certainly morally desirable that victims of oppression can resist their oppression without subjecting themselves to the second-order oppression of having to construct their identity and personal projects around this oppression. See Hay, “The Obligation,” at 29. 11 See, e.g. Azadeh Agah et al., We Lived to Tell: Political Prison Memoirs of Iranian Women (McGilligan Books, 2007); Y. Sooka, “An Unfinished War: Torture and Sexual Violence in Sri Lanka, 2009-2014”, (Bar Human Rights Committee of England and Wales, 2014). 12 See, e.g. Walter R. Allen et al., “The Black Academic: Faculty Status Among African Americans in U.S. Higher Education,” Journal of Negro Education 69(1/2) (2000): 112-127; Ebony O. McGee and Lasana Kazembe, “Entertainers or education researchers? The challenges associated with presenting while black,” Race, Ethnicity and Education (2015). 13 See, e.g., Caitlin Dewey, “Rape threats, then no response: what it was like to be a woman on Twitter in 2014,” Washington Post (December 17 2014) and Bethany Bell, “Twitter abuse: Women journalists get more threats,” BBC News (February 6 2015). 4 Vasanthakumar – January 2016 and oppression interchangeably.14 Institutional injustice is a capacious category, and ranges from what I will call persecution on the one hand, to structural injustice on the other. As a core case of persecution take torture and other grave mistreatment of detainees. Typically, perpetrators are state agents or quasi-state actors, acting with the direct endorsement or tacit permission of the state, but acting clandestinely. Persecution has the following features. First, it is clear that there is wrongdoing and that some individuals are suffering an injustice—that an injustice is occurring is common knowledge, at least between perpetrators and victims.15 Second, there are easily identifiable perpetrators and victims, even though there are other actors with more ambiguous standing (for example, there might be officials who are non-intervening bystanders or detainees who cooperate with officials in order to secure better treatment.) And third, what would constitute a remedy—end the torturing—is reasonably clear, even if the strategies most effective to bringing this about remain less so. Structural injustice, on the other hand, is inflicted unconsciously, through the ordinary workings of seemingly just institutions, through daily interactions and harmful stereotypes that, whilst publicly disavowed nevertheless prevail.16 Consider the on-going oppression of women and racial minorities. Gender oppression is perpetuated through putatively benign institutions that arose against gendered background assumptions, and whose operation continues to be informed by sexist stereotypes, implicit bias, and social norms and expectations. There are several manifestations, or potential manifestations, of structural injustice against women, ranging from perceptions of diminished competence in the workplace to being frequently interrupted in meetings to the widespread prevalence of sexual and intimate partner violence. Structural injustice is therefore characterised by the following features. First, there is a great deal of uncertainty as to whether and when a particular event is in fact an instantiation of injustice and oppression; 14 All instances of oppression involve injustice, although all instances of injustice do not necessarily involve oppression. Here, I follow Daniel Silvermint and others in treating oppression as a condition brought about through the subjection to injustice. 15 Irrespective of creative lawyering that casts torture as enhanced interrogation— for my purposes, torture stands exemplar as a case of a highly morally determinate injustice. 16 I.M Young, “Five Faces of Oppression” in Lisa Heldke and Peg O’Connor (eds) Oppression, Privilege, and Resistance (Boston: McGraw-Hill, 2004). 5 Vasanthakumar – January 2016 whether, for example, a woman is passed over for a promotion because she is not competent for the job, or because she is unfairly perceived as such. There is not, then, always clarity that wrongdoing is occurring. Second, the distinction amongst perpetrators, bystanders, and victims is tenuous. The perpetration of injustice is often indeliberate and runs contrary to principles that are embraced by social institutions, even as these collude to marginalise the poor, women, and racial minorities. Individuals comply with rules and norms, unconscious of their complicity in wrongdoing and unaware of the harms they cause. This means that even victims may be complicit in their oppression, even if unavoidably so.17 And third, it is therefore not obvious what would constitute a remedy, much less how such a remedy would best be secured. Thus, even though structural injustice inflicts considerable violence,18 it does so less obviously, including to victims. What distinguishes persecution from structural injustice, then, is the means by which mistreatment is inflicted—and hence the agents involved, the presence of intentional action, and the visibility of the oppression. These features determine the moral determinacy of the oppression which, as I will later argue, informs the nature of victims’ duties to rescue and resist. Let me make three further points. First, these are two modes of oppression rather than two different orders. Thus, persecution is not necessarily more grave or vicious than structural injustice; its harms are only more easily ascertained. Second, these two modes of oppression are not binary opposites but are two ends of a spectrum. Oppression therefore is a condition or state of being in the world;19 the spectrum from persecution to structural injustice tracks the different agents and institutions that produce this condition and with what degree of intentionality and culpability. Importantly, it also tracks the degree of moral determinacy, the relevance of which I elaborate upon in the next Part. And third, these two modes are not mutually exclusive. Persecution and structural injustice often reinforce one another and victims are often subject to both modes of oppression. As a result, particular injustices may be difficult to categorise since they are the result of both: an individual is more vulnerable to persecution because she is the victim of structural injustice, and this structural injustice often is undergirded or expressed by persecution.20 Hay, “The Obligation,” at 25. Jean Harvey, “Victims, Resistance, and Civilized Oppression.” 19 Silvermint, “Resistance,” at 205. 20 Violence against women and police brutality against racial minorities qualify as persecution, but are also manifestations of structural injustice and are enabled by prejudicial norms and stereotypes. 