THE MATTER OF EVENTS THOMAS CROWTHER I N THIS PAPER, I aim to develop a framework for thinking about matters of temporal ontology that enables us to understand a distinction between two categories of time-occupiers; a distinction often characterized as that between processes and accomplishments. After broadly characterizing this distinction, I argue that existing attempts to explain and understand this distinction fail. I maintain that the route to understanding this distinction is to further develop an analogy between spatial and temporal notions suggested in a number of places in the literature; for example by Alexander Mourelatos and 1 Barry Taylor. When this analogy is satisfactorily developed, it is possible to explain what correctness there is in existing attempts to characterize this distinction, and to explain some further puzzling issues within temporal ontology. I conclude by commenting briefly on a possible source of concern about the analogy. I In Metaphysics, 6 Aristotle draws a distinction between what he 2 calls energeia and kinesis. The distinction between energeia and kinesis has standardly been interpreted as a distinction between active occurrences which contain an end or purpose in themselves, and those that do not. In the translation of W.D. Ross, some actions, like 3 “making thin,” “have a limit.” Making thin is “not an action, at least Correspondence to: Thomas Crowther, Department of Philosophy, Heythrop College, University of London, Kensington Square, London W8 5HN, United Kingdom. 1 Alexander Mourelatos, “Events, Processes and States,” Linguistics and Philosophy 2 (1978): 415–34; Barry Taylor, “Tense and Continuity,” Linguistics and Philosophy 1 (1977): 199–220. 2 Aristotle Metaphysics, book 9 chapter 6, 1048b18–37. All citations and references to Aristotle are from Aristotle, The Complete Works of Aristotle, ed. Jonathan Barnes (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1984). 3 Metaphysics 9.6, 1048b18–19. The Review of Metaphysics 65 (September 2011): 3–39. Copyright © 2011 by The Review of Metaphysics. 4 THOMAS CROWTHER 4 not a complete one (for it is not an end).” This type of occurrence can be contrasted with one like “seeing” or “understanding”; a type of 5 movement “in which the end is present.” Aristotle, in this translation, goes on to say: “Of these processes, we must call the one set movements [kinesis] and the other actualities [energeia]. For every movement is incomplete—making thin, learning, walking, building; 6 these are movements, and incomplete movements.” In characterizing the notion of the completeness of movements in contrast to actualities, Aristotle suggests that the unfolding of an incomplete movement does not entail that a complete movement has occurred, though the occurrence of an actuality does: “At the same time we are seeing and have seen, are understanding and have understood, are thinking and have thought; but it is not true that at the same time we are learning 7 and have learnt, or are being cured and have been cured.” The nature of Aristotle’s own distinction between movements and actualities is a matter of controversy in Aristotle scholarship about 8 which I make no commitment here. But the idea that there is a distinction within the category of things which unfold over time—a distinction that concerns the ways that those things occupy time—and that something like this distinction is bequeathed to us by Aristotle’s remarks in the Metaphysics and the Nicomachean Ethics, is a familiar 9 one. 4 Metaphysics 9.6, 1048b19–20. Ibid., 1048b22–23. 6 Ibid., 1048b28–30. 7 Ibid., 1048b22–25. 8 See J. L. Ackrill, “Aristotle’s Distinction Between Energeia and Kinesis,” in New Essays on Plato and Aristotle, ed. Renford Bambrough (London: Routledge, 1965); Terry Penner, “Verbs and the Identity of Actions: A Philosophical Exercise in the Interpretation of Aristotle,” in Ryle, ed. Oscar Wood and George Pitcher (London: Macmillan, 1971), 393–460; Daniel W. Graham, “States and Performances: Aristotle’s Test,” Philosophical Quarterly 30 (1980): 117–30; Alexander Mourelatos, “Aristotle’s kinesis/energeia Distinction: A Marginal Note on Kathleen Gill’s Paper,” Canadian Journal of Philosophy 23, no. 3 (1993): 385–8; and Myles F. Burnyeat, “Kinesis vs. Energeia: A Much Read Passage in (but not of) Aristotle’s Metaphysics” in Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, vol. 34, ed. David Sedley (Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2008). 9 See in particular Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, book 10, chapter 4. 5 THE MATTER OF EVENTS 5 th In the 20 century philosophical literature, the establishment of focus on the idea that there is a distinction between the ways that things occupy periods of time is associated with the work of Gilbert 10 Ryle, Zeno Vendler, and Anthony Kenny. Building on the discussion in Ryle, Vendler distinguishes between verbs that are capable of taking 11 the continuous tense and those which are not. I might intelligibly answer the question “What are you doing?” with “I am running” or “I am walking,” but not “I am knowing that p” or “I am believing that p.” The latter verbs, he says, are statives; they single out a standing condition or a state, a way that someone or something is or can be. Like particular material objects, states such as knowledge and belief do not have temporal duration in the sense of having temporal parts or successive temporal phases over which they unfold. Running and walking, by contrast, are things that exist by developing or unfolding over a period of time. Given that such things exist by unfolding, it is not possible to—for example—merely walk at an instant of time, without doing so over some period of time. Where “” is a verb 12 employed in a genuine continuous tense predication: (U) If S is ing at t, S is ing during a period of time tx-tn, such that t is a time within that period. Occupants of this category can be distinguished from achievements. Unlike states, achievements—winning the race, finding one’s keys, or reaching the summit—are things that have an occurrent mode of existence. But, unlike walking and running, achievements do not exist by unfolding over periods of time. They occur instantaneously. 10 Gilbert Ryle, The Concept of Mind (London: Penguin, 1949), chapters 5 and 7, and Dilemmas (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1954), 100–6; Zeno Vendler, “Verbs and Times,” Philosophical Review 67 (1957): 143–60; reprinted in a revised form in Zeno Vendler, Linguistics and Philosophy, (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 1967); Anthony Kenny, Action, Emotion and Will (London: Routledge, 1963), chapter 8. Vendler and Kenny independently arrive at a similar typology of verbs. For the purposes of exposition of the key ideas, I focus on Vendler’s discussion (with a terminological qualification I mention below). 11 See Ryle, The Concept of Mind and Vendler, “Verbs and Times.” 12 Proper continuous tense predications can be distinguished from varieties of idiomatic uses of statives (for example, “I am loving it”). 6 THOMAS CROWTHER Both Vendler and Kenny acknowledge the existence of a distinction within the category of verbs capable of taking continuous tense forms between activities or processes, like walking, running, and drawing, and accomplishments, like walking to the shops, running a mile, and drawing a picture of a house. The precise nature of this distinction is one of the subjects of this paper. But to a first approximation, processes like walking are things that are capable, in principle, of continuing indefinitely, while accomplishments, like walking to the shops, involve progress towards a point at which they must terminate. Process and accomplishment verbs are distinguished from one another, Vendler and Kenny suggest, by characteristic tests. One such putative test concerns whether the relevant verbs can be followed by “for a time” or “in a time.” I can say that I have run or I have been running for an hour, or that I have walked for an hour. But I cannot say that I ran a mile for an hour, nor that I walked to the shops for an hour. I ran a mile in a certain amount of time, or walked to the shops in a certain amount of time. This is taken to manifest the fact that what Vendler and Kenny call activities or processes—things like walking, running and drawing—go on for periods of time. They do not take time, in the way that walking to the shops or running a mile— 13 what they call accomplishments or performances—do. The idea of a distinction between process and accomplishment is exploited in a variety of works across recent analytical philosophy, most particularly in connection with the idea that distinctions in the way that things occupy periods of time may help us to explain 14 important concepts within the philosophy of mind and action. But 13 When discussing the category that Vendler (in “Verbs and Times”) calls an activity, I shall talk instead of processes. It is not necessary that those goings on which can take imperfective form, which possess temporal parts, and which yet lack a telic point, are things done by rational agents (let alone things intentionally or purposefully done by them). Vendler’s activities I take to be an agential genus of the species of atelic process. In this I follow Mourelatos, “Events, Processes and States” (though not Mourelatos, “Aristotle’s kinesis/energeia Distinction: A Marginal Note on Kathleen Gill’s Paper”). 14 See, for example, Thomas Crowther, “Watching, Sight and the Temporal Shape of Perceptual Activity,” The Philosophical Review 118, no. 1 (2009): 1–27, and “Perceptual Activity and the Will,” in Mental Actions, ed. Lucy O’ Brien and Matthew Soteriou (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009); THE MATTER OF EVENTS 7 the nature of the distinction between process and accomplishment is highly problematic. Though it is natural to think that there is some difference between things like running and walking, on the one hand, and running a mile and walking to the shops on the other, it is hard to elucidate the nature of the distinction in a satisfying way. In formal semantics, there is intensive research on the explanation of progressive and perfective verb aspect; a programme within which 15 Vendler and Kenny’s work has been influential. But in analytic metaphysics—with a few important exceptions—the nature of the distinction between process and accomplishment, and of the more general idea that there might be systematic differences in the ways that temporal entities occupy periods of time, has been relatively 16 neglected. Brian O’Shaughnessy, Consciousness and the World (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000) and “Trying and Acting,” in Mental Actions; Helen Steward, The Ontology of Mind: Events, Processes and States (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1997); Rowland Stout, “The Life of a Process,” in Pragmatic Process Philosophy, ed. Guy DeBrock (Amsterdam: Rodopi, 2003); Matthew Soteriou, “Mental Agency, Conscious Thinking, and Phenomenal Character,” in Mental Actions; and Michael Thompson, Life and Action: Elementary Structures of Practice and Practical Thought (Harvard: Harvard University Press, 2008). 