A Theory of Policy Expertise∗ Steven Callander† June 11, 2007 Abstract This paper presents a new theory of policy expertise. In contrast to existing theories, I define expertise as direct knowledge of the policy process itself. Thus, expertise represents an understanding of how policies are transformed into outcomes, and does not reduce to the possession of a single piece of information (as in standard models), resonating more closely with how expertise is commonly understood. To establish the usefulness of the theory, I apply it to the well-studied problem of delegation and show that it provides a solution to the commitment problem of legislative-bureaucratic policy making. The theory also provides a measure of issue complexity, and predicts that only complex issues are delegated, consistent with empirical observation. The theory also opens up many further questions and applications, several of which are considered here. ∗ For helpful comments I thank Jonathan Bendor, Chuck Cameron, Olivier Compte, Sven Feldman, Sean Gailmard, Tom Hammond, John Hatfield, Keith Krehbiel, John Patty, and several seminar audiences. † Managerial Economics and Decision Sciences, Kellogg School of Management, Northwestern University, Evanston, IL 60208; scal@kellogg.northwestern.edu. It is by now well understood that expertise plays a central role in policy making. This fact, first articulated by Max Weber, raises a fundamental question: what does it mean to be an expert? Over recent decades models of policy have come to rely on a particular conception of expertise, encapsulated in the now-canonical “cheap-talk” model of Crawford and Sobel (1982). This model, borrowed from economics, provides a parsimonious and tractable theory of policy formation, and has formed the theoretical foundation for numerous influential studies of politics, ranging from Gilligan and Krehbiel’s (1987, 1989) seminal work into committee structure and legislative organization, to the enormous literature on Legislative-Executive branch relations (Bendor, Glazer, and Hammond 2000, and Huber and Shipan 2006, provide reviews), and even political debate (Austen-Smith 1990). Although the canonical formulation of the “cheap-talk” model is attractively simple, it provides a limited conception of expertise. According to this approach, expertise is equivalent to the possession of a single piece of information. This definition is not only discordant with expertise as commonly understood, but in the policy process it produces several peculiar properties. Most notably, it implies that a single statement from an expert can render an intelligent layperson an expert. For example, according to the canonical model a patient may acquire complete medical expertise upon hearing a single diagnosis from a doctor. Simplifications are necessary, of course, in any theoretical enterprise. Yet those inherent in the canonical model are excessive and I argue that these shortcomings not only limit our understanding of expertise but, more substantially, cast doubt on the structural soundness of all research built upon its foundation. In this paper I propose a new theory of policy expertise, one that is more suited to the political environment. In contrast to the canonical model, I define expertise over the policy process directly. In this theory an expert possesses superior knowledge of the process by which policy instruments are transformed into outcomes. Expertise can be, therefore, much more than the mere possession of a single piece of information. This representation is more in accordance with the common understanding of expertise, as described by Bendor, Taylor, and Van Gaalen (1985): “... bureaucrats [experts] typically possess special insight into the relation between programs and consequences.” The advantages of this approach are several. In particular, the theory provides a measure of the complexity of expertise, allowing policy issues to be categorized according to the varying degrees of simplicity and complexity observed in practice. To demonstrate the power of the new theory, I apply it to the study of policy-making, taking the legislative-bureaucratic relationship as my leading example. A central tenet of 1 this relationship is that the delegation of authority — although frequent — is not irrevocable as Congress always retains the right to pass overriding legislation. This power creates a dilemma: if Congress can learn from the expert recommendations of an agency, what prevents it from using this information toward its own ends? In principle, the canonical model of policy provides no barrier and Congress’ ability to subvert agency expertise gives rise to a problem of commitment. Congress’ inability to commit to the delegation of authority implies that agencies cannot protect their expertise from Congressional oversight, undermining the rationale for agency expertise and delegation more generally. Moreover, this puts Congress in the position of power, a conclusion in conflict with the traditional “Weberian” view of policy making.1 The theory of expertise I introduce avoids these difficulties, providing a solution to the commitment problem. This finding provides a formal explanation for agency power in the face of de jure legislative authority, thereby reconciling the formal treatment of policy development with the Weberian perspective. Central to this finding is the complexity of policy expertise. By offering a richer conception of expertise, the theory establishes exactly when and how Congress is able to subvert an agency’s expertise. I prove that only if issues are complex can Congress productively delegate authority and agencies be induced to develop expertise, a finding that