17 18 6 Vasanthakumar – January 2016 b. Resistance I have argued that victims’ epistemic privilege requires victims to alert others—to speak out and provide testimony. Victims’ testimony takes a number of formats: formal testimony before courts of law or other inquiries; detailed interviews to researchers from international human rights organisations and journalists; demonstrations and protests; articles and memoirs; and speaking up in casual conversation. These formats afford victims, variously, an opportunity for catharsis and redemption, to hold perpetrators to account, and to provide a record for future generations. I am primarily concerned with testimony’s epistemic function: the ability for victims’ testimony to provide second-hand knowledge to other bystanders, alerting them to the need for a rescue and impressing upon them the importance of undertaking such a rescue. On this account, victims resist injustice because it is a means of assisting other victims: their objective is to assist or rescue other victims and resisting the practices and perpetrators who harm their interests is one, arguably the most effective and enduring, way of doing so. This means that in some cases, of course, open defiance and resistance is not what is called for. In some cases, victims should surreptitiously assist other victims, say by lending a sympathetic ear or sharing coping strategies. Of course, even these forms of assistance could be cast as acts of resistance; by providing succour to victims they defeat perpetrators’ aims to dominate entirely their victims, or they enable victims to bide their time until opportunities for effective resistance arise.21 Even so, assisting victims and resisting the injustices they suffer are analytically distinct—on this account, victims have duty to do the latter only insofar as it is a means of securing the former. The duty to rescue is not an extension of victims’ duties to justice. 3. The Duty to Rescue I argue that a victim’s duty to resist is an instantiation of her duty to rescue. In the paradigm rescue case an agent happens upon a needy Equally, of course, assistance to victims that does not target the institutions or practices that cause their suffering could be accused of helping sustain those institutions and practices. 21 7 Vasanthakumar – January 2016 stranger who is drowning.22 If the agent is capable of rescuing the drowning stranger without sacrificing morally comparable interests then she has a duty to do so. If she cannot mount a rescue by herself—suppose she cannot swim well and so will risk drowning— then she has a duty to get help. And, if the coordinated effort of multiple agents is necessary to mount a rescue, then they have duty to so coordinate.23 Note the following. First, the needy stranger’s basic interests are under imminent threat. The gravity of his need means that, second, the capable agent bears the duty even though she is not at fault for the needy stranger’s plight. Her blamelessness means, however, that third, she is a capable agent only if she can attempt a rescue without sacrificing morally comparable interests. And finally, the duty to rescue is limited to securing the needy stranger’s basic interests.24 This focus on basic interests has three important implications. It means that the comparable costs that a capable agent can be expected to incur are limited by her basic interests and wellbeing. A capable agent would not therefore be expected to harm her basic interests or wellbeing to rescue the needy stranger—for example, to sacrifice a limb in order to save a life.25 I will elaborate on this later when I consider objection of demandingness. Second, it means that the weightiness of the duty depends on whether basic interests are at stake: there is no distinction, in terms of their grounds or weightiness, between the duty to rescue and the duty to aid, for example, between the duty to rescue the drowning child one encounters and the child starving on a distant continent.26 In both cases basic interests are at stake. What distinguishes them is the moral determinacy of the situation that confronts the capable stranger. Moral determinacy obtains when the capable stranger is aware that there is a needy stranger whose basic interests are under threat and is aware of This paradigm case comes from Peter Singer, “Famine, Affluence, and Morality,” Philosophy & Public Affairs 1 (1972): 229-243. 23 Stephanie Collins, “Collectives’ Duties and Collectivising Duties,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy (2013). 24 The duty to rescue can be grounded in duties of humanitarian aid, beneficence, and justice. The duty to rescue I focus on is motivated by the basic interests and well-being that are at stake for the needy stranger. They include life, bodily integrity and self-respect—interests essential for the exercise of autonomy 25 J. Quong, “Killing in Self-defence,” Ethics 119 (2009): 507-537. 26 F. Kamm, “Does Distance Matter Morally to the Duty to Rescue?” Law and Philosophy 19 (2000): 655-681. 22 8 Vasanthakumar – January 2016 what specific actions she must undertake to resolve this threat.27 Moral determinacy, therefore, is scalar: any given situation will be more or less morally determinate. The paradigm rescue case is an exemplar of moral determinacy; typically, the further one departs from the paradigm case, the less morally determinate the scenario. If there was another capable bystander, or various means of effectuating a rescue, or uncertainty about how feasible a rescue would be, the situation would be less morally determinate. And if there were multiple capable bystanders, a complex of potential causes for the stranger’s plight, and a number of ways of redressing this plight, the situation confronting any capable bystander would be correspondingly less morally determinate. Thus, the duty to rescue arises whenever basic interests are at stake; how morally determinate the situation is will inform how much discretion the capable bystander has in determining how to bring about a rescue. The weightiness of the duty does not change, only the clarity of when it arises and how it should be discharged. This means that the capable bystander’s discretion arises only from the epistemic uncertainty that attends moral indeterminacy—epistemic uncertainty as to whether she is confronted with an injustice and how she ought to act—and not because it falls to the bystander’s discretion to determine how weighty the duty to rescue will be and how easily it is overwhelmed by her other reasons for action. 28 Finally, the impetus of protecting basic interests also points to how the duty to rescue should be distributed. Often, there is more than one capable bystander, with varying degrees of culpability or connection to the needy stranger. There are therefore other candidates who might bear the duty to rescue.29 The duty could fall upon those morally responsible for the stranger’s plight, for example. Because they are blameworthy, burdening these agents with the duty to rescue is intuitively more appealing. Alternatively, the duty could fall to those who stand in some special relationship to the stranger—perhaps her V. Igneski, “Distance, Determinacy, and the Duty to Aid: a Reply to Kamm,” Law and Philosophy 20 (2001): 605-616. 28 This aligns with Violetta Igneski’s account of the moral difference between perfect duties to rescue and imperfect duties to assist the needy, but I argue that the indeterminacy arises exclusively because of empirical uncertainty. Unlike Igneski, I do not think that this uncertainty grants agents any leeway in determining how to weigh up their moral reasons for action. Violetta Igneski, “Perfect and Imperfect Duties to Aid,” Social Theory and Practice (2006). 29 David Miller, “Distributing Responsibilities,” Journal of Political Philosophy 9(4) (2001): 453-471. 27 9 Vasanthakumar – January 2016 family or friends—and who therefore have a special interest in her welfare. 