Abstracts 44th Annual Meeting of the Western Canadian Philosophical Association: 100 Years of Pragmatism University of Saskatchewan October 26-28, 2007 Pragmatism and the Normative Theory of Rationality Preston Stovall (Texas A&M University) Beiser has recently criticized Brandom’s normative reading of Kant as overlooking the problems uncovered by the early-20th century neo-Kantians. I defend Brandom’s program against Beiser’s criticisms, connecting Brandom’s work to the early-20th century pragmatists’ reconciliatory view of norms and facts. Inheriting this pragmatic conception, Brandom both avoids Beiser’s criticisms and offers an important analysis of philosophy’s engagement with culture. This paper illustrates how Brandom’s normative program impels us to derive a should from a must. Assessing Rawls’s Proviso _________________________________________________ Friday, October 26 Descartes, Dewey, and the Legacy of the Spectator Theory of Knowledge: A Reassessment Adam Hutchinson (Duquesne University) John Dewey characterized the philosophy of Descartes being in the thrall of a “spectator theory of knowledge”. For Richard Rorty Dewey’s reading of Descartes is the defining moment of pragmatism: it is when pragmatism becomes another antiCartesianism. I interpret Descartes early text Rules for the Direction of Mind and reconstruct what looks like an “actor theory” of knowledge While Descartes may end up with a spectator theory in the Meditations, there is an experimentalist impulse that pragmatist readings have failed to address. Mark Capustin (University of Manitoba) In this paper I examine Rawls’s view that religious persons can feel free to present religious reasons in public debate subject to the proviso that they will be able to present, in due course, arguments grounded in public reason. I argue in some cases it is impossible to have a justified belief that the proviso can be met, though it can nevertheless be reasonable to present contentious religious or moral reasons. Revamping Reflective Equilibrium as a Dynamic System Kevin Buzinski (York University) Part of the appeal of Rawls’ notion of reflective equilibrium is that it tries to close off moral loopholes, but Rawls goes awry when he tries to fit it into a top-down approach. I suggest that taking a bottom-up approach allows us to revamp reflective equilibrium as a dynamic system. This would allow reflective equilibrium to be used as a tool by casuists or certain moral particularists who permit a role for moral principles. Gettier’s Dichotomy Definite and Indefinite Articles in Elementary Predicate Logic David Johnston (University of Victoria) It is shown that Gettier’s original counter-examples to the traditional analysis of knowledge depend upon equivocations, and consequently that these examples do not refute the traditional analysis. Two further Getter-type examples are examined, and equivocations are found in these as well. Kent Peacock (University of Lethbridge) This paper describes a way of translating into predicate notation the indefinite and definite articles "a" and "the" which occur in what Russell [9] called denoting phrases, and demonstrates some of the applications of this modest notational innovation to elementary first-order predicate logic with identity. Conventions for Illocutionary Silencing Nicole Wyatt (University of Calgary) I present a speech act theoretic account of Catherine McKinnon’s claim that pornography of certain kinds actively silences women in terms of competing and overriding conventions. Other attempts to vindicate McKinnon focused on the notion of uptake: I note various well-known problems with this analysis and show that a convention based analysis does not suffer from those same problems. Levels of Reality Patrick McGivern and Alexander Reuger (University of Alberta) According to the standard view of ‘levels of reality’ (i) levels are populated by entities of varying complexity, (ii) there is a unique hierarchy of levels, and (iii) the inhabitants of adjacent levels are related by the parthood relation. Using examples from physics, we argue that it is more natural to view the inhabitants of levels as the behaviors of entities, that levels can be ordered according to different principles, and that the parthood relation between levels is not the standard ‘spatial’ parthood relation. We suggest that this account of levels better suits examples of explanation in science. WCPA 2007 Abstracts Saturday October 27 James and Rorty on Truth and Experience R. Chase Skorburg (Harvard University) In remembrance of Richard Rorty and on the occasion of the 100th anniversary of James’s Pragmatism lectures, this essay examines James and Rorty on truth and experience. It concludes that James’s views are more compelling, despite Rorty’s claim that he largely shares James’s positions. James’s richer account of experience and sophisticated correspondence theory of truth allow him to account for the influence of subjective context in inquiry without thereby adopting Rorty’s “ironism” regarding the constraints that objects of inquiry may provide critical thought. Martinich: Up to Scratch? Derek Postnikoff (University of Saskatchewan) A.P. Martinich’s pragmatic account of metaphor is based on Grice’s theory of conversational implicature. In this paper, Martinich’s theory is argued to be deficient; in particular, the connection between the notion of a dead metaphor and the literal/figurative distinction is shown to be inadequately discussed. 