15 See, for example, Emmon Bach, “The Algebra of Events,” Linguistics and Philosophy 9, no. 1 (1986): 5–16; David Dowty, Word Meaning and Montague Grammar: The Semantics of Verbs and Times in Generative Semantics and in Montague’s PTQ (D. Reidel: Dordrecht, 1979); Frederick Landman, “The Progressive,” Natural Language Semantics 1, no. 1 (1992): 1– 32; Manfred Krifka, “The Origins of Telicity,” in Events and Grammar, ed. Susan Rothstein (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1998); Henk J. Verkuyl, A Theory of Aspectuality (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993); Terence Parsons, Events in the Semantics of English (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1990); James Higginbotham, “On Events in Linguistic Semantics,” in Speaking of Events, ed. James Higginbotham, Fabio Pianesi, and Achille Varzi (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000), 49–79. Susan Rothstein’s Structuring Events: A Study in the Semantics of Lexical Aspect (Oxford: Blackwell, 2004) is an excellent survey of, and contribution to, the literature. 16 For exceptions see, for example, Barry Taylor, “Tense and Continuity” and Modes of Occurrence: Verbs, Adverbs and Events in Aristotelian Society Series, vol. 2 (Oxford: Blackwell, 1985); Mourelatos, “Events, Processes and States”; Steward, The Ontology of Mind: Events, Processes and States; Kathleen Gill, “On the Metaphysical Distinction Between Processes and Events,” Canadian Journal of Philosophy 23, no. 3 (1993): 365–84; Rowland 8 THOMAS CROWTHER It is my view that there is a metaphysical distinction between processes and accomplishments, and that an understanding of the distinction, as well as an understanding of the relations between concepts drawn on in understanding this distinction, can help us to do valuable philosophical work. I also believe that there remains a role for an investigation of these temporal notions that is independent of empirical work in formal semantics, and which draws on a range of 17 familiar metaphysical resources. That is what I hope to motivate in what follows. II The distinction between processes (for example, walking, running, and moving) and accomplishments (for example, walking to the shops, running a mile, and moving six inches) is naturally loosely characterized in terms of the thought that processes, but not accomplishments, are in principle capable of continuing indefinitely (even if, as it happens, every process does terminate). A difficulty for this proposal, though, is that most taxonomies tend to locate the notion of searching—looking for, or hunting for, or trying to find—in the category of accomplishment. But in the absence of a philosophical argument to show that all searching is successful, it is surely possible for an agent to continue looking for something indefinitely, even in principle. A further thought often used to characterize the distinction is that accomplishments, in contrast to processes, possess a terminal point, a point at which what is going on must cease. According to this suggestion, trying to find one’s keys is like walking to the shops and running a mile, and unlike walking and running, in that there exists a Stout, “Processes,” Philosophy 72, no. 279 (1997): 19–27 and “The Life of a Process.” 17 Though the backdrop to some of the discussion here is the formal semantic treatments of temporal sentences, a more sustained exploration of the relation between the ontology outlined here and work on the formal semantics of the progressive and the perfective will be undertaken independently. THE MATTER OF EVENTS 9 point at which trying to find one’s keys necessarily terminates (that is, finding one’s keys). But the distinction cannot just be drawn in terms of the possession of a terminal point, at least where the notion of a terminal point is understood in this way, for stopping ing is a terminal point for process and accomplishment alike, and necessarily so. Susan Rothstein initially characterizes the distinction between processes and accomplishments in terms of the idea that accomplishments, but not processes, possess a terminal point determined by “the nature of the eventuality” (that is, by the nature of the process or accomplishment) or by “the description of the 18 eventuality,” at which such things must cease. Perhaps stopping ing does not count as a terminal point that is determined by the nature of the process or accomplishment, in the relevant sense (in the way that having run a mile, or having found one’s keys does). But in the absence of some further explanation of what it is for a terminal point to be determined in this way, it is not obvious why it does not. Surely it is in the nature of walking, for example, as something that goes on throughout a period of time, that it can be terminated by stopping walking. Perhaps the distinction between process and accomplishment is not so much whether these different goings on possess terminal points, but whether the relevant unfolding time-occupier can be understood as unfolding towards or progressing towards such a terminal point. In the case of accomplishments, but not processes, terminal points are telic points. For someone to be walking around, say, by contrast with walking to the shops, is not for them to be doing something that unfolds towards a telic point. But the nature of such progression towards a telic point remains to be understood. Suppose a walk that Bill took went on from t1 to t10, and was a walk around, to nowhere in particular. Nevertheless, the walk must have gone on from one point in time, and one physical location, to another point in time, and a physical location (that may be the same) at which it stopped. But it might seem that given these facts about Bill’s walk, we can then understand what he was doing as involving progress towards that 18 Rothstein, Structuring Events: A Study in the Semantics of Lexical Aspect, 7. 10 THOMAS CROWTHER point of termination, the point at which his walk stopped, even though all he was doing was walking. Responding to this by insisting that this is because what he was doing was not really a process, but an accomplishment, the accomplishment of walking from one point to another, would be to abandon the distinction between process and accomplishment as it is found in the literature, rather than explaining what it consists in; for it will be true of anything that can be given in answer to the question: “What is he/she/it doing?” that it is a ing from one point to another, in this sense. The work of Ryle, Kenny, and Vendler contains a range of different Aristotelian tests that purport to divide processes from accomplishments, or to distinguish process-verbs from accomplishment-verbs. Perhaps these tests can help to illuminate the rationale for the distinction. One familiar proposal is that process verbs in the progressive or imperfective form exhibit perfective entailments that accomplishment verbs do not. If S is walking at t, then S (had) walked at t. But accomplishment verbs manifest the socalled imperfective paradox; if S is walking to the shops at t then S 19 had not walked to the shops at t. A related idea is that processes are homogeneous in a way that accomplishments are not. Suppose we take the property of homogeneity to be determined by the following: (H) ing is homogeneous iff if S ed from t1-t10, then for any time t during t1-t10 S (had) ed at t. Then the claim is that processes are clearly homogeneous, though accomplishments are not. If S walked from t1-t10, then at any time during t1-t10, S (had) walked at t. But it is not the case that, if S walked to the shops from t1-t10, then at any time during t1-t10 he (had) walked to the shops at that time. By t5, S had only walked part of the way to the shops. Not every subinterval of t1-t10, a time during 19 For discussion of the imperfective paradox from the perspective of formal semantics, see David Dowty, Word Meaning and Montague Grammar: The Semantics of Verbs and Times in Generative Semantics and in Montague’s PTQ; Taylor, Modes of Occurrence: Verbs, Adverbs and Events; Krifka, “The Origins of Telicity”; Landman, “The Progressive”; Rothstein, Structuring Events: A Study in the Semantics of Lexical Aspect. THE MATTER OF EVENTS 11 which he walked to the shops, is a period of time during which he walked to the shops. But homogeneity cannot be a criterion for distinguishing between 20 processes and accomplishments. David Dowty argues that not all processes are homogeneous; some processes are only homogeneous 21 “down to minimal parts.” The motional activities characteristic of humans (walking, swimming, running, dancing, etc.) involve . . . complex patterns of change of position, changes not just with respect to overall location but changes with respect to positions of parts of the organism . . . (N)ot every minimal subinterval (i.e. one consisting of more than a moment) of such activities is also an interval of that activity. E.g. small subintervals of the time of which x chuckles is true may not be instances of chuckling themselves (though perhaps intervals of x’s producing a glottal stop, etc.). Even particular sequences of more simple changes of position can be required for some activities. To take just one special sort of problem, there may be a sequential series of simpler activities required to characterize a certain complex activity, though no particular member of the sequence need occur first. Consider the case of waltzing; what minimal conditions must an interval meet for x waltzes to be true of that interval? Now since the waltz involves sequences of three steps, I believe it is reasonable to maintain that any interval at which x takes less than three steps is not an interval at which x waltzes is true . . . but merely an interval at which x makes certain movements with his or her feet . . . No doubt, a variety of other problematic cases would be uncovered by an investigation of other sorts of activities.22 For one to have waltzed or to have walked or to have run, it is necessary that one has taken a certain number of steps (and, we might add, has taken them in a particular order). One has not walked if one 20 The case for the existence of nonhomogeneous processes is most clearly associated with the work of Barry Taylor in “Tense and Continuity” and Modes of Occurrence: Verbs, Adverbs and Events, and David Dowty in Word Meaning and Montague Grammar: The Semantics of Verbs and Times in Generative Semantics and in Montague’s PTQ. See Rothstein, Structuring Events: A Study in the Semantics of Lexical Aspect and Krifka, “The Origins of Telicity” for discussion. 21 David Dowty, Word Meaning and Montague Grammar: The Semantics of Verbs and Times in Generative Semantics and in Montague’s PTQ, 166. For clarity, I here replace Dowty’s use of “activity” with “process.” 22 Ibid., 170–1. 