30 Neither of these agents, however, may be capable of mounting a rescue; in the case of perpetrators deliberately imperilling the stranger, they will be unwilling to do so. Meanwhile, the needy stranger’s plight beckons. Because the duty to rescue is driven by the stranger’s urgent need for rescue, it is therefore ahistorical and exclusively forward-looking: it only inquires into who can rescue her most efficaciously.31 Recall the duty to rescue is discharged once these basic interests have been secured, so the needy stranger’s other interests may secured by other agents acting on the basis of other reasons.32 Given this impetus from basic interests, it might seem that structural injustice cannot give rise to duties to rescue. Persecution involves an imminent threat to victims’ vital interests, while structural injustice involves ongoing subjection that diminishes victims’ life-chances and undermines their self-respect. If persecution is exemplified by torture, then structural injustice is exemplified by persistent stereotypes and institutional myopia. At first glance, then, structural injustice seems to threaten less vital interests and to do so without the same sense of emergency. Women being interrupted in meetings might not seem to threaten any basic interests. I want to resist this move. Structural injustice engenders a great deal of violence, for example, through police brutality, intimate partner violence, and the realities of incarceration. Less visibly, basic interests are threatened through poor health and malnutrition, or through low self-esteem and participation in risky behaviour and harmful relationships. And indeed, diminished self-respect and rational capacity is a basic interest. Death by a thousand cuts is still death. The relevant distinction between persecution and structural injustice is not whether basic interests are at stake so much as how clear or obvious it is when these interests are at stake and how they might be secured. Persecution and structural injustice might both jeopardise basic interests, but the former is always more morally determinate than the latter. Miller refers to this as the ‘communitarian principle’ for distributing responsibilities. “Distributing,” at 462-464. 31 Sometimes this may occasion an inquiry into the agents causally or morally responsible for the stranger’s plight, but only because this is necessary for an efficacious rescue. 32 At this point, other reasons for action might come into effect, such as the communitarian principle. And this does not mean that those who are morally blameworthy are let off the hook. They may be liable to compensate the rescuers or be subject to punitive measures. See Miller, “Distributing,” at 466-468. 30 10 Vasanthakumar – January 2016 To sum up, an individual is subject to a duty to rescue whenever a stranger’s basic interests are at stake and when she is capable of securing these interests most efficaciously and without sacrificing comparable interests. The more morally determinate the situation is— if it is clear that the individual’s actions are necessary for a rescue to succeed and it is clear what these actions are—the more specific her duty is; it is not more weighty but it is one for which she can more easily be held to account. Capable bystanders may have other duties to provide assistance, say when non-basic interests are at threat, that are of different orders and weightiness, but whenever basic interests are at stake, a duty to rescue arises. 4. Victims’ Epistemic Privilege and the Duty to Testify Why are victims, who have endured grave injustices, charged with the duty to rescue those who continue to endure these injustices? Victims’ capabilities, I argue, arise from their very experience of injustice. Because of this experience, victims are epistemically privileged: they have firsthand knowledge of oppression and have special standing when they share this knowledge. Victims are thereby uniquely positioned to rescue other victims. As it will turn out, victims often are unable to effect a rescue on their own since resisting oppression typically requires the coordinated efforts of many actors. But in virtue of their epistemic privilege they play a necessary, if circumscribed, role in bringing about such efforts. a. Knowledge Victims’ knowledge comes in two forms. First, victims have information. Victims are aware that there is ongoing injustice and that there exist victims urgently in need of rescue. Unjust practices are often hidden from public sight, prevailing in the isolation of prisons, in remote regions, or within marginalised communities. In many cases, only perpetrators and victims are aware that grave injustices are occurring, so absent a change of heart from perpetrators, it is only be with the escape of some victims that any potential rescuers are created. Beyond this, victims are also privy to certain details: about the nature of the oppression faced, the mechanisms by which it is inflicted, the personalities involved, and the gravity of the injuries suffered. Finally, victims may have important perspectives of what counts as a rescue— whether for victims, the defeat of oppression consists in reform or 11 Vasanthakumar – January 2016 abolition, independence or autonomy—and they may also have a better appreciation of what strategies will be most effective in bringing about this rescue. Second, victims have knowledge of injustice.33 As its victims, victims have unique perspectives on particular injustices: they are on intimate terms with oppression, and have a more nuanced and visceral understanding of the harms meted out by particular injustices. Victims can tell us what it felt like. In the case of grave injustices, these perspectives might seem superfluous; surely we all know that torture and sexual violence are wrong and inflict terrible harms on their victims. Any such widespread awareness has arisen in large part, however, from victims’ firsthand accounts. And indeed, these accounts ensure that actions and practices are recognised as harmful for the right reasons.34 Moreover, the harms inflicted by particular instances of injustice are unique, given particular social and political contexts. It is only through Primo Levi’s account that we have the image of the drowned and the saved in Auschwitz. And in other contexts, particularly structural injustice, the nature and degree of the harms inflicted by unjust practices would not even be recognised absent the testimony of victims. For example, when women describe their experiences of being ignored in meetings and the habits of self-censorship they develop as a result, they pierce the cloak of normalcy surrounding feminine bashfulness. Victims of injustice are in a position to be reliable providers of moral testimony: through experience, they have practical knowledge—or are more likely to have moral knowledge—than others, to better make certain moral judgements, to better appreciate when some particular moral norm is animated by a certain set of circumstances.35 In the terms of the paradigm rescue case, then, victims were drowning strangers who have come ashore. They are aware that there are drowning strangers in need of a rescue; of where these strangers are; of what might count as a rescue; of how harrowing the struggle at sea is; and therefore of the urgency with which this rescue should be 33 Margalit, Ethics at 168 distinguishes between political witnesses, who may be better at uncovering the facts about evil, and moral witnesses, who “tell[] what it was like to be subjected to such evil.” 34 For example, that sexual harassment is recognized as wrong because it infringes on women’s sexual agency and physical integrity, rather than because it is an “outrage against the modesty of a woman.” Indian Penal Code, Section 354. 