lntemational Journalof International EISEVIER Industrial Organization Journal of Industrial Organization 12 (1994) 549-568 Entry into a new market A game of timing Steinar Department of Economics, Holden” University of Oslo, P.O. Box 1095 Blinders, Norway Christian N-0317 Oslo, Riis’ Foundation for Research in Economics and Business Administration, N-0371 Oslo, Norway Gaustadalleen 21, Final version received September 1993 Abstract We study entry into a new market in a model where firms choose when to enter the market. An early entry is profitable because it yields a strategic advantage in the market; however, costs will also be larger owing to interest on the capital cost. It is shown that rent equalization need not occur, and that social welfare may be lower under competition than under pure monopoly. Furthermore, under some circumstances there is a strictly positive probability that the firms enter simultaneously, even in the limit when the period length converges to zero. 1. Introduction Recent theories in industrial organization attempt to endogenize the structure of market by analyzing entry and exit processes. However, as yet most of these theories use restrictive assumptions, among them that entry into the market occurs either simultaneously or sequentially in a pre* Corresponding author. ’ Thanks to Tor Jakob Klette, Karl Ove Moene, a referee, and participants at a seminar at the Department for valuable comments, and to Atle Seierstad for helpful discussions. 0167-7187/94/$07.00 0 1994 Elsevier Science B.V. All rights reserved SSDI 0167-7187(93)00433-O 550 S. Holden. C. Riis I Int. .I. Ind. Orgum 12 (19944) S49-.S66x determined order [see Gilbert (1987) for an overview of the literature based on the latter assumption]. While sequential entry may seem closer to reality, it is not satisfactory to let the order of entry be exogenous. In general, the profits of a firm depend on when the firm enters, and this makes it important also to model the process which determines the order of entry. In this paper we investigate a model with endogenous time of entry where firms may achieve a strategic advantage by building up capacity at an early stage when the market is very small. By an early entry, a firm will incur larger costs owing to interest on the capacity costs, yet the firm may be willing to do so in order to obtain a larger market share. Endogenizing the time of entry has important implications for the market structure. Previous studies (see references below) have mostly concluded that profits will tend to be equal in all firms, because the advantage of being the first entrant will be dissipated in the fight to become the first. Fudenberg and Tirole (1985) show however that rent equalization need not occur in three-player games, and they also set up a highly stylized two-player game (‘grab-the-dollar’) where firms may obtain different profits. In the present paper we show that firms may obtain different profits also in a standard duopoly model. The present paper draws upon and adds to two strands of the literature: on entry deterrence in models with endogenous timing, and on pure timing models. In the entry deterrence literature, our model is, to our knowledge, the first that allows for simultaneous entry when capacity decisions are endogenous. Gilbert and Harris (1984), Mills (1988) and especially Anderson and Engers (1990) use industrial organization models rather similar to ours, but without allowing for simultaneous moves. As will be shown below. in our model there will under some circumstances be a strictly positive probability of simultaneous entry, so ruling out simultaneous moves is not as innocuous as it may seem.’ Dixit and Shapiro (1986), Cabral (1989) and Robson (1990) consider models where simultaneous entry is possible. However, Dixit and Shapiro (1986) and Cabral (1989) only look at firms’ decisions of whether to enter or leave the market, while Robson (1990) considers a model where firms commit to a certain price. Endogenous capacities decisions complicate the model considerably compared with a pure entry model, but it also adds significantly to realism. The timing model we use has similarities with the model suggested by Fudenberg and Tirole (1985) in their analysis of the adoption of a new our entry decision also involves the choice of technology. However, capacity, and this requires a richer model than the one used by Fudenberg ’ The model itself is however Sundaram (1992). entirely non-stochastic. in contrast to, for example. Dutta and S. Holden, C. Riis I ht. .I. Ind. Organ. 12 (1994) 549-568 551 and Tirole (1985). We believe that the timing model used in this paper also allows for wider areas of application within games of timing, and thus is of independent interest. A novel result is that there may be simultaneous entry even in the limit when the period length converges to zero. The reason for this result lies in the possible discontinuity of the payoff function of the follower. The discontinuity arises as a consequence of the leader’s strategy shifting from ‘entry-accommodating’ capacity to ‘entry-deterring’ capacity as the market grows. In section 2, we present the basic industrial organization model of the paper. Since the interaction with the timing aspects complicates the analysis considerably, we have deliberately made the industrial organization model as simple as possible. Section 3 analyzes the consequences of endogenizing the time of entry. Section 4 concludes. 