12 THOMAS CROWTHER had, by or at a certain time, merely taken a step. Neither has one waltzed if one has merely taken the first of the steps in the tri-step sequence that one needs to take in order to have waltzed a waltz. So if one waltzed from t1-t10, it is not necessarily the case that at any time during t1-t10 one had waltzed. For there is a time during t1-t10 at which one had only just slid one’s left foot forward, or taken a graceful step to the right with one’s right leg. So, though walking and waltzing are paradigmatic processes, they fail to be homogeneous. They are only homogeneous “down to minimal parts”; down to those periods of time that, in the context, are sufficient for the complex of activities involved to have gone on. The fact that some processes are nonhomogeneous, once added to another plausible principle concerning the occupation of time, also shows that the nonentailments distinctive of the imperfective paradox cannot be sufficient to constitute criteria for distinguishing between processes and accomplishments either. Though the kinds of cases discussed show that homogeneity cannot be constitutive of processes as opposed to accomplishments, it remains the case that if S was walking from t1-t10 then he was walking during t1-t2, that is, the very time during which his first single 23 step was being taken. Whether ing is a homogeneous or nonhomogeneous process, or an accomplishment: (I) If S ed from t1-t10 then at any time t during t1-t10 S was ing at t. If Jake walked from t1-t10, then he was walking at any time during that period. But walking is a nonhomogeneous process. If Jake walked from t1-t10 it is not necessarily the case that Jake (had) walked at any time within t1-t10. So there will be times at which it is true of Jake that he is walking at that time, and yet false of him that he (had) walked at that time. Even if Jake (had) only lifted his left leg at (by) t, if Jake did walk from t1-t10 then he nevertheless was walking at t; he wasn’t merely raising his left leg at t. We ought to say that in such a 24 case, Jake was raising his left leg at that time in walking at that time. 23 Compare here Vendler, “Verbs and Times” and Anthony Kenny, Action, Emotion and Will. 24 A tempting line of thought can make it seem compulsory to resist this. Suppose that S took a step from t1-t2, then stopped what he was doing at t2, THE MATTER OF EVENTS 13 So it cannot be sufficient to distinguish some time-occupier (singled out here by “ing”) as an accomplishment, as opposed to a process, that S is ing at t does not entail that S has ed at t. For this is true of walking, as well as walking to the shops. Further, given the existence of nonhomogeneous processes, the patterns of applicability that Vendler notes in connection with “go on for,” “takes time” and “s in a certain amount of time,” and the patterns of propriety of the questions: “How long did it take?” or “For how long?” cannot be diagnostic either. In the case of nonhomogeneous processes, there is an event that is necessary for this process to be going on. In the case of walking, for example, it is necessary to have completed the cycle of right leg left leg movements to be walking. But given the background of events of this kind, and some further context (say, a soldier recovering from serious leg injury who performs the required cycle of right leg left leg movement extremely painfully and slowly) the question: “How long did it take him to walk?” seems perfectly acceptable. And in connection with such cases, we might also say that it took him a long time to walk this morning (by comparison with how long it took him yesterday morning), or that he walked this morning in fifteen seconds. A different suggestion is that what distinguishes processes from accomplishments might be that processes, unlike quantized and hence did not go on to do what is necessary in order to walk. So, throughout t1-t2, S was not walking, but merely taking a single step. Now, suppose a case in which S took a step and then went on to accomplish, from t2-t10, what is necessary in order to have walked. In this case, even though S completed the cycle of activities necessary to have walked, and so walked from t1-t10, it cannot be the case that S was walking throughout every subinterval of that time. For, throughout t1-t2 there is nothing going on in the case in which S did walk, which did not also go on in the case in which he did not go on to do so. What S was doing in both cases, throughout t1-t2, then, was just taking a single step with his left leg, not walking. The correct response is to resist the idea that throughout t1-t2, there is nothing going on in the case in which S did walk which did not go on in the case in which he did do so. In case he did, he was walking at that time, in taking a step. What the argument fails to be sufficiently sensitive to is that, what is going on at a time, or over an interval of time, can be determined by what goes on over a larger period of time, within which the interval, or time, is contained. 14 THOMAS CROWTHER 25 accomplishments, are cumulative. The intuition is that the accumulation of stretches of process of the same kind yields, or at least, may yield, a larger stretch of the same process, but that accumulating accomplishments does not. The accumulation of accomplishments only yields a series of accomplishments. Here is Susan Rothstein sketching the intuition that underpins this criterion: “Two events of running can be summed to form a plural event, but they can also, in the appropriate contexts (usually temporal adjacency), be put together to make a new singular event. Thus an event of running from 2pm to 3pm, and an event of running from 3pm to 4pm can be seen either as two distinct events of running or as a single event of running from 2pm to 4pm . . . While two events in run can form a singular event in run, two distinct events in eat three apples cannot be put together to form a new singular event in eat three 26 apples.” But there is something puzzling about these suggestions. If there was an event of running from 2pm to 3pm, and an event of running from 3pm to 4pm, then there was no time from 2pm to 4pm at which running was not taking place. Given that there was no time from 2pm to 4pm at which the runner was not running, though, there is a perfectly good sense in which one might justifiably resist describing what went on from 2pm to 4pm as involving two distinct events of running. If we are to assume that the runner stopped running at 4pm then there is a single run that the runner ran from 2pm that terminated at 4pm. (If the running had not stopped at 4pm, then there is a single event of running that was in progress from 2pm to 4pm and was still in progress at 4pm.) In such a case it ought not to be denied that there are two distinct periods of time during which running was going on, one that went on from 2pm to 3pm, and another that went on from 3pm to 4pm. For there is a period of running from t1-tn just in case 25 In the literature in linguistics, the claim is most clearly associated with the work of Manfred Krifka. See, for example, Krifka, “The Origins of Telicity.” For discussion see Rothstein, Structuring Events: A Study in the Semantics of Lexical Aspect. Rothstein follows Krifka in taking cumulativity to be the feature of processes that distinguishes them from accomplishments. Rothstein suggestively describes cumulativity as upwards homogeneity. 26 Rothstein, Structuring Events: A Study in the Semantics of Lexical Aspect, 9. THE MATTER OF EVENTS 15 there is running from t1-tn. Given this, it is true that, if there is a period of running from 2pm to 3pm and if there is a period of running from 2pm to 4pm, then there is a period of running from 2pm to 4pm. But if this is what the cumulativity of process amounts to, this fact clearly cannot be used to ground a distinction between processes and accomplishments. For if there was a period of running to the shops from 2pm to 3pm and a period of running to the shops from 3pm to 4pm, then so also there was a period of running to the shops from 2pm to 4pm. Correlatively, though it is true that distinct events of running to the shops can never sum to form a single event of running to the shops, it is also true that distinct events of running can never sum to form a single run, either. If I ran, paused for the briefest moment, and then ran again, then there are, at least on the face of it, two distinct events of running. But these two events cannot, at least not without shifting to some different notion of a run, constitute the same event of running. The thoughts that were used to initially characterize the distinction between process and accomplishment do not seem to take us nearer to understanding the nature of the distinction between these two temporal categories, and their place in the metaphysics of timeoccupation. And the usual tests offered in the literature to distinguish between processes and accomplishments do not seem to carve the distinction between process and accomplishment in the right place. III An observation made by a number of writers, amongst them, Barry Taylor and Alexander Mourelatos, is that there are basic 27 similarities between process verbs and substance stuff terms. The 27 See for example his discussion in Taylor, Modes of Occurrence: Verbs, Adverbs and Events, chapter 3. The idea of an analogy between the ontology of time-occupiers and the concept of mass and mass terms is a familiar feature of the semantic and metaphysical literature. See amongst others Mourelatos, “Events, Processes and States”; Taylor, “Tense and Continuity”; Emmon Bach, “The Algebra of Events”; David Dowty, Word Meaning and Montague Grammar: The Semantics of Verbs and Times in Generative Semantics and in Montague’s PTQ; Anthony Galton, The Logic of Aspect (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1984); Steward, The Ontology of Mind: Events, 16 THOMAS CROWTHER route to understanding the relation between processes and accomplishments—as well as, I claim, to understanding the relation of processes and accomplishments to other temporal categories—is to pursue and develop this analogy between spatial and temporal notions. Mass terms are those that, like “snow,” “rain,” and “gold,” are not 28 count-quantifiable but only mass-quantifiable. (Masses, I shall take it, are what mass terms refer to.) Without significant shift in the meaning of “gold,” there cannot be golds, two golds, more than one gold, or a gold. In cases in which a term such as this does take a plural form, it involves some shift in meaning from the nonpluralized form. Golds for example, are kinds or types of gold (for example red gold, yellow gold, and so forth) or else gold things (for example gold medals). Unless such a shift in meaning has taken place the question “How many golds are there?” is unintelligible. But there may be amounts of gold: there may be some gold, much gold, heaps or piles of gold, or not very much gold. In the case of mass terms like gold, one cannot intelligibly ask “How many?” only “How much?” The paradigmatic examples of masses are space-occupying stuffs: things like gold, bronze, water, and snow. But not all mass is stuff, at least in the sense of space-occupying stuff. What things are doing throughout a period of time, or what they are engaged in throughout a period of time, are like masses or substance-stuffs in not being countquantifiable, only mass quantifiable. There can no more be two walkings or three runnings than there can be two golds or more than one rain. At least without significant departure from the process verb sense of the word, one cannot intelligibly ask: “How many runnings were there?” But there may have been a little light running, a considerable amount of running, or more running than was good for me. This is true not only of the semantic values of process verbs in Processes and States; Rothstein, Structuring Events: A Study in the Semantics of Lexical Aspect. 