2 Truth, Lies & Poetics: Collapsing the Standard-Nonstandard Distinction in Discussions of Metaphor Diana B. Heney (University of Saskatchewan) In “A Theory of Metaphor”, A.P. Martinich proposes to divide metaphors into two categories: standard and nonstandard. The purpose of this essay is twofold: to explain the distinction as Martinich sees it; and to show that such a distinction is detrimental to the philosophical study of metaphor. The discussion of several examples supports the latter point, and leads to the suggestion that a genuine taxonomy of metaphor would be more helpful than the standard-nonstandard distinction. emotion, the bearing his theory of emotion generation would have on modern approaches in psychology is hard to deny. On-Stage Illocution Peter Alward (University of Lethbridge) In this paper, I consider three theories of theatrical speech acts: the illocutionary pretense account, the sui generis theatrical illocution account, and the game model. I argue that the latter two theories run into insuperable difficulties. Finally, I develop and defend a version of the illocutionary pretense account. Reflections on Laws, Metaphysics and van Fraassen The Battle of the Absolute: Pragmatism, Pragmaticism and Spinozism Shannon Dea (University of Waterloo) Between 1904 and 1909, Peirce repeatedly identified Spinoza as a pragmatic forebear. This corresponded to Peirce’s coining of the term “pragmaticism” to distance himself from the nominalistic, anti-metaphysical variety of pragmatism then in ascendance. This essay sketches some of the similarities between Peirce and Spinoza, and some of the differences between Peirce and James through discussions of (1) Spinoza’s Peircean synechism, and (2) the so-called “Battle of the Absolute” waged by James and Royce. One Hundred Years Later: William James and the Psychology of Emotion. Joseph Palencik (University of Buffalo) This paper addresses the significance of William James’ theory of emotion in experimental psychology. While many of James’ detractors have pointed to the problems with his definition of WCPA 2007 Abstracts Bryson Brown (University of Lethbridge) Bas van Fraassen has long defended an austerely empiricist philosophy of science. To allow for the less empirical aspects of our scientific practice, van Fraassen draws a sharp line between cognitive and merely pragmatic aspects of commitment to scientific theories. However, realistic intuitions are hard to put aside. When we think of examples, certain counterfactuals (viz. ‘If I had dropped this chalk, it would have fallen to the floor’) seem straightforwardly true. The height of a flagpole, together with its geographic circumstances and the elevation of the sun, seems to explain the length of the resulting shadow, while the length of the shadow does not explain the height of the flagpole. Reconciling these intuitions with empiricist ideas about how we come to know what we know about the world is difficult. This paper generalizes an argument van Fraassen directs against the contingent relations between universals account of laws, and proposes a nonmetaphysical alternative to van Fraassen which does more justice to our attitude towards laws. 3 Underdetermination Revisited: Salvaging Feminism from the Obscurity of ‘Vicious Relativism’. Doing the Will of Beliefs: A Critical Assessment of William James’ Defense of Religious Faith Mary Butterfield (University of Victoria) My purpose in this paper is to delve into the complex nest of issues surrounding philosophy of science and epistemological agency. My focus will be on epistemology as somehow a social enterprise, drawing explicitly on the work of Lynn Nelson in her paper “Epistemological Communities”. My main opponent in this discussion is Susan Haack, most notably the monistic realism expressed in her paper “Science as Social – Yes and No”. My aim is to demonstrate that there are good reasons to reject both Haack’s monism and her account of how knowledge – particularly scientific knowledge – is acquired. I will examine Haack’s rejection of science as a social enterprise in relationship to her views about underdetermination, as well as her individualistic epistemological commitments. Nelson’s goal in “Epistemological Communities” is to uncover a middleground between empirical objectivism and judgmental relativism; I argue that Haack’s sweeping assessment of feminist critiques of science ultimately do not hold up to either Nelson’s rearticulation of underdetermination or her subsequent position that it is communities, not individuals, that are the agents of epistemology. Chad Hale (University of South Florida) In this paper, I engage in a brief explication and clarification of James’ “The Will to Believe” before going on to criticize it on two points. First, I criticize James for the ethical irresponsibility of his claim