35 See Paulina Sliwa, “In defense of moral testimony,” Philosophical Studies (2012) 158: 175-195, at 179-181. 12 Vasanthakumar – January 2016 effected. There are others on the shore, of course, who may be better swimmers, but they do not know where to look, or if they do see the drowning strangers, do not realise they are drowning or appreciate the gravity of their plight. b. Standing Victims’ epistemic privilege arises not only from their firsthand knowledge of injustice, but also from their standing as those who have encountered oppression as its targets. Victims’ standing manifests itself in three ways. First, they are more credible. Their experience of oppression makes it more likely that they are appropriately motivated when they alert others. In the main, this means that victims are usually the only individuals with firsthand knowledge who are actually willing to testify about injustice. It also means that when they do, they can more easily be relied upon to provide a truthful account—unlike perpetrators, they lack the incentive to gloss over uncomfortable details, to sanitize their complicity in wrongdoing, or to minimize the gravity of this wrongdoing.36 Second, victims of injustice have greater authority, especially when it comes to articulating what justice might require, and identifying what will count as an adequate remedy or restitution for their suffering. Even well-meaning bystanders making a searching inquiry into this question could not succeed without consulting the views of victims. Victims constitute a class of individuals with particular and grave interests at stake, and their views—on their experiences of injustice and on what resistance might require—correspondingly have a particular, and unique, weight. As I will later discuss, by no means does this make victims’ perspectives dispositive on either the question of the presence or remedy of injustice. And finally, it is important that victims themselves assert these interests. Oppressive institutions and norms often are predicated on claims about victims’ lack of moral agency and worth. Insofar as victims’ resistance is an expression and exercise of self-respect and agency, it necessarily undermines oppression, and when this resistance takes the form, at least initially, as testimony, it undermines oppressors’ denial of victims’ epistemic subjecthood.37 Equally, of course, they may be thought prone to exaggerate. I address this concern, and identify potential remedies, in the next section. 37 Miranda Fricker, Epistemic Injustice: power and ethics of knowing (Oxford UP, 2007). 36 13 Vasanthakumar – January 2016 c. Limitations This may seem to move too quickly. After all, victims’ knowledge and standing are subject to a number of qualifications. Even in relatively morally determinate circumstances characterised by clarity, victims’ knowledge about wrongdoing may be limited. Consider detainees subject to torture and other abuse. Depending on the circumstances of their detention, they often are isolated, unaware of the extent or nature of the oppression they suffer, of the institutional hierarchy undergirding this oppression, or of the individual identities of perpetrators or other victims. Given their treatment, they may frequently be disoriented, unconscious, or unable to remember particular incidents or individuals. These limitations arise even more acutely with respect to structural injustice. Structural injustice is invisible, and seemingly incidental: it is inflicted through the normal workings of complex institutions and rules that are seemingly fair and transparent. When individuals lose through these institutions, this loss is easily regarded as a matter of individual failure or bad luck rather than as an injustice. This is true for victims as well. Recognising the fact of structural injustice often requires more than the experience of it—it requires a broader understanding of historical trends and causal patterns that connect together seemingly isolated individual occurrences to reveal both the existence and extent of structural injustice. Victims’ experience of oppression, then, does not always suffice for epistemic competence; much less, it might seem, for epistemic privilege. After all, other actors might be privy to better information. In the case of torture, for example, perpetrators would seem to have better information about the practice, prevalence and persons involved in the perpetration of abuse. And in the case of structural injustice, although victims can acquire information about the fact and prevalence of structural injustice, there is good reason to think they are less likely to do so, given their often diminished access to education and facility with certain types of explanatory or evidentiary tools.38 Of course, this disadvantage should not be overstated because victims still have experiential knowledge of injustice. Perpetrators are often unable to recognize their conduct as oppressive. And even if victims See Alison Wylie, “Why Standpoint Matters,” Science and Other Matters: Issues in Philosophies of Science and Technology (2003); Carol Hay, “The Obligation to Resist Oppression” at 28. 38 14 Vasanthakumar – January 2016 have imperfect information, they alone have access to knowledge of what victimhood feels like.39 But even here, victims may fall short. If victims have internalised oppressive norms, they will not feel humiliation, outrage or indignation when injustice touches their lives—or will not recognise their feelings as such. A woman who treats as natural the casual condescension of her male colleagues would be ill-placed to articulate to others the ways in which such condescension feels and the harms it inflicts. Eager to avoid the trope of the ‘angry Black man,’ a victim of racial injustice might refuse to acknowledge, much less express, the rage he feels. The converse is also true. Victims may be prone to indulge in a sense of victimhood, quick to point to injustice as the source of their misfortune, failures, or feelings of discomfort, and prone to exaggerate the harms they experience. Particularly in the case of structural injustice, this suggests that the two forms of knowledge are intertwined and interdependent. Without knowledge that oppression exists, victims cannot recognise or make sense of their own experience of injustice as injustice—they will lack any experiential knowledge of the harms injustice inflicts. And a robust understanding of the nature and prevalence of oppression guards against an extravagant sense of the harms it inflicts. At the same time, an inquiry into the existence and extent of structural injustice often is instigated by testimony of individual harms: a victim articulates the grinding humiliations of seemingly minor occurrences—routine police stops, scepticism from officials, wariness from strangers—the gravity of which prompts attention and investigation. 