28 See the essays in Francis Pelletier, ed., Mass Terms: Some Philosophical Problems (Reidel: Dordrecht, 1979); Dean Zimmerman, “Theories of Masses and Problems of Constitution,” Philosophical Review, 104, no. 1 (1995): 53–110; Kathrin Koslicki, “The Semantics of Mass Predicates,” Nous 33, no. 1 (1999): 46–91; Helen M. Cartwright, “Some Remarks about Mass Nouns and Plurality,” Synthese 31, nos. 3/4 (1975): 395– 410; “Amounts and Measures of Amount,” Nous 9, no. 2 (1975): 143–64. THE MATTER OF EVENTS 17 their imperfective form, but also of the semantic values of accomplishment verbs in that form. There cannot be two walking to the shops(s) or three running a mile(s), and it does not make sense to ask how many walking to the shops(s) there were. Though there cannot be two walking to the shops(s), walking to the shops admits of mass quantification: there may be more walking to the shops, less walking to the shops, or enough walking to the shops. What things are doing throughout periods of time and substancestuff are constituents of the same basic ontological category; they could be thought of as temporal and spatial masses. What things are doing is time-occupying stuff. Both substance-stuffs and time-occupying stuffs, respectively, fill out space and time in the same way. If S is ing at a time t, then there must be a period of time from t1-tn such that S is ing from t1-tn and t is within that period of time. That was the principle of timeoccupation spelled out as (U), above. Likewise, where they are present, substance-stuffs necessarily occupy regions of space. If there is gold at place p, then there must be a set of places p1-pn (a region of space) such that there is gold from p1-pn and p is within p1-pn. Where they are present, even the smallest amounts of mass must occupy regions of space; masses are spread out around a region of space in the way that what something is doing must go on throughout a period of time. Though it is significant that there is an analogy between the notions of substance-stuff and time-occupying process and accomplishment, this thought is only one aspect of a more complete structural analogy. While there is discussion that acknowledges the existence of this analogy, what has not emerged clearly enough from those treatments is the idea that the relation between physical stuffs and space-occupying particulars can provide a model for the relation between temporal stuffs and time-occupying particulars that helps us to articulate a rationale for the distinction between process and 29 accomplishment. 29 In the course of mentioning the analogy between spatial stuffs and temporal processes, Daniel Graham attributes to Aristotle the thought that “motion events are comprised of motion processes.” Understanding “comprises” as “is made of” or “is constituted from,” this is just the aspect of the analogy I aim to develop. Whether Aristotle himself held this view is 18 THOMAS CROWTHER Space-occupying material particulars are distinct from masses, for reasons just given; unlike masses, space-occupying particulars are countable; there can be two trees, more than one human being, and several lumps of gold. But though they are nonidentical with them, space-occupying material particulars consist of—are made of, or composed of—space-occupying stuff. Some gold medal, then, is gold stuff not in being identical with that stuff, but in virtue of the fact that gold is the stuff the medal is made of. Space-occupying spatial particulars do not consist of mere spatial boundaries or a set of things that mark limits of the thing, but fill out the space that they occupy. The way that those particulars fill out the space that they occupy is determined by the stuff from which it is made, and how that stuff is arranged throughout that space. There are different notions of spatial boundary that have application to spatial particulars. There are the spatial boundaries of complete space-occupying particulars. The spatial boundaries of space-occupying particulars cannot be mere sets of spatial points, or spatial locations, at least where those locations are understood as determined by an absolute frame of reference. The spatial boundaries of a particular move when the space-occupying particular whose boundary it is moves. But the relevant set of points in an absolute space or a set of spatial locations in such a space does not. Against the idea that such spatial boundaries can be identified with any set of points in space, whether determined with respect to an absolute or relative frame of reference, is the fact that the spatial boundaries of a space-occupying particular have spatial locations. It is unclear how such boundaries can have a spatial location if they are identical with these locations. Spatial boundaries are understandable in terms of the notion of a particular kind of change. If there is a space-occupying particular, O, from p1, p2 . . . pn, then the set of places p1, p2 . . . pn is the set of places at which there is a change in the way that space is occupied; from the presence of that spatial particular to its absence. Spatial boundaries are, at least, changes in the pattern of distribution of space-occupying stuff that constitutes an object, from its presence something I don’t take a view on here. See Daniel W. Graham, Clarendon Aristotle Series: Aristotle’s Physics Book 8 (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1999), 191–2. THE MATTER OF EVENTS 19 to its absence. The stuff of which a particular is made is absent at the position of the temporal boundary (or the set of places that is the set of places at which the boundary is located) because a position (or set of places) is not within a region of space throughout which the relevant stuff is present. Understanding a spatial boundary of a complete spatial particular as a change in the occupation of space does not entail that the change is something that occurs in time. Where the spatial boundary is the spatial boundary of a complete spatial particular, the change consists in the fact that there is spaceoccupying stuff that composes a complete O throughout the region p1, p2, p3 . . . px, and there is a region around p1, p2, p3 . . . px such that there is no space-occupying stuff that composes an O within that region. There are also the spatial boundaries between the nondetached spatial parts of complete space-occupying particulars. There are different ways that this notion might be understood, corresponding to which are two different ways of determining a spatial part of a complete space-occupying particular. First, there is the spatial boundary between nondetached spatial parts of a particular, where those spatial parts are determined by features of, or properties of, the complete spatial particular; for example, the spatial boundary between the stem and the roots of a particular plant, or the boundary between the neck and the upper torso of a particular human being. Alternatively, there may be the spatial boundary between the nondetached spatial parts of a spatial particular where the relevant notion of spatial parthood is determined, not by features of the complete particular, but just by distinctions within the region of space that the particular occupies (where this spatial region is determined with respect to the spatial boundaries of the spatial particular, rather than by its position in absolute space). So, in this sense, there may be the spatial boundary between that spatial part of the object that falls within (occupies) p1, p2 . . . pn, and that spatial part of the object that falls within (occupies) p3, p4 . . . px. An ontology of this kind affords a suggestion for filling out the suggested analogy between spatial and temporal notions. Events understood as dated, particular occurrences, which occupy durations of time, are temporal particulars. Events in this sense are particular, completed, quantities of time-occupying stuff. These time-occupying 20 THOMAS CROWTHER temporal particulars are distinct from time-occupying stuffs. They are countable, and cannot be mass-quantified. There can be more than one walk or more than one walk to the shops. There cannot be more 30 (a) walk or less (a) walk to the shops. Events are not identical with stuffs, whether walking or walking to the shops; they are temporal particulars that are composed of, or made out of, these time-occupying stuffs. A particular walk that I walked this morning is not identical with walking, but constituted from the process of walking. A walk from t1 to t2 is a particular that fills out the period of time it occupies, and fills it out in being constituted from time-occupying stuff— walking—that fills it out. The analogy with spatial notions yields a corresponding conception of the category of achievements modelled in terms of the notion of a spatial boundary. Achievements are temporal boundaries. And there are distinct types of temporal boundary that are relevant to the case of complete temporal particulars. One type of temporal boundary is the temporal boundary of a bounded temporal particular. By analogy with the corresponding spatial notion, the boundaries of temporal particulars are not times, but are located at times. A temporal boundary of a temporal particular is a change in the occupation of time by the time-occupying stuffs of which temporal particulars are constituted: from the presence of that stuff to its absence. Any time at which there is such a change is not a time at which the stuff from which the relevant particular is made is present; for (contrary to (U)) there is not a region of time that t falls within such that there is time-occupying stuff throughout that region. This class of temporal boundaries consists of starts or stops of processes or accomplishments. As well as the temporal boundaries of complete temporal particulars, there are temporal boundaries between the nondetached temporal parts of those temporal particulars. Some of these temporal parts of temporal particulars are determined by 30 Such events are also sometimes picked out as a particular walking or a particular walking to the shops. Again, here, there cannot be more than one walking or more than one walking to the shops. This, clearly, does not impugn the sense in which what things are doing cannot be countquantifiable. For walking and walking to the shops here are referents of general nouns that are those things that were or will be done or completed by some agent, not what someone was or will be doing. THE MATTER OF EVENTS 21 features or properties of the things which unfold over a period of time. There is the achievement which is the temporal boundary between particular temporal parts of the building of a bookcase, where that boundary is intelligible in terms of the change from a phase of correctly positioning the sides of the bookcase with relation to the top and bottom, to banging nails into wood. This is a change between temporal phases of the event, because the accomplishments out of which the event is constituted are distinct types of accomplishment. Alternatively, there are the temporal parts of the building of the bookcase which are merely the changes from the phase of activity that occurs from t1-t2, to that which occurs from t2-t3. Here, the boundaries are the starts and stops of phases of activity, nondetached temporal parts of the event, where those phases are determined just by the fact that we can distinguish periods of time within the duration of time over which the temporal particular occurred. IV Different categories of spatial particulars