resonates well with empirical and anecdotal evidence (Ringquist 1995; Epstein and O’Halloran 1999). My results contrast with and complement the standard institutional-constraint approach taken in the literature (Weingast and Moran 1983; Epstein and O’Halloran 1994, 1999; etc.). This line of work, in recognition of the natural constraints to action built-in to political systems, incorporates exogenous constraints — or frictions — into models of policy making. These frictions restore agency power by restricting Congress’ ability to override agency actions. To highlight the difference between this approach and the one proposed here, the model I develop is intentionally frictionless, showing that the power of bureaucratic agencies I identify is due to the complexity of expertise and not exogenous constraints. The difference between the institutional-constraint approach and my expertise-based model is seen most clearly in what they each imply for the nature of agenda control. As Bendor et al (1985) observe, agency power derives from an ability to control the policy making agenda, although this power comes from two sources: official control of the alternatives that can be offered for consideration, and unofficial control that is wielded merely through the authority of expertise. Bendor et al refer to these two sources as 1 Weber viewed the agency as powerful, concluding that “Under normal conditions, the power position of a fully developed bureaucracy is always overtowering. The “political master” finds himself in the position of the “dilettante” who stands opposite the “expert.”” (Quoted from Gerth and Mills (1958), page 232). 2 Type 1 and Type 2 agenda control, respectively (see also Weber in Gerth and Mills 1958). The frictions of the institutional-constraint approach induce agenda control that is closer in spirit to Type 1. In contrast, no such constraints are present in my theory and any power obtained by the agency is purely of Type 2. A formal explanation for Type 2 agenda control, such as is provided here, is of interest not just as a counterpoint to existing results, for as Bendor et al (1985, p. 1042) argue, Type 2 control is itself an empirically relevant case (see also Miller and Moe 1983): “A bureau’s influence rests not on it formal authority [Type 1] — its ability to manipulate the rules — but, as Weber noted, its control of information, its ability to manipulate either the construction of policy alternatives or information about the consequences of different alternatives [Type 2].” The theory also offers predictions about the nature of delegation should it occur. On complex issues an expert agency is fully empowered when delegated to and acts as if the threat of oversight did not exist, always achieving its own ideal policy outcome. In contrast to standard models with imperfect oversight, the agency does not shade its policy proposal toward the legislator’s preference. I also find that the types of agencies to whom authority is delegated, as well as the conditions under which delegation occurs, differ from extant models, most notably predicting a failure of the famous ally principle. The legislative-bureaucratic relationship is but one instance of policy making and the theory is applicable more broadly. It applies with equal force to informational theories of legislative organization founded by Gilligan and Krehbiel (1987, 1989), which also employ the canonical cheap-talk model of expertise and faces a similar problem of commitment (Diermeier 1995). The theory is also relevant to decision making in the absence of delegation, in static and dynamic environments, and within governments, bureaucracies, and private firms.2 In fact, it can be applied to any decision making situation in which actions are distinct from outcomes and connected by a “policy” process, including political debate. The conception of expertise offered here is informational, and in this sense shares a lineage with the canonical model. Although this formulation is open to broad interpretation, it does not capture expertise in its full breadth. An alternative perspective views expertise as an ability (or a strategy) rather than a difference in knowledge (Page 2006, 2007; Hong and Page 2001). Reconciling these different perspectives is difficult if information-based expertise is limited to a single piece of information. By offering a richer theory, I provide the generality necessary to complement the work of Page and others. Integrating these ideas is a natural objective of future work. 2 Aghion and Tirole’s (1997) concept of formal and real authority is reminiscent of the earlier Type I and II agenda control of Bendor et al. (1987), although their focus is not on the information extraction problem that is central here. 3 POLICY PROCESSES AND EXPERTISE Policy outcomes can seldom (if ever) be chosen directly. Rather, policy makers choose policy instruments (referred to simply as policies) that, once implemented, deliver outcomes, and it is these outcomes that directly motivate political actors. Denote the set of policy instruments by I and the set of outcomes by O. Policies are transformed into outcomes by a policy process ψ, such that ψ : I → O. An issue is defined by the set of possible policy processes, denoted by Ψ where ψ ∈ Ψ. In this setting a natural definition of an expert — and the one adopted here — is someone (or some organization) with superior knowledge of ψ; that is, superior knowledge as to which ψ in Ψ is the true process. Put less formally, one is said to be an expert if one possesses superior knowledge to the layman about how policies are mapped into outcomes. Both laymen and experts possess beliefs about the true mapping