39 To a limited extent, others can gain access to the experience of injustice. For example, in 2008 Christopher Hitchens underwent waterboarding, then recognized by the US government as a lawful interrogation technique, to provide “firsthand knowledge” that it was in fact torture. C. Hitchens, “Believe me, it’s torture,” Vanity Fair July 31, 2008. Available at: http://www.vanityfair.com/news/2008/08/hitchens200808. Hitchens details the experience of being drowned and the subsequent claustrophobia and sense of smothering he feels whenever he is short of breath. Hitchens’ experience of waterboarding was voluntarily undertaken, was done with the knowledge that it would be terminated as soon as he signaled, and was done without verbal insults and other humiliations—the means by which he gains access to the experience of waterboarding necessarily precludes the sense of domination and despair that characterize torture and arbitrary detention. Acquired experience is less availing in the case of structural injustice where there are few discrete experiences that can be replicated. It is not impossible, of course, but its probative value is more limited. See, e.g., J.H. Griffin, Black Like Me (1961), a memoir of a white Texan man who transformed his appearance to pass as Black and who reported on his experiences in the South. 15 Vasanthakumar – January 2016 Because victims’ standing follows, in large part, from their knowledge, limitations in their knowledge—and certainly perceptions of these limitations—infect the strength of their standing. Irrespective of their truthfulness, victims are not always regarded by others as the most credible witnesses; they are easily dismissed as oversensitive, suspected for exaggerating the harms they have suffered, or otherwise treated as “unreliable witnesses to their own lives.”40 In fact, this incredulity is an important tool of oppression. 41 Whatever the limitations of their knowledge and standing, however, victims are essential to resistance efforts. Imagine a resistance movement that involves no victims. There would be reason to question whether there are indeed victims of injustice in need of rescue; whether these rescue efforts accurately and effectively target the injustices suffered; and whether they bring about a state of justice, or at least, greater justice that victims would recognise as such. And the absence of victims would replicate the very marginalisation these resistance efforts seek to redress, imperiously acting for victims who are treated as passive agents. Resistance efforts that involve no victims are suspect enterprises. d. Testimonial virtue Victims are not always the most competent or the most credible testifiers. And in fact, the aims of accuracy and credibility are often in tension with one another: confronted by accounts of brutality or violence they knew nothing about, bystanders may be incredulous, suspecting that victims are exaggerating or are overly sensitive. Attempting to appear credible, however, might compel victims to satisfy standards of reasonableness that are stacked against them, or to speak in a register which prevents them from speaking truthfully about their experiences.42 I will briefly outline two aspects of the role of witness—the development of testimonial virtues, in community with others—that potentially help navigate this tension. Rebecca Solnit, Men Explain Things To Me (Chicago: Haymarket Books, 2014), at 8. Fricker, Epistemic Injustice. 42 The campaign against sexual harassment had to re-describe centuries-old practices in terms of sex discrimination, and this recharacterisation conflicted with prevalent notions of common sense and reasonableness. See, e.g. Reva B. Siegel, “Introduction: a Short History of Sexual Harassment Law,” in Directions in Sexual Harassment Law (ed. Catherine A. Mackinnon and Reva B. Siegel) (Yale UP, 2003). In recent campus protests in the United States, for example, student protestors have talked about their pain in ways that have been accused of as disruptive and lacking in civility. See, e.g. Zareena Grewal, “Here’s what my Yale students get: free speech and anti-racism aren’t mutually exclusive,” Washington Post (November 12, 2015). 40 41 16 Vasanthakumar – January 2016 Testimony occasions a number of virtues: the epistemological virtues of conscientiousness, open-mindedness, perception, and intuition; the testifier’s virtues of honesty, transparency, and courage; and the audience’s virtues of trust, critical reflectiveness, and self-monitoring. Because victims testify in aid of others, they are motivated, or ought to be, to be both accurate and credible, and these virtues guard against tendencies of denial, exaggeration, or self-indulgence. These virtues are more easily developed when testimony is seen as a collective enterprise. When victims speak to one another about the injustices they experience, they have a less hostile environment in which to articulate their experiences and gain confidence in their perspectives. These deliberations also allow victims to check against self-deception, and to acquire information that adds nuance to their own understanding of events. Feminist consciousness-raising groups in the 1960s, for example, provided spaces in which women could articulate, however inchoately, their frustrations; were able to situate these frustrations into an emerging framework of gender justice; and were able to consult one another for sympathy, support, and solutions. This is true even in cases of persecution, where victims share information, discover patterns, and identify key figures. Speaking to one another bolsters victims’ confidence in their understanding of their own experience; the need to communicate this understanding to others requires them to temper their assertions, to connect their sense of injustice with evidence of injustice, to give reasons and explanations and illustrations.43 By no means does the collective nature of testimony make it especially cohesive. Victims disagree about the facts of the matter. In some cases, they will disagree over whether or not oppression is in fact present, over whether a given event or phenomenon is in fact a manifestation of injustice. Victims may offer competing interpretations of the same events, dispute the characterisation of other victims, or the romanticisation of suffering. 44 Victims also disagree over what counts This is important to ensure that victims do not end up in ‘echo chambers,’ speaking only to those who share their perspectives and becoming more strident in these. For example, those who bemoan the ‘war against Christmas’ in the United States. Having to persuade others not only protects against these forms of selfdeception but ensures that victims are more credible and enjoy better standing. If, by contrast, the duty to resist is an extension of the duty of self-respect, these considerations fall at the wayside. It would be imperative that the victim speak truthfully of her experience without worrying about credibility or persuading others. 