2. The model We consider a market for a new product. Let g(t) be an indicator for the size of the market at time t, and assume that g’(t) > 0 for all t, SO that demand increases over time. Furthermore, g(t) converges towards g”“” when t approaches infinity, so the market stagnates eventually. Two identical firms wish to enter the market. Each firm can enter the market at any point in time after 0, and each firm is only allowed to enter once. There is complete information regarding the payoff functions of the firms. Furthermore, if one firm enters, the other will become aware of this immediately. At entry, a firm i builds up capacity x,, and this choice is irreversible. The capacity can either be high, x,,, in which case subsequent entry is deterred, or low, xd (in a previous version we considered a model with a continuous choice of capacity). The investment costs, which are incurred at entry, are either c(x,) or C&Y,,), where c(x,) < c(x,). If only one firm has entered in capacity xi, the net revenues at time t are R(x,, O)g(t) >O for all f, i = d, m. If the other firm also has entered, in capacity x,, j = d, m, the net revenues of a firm that enters in capacity x, at time r is R(x,, x,)g(t). We assume that R(xd, 0) > R(x,, xd) > 0. If a firm does not enter the market at all, it obtains zero profit. We assume that no firm can earn a positive profit by entering at time 0, that is. R(x,, 0) I g(s) emrs ds - c(xi) < 0, i = m, d, (1) where r is the real rate of interest. We first consider the decision problem of the last firm to enter (the follower) when the other firm (the leader) has already entered. If the leader 552 S. Holden, C. Riis I Int. J. Ind. Organ. 12 (1994) S49-568 best off by not entering. enters in capacity x,, the follower is by assumption possible profit of the If the leader entered in capacity xd, the maximum follower (discounted to time 0) is FD =max R(xd, xd) I (2) g(s) em” ds - c(x d) emrr We assume that FD > 0 [this is obviously fulfilled for suitable values of R(x,, xd), g(t), r and c(x~)], so that if one firm enters in capacity xd, the other firm will eventually also enter. The optimal time of entry of the follower, T, is given by the first-order condition (3) R(XdY xlJ)g(r) = +CJ. As g(t) is increasing in t, (3) determines a unique optimal time of entry r of the follower. The leader is assumed to be able to perfectly forecast the ensuing action taken by the follower, represented by the optimal time of entry, 7. We first investigate the leader’s choice between entry deterrence and entry accommodation when the time of entry of the leader, t, is taken as exogenous. The profit under the entry deterrence (monopoly) strategy is M(t) = qx,, The profit under 0) J g(s) eprs the entry em”. - accommodation (4) (duopoly) D(t) = R(xd, 0) i g(s) e-rs ds + R(xd, xd) /g(s) strategy is emrs ds - c(xd) emrr. 7 I (5) Given the time of entry, t, the leader clearly chooses the strategy that gives the higher profit. (If both strategies give the same payoff we assume that the leader chooses the entry accommodation strategy.) Thus the profit of the leader as a function of time of entry is L(t) = max[D(t), M(t)]. (6) As shown in the appendix, either one of the strategies is the more profitable for all t, or there exists a unique point in time tM for which M(tM) = D(t”), M(t) < D(t) for t < t”, and M(t) > D(t) for t > t”. The crucial issue in the model is how the relationship between L(t) and F(t) depends on time. Lemma 1. There exists a unique point in time t* such that if the leader S. Holden, C. Riis I Int. .I. Ind. Organ. 12 (1994) 549-568 553 enters before t* it is more profitable to be the follower, while if the leader enters after t* it is more profitable to be the leader, that is, F(t) 2 L(t) for all t d t* [and F(t) > L(t) for all t < t*], F(t) < L(t) for all t E (t*, T) and F(t) G L(t) for all t 2 T. L(t) is continuous for all t, while F(t) is continuous except at t”, where the leader changes strategy from duopoly to monopoly. All proofs are in the appendix. Since entry is uncoordinated, there is a risk of simultaneous entry. We assume that if simultaneous entry occurs, the payoffs are independent of the planned capacities. This is clearly a restrictive assumption. However, without this assumption the choice of capacity will depend on the risk of simultaneous entry, which will complicate the analysis considerably. A possible justification of the assumption is that although the commitment to enter (which could take the form of the signing of a contract) is made at a single point in time, the actual process of installing capacity takes some time. This enables the firms to choose the duopoly capacity if simultaneous entry occurs.’ A simultaneous entry at t gives w>=WXd,Xd) I g(s) e _ ” ds - c(xd) em”‘. (7) On comparing (2) and (7), it is clear that S(t) is increasing monotonically until T, where S(T) = FD. Thus, S(T) = F(T) = FD if the leader has chosen the duopoly strategy and S(r) > F(T) = 0 if the leader has chosen the monopoly strategy. Note that F(f) is non-increasing in t before 7. Furthermore, we know that sufficiently early in the game S(t) < 0, and thus S(t) < F(t) irrespective of which strategy the leader chooses. Thus, there exists a unique point in time t’ such that F(t) > S(t) for all t < t’, and F(t) s S(t) for all t b t’. If the leader chooses the duopoly strategy, then t’ = 7, while if the leader chooses the monopoly strategy, then t’ CT. In this case, t’ = min[T, max[t”, t”]], where t” is given by S(t”) = 0. The structure of the market depends on the intersections of the F. D and M curves. There are three different cases, depending on how profitable the monopoly strategy is compared with the duopoly strategy. It turns out that in equilibrium entry will occur at t” in all cases. In case 1 (Fig. l), the ’ More formally, assume that time is discrete (cf. section 3 below) and that it takes one period to build capacity. Furthermore, between periods there is an interim moment where firms can costlessly change their choice of capacity. Finally, assume that payoff functions are such that under simultaneous entry it is more profitable to choose the duopoly capacity irrespective of which capacity the opponent chooses [this is obviously fulfilled for suitable values of R(x,. x,), R(x,, x,). R(x,, x,) and R(x,. x,,)]. In this setup, if simultaneous entry occurs, the unique Nash equilibrium is that both firms choose the duopoly capacity. 554 S. Holden. C. Riis I ht. J. Ind. Organ. 12 (1994) 549-568 L(t) F(t) t- t’ T t t” Fig. 1. duopoly strategy is more profitable than the monopoly strategy at t*, so that the leader will enter in the duopoly quantity. Here, t* < tM (or tM does not exist .) In order to develop some intuition, we shall loosely explain some of the results that will be derived formally below. Consider Fig. 1. For f < t*,F(t) > -W) = max[W), M(t)], so that both firms will wait in the hope that the other firm enters first. For t> t*, L(t) > F(t) so that both firms will try to preempt the other firm. However, in the interval (t*, t’), the leader chooses the duopoly strategy as D(t) > M(t). Thus, F(t) > S(t), so that both firms will rather be the follower than enter simultaneously. Hence, in a symmetric equilibrium the firms cannot enter with certainty within this interval. For f 2 t’, however, M(t) > D(t) and thus S(t) > F(t). Here, both firms will enter with certainty, as simultaneous entry is better than being the follower. In case 2 (Fig. 2), the monopoly strategy is more profitable relative to the duopoly strategy, so that it is more profitable to be the follower than to be the leader immediately before the point in time where the monopoly strategy becomes more profitable than the duopoly strategy. Here, tM = t* < t’. In this case the payoff function of the follower is discontinuous at t*, and there will be a strictly positive probability of simultaneous entry at t*. The intuition is that after t* it is strictly better to be the leader than to be the S. Holden, C. Riis I ht. J. Ind. Organ. 12 (1994) 549-568 555 Fig. 2. follower, thus both firms are so eager to preempt the opponent that they accept the risk of simultaneous entry. Case 2 has two subcases. In subcase (a), which is illustrated in Fig. 2, S(f*) < 0 so that tM = t* < t’. In subcase (b) s(t*) 2 0, so that t* = t’. In case 3 (Fig. 3), the monopoly strategy is even more profitable compared with the duopoly strategy, so that the monopoly strategy is more profitable than the duopoly strategy even at the first point in time where the leader can obtain positive profits. Here, tM < t* <t’ (if tM exists at all). 3. A game of timing The model in section 2 was, for convenience, developed in continuous time. However, as emphasized by Fudenberg and Tirole (1985), strategies in continuous time do not contain enough information to represent all the equilibria that exist in discrete-time models [see also Simon and Stinchcombe (1989)]. For example, in a model in continuous time, if both firms enter with certainty at the same point in time, then simultaneous entry is certain to occur. In a discrete-time model, however, one can also include the ‘intensity of entry’, that is, the probability that a firm enters in each period. S. Holden, C. Riis I Int. J. Ind. Organ. 12 (1994) 54%St% Fig. 3 In the limit when the period length converges to zero, an entry will occur immediately irrespective of whether the per period probability is 0.9 or 0.1. The probability that simultaneous entry occurs will however vary with this probability. As will become apparent below, we need the ‘intensity of entry’ to adequately represent aspects of real economic significance. Thus, in this section time is assumed to be divided into periods of exogenous length. The focus is on the limit when the period length approaches zero. The type of strategies we adopt in this section is based on much of the same intuition as the strategies of Fudenberg and Tirole (1985). However, the different economic setting causes an important technical difference. In both models, there is a certain point in time t” from which it is advantageous to be the first to enter. In Fudenberg and Tirole (1985) the payoff of the follower is increasing over time, so the players will not consider the possibility of entering before r*. In our setting, however, the strategy of the leader may shift from entry accommodation to entry deterrence at t*, so the payoff of the follower drops at t*. Hence, the players may choose to enter with a certain probability before t *, in order to reduce the risk of becoming the follower if entry is after t*. Thus, we cannot use the strategies of Fudenberg and Tirole, where entry ‘immediately’ before a certain point in time is not possible. S. Holden, C. Riis I Int. .I. Ind. Organ. 