of the epistemic legitimacy of faith in light of the pragmatic view that belief is always tied up with action. Second, I call into question the existence of actual cases of Jamesian indeterminacy by examining whether they ever occur in real situations and by examining whether we can ever choose our beliefs in a pragmatically meaningful sense, real situation or not. To Be or To Do: A Question in Scientific Realism Jonah P.B. Goldwater (City University of New York) A scientific realism in which one distinguishes the ‘nature’ of a thing from its detectable actions bears a closer resemblance to religious thinking than scientific; the anti-supernaturalist should reject this distinction. Three important consequences follow: The very idea of empirically equivalent rival theories, and the metaphysical principle that dispositional properties require categorical grounds, become unintelligible, and intuitions about the form of, and epistemological access to, truth-bearing statements may have to be considerably revised. WCPA 2007 Abstracts Out of Control: The Motive of Duty and the Kantian Criterion of Summonability Shruta Swarup (Simon Fraser University) Kantians take summonability to be a necessary characteristic of moral motives. They privilege the motive of duty over emotional motives on the grounds that it satisfies this criterion while the emotions do not. I argue that the Kantian is guilty of equivocating on the concept of summonability, and that the motive of duty and the emotions are in fact in the same boat with respect to this criterion when it is properly disambiguated. A Proof That Egalitarianism Is Either False Or Banal Paul Viminitz (University of Lethbridge) In this paper I argue that the only equality that need be postulated between agents qua heading into a theory of normative ethics and/or politics is that the agents in question be equally involved in interactivity in which there’s a cooperative dividend to which they can have access if and only if they can bring themselves to (in some sense) cooperate. The kind of equality to which they’re end-of-pipe entitled, however, 4 is determined by whether or not an egalitarian distribution of the dividend-type in question between the persons in question can or cannot be expected to maximize the utility of the institutor-pair in question. The upshot of this view, then, is that, our intuitions to the contrary notwithstanding, the notion of equality can play no interesting role in either ethical or political thought. Perceptual Intentionality: Dretske versus Searle Victor Rodych (University of Lethbridge) On John Searle’s account, perceptual “experiences have Intentionality” because “experiences are as inseparable from their conditions of satisfaction as are beliefs and desires.” One cannot, according to Searle, see a yellow station wagon without understanding what a yellow station wagon is. In his “The Intentionality of Perception” (2003), Fred Dretske argues, much to the contrary, for an extensional account of visual experience such that ‘“S sees x” (like “x killed S”) is extensional because it describes a causal relation between S and x.’ On Dretske’s view, “S sees a yellow station wagon” is true provided that the appropriate causal relation obtains between a yellow station wagon and S, even if S sees something as (or believes s/he sees) a brown truck. In this paper, I endeavour to show (1) that the most important questions for epistemology and learning theory concern the nature of intensional visual experience (e.g., seeing x as a y), veridical visual experience, and unveridical visual experience, and (2) that unlike Searle’s intensional account, Dretske’s extensional account does not begin to address these important questions. Contra Dretske, Searle’s question “Under what conditions does one take oneself to be seeing that Sally is in front of one?” is neither illusory nor unproblematic. WCPA 2007 Abstracts Nozick, Parfit, and Platonic Glasses Wesley Cooper (University of Alberta) The Closest–Continuer schema of identity is distinguished here from the Closest–Continuer theory of personal identity, the latter applying the former to personal identity by reference to the self’s self-defining activity. Nozick’s “Platonic glasses” mode of conceptualizing personal identity is defended against Parfit’s objections and extended beyond hypothetical branching to the actual branching hypothesized by the “no-collapse” theories of quantum mechanics. The reader may wish to consult Lev Vaidman’s Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy essay, “Many-Worlds Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics”, for an accessible and sympathetic treatment of this interpretation.(Vaidman 2002) See also David Deutsch’s philosophical essay on what he calls the “multiverse” in The Fabric of Reality.