44 For example, Ta-Nehisi Coates recounts an incident in which a white woman pushes his dawdling young son, narrating both his response and situating it within a 43 17 Vasanthakumar – January 2016 as resistance, both in terms of what strategies will be most effective and what goals to prioritise. Some victims may seek to change attitudes and practices through grassroots engagement whilst others aim at legislative amendments; some may seek criminal trials for perpetrators whilst others focus on reconciliation.45 Testimony thus engenders deliberation, accountability, and critical reflection. And the earnest dissensus it produces reveals, at the very least, some consensus over the existence of oppression and its gravity, and bolsters the credibility of their claims that there are victims in need of rescue. However circumscribed, then, the role of testifying is demanding and, as any cursory survey of popular discussions on race and gender suggest, fraught. But rescuing the oppressed often requires more: it is a long-term enterprise that typically involves defeating practices deliberately instituted by powerful state actors. It will call for a combination of strategies, including indirectly applying pressure to perpetrators through international organisations, governments and civil society organisations as well as directly resisting perpetrators through armed opposition. It requires coordination amongst multiple actors who may have different interests or agendas and the exercise of political judgement to gauge changing political events and opportunities. In short, resisting injustice is far more complex than the paradigm rescue case, and may require more than testifying once. 5. Two Objections framework of historical and ongoing violence against black bodies. Ta-Nehisi Coates, Between the World and Me (Melbourne: The Text Publishing Company, 2015) at 93-96. In his review of Coates’ work, Thomas Chatterton Williams disputes Coates’ characterization of the event, deems his reaction disproportionate, and argues that treating blacks with ‘infantilising care’ precludes their equal freedom. See Thomas Chatterton Williams, “Loaded Dice,” London Review of Books December 3, 2015 Vol 37(23): 15-18. 45 Thus, if victims of structural injustice appear inactive, this may reflect only a different strategy of resistance rather than a shirking of their duties. Some include ‘internal resistance’—a rejection of oppressive norms and an awareness of their operation without more—as resistance, and some times the only form of resistance that is available to victims. See Boxhill, The Responsibility,” at 10. Hay distinguishes this from acquiescence, acting in bad faith, or ignorance, none of which constitutes resistance. Hay, “Obligation” at 33-34. On my account, ‘internal resistance’ counts as such only insofar as it diminishes the oppression of others, which it may do so indirectly. 18 Vasanthakumar – January 2016 This invites two objections (at least). First, is the duty to testify—even once—too demanding? Can we, for example, require victims of torture to share their traumatic experiences in order to rescue others left behind, or should we treat any such effort as supererogatory? Second, does testifying exhaust victims’ duty to rescue? After all, the basis of victims’ special capabilities, and hence their special duties, arises from their epistemic privilege. Once they publicise their knowledge, they would seem to lose this privilege—do victims become just one of many bystanders with no further duty to monitor, advise or urge on? Let me address these objections in turn. a. Demandingness The capabilities account burdens blameless strangers for being in the “wrong place at the wrong time with the right resources.”46 Victims are doubly burdened as the victims of injustice and the agents charged with its defeat. And defeating injustice is always more onerous and complex than the paradigm rescue case. Attributing any duties of rescue to victims might seem too demanding. I will argue, however, that demandingness will not act as a limitation on victims’ duties to testify and resist injustice. Under the capabilities account, a victim has a duty to assist only if she can do so without sacrificing ‘morally comparable’ interests. The duty is more or less demanding depending on which of the victim’s interests are counted and with what weight.47 In the paradigm rescue case, for example, a bystander would not have a duty to rescue a drowning stranger if she cannot swim, if she can swim but the conditions are such that she is at real risk of drowning, or if she could save the drowning stranger but only by sacrificing a limb. If, however, rescuing the stranger would require the bystander to ruin expensive shoes, let a friend down, or miss a job interview, the bystander would have a duty to rescue. Where the line is drawn is a function of the interests at stake for the bystander and the degree to which her efforts are both necessary and sufficient to rescuing the needy stranger—that is, the degree of moral determinacy. Thus, even a frivolous sacrifice would not be called for if futility was a certainty. D. Jamieson, “Rights, Justice,” at 353. A less demanding iteration of the duty to rescue would allow an ‘agent-centred prerogative’, whereby the capable bystander is permitted to grant her own interests and personal projects greater weight than those of the needy stranger. Thus, she might be relieved of the duty even if morally comparable interests are not at stake. See Samuel Scheffler, Rejection of Consequentialism (Oxford University Press, 1994). 46 47 19 Vasanthakumar – January 2016 Take the victim of torture who flees her persecutors and finds refuge elsewhere. Would it be too demanding to require her to tell others about her experiences? First, let’s consider whether testifying calls on the victim to sacrifice ‘morally comparable’ interests. It might be argued that providing testimony, particularly of traumatic experiences, is psychologically infeasible. Victims may be too traumatised to revisit their experiences, may be unable to make sense of their experiences, and may be unable to articulate these to others. For such victims their experience of injustice is debilitating rather than enabling. Such victims, however, would not count as capable bystanders; they are not candidates for bearing a duty to rescue. Even if a victim is capable of testifying, however, it might seem that the costs of doing so are too great. This is certainly true when a victim imperils her basic interests by testifying. For example, torture victims who remain within the reach of their torturers do not have a duty to speak up if doing so leaves them open to retribution. Morally comparable interests are clearly at stake. Testifying may also be psychologically traumatic. Some might argue that revisiting humiliating and traumatic experiences and publicising these to strangers is not merely costly; it is asking victims to harm themselves in order to help others.48 And once they testify, victims confront further costs. They may be met with incredulity, ridiculed in the media, or have their personal lives scrutinised by skeptics. There is no question that testifying, even once, is demanding; a cursory reading of torture survivors’ accounts makes clear the difficulties they face in recounting painful and humiliating episodes. This does not mean that the requirement to testify is overly demanding, however, especially when it is weighted against the basic interests at stake for those who remain subject to torture and other abuses. Morality is demanding, but its demandingness does not tell against its being true.49 This analysis changes as the degree of moral determinacy diminishes. Consider cases of structural injustice. As I have argued, structural injustice can undermine the basic interests of its victims, including bodily integrity and self-respect. What is unclear, however, is when a particular incident or event is a manifestation of structural injustice, whether and how closely it undermines the basic interests, of which victims, and what actions will provide a remedy. Similar indeterminacy applies to the risks the victim undertakes by testifying or speaking up, 48 49 I am grateful to Diletta Laura for pushing me on this point. Robert E. Goodin, “Demandingness as a Virtue,” Journal of Ethics (2009). 