12 (1994) 549-568 557 We assume that a possible entry in a period k takes place at the beginning of the period, at time t,. Let pi be the probability that firm i enters in period k, conditional on the other firm not having entered before, and let G;(t) be the cumulative probability that firm i has entered by time f, conditional on the other firm not having entered before. Thus, Gi(tk) = C,& P1. Let k* be the last period before t*, k’ the first period after t’ and K the first period after T. (In case 2(b), t* = t’, so that k* + 1 = k’.) To simplify notation, let subscripts denote periods, so that we use L,, F, and S, for L(t,), F(t,) and S(t,T). Thus, Fk 3 L, for all k c k* (and Fk > L, for all k < k*), Fk <L, for all k E (k*, K) while Fk <L, for all k 2 K. Moreover, S, < Fk for all k <k’, while S, 2 Fk for all k 3 k’. Proposition 1. In a subgame perfect equilibrium (SPE), in the limit when the period length approaches zero, we have for any E > 0 and u > 0, G,(t* + e) > 1 - (T and/or G,(t* + e) > 1 - u, G;(t* - .e) = G,(t* - e) = 0. That is, no firm will enter before t* certainly enter before t* + E. E, and one of the firms will almost Proposition 1 applies to all SPE, no matter whether they are pure or mixed. Let us now consider the equilibria with pure strategies. Assume that firm i plans to enter with certainty in period k. If k > k* + 1, the best reply of firm j is to enter in period k - 1, as L,_, > Fk.3 If k 6 k*, the best reply of firm j is to wait and let firm i enter first, as L,_,, < Fk for all k c k* and s > 0. Proposition 2 follows immediately from this reasoning. Proposition 2. The unique pure strategy SPE is given by the following strategies. One firm plans to enter with certainty in period k* + 1. The other firm enters either in period k*, or plans to enter in period k* + 2, depending on what gives the higher payoff. (Zf the two alternatives of the second firm give the same payoff, then there exist two equilibria, one for each alternative.) (There is clearly also an equilibrium where the identities of the firms are reversed). A problem with the pure strategy equilibria is that they must be asymmetric (otherwise simultaneous entry would occur with certainty). Thus, there is a need for some sort of coordination device to determine 3 If period of L(r). k is after L(t) has reached its maximum, firm j will instead enter at the max point 558 S. Holden, C. Riis I Int. J. Ind. Organ. 12 (1994) 549-568 which firm chooses which strategy. However, if there exists a coordination device it should ideally be incorporated in the model. This is particularily important in situations where the firms obtain different profit levels, as both firms then would wish to be the one obtaining the higher profit. We then proceed to characterize the equilibria with mixed strategies. Lemma 2. If there is no entry before period k’, both firms will enter certainty in period k’, that is, Gi(tk,) = G,(tk,) = 1. Lemma 3. In an SPE with probability of entry in period (k”, k’]. with symmetric mixed strategies, the common k, pk, will be strictly positive for all k E As will become apparent below, strictly positive probability of entry in cases 1 and 2 there before and at k”. will also be a Proposition 3. The unique symmetric SPE strategies are given by the following vector of probabilities of entry (p, , pz,. . , p,,. . . pkCm,,pk. ,. .), where p, = 0 for s < r and s > k’, while p,, > 0 for s E [r, k’], and where r is the last period where the following condition holds: The relationship between Pktl =~#-Sk)l(Lk the probabilities -&+,I+ is given c .s>k+l by PAL,+, -L,)I(L,-Sk+,), k= I,..., k’ - 2, px, =pk._,(Fk,m, -S,.p,)i(L,.m, (9) -S,.), (IO) and k’-1 Pk’ = I- c k=r pk. (11) Proposition 4. When the period length converges to zero, the expected profits of the firms in an equilibrium with symmetric strategies converges to L(t*). Note that if FD > L(t*) > 0, then differ even if their expected payoffs the realized payoffs are the same. of the firms may Proposition 5. When the period length converges to zero, we have: In case I, where F(t*) = FD = L(t*) > 0, and in case 3, where F(t*) = L(t*) = 0, the probability of simultaneous entry goes to zero. In case 2(a), where F(t*) = S. Holden, C. Riis I ht. 559 J. Ind. Organ. 12 (1994) 549-568 FD > L(t*) > 0 > S(t*), the probability of simultaneous entry before or at t*, p-(S), is given by p-(S) = L(t*)(FD - L(t*))I[(2FD - L(t*))(L(t*) + FD - 2S(t*))] > 0. The probability H(t*) The before (12) that an entry = 1 - [l - Gi(t*)]’ = L(t*)/(L(t*) In case 2(b), p-(S) where before = [L(t*)(2FD risk of simultaneous entry or at t”, is given by p+(s) occurs or at t* is given by - L(t*))]/(FD)2 > 0. t”, p’(S), after conditional - 2S(t*)) > 0. (13) on no entry (14) F(P) = FD > L(t*) > S(t*) 2 0, we have = [L(t*)) - (1 - H(t*))S(t*) - H(t*)(L(t*) {[S(P) - (L(t*) + FD))/2]H(t*)} + FD)12]I >O, (15) H(P) = 1 - [(FD - L(t*))/(FD - S(t*))]’ > 0, (16) p+(s) (17) and = 1. Cases 1 and 3 are very similar to the standard results in timing games [Fudenberg and Tirole (1985), Gilbert and Harris (1985)]. In both cases, both firms obtain the same payoff, and there is no conflict as to who enters first. Thus, they will mix with a low probability of entry, and the risk of simultaneous entry will be zero in the limit when the period length converges to zero. Indeed, if there were a non-negligible risk of simultaneous entry, both firms would prefer to wait and let the other firm enter first. Note also that a comparison of cases 1 and 3 shows that the existence of an entry-deterring