differ in their boundary conditions. And this difference provides a clue to the nature of the temporal distinction between processes and accomplishments. In discussing the putative homogeneity of processes, Barry Taylor writes: “[J]ust as every three-dimensional spatial area within a lump of homogeneous gold is itself such a lump of gold, so every period within 31 a period of falling is itself a period of falling.” Now, there is a reading according to which this is obviously false. It is simply not true that every three-dimensional spatial area within a lump of gold is a lump of gold. Every three-dimensional spatial area within a lump of gold is an 32 area in which there is a nondetached part of a lump of gold. What is correct, though, is that there is a sense in which the spatial boundaries of lumps, piles, heaps, chunks, pieces, bits, and blobs, of stuff are promiscuous in the way that the spatial boundaries of gold rings, horses, trees, and statues of Venus pulling on a slipper, are not. 31 Taylor, Modes of Occurrence: Verbs, Adverbs and Events, 70. I here assume that the spatial boundary of the lump of gold itself does not count as a spatial area within the lump. 32 22 THOMAS CROWTHER According to our earlier discussion, a spatial boundary of a quantity of substance-stuff is a change in the occupation of space from spaceoccupying stuff to its absence. Spatial boundaries are located at the places at which there are such changes, the places at which there is a change from some to no more space-occupying stuff of the relevant kind. Then, any set of points in space at which there is a change in the occupation of space from the presence of a certain kind of stuff, say, bronze, to its absence, is the location of a spatial boundary of a lump of, or a piece of, bronze. But it is not the case that any set of points in space that are the locations of a spatial boundary of the presence of bronze can be the spatial boundary of a bronze statue of Venus pulling on a slipper. It may be that the spatial boundary is the boundary of half of a bronze statue of Venus pulling on a slipper, or of a bronze foot, or of a bronze doorknocker. Though lumps of bronze and bronze statues are both space-occupying particular things, that is, they are bounded and discrete entities made of space-occupying stuff, they have different completion conditions. Any boundary, of the presence of bronze and its absence, completes a lump of bronze. But it is not the case that every change in the occupation of space by bronze completes 33 a bronze statue of Venus. The fact that not every collection of points at which there stops being bronze completes a bronze statue of Venus is a consequence of the fact that, in order to be a statue of Venus, the stuff of which it is made—the bronze—must be organized in the right way. In the case of an artificial kind like a statue of Venus, there is potentially a quite complex account that needs to be given about what is required for the satisfaction of completion conditions; about what the sortal principle of identity and individuation for particulars of that kind involve. Such a statue must have the right shape; where its having that shape consists, at least in part, of having nondetached spatial parts which are shaped in the right ways and which relate to one another in the right way. In addition, the particular must be a statue; so, it must be the product of a particular kind of activity on the part of a producer. I 33 This can be expressed in terms of a point about the division of the relevant thing. Carve away at a lump of bronze however one likes and one will be left with lumps of bronze. But not any carving away at a statue of Venus results in a statue of Venus. THE MATTER OF EVENTS 23 34 leave these details aside. In the case of natural kinds like trees, cats, and dogs, the stuff of which those things are composed is organized according to certain functional constraints involving characteristic patterns of material coherence at a time, and over time, and distinctive 35 patterns of reproduction, amongst other things. For all such spatial particulars, even if filling out space in a certain way may not be sufficient for the existence of such a thing (plausibly, things like bronze statues of Venus and Vermeer’s View of Delft), space must be filled out in a certain way in order for such a complete spatial 36 particular to be present at a place. And, again, it is the sortal concept or principle of explanation for things of that kind that determines how it is that the matter must be organized and must fill out space for a particular of that kind to be present. In light of this, a natural thought is that processes and accomplishments are to be understood as temporal analogues of the spatial distinction between a particular that is a mere lump of F, and a particular that is a G made of F, where Gs require F to be organized in 37 a characteristic way. The temporal boundaries of a period of ing are the times at which there is a change in the occupation of time from the presence of ing to its absence. Those boundaries are the achievements which 34 See here David Wiggins, Sameness and Substance Renewed (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001), chapter 3, sections 3–5. 35 See ibid., chapters 2 and 3. 36 There are many further issues raised here that I cannot address here. It is not implausible that the same thing is true of sortally-individuated Aristotelian primary substances. An accidental arrangement of spaceoccupying stuff in the physical form of a human being is not obviously a human being. Perhaps it is essential that a human being has a certain kind of parental and genotypic origin. I make no commitment here about how this issue is to be resolved. What is necessary at this point is only the claim that a certain type of spatial form is necessary. I note only that the necessity of a certain kind of origin does not make all such particulars artifacts, particulars of artifactual kinds having an essential explanation in terms of the intentions or aims of rational agents. 37 Taylor in Modes of Occurrence: Verbs, Adverbs and Events, 70, writes: “[F]alling delimits time as a homogeneous stuff fills space, whereas stabbing delimits time as a substance delimits space.” This is suggestive, but not quite the account I endorse here. It is a stabbing that delimits time as a substance delimits space. 24 THOMAS CROWTHER constitute the starts and stops of a period of ing. Then, where ing is a process, any set of temporal boundaries of ing are the boundaries of a complete event; a temporal particular made of ing. For example, if S starts walking at t1 and stops walking at tn, then there is a complete event, a walk, that S has walked (or that has occurred) such that t1 and tn constitute its temporal boundaries. Particular events which are composed of processes are temporal chunks or lumps—stretches—of the temporal stuff that is process. But where ing is an accomplishment, the completion of a requires not just that there are temporal boundaries which are starts and stops of ing, but requires that the period of ing has a particular set of temporal boundaries. If S starts walking to the shops at t and stops walking to the shops at tn, it is not necessarily the case that there is a complete walk to the shops that S has walked such that t1 and tn are the temporal boundaries of an event that is a walk to the shops. What may have been completed is only an event that is part of a walk to the shops; an event that is constituted by a process or an accomplishment that is a subprocess or subaccomplishment of a walk to the shops. Accomplishments, then, are the temporal analogues of sortally governed spatial particulars, like gold medals or gold statues of Venus pulling on a slipper. What is distinctive about accomplishments, in contrast to events, is that the temporal stuff that constitutes the putative accomplishment has to take a particular, restricted, temporal form. If we understand the nature of the spatial form that spaceoccupying spatial particulars need to take as determined by the nature of the sortal principle for things of that kind, correspondingly, we can understand the nature of the temporal form that accomplishments need to possess as determined by a temporal sortal principle for things of that kind. The temporal sortals for accomplishments are principles of explanation for complete events of a certain kind that contain, at least, information about what the beginnings and ends of a particular event must be like to be an event of that kind, and which incorporate restrictions on what kinds of events of starting and stopping can constitute the points of completion of events of this kind. Suppose we take it that what makes a kind artifactual is that particulars of that kind have to be made from an activity deriving from, or explained in terms of, the intentions or aims of rational agents. Then, it is plausible to think that in the temporal case, as in the spatial THE MATTER OF EVENTS 25 case, there is a distinction between artifactual and natural kinds. There are some accomplishments, like the fall of some particular cherry stone to the ground at some date and time, the temporal form of which is determined by temporal sortals which are nonartifactual or natural; the completion conditions for such occurrences are determined by what occurrences are necessary for the satisfaction of the reproductive functions of the type of organism from which the stone falls, reproductive functions which are constitutive of a cherry tree being the type of thing it is. There are other accomplishments, say, the convoluted flight of a heat-seeking missile that eventually achieves its proper destructive end, that are a kind of accomplishment the principle of identity of which is artifactual; involving essential reference to the intentions or aims of the designers of the missile and its software. It is facts about the programmers of the software that controls the flight of such missiles that determines how the flight of such missiles ought to begin, and how it ought to terminate. On this view, given the simple criterion offered for something’s being an artifactual particular, the intentional or agential bodily actions of rational agents would also appear to count as artifactual particulars. Bodily actions necessarily involve movements of the agent’s body, but they are movements explicable in terms of the intentions or aims of the rational agent. Assessing and developing this idea would take me well beyond the scope of this paper. I note only that there need not be much that is controversial about such a suggestion, at least, given that I here understand “explicable in terms of the intentions or aims of a 38 rational agent” in a relatively unrestricted way. At the core of this approach is the fact that lumps of stuff, whether spatial or temporal, are particulars, and so that the category extends further than those particulars which possess boundary 39 conditions restricted by the nature of things of that kind. The 38 Of course, any satisfying development of this suggestion would distinguish between the way that the intentional bodily actions of human beings are explained by their intentions or aims and the completely different way that the intentions of programmers explain the movements of heatseeking missiles. 