20 Vasanthakumar – January 2016 for they themselves remain subject to the systemic injustice. For example, structural oppression of women does violence to their basic interests in bodily integrity and self-respect, but it also manifests itself in casual sexism and implicit bias. A woman may notice that she and her female colleagues are frequently interrupted in a work meeting. It may be unclear to her, however, whether this is an instance of structural oppression (perhaps she is surrounded by over-enthusiastic colleagues who interrupt men and women equally); what interests, if any, it implicates; how she might act to secure any interests that are in jeopardy; and whether she can intervene without risking retaliation or ridicule herself. That is, it will be unclear whether basic interests are at stake, whether she sacrifices morally comparable interests to those at stake, and whether her doing so will in fact make a difference. Note that the demands of testimony for cases of structural injustice are often more insidious, and potentially more burdensome, than those in the case of persecution. With torture, the moral requirement is that victims of torture must revisit and recount deeply traumatic events. Structural injustice, on the other hand, seems to require victims to be eternally vigilant—to read situations for ways in which they may be instantiations of structural injustice, to deliberate over whether or not they ought to speak up, and to address themselves constantly to the structural injustices they encounter. This leads easily into what Hay has described as a ‘second-order’ oppression: not only do oppressive institutions constrain and burden victims’ life choices, but resisting these institutions similarly overdetermine individuals’ identities and life choices. Moreover, the immediate costs of speaking up are not always obvious, and in some cases the threat of violence is ever-present: mild remonstrations with the police may invite excessive force; a 140character tweet prompts graphic threats of violence. As a result of this uncertainty, the victim’s duties are less clear-cut: she has greater discretion in judging the situation, gauging the different interests at stake, and deciding on a course of action. In this regard, her duties are akin to imperfect duties.50 Absent such indeterminacy 50 Although here, her discretion comes about only because of epistemic uncertainty rather than because she has discretion to weight interests differently. A torture survivor might similarly have such discretion. Suppose there is already a considerable body of testimony from other victims and witnesses, so that the additional gains from her testimony are likely to be marginal, or conversely, that hers is the only testimony and is unlikely to have any impact; in such cases, because the situation confronting the survivor is less morally determinate, there is greater room for divergent judgments about how she ought to act. Again, to emphasise, 21 Vasanthakumar – January 2016 and when basic interests of victims are in jeopardy, victims often will be morally required to inform others of the need for rescue. Of course, this does not mean that they invite condemnation if they remain silent. We might be sympathetic when the victims of torture refuse to speak to others about their experience and humbled when they choose to do so, but these reactive attitudes only recognise how demanding the moral requirement is; not that it is not in force.51 b. Noncompliance Perhaps a more fatal challenge to victims’ duties arises from concerns about fairness. Victims’ duties arise because others have failed to comply with the requirements of morality. This non-compliance potentially arises at two points: when perpetrators commit injustices against victims, and when capable bystanders, including other victims, fail to do their part after they have been alerted. The noncompliance of others often is thought to diminish an individual’s duties. It is perpetrators’ noncompliance, however, that occasions victims’ duties. Recall that the primary appeal of the capabilities account is its forward-looking focus on providing a remedy for the needy without considering questions of blameworthiness—of the capable agent, the drowning stranger, or of any perpetrators. That is, bystanders have a duty to rescue even when they are blameless and when blameworthy agents are present.52 Of course, the presence of perpetrators matters: it potentially increases the costs of rescue, it may determine how such a rescue is best carried out, and perpetrators may be liable for recompense after a rescue has been executed. But the non-compliance of perpetrators does not preclude a duty to rescue. Indeed, non-compliance is not relevant in and of itself, but matters only in terms of how costly it makes the duty to rescue. This is also true at the second point of non-compliance victims may confront once they have alerted others. Most rescue efforts require coordination amongst multiple actors: multiple victims to more effectively alert other bystanders of the need for a rescue, and these other bystanders to act to bring about a rescue. If all similarly situated these are divergent judgments about how effective her actions are likely to be and not about how to balance or weight ‘morally comparable’ interests. 51 This also means that testifying is not supererogatory—it is not merely morally desirable but required. 52 David Miller “Distributing,” at 460 (although Miller considers only when blameworthy agents are incapable of providing a remedy.) 22 Vasanthakumar – January 2016 victims testify, and all capable bystanders pay attention and act, then it may well turn out that victims’ duties are easily discharged and concerns about their demandingness are misguided. What, however, if other victims refuse to testify? Or, if multiple victims testify to a world that pays no attention? Must victims keep speaking, trying to motivate or pressure others to do their part? Broadly, there are three answers to the question of how far conscientious agents must take up the slack: individuals do more than their fair share, they do only their fair share, or they do less.53 The rationale behind these three can be illustrated if we return to the paradigm rescue case. Imagine there are four drowning strangers and four equally capable bystanders, such that a fair allocation requires each bystander to rescue one drowning stranger. If one of the bystanders walks away without attempting a rescue, the remaining three—the conscientious bystanders—could not rescue their allocated strangers and then walk away. Indeed, if three walked away leaving behind only one bystander, and this sole bystander could rescue all four strangers at no excessive cost to herself, then she is required to do so. The need is so great and can be met at such relatively low cost that the lone rescuer is required to do more than her fair share. Imagine now that there are hundreds of drowning strangers and tens of capable bystanders. The bystanders can save the strangers only by creating and sustaining appropriate institutions, the success of which depends on broad-based participation. If a sufficient number of bystanders are unwilling to participate, the conscientious bystanders cannot make it up, since success depends on the number of participants rather than the extent of their efforts. In this case, perhaps conscientious bystanders are required only to do their fair share to maintain these institutions. In the face of non-compliance, victims’ responsibilities remain the same because additional efforts would make no difference to the outcome. And third, some answer that individuals should do less than their fair share if a rescue is rendered futile by others’ non-compliance. If a victim was reasonably certain that no compliance from other potential rescuers was forthcoming, and that without such compliance her efforts would be futile, then she arguably is required to do less than her fair share would be under conditions of perfect compliance. This David Miller, “Taking up the Slack? Responsibility and justice in situations of partial compliance” in Carl Knight and Zofia Stemplowska (eds) Responsibility and Distributive Justice (Oxford, 2011). 