ψ, which are denoted by α (.) and φ (.), respectively. These beliefs in turn induce, for a given policy instrument, beliefs over outcomes; in a slight abuse of notation, let α (o|p) represent the probability a layman assigns to instrument p ∈ I producing outcome o ∈ O, and φ (o|p) the corresponding belief of an expert. If the expert possesses complete knowledge of the policy process then his beliefs φ (.) are degenerate.3 With a conception of expertise in hand, it is now possible to explore both the nature of expertise and how it affects decision making. Three components of expertise are prominent. The first two are straightforward and are present in standard models: the cost and difficulty of attaining expertise, and the informational advantage an expert holds over a layman (reflected in the tightness of expert beliefs φ versus those of α). The third component, complexity, is less obvious but equally important to policy making, and is the focus of much of the analysis here. Complexity describes the interrelation of different pieces of expert knowledge, measuring how the outcomes of different policies are connected (or correlated). For example, if one possesses superior knowledge about the current state of social security, this should translate into superior — but not perfect — knowledge of the likely outcomes from social security privatization, with the accuracy of this knowledge depending on the complexity of the issue. In the following sections I provide a formal definition of issue complexity and use this measure to categorize the different degrees of expertise that are possible. Extreme Policy Processes According to the canonical model, policy follows the simple process: ψ: 3 x = p + θ, A degenerate distribution assigns all belief to a single outcome (no uncertainty remains). 4 (1) policy outcome x 6θ = 2 θ = 1 θ=0 ¡ ¡ ¡ ¡ ¡ ¡ ¡ ¡ ¡ ¡ ¡ ¡ θ = −1 ¡ ¡ ¡ ¡ ¡ ¡ ¡ ¡ ¡ ¡ ¡ ¡ ¡ ¡ θ = −2 ¡ ¡ ¡ ¡ ¡ ¡ ¡ ¡ ¡ -p ¡ ¡ 0 ¡ ¡ ¡ ¡ policy ¡ ¡ ¡ ¡ ¡ instrument ¡ ¡ ¡ ¡ ¡ ¡ ¡ ¡ ¡ ¡ ¡ ¡ ¡ ¡ ¡ ¡ ¡ ¡ ¡ ¡ ¡ ¡ ¡ ¡ ¡ ¡ ¡ ¡ ¡ Figure 1: The Canonical Model: ψ (p) : x = p + θ where x is the outcome, p the policy instrument chosen, and θ is a shock, or state of the world.4 The central assumption in this model is that expert and laymen alike know that the policy process (ψ) is linear and additive in components, with the only difference being that the expert possesses knowledge of θ whereas the layperson does not. Thus, both players know how policies are mapped into outcomes and the difference between them reduces to a single piece of information. Formally, the canonical model restricts the set Ψ of possible mappings to consist entirely of functions of the form of Equation 1, differing only in the value of θ. Figure 1 depicts the possible policy processes for various realizations of θ. The key property of this structure is that the potential policy processes do not intersect (all lines have slope one and differ only in the intercept term). This allows the processes to be easily distinguished from one another such that the revelation of a single fact exposes the true policy process, rendering a layman an expert. For instance, learning that ψ (2) = 4 implies with certainty that θ = 2 and that the policy process is described by x = p + 2. I refer to expertise that satisfies this property as perfectly invertible.5 If expertise is invertible for every process in an issue — as in the canonical model — I say 4 The original assumptions of Crawford and Sobel (1982) generalize this form in several respects, although the following criticisms apply to their general structure with equal force. 5 More formally, expertise over a process ψ is invertibile if for each p ∈ P and ψ 0 ∈ Ψ, ψ (p) 6= ψ 0 (p). Invertibility depends, therefore, on ψ as well as the composition of the set Ψ (this definition allows for some ψ ∈ Ψ to be invertible and others not). Note that invertibility does not depend on linearity or monotonicity of the policy process. 5 that the issue itself is invertible. As is evident, the canonical model represents an extreme and simplistic view of the policy process. To see the type of issue to which this model can be applied, it is helpful to consider a simple example. Consider a man who wishes to learn which day of the week it is (an absentminded professor perhaps) and who consults an expert with knowledge of the current day. Suppose that the expert does not answer the man’s question directly but does inform him that tomorrow is Tuesday. Obviously this is not the information the man seeks. However, the man is nevertheless able to infer from it that the current day is Monday. He is able to do this as the expert’s information answers a related question, and the man knows how the answers to these questions are connected. More specifically, the man knows the process by which days of the week are connected (if he did not possess even this knowledge the difference between an expert and layman would be much greater). Consequently, in learning that tomorrow is Tuesday the layman is instantly updated to expert status with respect to days of the week, knowing not only the current day but also that in four days it will be Friday. This example fits the canonical model precisely. In fact, the canonical model only describes issues that possess expertise of similar simplicity. For instance, for it to apply it must be that all players agree — laymen and experts alike — on the ordering of policies and outcomes. That is, experts and laymen both know that a larger instrument p leads to a larger outcome x, for any realization of θ. In fact, it is required that all players are aware that an increase in p induces the exact same increase in x, regardless of the