39 A failure to acknowledge this, I maintain, is a difficulty in the account offered in Mourelatos, “Events, Processes and States.” Though Mourelatos does say that “all and only event predications are equivalent to count- 26 THOMAS CROWTHER proposals need refining and developing, and not all of that can be undertaken here. But in advance of such refinement, it is helpful to clarify some distinct notions of a lump (or a chunk, or a piece) relevant to this analogy between spatial and temporal notions. One might distinguish between the notions of a lump and a mere lump. Something is a lump of F (or a quantity of F) in the liberal sense if and only if it is a complete, spatially bounded particular made of F. Particulars which have restrictive boundary conditions imposed by their natures qualify as lumps in this liberal sense. But contrasting with this is the notion of a mere lump, or a lump in the formal sense. Something is a mere lump of F if and only if it is a complete, spatially bounded particular made of F, and it does not possess restrictive boundary conditions for the occupancy of space or time in virtue of its nature. Mere lumps of F are disorganized or nonorganized quantities of F just in the sense that they do not fall under sortal predicates that determine restrictive boundary conditions for them. That a particular, a, is a mere lump of F is consistent with it possessing parts that do fall under sortal predicates that determine restrictive boundary conditions, as some mere lumps of space-occupying stuff may be nonhomogeneous, and have such particulars as parts. quantified existential constructions” (Ibid. 429), he also implies that as they are relevant to events, these count-quantified constructions are of a particular type, one that rules out individuation through “extrinsic containers.” This is what Mourelatos is most naturally read as saying, when he writes: “[E]vents are not merely countable but also fall under sorts that provide a principle of count . . . events thus occupy relatively to other situations a position analogous to the one objects or things or substances occupy relatively to stuffs and properties and qualities” (Ibid., 430). On the most natural reading of this, “substances” is to be read as “Aristotelian primary substances” (horses, dogs, trees) rather than as, say, “lumps of clay,” or “lumps of bronze and silver.” Given this view, then, an event for Mourelatos is to be understood as a “completed accomplishment.” If that is right, then the temporal ontology that he presents is incomplete. The intuition that drives Mourelatos’s discussion is that there is a distinction between mass and particular in the case of spatial notions, and that this is applicable to the temporal case. But now it appears that there is no room for the thought that bounded stretches and phases of process, like a walk around that went on for a few minutes, are complete temporal particulars too. A walk around, or a stretch of walking around is not stuff, but a bounded quantity of it. THE MATTER OF EVENTS 27 Sortal concepts for space-occupying particulars determine what is proper or correct for those particulars; it is essential to conceiving of a particular as being made of space-occupying stuff that has the form determined by some particular sortal concept that there is then a condition of correctness determined by that sortal in terms of which the relevant particular is susceptible of evaluation. A particular that is only a half of a bronze statue of Venus pulling on a slipper is incomplete, and, in the relevant sense, defective. That particular is not how a complete statue of that kind ought to be. There is a constitutive connection between being evaluable in the light of the principle and there being something made of the relevant organized stuff at that place. In the case of space-occupying spatial particulars, what it is for there to be some space-occupying stuff organized according to the sortal principle for a particular kind of thing, F, at a point in space, is just for there to be, at that point, something that can be evaluated in terms of the correctness condition for a complete F. If the correctness condition is met, there is a complete F at that point in space. If the correctness condition is not met, there is an incomplete F at that point in space. What it is for there to be stuff organized according to the sortal principle for Fs, and so assessable for completeness or incompleteness in the light of that principle, is potentially a highly variable and context-relative matter. As we have seen, some of these sortal principles may be artifactual, though some are no doubt natural. Similarly, sortal concepts for temporal particulars determine what is correct for those particulars. A stretch of walking to the shops which is only a walk to the front door is incomplete, and so improper or defective. It is not how a complete walk to the shops should be. As in the case of spatial particulars, there is a constitutive connection between being assessable as either complete or incomplete in the light of a particular sortal condition for Fs, and there being, at the relevant point in time, a quantity of time-occupying stuff arranged in an F-like way. In the light of this discussion of completion and correctness as it applies to accomplishments and Aristotelian primary substances, it might appear strained to describe lumps as having liberal completion conditions, or to describe them as possessing boundary conditions, or completion conditions which are unrestricted. If the function of a boundary condition or a completion condition is just to determine 28 THOMAS CROWTHER what counts as correct, then it may seem problematic that there is no such thing as an incorrect boundary for a mere lump, or no such thing as an incomplete lump. But isn’t it the case that there is correctness, or a correctness condition, only where there is the possibility of incorrectness? This need not be a worry. In the case of mere lumps or pieces or blobs of F, the applicability of the notion of correctness or propriety in the case of boundaries derives from the notion of what is permitted, by the nature of what kind of particular is in question, with respect to these boundaries. That a boundary for a spatial particular which is a mere lump of F completes a mere lump of F (and so is correct for a lump) does not entail that there must be something it is for it to be an incomplete lump, for that this boundary completes the F is that it is a boundary which is permitted for lumps. And that there is a boundary which is permitted does not entail that some boundaries are not permitted. (By contrast, we could think of the completion conditions for accomplishments and Aristotelian primary substances as determining correctness conditions that take something like the form of obligations). At the outset, in discussion of one proposed way of thinking of the idea of an accomplishment, I discussed the possibility that the de facto starting and stopping points of a stretch of process might automatically count as terminal points or telic points, in a sense that would make such a stretch of process (and thereby any stretch of process) an accomplishment. Call “walking from A to B” in this sense, a resultant accomplishment. Resultant accomplishments do not count as genuine accomplishments because it is not possible to conceive of them as stretches of process organized around a principle that determines conditions of correctness in the way it does for genuine accomplishments. Suppose S merely walked from t1 to t2, but that S walked from A to B during that time. Then it is true that what S was doing during that time was, in the relevant resultant accomplishment sense, walking from A to B. But that he was walking from A to B at some time between t1 and t2 is not for there to be temporal stuff at that time organized around the telic goal completed in walks from A to B. For walking from A to B in this sense is not governed by a correctness condition that allows for evaluations of what transpires in terms of a success or failure to meet the conditions required for complete events of the kind: a walk from A to B. There are no THE MATTER OF EVENTS 29 incomplete walks from A to B where walking from A to B is a resultant accomplishment, and where “incomplete” indicates “not as required by the nature of the event-type to which it belongs.” What could such an incomplete event be? Just the traversing of only half the distance to B? But that cannot be correct. This would leave it obscure why such a walk is an incomplete walk to B rather than to other points intermediate between the point of termination of the walk and B, or to C or to D or to E, and so forth. V In the first section of the paper, I argued that some familiar criteria suggested as ways of distinguishing between process and accomplishment face difficulties. But these suggested criteria appear to latch onto recognizable features of process and accomplishment to some degree. It is significant that it is possible to articulate what is correct about these different suggestions about the distinction between process and accomplishments in light of the idea that there is a distinction between the completion conditions of processes and accomplishments. Homogeneity. In introducing the idea of a distinction in completion conditions, I have already suggested that this thought captures something of the intuition behind the idea of the homogeneity of process in comparison with accomplishment. If ing is a process, then whenever ing starts and stops, those starts and stops are the boundaries of a complete . In the case of process, had t1 and t10 been points at which ing started and then stopped, there would be a complete temporal particular which is a stretch of ing. There is a different way to illuminate this idea, in terms of notions drawn from related features of the category of mass. Though time-occupying and space-occupying stuff cannot be count quantified, it can be mass quantified. Though there cannot be two stuff(s) or more than one stuff(s)—at least where “stuff” refers to stuff itself rather than to types of stuff—there can be some stuff, more stuff, and enough stuff. In the light of this idea, what appears to underpin the homogeneity of process is that, in the case of a process, if there is some ing from t1t10, then necessarily there is enough ing from t1-t10 for a complete (even if, because the ing may not yet have stopped, there is not a 30 THOMAS CROWTHER complete ). That is true even for processes like walking and waltzing that are nonhomogeneous according to (H) above. If there is some walking from t1-t10, there must be enough walking from t1-t10 for there to be a complete walk from t1-t10 (even if there is not a complete walk because the walking has not yet terminated). Accomplishments are nonhomogeneous in this sense, in that the positioning of the boundaries of the relevant time-occupying stuff, as well as its mode of organization, must meet certain conditions for there to be enough ing for a complete event of that kind to occur; for there to be some ing is not for there to be enough ing for a . Whether there is enough of the relevant stuff is dependent on whether the requirements for boundaries determined by the sortal principle are met. Cumulativity and quantization. There were difficulties in thinking that complete stretches of processes are cumulative or upwardly homogeneous in the sense that they could