(Deutsch 1997) Frege on Number Properties Andrew Irvine (University of British Columbia) In the Grundlagen Frege offers seven main arguments, together with a series of more minor supporting arguments, against Mill's view that numbers are properties of “external things.” This paper reviews all seven of these arguments, concluding that none are conclusive. Track-Record Arguments and Informal Logic Patrick Bondy (University of Windsor) In his paper “An Epistemological Approach to Argumentation” (2003), Alvin Goldman argues that epistemology can give an adequate account of what he calls “epistemically circular” arguments, and informal logic cannot. In this paper, I argue that although informal logicians have not given an adequate account of this kind of argument, they have the tools to do so, 5 and I give a preliminary account of this kind of argument with the tools of informal logic. scientific and philosophical studies of the mind. This runs directly counter to the phenomenological reading. Limits on Humor’s Philosophical Function Pragmatism, Genealogy, and the Value of Truth Christopher Moore (University of Minnesota) Humor helps reveal hypocrisy, negative stereotypes, and one’s own unchallenged assumptions, and so has existential, moral, and political benefits. But it may also foster hubris, complacency, and nationalism. I systematize humor’s general edifying possibilities and their preconditions. Something funny, no matter how great or wise it is, has no critical or diagnostic power by itself. I consider in particular levity; satire; the genre “comedy”; and what I call Socratic humor. Mark Migotti (University of Calgary) Humour and Play: Grown-ups at Recess Robin Tapley (Thompson Rivers University) The importance of play is not restricted to childhood. Play, besides being fun, serves several functions. Play puts us into contact with other people in a way that is friendly, relaxed, and signals our acceptance. Play hones certain skills that have adaptive features. Play teaches social skills. All of these features of play are the same functions and features of humour. Humour is adult social play. Why William James Is Not a Phenomenologist Alexander Klein (University of Toronto) A prominent reading portrays James’s Principles as a work that ultimately abandoned mental science for transcendental phenomenology. In fact, one of that work’s overarching aims was to show how mental science could operate independently of transcendental philosophy. Debates had erupted over the scientific status of psychology, and James responded by showing how a division of labor could be created between WCPA 2007 Abstracts In Truth and Truthfulness, the last book published in his lifetime, Bernard Williams sets out to legitimate the value of truth by means of a vindicatory genealogy. Correctly taking Richard Rorty's dismissive views on truth to be inimical to such an undertaking, he incorrectly takes those views to by characteristically pragmatist. In this paper I expose some of the damage Williams does to his own cause by failing to give Peircean pragmatism its due. A Curate’s Egg: “All language is metaphor” R.E. Jennings and A.J. Hartline (Laboratory for Logic and Experimental Philosophy, Simon Fraser University) So-called “pragmatic” accounts of metaphor suggest that in the ordinary way linguistic productions have a compositional and more-or-less context independent “literal meaning”, and that in metaphor this literal meaning interacts with the context of utterance to produce a new “meaning” that stands somehow apart from literal meaning. In this picture, language is, as it were, ’officially’ an instrument for producing sentences with truth-values. Nevertheless, it remains open to the speaker to use the language in a range of “tricky” ways, exploiting the capacity of physical context and a hearer’s experience to supplant the truth conditions of one production with those of another. The simple recognition that linguistic production is primarily a physical intervention has deep consequences for the larger view of language from which this view of metaphor arises. The overall shape of the account demanded by the physicality of language is that of a higher-order physical theory. In such a theory, the resources of compositional semantics are 6 largely abandoned. Semantic compositionality hypothesizes a (momentarily) static language in which fixed meanings are composed into complex meanings. By contrast physical theory recognizes composition as the principal instrument of language change. Indeed language change becomes the central object of investigation. A primary question for such a theory is: how does the capacity of linguistic productions to produce effects of one type engender the capacity of later productions to produce effects of another. A subsidiary question concerns the typing of such effects. This sort of account does not the view that language has some context-independent function. Rather, it accepts only that at a given moment in the history of a language, linguistic change has eventuated in a complex neurological and physical preparation for further linguistic intervention, a preparation available for various kinds of exploitation. The overall shape of this kind of account is that of a pragmatic account of metaphor with no hypothesized base function for language, and a fortiori none envisaged within a naive compositional semantics. In the end we endorse a straitened and theoretically disciplined counterpart of the rhapsodic thesis that all language is metaphor. What