technology induces an early entry, and thus lowers industry profits. Case 2 (Fig. 2), on the other hand, is in contrast to the standard results. Here, the firms are not indifferent as to which firm enters first. In a symmetric equilibrium, the firms still mix over entering in the periods immediately around t*. However, before t*, L(t) <F(t) = FD and both firms will ‘wait longer’ in the hope that the other firm enters first. After t*, L(t)>F(t)=O [ su b case (a)] and the firms will ‘hurry more’, trying to preempt the other firm. The probability mass of entry will be much more concentrated close to t* in case 2 than in the other cases. As the probability mass is more concentrated, there will also be a non-negligible probability of simultaneous entry. Indeed, it is only because there is a risk of simultaneous 560 S. Holden, C. Riis I Int. J. Ind. Organ. 12 (1994) S49-S68 entry that the probability mass is not completely concentrated in the last period before f* and the first period after. The expected payoff of the firms is L(t*). This implies that the possible gain from F(t”) > L(t*) is dissipated through the risk of simultaneous entry or an entry after t”. A further difference between case 2 and most two-firm games with endogenous timing is that the firms obtain different profits, unless simultaneous entry occurs. Compared with Fudenberg and Tirole, the difference in results derives from the fact that we have a richer model, where firms not only decide when to enter, but also in what capacity. This additional feature implies that the optimal response of the follower may be a discontinuous function of the time of entry of the leader, which again implies that entry can also take place at a point in time where the profits of the follower differ from the profits of the leader. 4. Concluding remarks If firms enter sequentially into a market, the first firm will claim the bigger market share and thus obtain greater profits. But which firm will be the first? We have analyzed this problem in a dynamic model where firms themselves choose when to enter. As an early entry is more costly, firms weigh the additional costs against the benefit of obtaining a larger market share. The actual outcome of the game will depend on the cost and demand structure of the market under consideration. We show that under standard assumptions in duopoly theory, the firms will in most cases obtain equal profits, but it is also possible that their profits differ. In contrast to most of the previous literature. we explicitly allow for the possibility of simultaneous entry. It turns out that under some circumstances there is a strictly positive probability that simultaneous entry occurs, which emphasizes the importance of allowing for this possibility. The reason for this result lies in the discontinuity of the payoff function of the follower at the point in time where the leader shifts from ‘entry-accommodating’ to ‘entry-deterring’ capacity. Note that the discontinuity of the payoff function of the follower is caused by the change in strategy of the leader, and does not depend on the fact that there are only two available capacities in our model. The timing model we use can be viewed as an extension of the model of Fudenberg and Tirole (1985). We believe that this part of our model can be used in a large variety of timing games, and thus be of independent interest. Case 3 shows that under endogenous timing, social welfare may be lower under competition than if one firm has been given the monopoly rights. The reason for this is in the spirit of Posner (1975), that the monopoly profits are dissipated by the early entry induced by the competition to become the S. Holden, C. Riis I Int. J. Ind. Organ. 12 (1994) 549-568 561 monopolist. In a previous version of the paper with a continuous choice of capacity, this result is even stronger, by the fact that the early entry (to obtain monopoly) also leads the monopolist to choose a lower capacity than what would have been chosen by a firm that had been given the monopoly rights from the outset. Appendix The relationship between M(t) and D(t). The possibility that one of the strategies is the more profitable for all t is trivial, so we focus on the existence of t”. Here we show that M(t) = D(t) implies that M’(t) > D’(t) which, as M(t) and D(t) clearly are continuous, ensures that there exists at most one point in time tM for which M(t”) = D(t”). Furthermore, M(t) < D(t) for all t < t”, and M(r) > D(t) for all t > t”. The slopes of the functions D(t) and M(t) are D’(t) = [ - R(xd, O)g(t) + rc(xd)] eer’, M’(t) = [ - R(x,, From (Al) [R(x,, it follows O)g(t) + rc(x,)] eP”. that M’(t) > D’(t) 0) - R(Xd, O)] q (Al) if < c(x,> - C(X,). (A4 We have Rkll~ 0) 1 g(s) emrv ds - = R(xd, 0) < R(.xd, 0) c(x,) emr’ 1g(s) emrs ds + R(xd, I xd) [g(s) eers ds - c(x,) ePr’ (-43) g(s) e-rr ds - c(x,) em”, where the equality follows from M(t) = D(t), from R(xd, xd) < R(xd, 0). (A3) implies that J,“g(s) emrs ds [R&n, 0) - R(xd, 011 Since g’(t) > 0, we have e-,l while the inequality <4%1>- 4%). follows (A41 S. Holden, 562 C. Riis I Int. .I. Ind. Organ. 