simply be added together to produce stretches of processes of the same kind. I have already explained the difficulties with the notion of cumulativity when explained in this way. I also noted that the view that the unfolding of a process consists of phases of that process that can each have the same character of the unfolding whole will not be sufficient to distinguish process from accomplishment. But there is something correct about the idea that processes are cumulative in a way that accomplishments are not, that can again be illuminated by the analogy with notions of mass and a compositional ontology. An idea implicit in the discussion of homogeneity immediately above was that, if there is enough walking from t1-t10 for a complete event of walking (a complete walk), it does not follow that there is a complete walk from t1-t10. The walking that went on from t1-t10 may be a nondetached temporal part of a walk that went on from t1-t20. But in the case of accomplishments, if there is enough walking to the shops from t1-t10 for a complete walk to the shops, there must be a complete walk to shops that took place from t1-t10. If there is enough walking to the shops from t1-t10 for a walk to the shops, then this walking cannot be a nondetached temporal part of a complete walk to the shops that extends beyond those intervals. These facts about what is entailed by having enough process or accomplishment for a complete particular of the relevant kind are reflected in the fact that, if there is enough walking from t1-t10 for a complete walk, it does not THE MATTER OF EVENTS 31 follow that S stopped walking at t (it does not follow that t1 or t10 are the temporal boundaries of a complete stretch of walking), whereas if there was enough walking to the shops from t1-t10 for a complete walk to the shops, t10 is of necessity a point at which there was the termination of (the later temporal boundary of) the walk to the shops. So process, by contrast with accomplishment, can accumulate in the sense that, if there is enough walking for a complete walk from t1-t10, then further phases of this walk can accumulate from t10 onwards. A related way to express the idea that process is cumulative, by contrast with accomplishment, concerns differences in the way that processes and accomplishments relate to another mass quantifier as a consequence of the facts just noted. Given the fact that, if there is enough walking from t1-t10 for a complete event of walking, then that does not entail that there is a complete walk from t1-t10, it follows that, if there is more walking after t10, it is not necessarily the case that there is another walk that occurs after t10. It could just be the continuation of the same walk. On the other hand, if there is enough walking to the shops from t1-t10 for a complete event of walking to the shops, then any more walking to the shops after t10 would have to constitute a different, another, walk to the shops. Progress and the imperfective paradox. In exploring suggestions about how to distinguish between process and accomplishment, it was suggested that in the case of accomplishments, from the fact that O is ing at t, it follows that O has not yet ed at t, but that in the case of processes, if O is ing at t, O has ed at t. This is the phenomenon that has come to be known as the imperfective paradox. Different features of this data might be picked out as an imperfective paradox that is in need of explanation. The first is the apparent contrast between the entailment and failure of entailment in the process and accomplishment cases. A second feature in need of explanation is how it can be that, in the case of accomplishments, something can be ing at t, and not only has not ed by t, but will not at all. What is particularly in need of explanation is the fact that the introduction of the idea of a process of ing appears to involve the idea of a particular event unfolding, a , and yet the occurrence of ing is consistent with the nonexistence of the that is unfolding. Yet, how then are we to make sense of the notion of the unfolding of a which may never 32 THOMAS CROWTHER exist? How, indeed, are we to make sense of the notion of progress or unfolding at all? In connection with the first of these features, it has already been noted that the pattern of entailment is not indicative. There are nonhomogeneous processes. So something can be ing even though it has not yet ed (walking, chuckling, and so forth). But there are features of processes and accomplishments that emerge from the temporal ontology sketched out here that the pattern of entailment reflects. Given an agent who is walking to the shops at t, then were that agent to have stopped walking to the shops at t, there would not have been a complete walk to the shops at t. But given an agent walking at t, were that agent to have stopped walking at t, then necessarily there would be a walk that was completed (a complete stretch of walking). Again, the existence of nonhomogeneous processes does not have an impact on this difference between the respective modes of time-occupation. Suppose we then focus on the second feature of the data. If the question is how it can be that it may be that an accomplishment is going on at a time though it will not be complete, the suggestion pursued here is that this is to be understood in terms of the idea that there is a requirement on the unfolding of such an accomplishment, determined by the nature of the particular event that is unfolding, such that the unfolding that occurs is subject to that requirement for its completion condition, even though it will fail to meet that requirement for completion. Suppose that the question is how this can be explained, given that, in the case of accomplishments, a appears to be in progress, though there isn’t and won’t be a . Here, I can offer only some brief suggestions about how the ontology sketched here allows us to make some distinctive suggestions about this complex issue, and repeat that a study of the relations between these ideas about temporal ontology and the claims advanced within formal semantics of the progressive and perfective aspect will be undertaken in further work. The analogy with spatial notions is instructive again here. Spaceoccupying stuffs necessarily occupy regions of space. If there is bronze at p, then there is bronze throughout a region of space within which p is contained. But if there is a region of space throughout which there is bronze, within which p is contained, then there is a THE MATTER OF EVENTS 33 space-occupying particular at p which is made of bronze. Spaceoccupying stuff, then, is what bounded space-occupying particulars are made of. But the space-occupying particular that is made of bronze, which is present at p, may vary depending on whether the bronze that is present is organized in any way or not. It may be that p falls within a region of space throughout which there is bronze, given that it falls within a region of space occupied by a mere lump of bronze, that is, a quantity of bronze not organized any way at all. Yet it may be that there is bronze at p, and a region throughout which there is bronze which contains p, in virtue of the fact that there is a particular present at p which is made of bronze organized according to the sortal statue of Venus balancing on one foot pulling on her slipper. If there is a particular present at p which is made of bronze organized according to that sortal, then there is either, at that location, a complete statue of Venus pulling on her slipper. or a particular which is a part of such a statue, a bronze upper torso bent over in concentration, say. If there is bronze at p, then what spatial particular is present at p is determined by what is present in a region of space that surrounds p, and how that bronze is organized throughout that region. For any set of regions of space around p, that region will not determine what it is that is present and made of bronze at p, unless that region is the set of points in space that marks the boundary of the space occupied by a spatial particular made of bronze (a set of points at which there is a change from there being something at that point made of bronze to there not being anything at that point which is made of bronze). The set of points in space that marks the boundary of the space occupied by a spatial particular made of bronze is not necessarily a set of points beyond which there is no more bronze. Something may be made of bronze even if bronze is only one of the space-occupying stuffs of which it is made. So there is something made of bronze present at p if there is a statue of Venus at p which is made of a bronze torso, but which has wooden limbs and a wooden head. In a structurally identical way, if there is ing at t, then there is a period of time within which t falls throughout which there is ing. In the same way that there cannot be bronze merely at a location p, if there is something processively unfolding at t, then there must be a period of time over which that thing is unfolding. But where there is 34 THOMAS CROWTHER ing over a period of time that contains t, then there is some temporal particular which is made of ing—that is, an event which is made of ing—which occurs at t, and which has temporal boundaries that occupy a region of time within which t is contained. If there is ing at t, then there may be a temporal particular made of ing that occurs at t in virtue of the fact that ing is an unorganized process, and that there is a temporal particular the boundaries of which contain t, that is, a mere stretch (a temporal lump) of ing. But in the case of accomplishments, the event made of ing which occurs at t, the temporal boundaries of which contain t, may be either a complete , or a which is a temporal particular which is part of a . For example, if there is walking to the shops at t, then at t there is walking organized according to the end of getting to the shops. If there is walking organized according to the end of getting to the shops at t, then there must be a region of time occupied by walking organized in that way. And if there is a duration occupied by walking organized with the end of getting to the shops, then there must be a bounded temporal particular made of walking organized according to that end that occurs at t. But this event may be a completed walk to the shops, or it may be an event which is merely a walk halfway to the shops; a walk which is only a part of a walk to the shops. So for there to be something progressively unfolding at a time requires the occurrence of an event at that time. There cannot be time-occupying stuff at a time without a time-occupying particular occurring at that time. But the nature of the event, the occurrence of which is required for there to be the progressive unfolding of something, is determined through the notion of composition by time-occupying stuff; it is a temporal particular made of such progressively unfolding material. Incomplete accomplishments, as well as complete accomplishments, are made of progressively unfolding material; organized processes, or processes that possess a temporal form provided by a temporal sortal or temporal principle of individuation for complete events of that kind. If the core of the imperfective paradox is that something can be progressively unfolding, without its being the case that there will be a complete event of the relevant kind, even though there must be some completed events introduced by the idea that ing is going on then it is these facts that explain it. It is true that, for something to be going on—whether process or accomplishment—there must exist temporal THE MATTER OF EVENTS 35 particulars, which are, necessarily, bounded and complete temporal items. But if ing is going on, then the temporal particular that is required to exist simply by the nature of the unfolding of ing is a temporal particular that is made of, or composed of, ing, not a temporal particular which is a . In the case in which the completion conditions for events of the type are not met, these particulars are temporal particulars which are temporal parts of events of the relevant 40 kind. In light of these ideas, we can then suggest the following modest account of progress: that for ing to be in progress or to be unfolding at t—whether it is process or accomplishment—is for there to be a temporal particular made of ing such that t falls within its temporal boundaries, or, equivalently, for it to be the case that S started ing at some time prior to t, and S has not yet stopped ing at t. The idea of a compositional temporal ontology modelled on spatial notions, then, not only allows us to understand the distinction between process and accomplishment, but offers up attractive suggestions about other puzzling features of temporal notions. 