is the Julius Caesar Problem and What is Frege's Solution? David G. Laverty (University of Toronto) In this paper, I defend three theses: (1) the problem posed by the so-called Caesar Problem for Frege's overall program derives from his conception of objects; (2) contrary to what many Frege scholars have said, the explicit definition of numbers in terms of extensions, carried out in the Grundlagen, does resolve this problem; (3) in his mature phase, Frege did not abandon the method of contextual definition. WCPA 2007 Abstracts ‘Here is a culture that is cheating itself’: Wittgenstein and Rosenzweig on the Loss of Religious Discourse Eleanor Akins (University of Regina) Can any positive aspects of religious discourse be reclaimed, to refresh our outlook while being intellectually and ethically sound? A look at Wittgenstein’s ‘religious point of view’ and Rosenzweig’s ‘new thinking’ investigates this question. Each regrets the loss of religious discourse and favors a religious sensibility accenting particularity and pragmatic utility. Despite similarities in their attention to language, context and dynamic change, differences are cited as openings for further study. Schopenhauer, Suffering, and the Value of Life Julianne Chung (University of Calgary) In this paper, I will first defend several core elements of Schopenhauer’s pessimism and show how these elements, taken together, suggest that life is not worthwhile. I will then discuss whether or not it is possible to accept these core elements whilst consistently maintaining, pace Schopenhauer, that life can be worthwhile. Liberal theory and First Nations’ Indigenous Rights Sandra Tomsons (University of Winnipeg) According to political philosopher Will Kymlicka, Canada’s Aboriginal people must accept the political reality that their Aboriginal rights are not theirs to define. Non-Aboriginal judges and politicians have the power to “protect and enforce” Aboriginal rights. They do so presently presuming a liberal theory which understands them “...as matters of discrimination and/or privilege, not of equality.” Consequently, Aboriginal rights must be understood as “...an essential component of liberal political practice.” Aboriginal rights will only be secure if they can be seen from the non-Aboriginal perspective (i.e. 7 liberalism) as consistent with, rather than competing with, liberalism. My paper challenges Kymlicka’s claims about political reality and the constraints he imposes on how Aboriginal rights can be understood. I argue that the national minority account of Aboriginal rights Kymlicka constructs to find a space for these rights in liberal theory is inconsistent with liberal theory. The reasoning that refutes his account also reveals that liberal theory supports the claim that Aboriginal people are entitled to define their rights. Aristotle’s Pragmatic Methodology for Ethical Inquiry Martin Tweedale (University of Alberta) Aristotle has a pragmatic view of ethical inquiry in the sense that he takes the ultimate aim of it to be the improvement of our lives, as opposed to viewing it as aimed at knowledge. Given this I claim that it is not surprising nor objectionable if he ends up holding some sort of limited relativism in ethics, and in fact I argue that he does indeed leave his inquiry open to that result. Locke and Boyle on the Primary/Secondary Quality Distinctions or Why the Primary/Secondary Quality Distinction Isn't Jack MacIntosh (University of Calgary) Many philosophers in the early modern period, with Locke as a paradigmatic example, offered distinctions which it is customary to refer to as the distinction between primary and secondary qualities. In this paper I argue that there is not such a single distinction, and that attention to the texts reveals that the various distinctions on offer are quite distinct distinctions. They may be interesting, ingenious, or philosophically interesting, but they are not one distinction. WCPA 2007 Abstracts Can Babies Read Minds? Infant Theory of Mind: An Understanding of Mental States or Behaviour Serife Tekin (York University) Onishi and Baillargeon (O&B), in a study on infant cognition, relying on the results of a non-verbal false belief task, propose that 15-month old infants understand false beliefs. I argue that the infants’ behavioural response in the study may be an indication of their recognition of the discrepancy in the behaviourial regularity, not their understanding of mental states. Thus, I argue that O&B’s attribution of false belief understanding to 15-month old infants is problematic. Sunday October 28 Pragmatic Conceptual Analysis Justin C. Fisher (University of British Columbia) Pragmatic Conceptual Analysis (PCA) is a proposed empirical methodology for doing philosophical analysis. PCA suggests that we think of our shared concepts as having whatever application conditions they would need to have in order best to continue delivering benefits as they have regularly delivered benefits in the past. I argue that PCA reveals not only the application conditions we ought to use for our concepts, but also the correct application conditions they already have. Neopragmatism and