12 (1994) 549-568 j”,“g(s) emrs ds > g(t)Jcmem”.’ds e - rl e g(t) --r, r . It is clear that (A4) and (A5) imply (A2). QED Proof of Lemma 1. First consider the case where no entry has taken place before the optimal time of entry of the follower, T. If the leader chooses the duopoly strategy, the follower will enter immediately, and both firms obtain the same payoff. However, if the monopoly strategy is more profitable and is thus chosen by the leader, the follower obtains zero payoff. Then consider the possibility of entry before 7. If entry occurs early in the game, the leader obtains negative profit by assumption, whereas the follower always obtain a non-negative profit. If entry occurs immediately before T, however, the profit of the leader is greater than the profit of the follower [compare (2) and (5)]. Furthermore, inspection of (5) shows that [as g’(t) > 0] if L(t) > F(t) for t = s, then L(t) > F(t) for all t E (s, T). The continuity of L(t) and F(t) follows from the continuity of payoff functions, except at the point in time where the leader changes strategy. QED Proof of Proposition 1. We first prove that G,(t* + F) > 1 - u and/or G,(t* + E) > 1 - u. The intuition in the proof is that after t*, the first firm to enter will obtain the higher profits. Thus, both firms will try to preempt the other firm. Define 7r, = max{(L(t) + F(t))/2lt b t*}.’ Thus, given that no firm has the expected profits of at least one of the entered by t*, in equilibrium, firms, say firm i, is less than or equal to n,. Then define t, by L(t,) = TI-,, and consider the interval (t, + ~/2, t, + E). Let K denote the set of all periods within this interval. Observe that L, > TI-,for all k E K. Thus, the only thing that can prevent firm i from entering with certainty in this interval is the risk of simultaneous entry. To obtain a more precise condition, let q), denote the probability that firm i enters in period k conditional on no entry before k [SO 4; =A/(1 - G,k-l))l. Thus, firm i will enter unless the expected profits of entering in period k, qiSk + (1 - q’JLk < 7~,, or equivalently qi 2 (L, r,)l(L, 7 S,). Define zk = (L, - rI)l(L, -S,), so that firm i will enter unless qi 2 zk for all k E K. To prevent firm i from entering within this interval, the probability that firm j enters during this interval must be 1- n kEK (1- 4:) a I- rI (1 -zk). kEK ’ This maximum clearly exists, as L(t) is continuous, and at this point F(t) < F(t”) for all t > t”. Moreover, approaches infinity, because of the discounting. while F(r) is continuous except at t”, L(t) + F(t) converges to zero when I S. Holden, C. Riis I Int. J. Ind. Organ. 12 (1994) 549-568 563 When period length to zero, number of in K goes towards infinity. As the zk’s are fixed [as L(t) and S(t) are continuous] and strictly greater than zero, it is clear that to prevent firm i from entering, the probability that firm j enters during the interval (ti + ~12, t, + &) must approach unity. Hence we know that the probability that an entry occurs before t, + F approaches unity. Then define 7r2 = max{(l(t) + F(t))/2lt* s t < t, + E}. In equilibrium, the expected profits of at least one of the firms, say firm i, must now be less than or equal to v~, as we know that an entry will occur before t, + E. Then define t, by L(t2) = 7~2, and consider the interval (t2 + e/2, f2 + E). Just as above we can show that to prevent firm i from entering with certainty in one of the periods in this interval, the probability that firm j enters during this interval must approach unity. Hence we know that the probability that an entry occurs before t, + E approaches unity. This reasoning can be applied recursively as long as L(t) > F(t). Each time the difference between L(t) and F(t) will be approximately halved. The procedure will not stop until we have reached t*, which proves that the probability that an entry has occurred immediately after t* will approach unity. We now proceed to prove that Gi(t* - .Y)= G,(t* - E) = 0. Consider the choice of firm i of whether to enter at t* - F or somewhere in the interval (t* - ~/2, t*). When the period length converges to zero, the number of If the conditional periods in the interval (t* - e/2, t*) goes to infinity, probability that firm j enters in period k, conditional on there has been no entry before k, qi, does not approach zero for any period k in the interval (t* - ~/2, t*), then the probability that j enters within this interval will certainly go towards unity (as shown in the first part of the proof). In this case it is better for firm i to wait and obtain FD than to enter at t* - E, as L(t) < FD for all t < t*. On the other hand, if qi does approach zero for some period k in the interval (t* - ~/2, t*), then it is better for firm i to enter in this period and obtain L(t* - ~/2) with certainty, than to enter at period L(t* - E), as L’(t) > 0. QED Proof of Lemma 2. Note that S(t) s F(t) for all t 3 t’, so that if the other firm enters, then the best reply is to enter. Under duopoly [D(t) > M(t)], L(t) has already reached its maximum at t’, so entry is the best strategy also if the other firm does not enter [as L(t) 2 F(t)]. Under monopoly, we must consider the period where L(t) has reached its maximum (we know that a maximum will exist, as the market stagnates and the profits are discounted to time zero). When L(r) has reached its maximum, entry is the best strategy irrespective of whether the other firm enters or not. Thus, if no entry has occurred before that, there will be simultaneous entry with certainty. Using backwards induction from this period, it is clear that (as L,_, > S, for all 564 S. Holden, C. Riis I Int. 1. Ind. k > k’ under monopoly) entry after k’, and thus also at k’. Organ. 