40 In advance of further discussion specifically focused on the relationship between these metaphysical claims and a formal semantics of the progressive—which is to be undertaken elsewhere—one ought to be very cautious about taking these metaphysical claims to immediately generate consequences for any semantic theory of the progressive. However, were the contours of the account here mirrored in a formal semantic treatment, they might seem to suggest an account according to which the truth of any sentence in the progressive at a time does entail the truth of a sentence that reports that there is a complete event that occurs at that time. That would appear to mark such a position out as an event theory of the progressive. (See Landman, “The Progressive”; Terence Parsons, Events in the Semantics of English, amongst others.) By contrast with more familiar event theories though, the account that might seem to suggest itself couldn’t be construed as an attempt to explain the truth conditions of the progressive in terms of the perfective without progressive remainder. The idea of something unfolding in a certain way (so, of the truth of a sentence with progressive aspect) figures essentially in determining what complete event it is the existence of which is entailed by the progressive. Any such semantics would also be distinctive in according a central place to temporal mass predications in determining the relations between the progressive and perfective. 36 THOMAS CROWTHER VI I want to draw the paper to a conclusion through raising a worry about the existence of an analogy between spatial and temporal notions. It might be said that, in the case of space-occupying, spatiallybounded particulars, there is a clear rationale for supposing that there are space-occupying stuffs from which those particulars are made. A space-occupying spatial particular can be composed of different matter at different times at which it exists. So, a statue may be composed of marble at t, and after renovation, at t + n, it is composed of imitation marble. Space-occupying particulars can be subject to distinctive kinds of changes, or, they can persist through certain kinds of change, and distinguishing between a particular and what it is made 41 of is what enables this to be explained. The notion of composition has application to spatial particulars in virtue of there being modal facts about spatial particulars that need to be explained: that there are kinds of changes in properties that they are capable of undergoing while remaining the same. But there are no modal facts of this kind about particular events, because events cannot change their 42 properties; they possess all of their properties necessarily. What it would be for the Battle of Waterloo to have turned out differently, for example, would be for there to have occurred a numerically different battle from that which did occur, that shared many of its properties, but diverged in some. But in the absence of the possibility of change, those modal facts that motivate a compositional ontology in the case of space-occupying spatial particulars are absent from the temporal case. That leaves it simply mysterious what the motivation is for drawing on the notion of constitution in connection with notions of time-occupation. 41 A further thought might be that we can distinguish between a spaceoccupying spatial particular and the stuff of which it is made because the stuff of which something is made can outlast the spatial particular that it composes, or constitutes. The statue cannot be identical with the piece of clay, because the statue may go out of existence while the piece of clay persists. 42 For this view see, for example, Donald Davidson, “Thinking Causes,” in Mental Causation, ed. John Heil and Alfred R. Mele (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1993), 3–17; and Michael R. Ayers, Locke, 2 vols. (London: Routledge, 1991), 104–5. THE MATTER OF EVENTS 37 But it cannot be that the very rationale for the applicability of the notion of composition in the spatial case derives from the idea of changes in what something is composed of over a period of time. The idea of a change in composition of a spatial particular presupposes the applicability of the notion of composition to such a particular. A more basic rationale for the idea of the composition of a spatial particular by space-occupying stuff is simply that for there to be some bounded spatial particular at a place in space or throughout a region of space is not just for there to be a set of places or positions which delimits a region of space, which is the spatial boundary of a particular. For that will not distinguish between there being a space-occupying spatial particular at that place, and a hole in a space-occupying particular at that place. For there to be a space-occupying spatial particular that occupies that region of space is for space to be filled out in a certain way throughout that region of space, where for space to be filled out in a certain way is inconsistent with it being empty, that is, not filled out at all, or filled out with something else. The idea of the composition of particulars from stuff seems to have its ultimate grounding in these basic metaphysical intuitions. And these basic intuitions are as much applicable to the temporal case as they are to the spatial case. For a temporal particular, which is the doing of something by some agent, to exist over a bounded period of time tx-tn is not just for tx-tn to be the temporal boundaries of a temporal particular. For a temporal particular to exist from tx-tn is for the time from tx-tn to be filled out in a certain way, where that excludes it not being filled out at all, that is, for the agent of the action to have been doing nothing, and excludes it being filled out in other ways, that is, excludes the agent’s having been doing something else. It is true that there are differences in the way that facts about the notion of composition are manifest across the spatial and temporal cases. The kind of feature of spatial particulars raised in the initial worry is one of these. But that is because the analogy that has been used here is a structural metaphysical analogy that holds between things which are of importantly different metaphysical kinds. Spatial and temporal particulars are not identical kinds of particulars. Spatial particulars do not have a temporal mode of existence; they do not unfold over a period of time, as temporal particulars do. So the way that the natures of spatial and temporal particulars determine 38 THOMAS CROWTHER boundary conditions for particulars of the relevant kinds, and the facts about composition and boundaries that are consistent with their having the natures that they have, will be correspondingly different, given these basic difference in mode of time-occupation. These claims about the differences in the mode of occupation of time by spatial and temporal particulars, and that spatial and temporal particulars are of distinct kinds, are, of course, controversial, and defending them would require serious engagement with arguments in favour of a fourdimensionalist ontology. The relevant point here, however, is that at least if one takes a naïve metaphysics of spatial and temporal particulars seriously, according to which there is a distinction between these kinds of particulars, then it can be no argument against the analogy that there are differences in the way that these different features are realized. Even granting this, it is worth noting just how much similarity there is between the realizations of these structural features across the cases. It is true that the nature of a temporal sortal does not provide information about what changes a bounded temporal particular is capable of undergoing, where these changes are changes in the properties of an atemporal thing that persists whole over a period of time. Nevertheless, it is true that a temporal particular can be made of different stuff at different phases of its existence; the very same birthday party may have been composed of the exchange of small talk at t1-t2, and debauchery at t8-t10. Temporal particulars may have temporal profiles across a period of time, during which there can be changes in the way that time is occupied, where the changes consistent with their composing the same event or not over that time are determined by the nature of events of that kind. That is itself a significant further analogy with the spatial case. I have tried to argue that a temporal ontology that is based on a more fully developed analogy between spatial and temporal notions reveals a plausible way of understanding the distinction between process and accomplishment. The idea that there is a metaphysical distinction between temporal stuffs and the things they are constituted out of, as well as the idea of a distinction between whether timeoccupying stuff is organized by a restrictive temporal sortal or not, will both stand and fall, ultimately, on how much philosophical explanation these ideas enable us to do. I have then tried to motivate the idea that certain puzzling notions within temporal ontology can be better THE MATTER OF EVENTS 39 understood in light of such an ontology. Though the discussion can only be developed here so far, it is to be hoped that it provides a number of pointers for the direction in which further research is to be 43 pursued. Heythrop College, University of London 43 I am grateful to Mark Sainsbury for conversations about spaceoccupying stuffs that sparked my interest in the lines of thought pursued in this paper. For helpful comments and discussion thanks are due to Mark Eli Kalderon, Michael Martin, Ian Phillips, Mark Textor, Rory Madden, Matthew Manning, David Papineau, and Rowland Stout. Particular thanks are due to Jennifer Hornsby, Matthew Soteriou, and Guy Longworth for extensive discussion and written comments on earlier drafts of this paper. Any errors are mine.