Normative Pragmatism in Semantics Jaroslav Peregrin (Charles University) While the traditional view was that in order to understand language and our linguistic practices we must explain meaning, the 'pragmatic turn' emerging within the writings of various philosophers of the second half of the twentieth century caused a basic change of the perspective: the tendency to concentrate 8 directly on explaining the linguistic practices and leave the need for explaining meaning to emerge subsequently. In the paper I want to distinguish between approaches to meaning of neopragmatists like Quine and normative pragmatists like Brandom. I will try to show that it is the latter that is able to elucidate the concept of meaning in a truly illuminating way. Basic Logical Knowledge and Justification David Boutillier (University of Western Ontario) The paper has two goals. The first goal is to explain what the problem of basic logical knowledge is. The second goal is to present a sketch of an approach to the problem. The approach sketched employs a transcendental argument aimed at helping to show how it is possible for a basic logical knowledge to be justified. The approach avoids appeal to intuition, convention, and psychology. The Municiple Bi-Laws of Thought Dave DeVidi (University of Waterloo) What I want to consider today is logical pluralism: in particular, I want to investigate the question of whether there is any sense in which it is both interesting and true that there is a plurality of logics. Priest on the Hooded Man Chris Tillman (University of Manitoba) In Towards Non-Being Graham Priest offers a novel resolution of the Hooded Man paradox (as well as its modern guises in the work of Gottlob Frege, Saul Kripke, Nathan Salmon, and others). Millians and Fregeans have offered familiar solutions to this paradox, but Priest’s solution promises the virtues of its familiar competitors without the attendant costs. The goal of WCPA 2007 Abstracts this paper is to evaluate Priest’s proposal. I argue that the proposal should not be accepted. When Racial Slurs Fail to Express: A Reply to Boisvert Brandon Johns (University of Southern California) In “Expressive-Assertivism and ‘The Embedding Objection’,” Daniel Boisvert offers an ethical expressivist-cognitivist hybrid view called Expressive-Assertivism (EA). On EA, utterances of moral sentences both express a mental state and assert a descriptive fact about the world. One virtue Boisvert claims for EA is that it is capable of solving The Objection from Missing Expressives (OME). Key to Boisvert’s solution is his comparison of moral terms to pejorative language. In this paper, I argue that supertrue pejorative sentences fail to express contempt. And so Boisvert’s appeal to pejorative language in order to solve OME will not succeed. Does the Bayesian Solution to the Paradox of Confirmation Really Support Bayesianism? Brian Laetz (University of British Columbia) Bayesians seem to present their solution to the paradox of confirmation as grounds for preferring their theory to Hempel’s. They point out that, unlike Hempel, they can at least say that a black raven confirms that all ravens are black more than a white shoe. However, I point out that if this is an advantage over Hempel’s approach, it is cancelled out by the fact that Bayesians are equally committed to the claim that black ravens confirm that all non-black things are non-ravens more than white shoes, unlike Hempel. In light of this, I reexamine the dialectic between Bayesians and Hempel at length. 9 What is Carnap's Logical Empiricism? Sam Hiller In this talk, I describe a unique interpretation of Rudolf Carnap's philosophical position at the time of his seminal work, The Logical Syntax of Language. After outlining this position, which I call "language engineering," I then proceed to show how Carnap's major philosophical tasks fit within this framework. I close by examining how two of Carnap's principle philosophical commitments - the principle of tolerance, and empiricism must be understood. Friendship, Complacency, and Non-Reductive Utilitarianism Andrew Peter Ross (Queen’s University) Contemporary utilitarianism has drawn repeated criticism over its apparent inability to accommodate the value of friendship. Many recent replies to this objection have attempted to indirectly justify friendship by arguing that pro-friendship dispositions are actually conducive to the greater good. In response, critics have argued that this strategy does nothing to solve the problem of “alienation”. This paper will consider Elinor Mason’s reply to this objection. It will be argued that Mason’s strategy places overtly repressive conditions for sacrificing friendships, forcing moral agents into states of ethical complacency. Following this, I will advocate what I call a "non-reductive" strategy to avoid that will avoid the complications introduced by Mason's argument. Against Intrinsic Value Ryan Tanner (University of Calgary) In this paper I argue against a certain standard view of intrinsic value. I begin with distinguishing three ways in which we tend to describe things as valuable, arguing that only two of them actually refer