12 (1994) 549-S@ will be the dominant strategy in all periods QED Proof of Lemma 3. Observe first that in a symmetric equilibrium, the firms will not enter with certainty before k’, as Sk < Fk for all k <k’. Combined with Lemma 2 this ensures that pks > 0. Assume then that pk > 0 for all k E [s, k’]. We want to show that this implies that pr_, > 0. pk > 0 for all k E [s, k’] implies that the expected profits of entering are the same for all periods within this interval. The expected profits of entering in period k’ are at most FD, because this strategy either leads to the firm being a follower or simultaneous entry at k’. Thus, if the probability that the other firm enters in period s - 1 is zero, then it is strictly better to enter in period s - 1 and obtain L,,_, > FD. Thus, we cannot have p,%~, = 0. Using induction, starting with s = k’, it is clear that pk > 0 for all k E (k*, k’]. QED Proof of Proposition 3. The proof is based on a construction of the equilibrium strategies, which proves both existence and uniqueness. From Lemma 3 it follows that the firms mix over all periods in the interval (k*, k’]. Consider two periods, k and k + 1, within this interval. [In case 2(b), consider the two periods, k* = k’ - 1 and k’.] As both pk>O and pk+, >O, both firms must be indifferent between entering in period k or period k + 1. The expected payoff of firm j if it enters in period k is ,ZkP.,F, while + PA, the expected c p,Fs +PJ~ r<k By setting + Pk+lLk + ,,,T+, payoff of j if it enters +~k+,Sk+, + c ,>A+1 (A6) and (A7) to be equal, P k+, =~k(Fk-Sk)l(Lk-Sk+l)+ W) PsL,, in period k + 1 is P$L,+I. (A7) we obtain c F.>k+I PAL,+, -Ld’(L, -%+,I. (9) From Lemma 2, p, = 0 for s > k’. Thus, pk’ =pk.-*(Fk’_, - S,._,)I(L,._, pkc is given by -s,.>. Moreover, let r be the first period with a positive there is entry with certainty at k’, it follows that (10) probability of entry. As S. Holden, C. Riis I ht. .I. Ind. Organ. 12 (1994) 549-568 56.5 k’-1 pk’= 1 - c k=r (11) Pk. We can use (9) recursively, and (lo), to find the relationship between the probabilities of entry in all periods with strictly positive probability of entry. For a given first period with strictly positive probability of entry, (9), (10) and (11) give us the necessary equations so that we can solve for unique values of the p’s. It then remains to find r. This can be done by the following iterative procedure, where we set r = k’ initially. (1) Assume that r is the first period with strictly positive probability of entry, thus p, > 0 for all s 2 r, while p, = 0 for all s <r. (2) Construct the equilibrium strategies by using (9), (10) and (11). (3) Check whether the following condition holds: If (A8) holds, both firms will strictly prefer to enter in period r - 1. Thus, we set r = r - 1 and return to (1). If (AS) does not hold, then we know that (8) holds. As L’(t) > 0 in the relevant interval (t < t*), (8) also implies that L, cp,S, + c p,L,, J>r all k < r. (A9) In this case no firm will profit by entering before period r, and we have found the first period with strictly positive probability of entry. We know that the procedure will stop, and a unique first period will be found, because if we come close enough to time zero then, the expected profits of being the leader will become negative. As the expected profits in equilibrium are positive, (A9) must hold before this point. QED Proof of Proposition 4. That the expected profits converge to L(t*) is equivalent to expected profits being in the interval (L(t*) - CT,L(t*) + a). We first show that the expected profits are at least L(t*) - (T. From Proposition 1 we know that a firm can obtain at least L(t* - E) by entering at time t* - F, as there is no risk of simultaneous entry then. Since L(t) is continuous, any firm can obtain at least L(t*) - cr, for sufficiently small F. We then show that expected profits cannot be more than L(t*) + cr. In cases 1 and 3 this is immediate from two observations: (1) L(t) and F(t) are continuous, and (2) Proposition 1 ensures that entry occurs sufficiently close to t*. In case 2, F(t) is discontinuous, and we may have FD > L(t*). Consider first the possibility that the probability of entry before t* is zero, H(P) = 0. In this case the expected profits must be lower than L(t* + E) by Proposition 1, and thus less than L(t*) + (T for sufficiently small E. Consider S. Holden. C. Riis I Int. J. Ind. Organ. 12 (1994) 549%-568 566 then the possibility that H(t*) > 0. This implies that the firms have a positive probability of entering before t*. In a mixed strategy equilibrium, firms are indifferent to each of the alternatives they mix over. The expected profits of entering in the first period with a positive probability of entry cannot be higher than L(t*). QED Proof of Proposition 5. In case 1, where F(t*) = FD = L(t*), the probability of simultaneous entry can be inferred directly from Proposition 4. As the expected payoffs of the firms are equal to the payoffs each of the firms receive if there is not simultaneous entry (L(t*)), whereas the payoff under simultaneous entry is lower, it follows that the probability of simultaneous entry must converge to zero with the period length. In case 3, where L(t*) = 0, neither of the players will enter before t* as L(t)<0 for t <t*. Thus, the probability of simultaneous entry can be inferred directly from Proposition 4, just as above. We now turn to case 2, where F(t*) = FD > L(t*) > 0. We first show that the probability that the entry occurs before or at t* is strictly