53 23 Vasanthakumar – January 2016 scenario, however, is one where the duty to rescue would not even arise: the victim is effectively on her own, unable to provide a rescue by herself. There are of course further variations within these scenarios, with correspondingly different outcomes. Some have thus urged—and I am inclined to agree—that there is no single answer, and individual’s duties should be considered on a case-by-case basis.54 Three general points, however, can be made about non-compliance in the context of victims’ duties. First, and most important, the non-compliance of others is itself irrelevant to the question of what duties victims ultimately bear. Instead, their duties are determined by the cost and effectiveness of their additional efforts by their ability to rescue at no excessive cost to themselves. Thus, although the non-compliance of others indirectly informs the victim’s duties, it does not by itself limit them. The single answer, then, is that when individuals can secure the basic interests of others without sacrificing morally comparable interests, they have a duty to do so—whether this duty arises and what it requires, given the non-compliance of others, will be decided on a case-by-case basis. Second, how the non-compliance of others informs victims’ duties cannot be determined ex ante. Given the complexity, coordination, long-term strategising and happenstance that characterise resistance efforts, it is impossible to determine at the outset which strategy to pursue amongst the many available, the minimum number of compliant bystanders required before a rescue is futile, and the types of actions these bystanders ought to take. Victims cannot know what rescue scenario they confront because this is still indeterminate; they can only make assessments of how burdensome their responsibilities are proving to be. This means that they should persist in their efforts to provide a rescue up to and until the costs will, with reasonable certainty, outweigh any benefits to be gained. A victim could not, confronted by the enormity of the injustices to be remedied and an apparent lack of interest from others, decide that any effort would be futile and walk away. And finally, the forward-looking focus of the capabilities account does not mean that wrongdoers are let off the hook. Perpetrators, beneficiaries and bystanders of injustice have important roles to play in the account I’ve developed here. Ending unjust practices often Laura Valentini, “Ideal vs. Nonideal Theory: a Conceptual Map,” Philosophy Compass (2012) at 655. 54 24 Vasanthakumar – January 2016 requires the cooperation of perpetrators, and this cooperation is often garnered through the pressure imposed by bystanders and victims. In addition, perpetrators may be liable to both victims and rescuers for recompense of some sort, and they may be subject to punishment; accountability of this sort is often integral to ending unjust institutions and practices. Questions about fairness are relevant, then, but postponed. Given that victims have already endured grave injustices, a duty to resist may seem to be a heavy burden that is unfairly borne. This does not mean that there is no duty. Individuals who are uniquely positioned to rescue others have a duty to do so, irrespective of how they came to be in this position. Victims of injustice often are in this position. They are not the sole rescuers or even the rescuers with the most substantive role. Indeed, the opposite often is true. However, to the extent that victims’ testimony is essential for such a rescue to even occur, and so long as alerting others does not require them to sacrifice morally comparable interests, victims have a duty to do so. 6. Conclusion Victims resist injustice because it is in their interests to do so and because it is required by their self-respect. Their resistance is also demanded by a duty to assist fellow victims. I have provided an account of victims’ duties to resist within the framework of a duty to rescue, arguing that their firsthand experience of injustice uniquely positions them to initiate resistance. Their duty consists primarily in testifying about their, and others’, suffering, alerting others to the fact of injustice and the need for rescue. This account is distinct in several key respects to its alternatives. First, it better coheres with victims’ moral discourse and political practice. By casting victims’ duties as other-regarding, it makes sense of victims’ beliefs that these duties are owed to others, and renders coherent moral practices like expressing disappointment and betrayal when fellow victims appear not to be doing their part. The focus on speaking up identifies the importance of developing testimonial virtues and the importance of doing so with others, again making normative sense of on-going debates amongst victims and others about how to fulfil the requirements of truthfulness and credibility. And this account carves out a role for victims that is connected to those of bystanders 25 Vasanthakumar – January 2016 and perpetrators, again, a more accurate reflection of actual resistance efforts. Second, it provides a more systematic way to think through the limits of victims’ duties. Other accounts merely stipulate that the duty is demanding and should therefore be regarded as imperfect, leaving it to the discretion of victims how weighty this duty will be and what its performance will call for. Or they make the very existence of the duty discretionary, contingent on victims’ voluntary acceptance of responsibilities to resist. The instant account identifies moral determinacy as a key factor that spells out when a victim should act and how much discretion she has to determine how she will act, but overall provides a more robust and demanding ground for victims’ duties. And finally, this account gestures towards institutional responses. If victims play an essential role in identifying and remedying injustices, like whistleblowers and civil disobedients,55 then there ought to be institutional protections that enable their performance of this role, that create these roles, or that at the very least lessen the burdens they face. More broadly, by foregrounding victims’ epistemic privilege, this account recognises victims of injustice as moral agents with unique perspectives on injustice that are essential for both theorising and realising justice. It takes cognisance of the essential role that victims have played in realising justice, and the normative reasons that motivate and require this role. And by theorising from injustice, it treats injustice not merely as a “surprising abnormality”56 but instead as a reality rich in normative reasons, moral perspectives and political action. See, e.g. David Lefkowitz, “On a Moral Right to Civil Disobedience,” Ethics 117 (2) (January 2007): 202-233. 56Shklar, The Faces, at 17. 55 26