to intelligible, or at least demonstrable, ways in WCPA 2007 Abstracts which a thing has value. Then, taking Irwin Goldstein’s case for the intrinsic badness of pain as a good example of an attempt to demonstrate the existence of intrinsic value in the sense at issue, I argue that in fact intrinsic value is at best a trivial concept, and at worst is unhelpful and grossly unsubstantiated. Against Wide Categories: Aesthetic Adjectives and Judgment Josh Johnston (University of British Columbia) This paper explores the view of aesthetic ambifunctionality and the role aesthetic adjectives play in judgment. Aesthetic ambifunctionality holds that aesthetic adjectives can vary in their use, that is, they can be used both predicatively and attributively in aesthetic judgments. Aesthetic empiricism views adjectives as playing only a predicative role, while aesthetic contextualism views them as playing only an attributive role. The ambifunctional view is presented as a compromise between both of these two extremes. Naturalism, Death, and Functional Immortality Charlie Hobbs (Southern Illinois University) I consider a naturalistic approach to death, seeking to articulate a naturalistic or “functional” version of immortality. Making use of John Dewey and other classical American philosophers, I first articulate the naturalism of this project. I then discuss what such naturalism means for understanding the self and its survival. Finally, I consider the existential question about to what extent such a view of immortality is satisfying. Technology and Freedom in Heidegger Jeff Kochan (University of Alberta) The themes of technology and freedom run widely and powerfully through the collected works of Martin Heidegger. In 10 this essay, I will discuss his treatment of them in two of his more well-known and influential works: Being and Time and “The Question Concerning Technology.” I will argue that, in the earlier text, Heidegger understands freedom as unfolding within limits circumscribed by technology, whereas, in the later text, he understands technology as unfolding within limits circumscribed by freedom. Can Someone Choose Hell? Joel Buenting (University of Alberta) I propose that theories of choosing hell ought to satisfy these desiderata: (i) they ought to specify sufficient conditions for damnation (D1) and (ii) they ought to preserve an acceptably high ratio of sinners in hell to the blessed in heaven (D2). Rejecting God (Geach 1977), rejecting God based on fully informed decisions (Talbott 2005), rejecting God based on wellinformed decisions (Craig 1989) and choosing hell based upon choosing evil (Walls 1992, 2004) fail in various ways to satisfy D1-D2. WCPA 2007 Abstracts 11 Symposia Philosophy, Teaching, and the Art of Living Douglas R. Anderson (Southern Illinois University) John Russon (University of Guelph) Cherilyn Keall (University of Guelph) Anderson, Douglas R. Philosophy Americana: Making Philosophy at Home in American Culture. (New York: Fordham University Press, 2006). Russon, John. Human Experience: Philosophy, Neurosis, and the Elements of Everyday Life. (Albany, NY: State University of New York Press, 2003). As a pragmatist, William James believed that teaching and learning are part of a philosopher’s task. This part of a philosopher’s task is especially difficult because the philosopher must teach (and learn) not just any particular science or skill, but rather the art of living in general. The pursuit of self-knowledge is an integral part of practicing such an art, and I propose bringing into dialogue with each other two books that take up the issue of self-knowledge as it relates both to philosophy and teaching on the one hand and to the practice of conducting a human life on the other hand. The first is Douglas R. Anderson’s new Philosophy Americana: Making Philosophy at Home in American Culture, which contains a collection of essays in which Anderson brings James, Royce and Dewey into conversation with popular culture including music, teaching, and religious experience. The second is John Russon’s award-winning Human Experience: Philosophy, Neurosis, and the Elements of Everyday Life, which complements Anderson’s book insofar as it shows how the view of the human situation as developed in Contemporary European Philosophy is relevant to the practice of conducting a human life. Together these two books not only demonstrate WCPA 2007 Abstracts the truth of James’ view that teaching and learning are part of a philosopher’s task, but they also provide valuable insights of their own into how individuals can become more adept at practicing the art of living. Propositions and Propositional Acts James Young (University of Victoria) Peter Alward (University of Lethbridge) David Johnston (University of Victoria) It is argued that semantic theory should replace propositions with propositional acts in its theoretical ontology. It is shown that propositional acts are equally capable of accounting for the various linguistic phenomena that are of interest to philosophers, and also that a semantic theory based on propositional acts is more ontologically parsimonious than one based on propositions. 12