positive. Assume the opposite, that Gi(t*) = G,(t*) = 0, and consider firm i’s decision in the last period before or at t*. If firm i deviates by entering it will obtain L(t*), whereas in a symmetric equilibrium it can at most expect L(t*)/2 if it waits to after t*. Thus, it is optimal to deviate, and we know that G,(t*) > 0. First consider subcase (a), where S(t*) < 0, where we first find H(t*), the probability that an entry occurs before or at t*. In a mixed strategy equilibrium, firm j must be indifferent as to whether it will enter ‘early“‘ and become leader with certainty [payoff L(t*) when the period length converges to zero], or wait and let the other firm enter first, i.e. plan a ‘late’ entry (in the hope that the other firm enters before t*).The expected payoff of firm j if j plans to enter so late that i is almost certain to have entered, is (A 10) G,(t*)FD, where Gi(t*) is the probability that firm i enters before or at t*. As firm j mixes over both these alternatives, we must have L(t*) equal to (AlO), which is equivalent to G;(t*) = L(t*)IFD. Thus, in a symmetric (All) equilibrium, H(t*) = 1 - [l - G&*)1* = [L(t*)(2FD - L(t*))]/(FD)* > 0. (13) We then proceed to find the probability of simultaneous entry after t*, conditional on no entry having taken place before t* [p+(S)]. Observe that if no entry has taken place by t*, the expected payoff of entering in a late period is zero, as this entails becoming the follower (almost) with certainty. S. Holden, 561 C. Riis I Int. J. Ind. Organ. 12 (1994) 549-568 As this is one of the alternatives firm j mixes over, the expected payoff of firm j, given that no entry has occurred before t*, must be equal to zero. The expected payoff of j can however also be calculated in another way. If there is no simultaneous entry, j has probability one-half of becoming the leader, and one-half of becoming the follower (as the firms use symmetric strategies). Thus the payoff of firm j if no entry has occurred before t*, is [l -p’(S)]L(t*)/2 and by setting p’(S) this expression = L(t*)l[L(t*) Observe that becoming the is strictly less We are now denoted p-(S). equal to zero we obtain - 2S(t*)] > 0. (14) it is only because simultaneous entry is strictly worse than follower [,S(t*) < 0] that the probability of simultaneous entry than one. ready to find the probability of simultaneous entry before t*, The ex ante expected payoff of firm j, is -p-(S))(L(t*) H(t*)[(l (A121 +p+(S)S(t*), + FD)/2 +p-(S)S(t*)] + (1 - H(t*))O, (A13) where the first (last) term is the payoff if the entry takes place before (after) t*, and where we in the last term have inserted that the expected payoff is zero if no entry has taken place before t*. From Proposition 4 it follows that (A13) is equal to L(t*), and we can solve for p-(S) to obtain p_(S) = [H(t*)(L(t*) + FD) + (1 - H(t*))O - 2L(t*)]/ [H(t*)(L(t*) = L(t*)(FD + FD - 2S(t*))], - L(t*))I[(2FD - L(t*))(L(t*) + FD - 2S(t*))] >o. (12) As all terms are strictly positive, it is clear that In case 2(b), where F(t*) = FD > L(t*) > S(t*) 2 that if there is no entry by t”, then there will certainty in period k’, the first period after expected payoff of firm j if it plans to enter in G;(t*)FD which, that + (1 - G,(t*))S(t*), by the same argument equilibrium, (Ala) as above, G;(t*) = [L(t*) - S(t*)]/[FD In a symmetric p-(S) is greater that zero. 3 0, it is clear from Lemma be simultaneous entry with t*, so that p+(S) = 1. The period k’ is must -S(P)]. it follows that be equal to L(P), implying (AN 568 S. Holden, C. Riis I Int. J. Ind. Organ. 12 (1994) 549-568 H(t*) = 1 - [l - Gi(t*)]* = 1 - [(FD - L(t*))I(FD The ex ante payoff N(t*)[(l - &s(t*))]’ > 0. (16) of firm j is -pP(S))(L(t*) + FD)/2 +p_(S)S(t*)] + (1- H(t*))S(t*), (‘416) which must p_(S) be equal to L(t*). This yields = [L(t*) - (1 - H(t*))S(t*) - H(t*)(L(t*) + FD)12]I{[S(t*) - (I&*) + FD)/2]H(t*)} >o. Substituting out for H(t*) from (16) shows that p-(S) (15) > 0. QED References Anderson, A. and M. Engers, 1990, Strategic investment and timing of entry: Stackelberg equilibrium with rent dissipation, Paper presented at World Congress of Econometric Society in Barcelona. Cabral, L., 1989, Essays in industrial organization and regulation. PhD Dissertation, Stanford University. Dixit, A. and C. Shapiro, 1986, Entry dynamics with mixed strategies, in: L. Thomas, ed., The economics of strategic planning (Lexington Books, Lexington, KY). Dutta, P.K. and R. Sundaram, 1992, Markovian equilibrium in a class of stochastic games: Existence theorems for discounted and undiscounted models, Economic Theory 2, 197-214. Fudenberg, D. and J. Tirole, 1985, Preemption and rent equalization in the adoption of new technology, Review of Economic Studies, LB, 383-401. Gilbert, R.J., 1987, Mobility barriers and the value of incumbency, in: R. Schmalensee and R. Willig, eds., Handbook of industrial organization (North-Holland, Amsterdam). Gilbert, R.J. and R.G. Harris. 1984, Competition with lumpy investment, Rand Journal of Economics 2, 197-212. Mills, D.E., 1988, Preemptive investment timing, Rand Journal of Economics 19, 114-122. Posner, R., 1975, The social cost of monopoly and regulation, Journal of Political Economy 83, 525-542. Robson, A.J., 1990, Duopoly with endogenous strategic timing: Stackelberg regained, International Economic Review 31, 263-274. Simon, L. and M. Stinchcombe, 1989, Extensive form games in continuous time: Pure strategies, Econometrica 57, 1171-1214.