state of the world (e.g., that tomorrow and today are always one day apart). Not surprisingly, it is rather difficult to imagine real policy issues that satisfy these extreme conditions. Even for numerate issues such as the minimum wage, knowledge of the status quo (which corresponds to a point in the mapping) does not educate nonexperts on what to expect from a $1 increase. In practice policy processes are neither linear nor monotonic, and often are rather chaotic. More importantly, the functional form of the mapping is itself not clear and expertise is far from invertible. To adequately capture expertise, therefore, a more general framework is required. Occupying the opposite extreme to the canonical model is the category of noninvertible policy processes. Non-invertible expertise is so complex that knowledge about outcomes is unrelated across policy instruments. Therefore, learning one point in the mapping reveals nothing about other policy instruments (in contrast, for invertible issues it reveals everything). To be sure, learning that ψ (p) = x allows a layman to rule out any process that does not pass through this point, but this information does not reduce the set of possible policy processes enough for the layman to learn about other instruments. To accommodate this property, both the types of processes allowed and the breadth of the issue itself (the set Ψ of available processes) must be substantially more general than 6 in the canonical model. Non-invertible processes do not submit to a particular functional form or even family of functions, and the processes need not be continuous (although they can be). In fact, from a layman’s perspective, a non-invertible policy process is essentially a random function, with the outcome from different policy instruments — even those that are “close” — entirely uncorrelated with one another. If every process in an issue is non-invertible I say the issue itself is non-invertible. To see the type of expertise this extreme entails, let us again turn to a simple example (that approaches the extreme of non-invertibility). Suppose the same man has now suffered a significant leg wound and consults a doctor. The doctor informs him that band-aids are an effective treatment for minor abrasions. As before, the expert has answered a related question, but in this case the information provided is less useful to the man. He not only is not updated to expert status, but arguably is no better positioned to choose his optimal treatment.6 Indeed, were the man to suffer a heart attack one could be sure the doctor’s advice on band-aids would be entirely useless. The difference between this and the days of the week example is the complexity of expertise. Medical expertise — as with expertise on all complex issues — is more than the mere possession of a single piece of information, and does not fit the canonical specification. Non-invertible expertise takes complexity to the extreme. As with perfectly invertible expertise, public policy examples that fit this extreme perfectly are difficult to come by. Despite the lack of realism, however, non-invertibility is the natural counterpoint to invertible mappings and the canonical model. It may be extreme to assume outcomes are completely independent, but it serves to show that the opposing assumption of perfect invertibility within the canonical model is equally extreme. Invertible and non-invertible policy processes are defined formally as follows. These extreme cases cover only a fraction of all possible processes. I label the remaining processes (and issues) as partially invertible, and take up this case in the following section. Definition 1 Suppose the layperson learns ψ (p) = y, where p ∈ I and y ∈ O, and using Bayes’ rule forms the updated beliefs β (.|p). (i) ψ is invertible if β (.|q) is a degenerate distribution for each q 6= p. (ii) ψ is non-invertible if α (x|q) ≡ β (x|q) for each q 6= p and x ∈ O. (iii) If the policy process is neither invertible nor non-invertible, it is partially invertible. Partially Invertible Policy Processes Reality, most often, lies somewhere between the extremes, and partially invertible policy processes more accurately capture expertise as it is commonly understood. The set of partially invertible policy processes and issues is enormous, covering every possible case except those of the two extremes. 6 If the blood loss is 100 times that from a minor cut, should the patient apply 100 band-aids? 7 Although partial invertibility is by itself a step closer to reality, it gives rise to more questions about the nature of expertise. For instance, what exactly does a layman learn from the recommendation of an expert (if it is neither everything nor nothing)? Does learning depend on the issue itself? Can some potential outcomes be ruled out? Does a layman learn different things about different policies? To accurately capture the policy process, therefore, it is necessary to push beyond the issue of invertibility and refine the set of processes and issues further. Generalizing the canonical model is, however, not straightforward. A principal reason for the longevity of the canonical model is its simple representation of policy. To usefully generalize this model it is necessary to obtain a tractable family of policy processes that satisfies partial invertibility as well as address the questions raised in the previous paragraph. Unfortunately, simple generalizations with common functional forms (such as linear, quadratic, or any polynomial form) exhibit some (and often many) undesirable properties. To see the possibilities that may arise, consider a simple generalization of the canonical model in which the slope of the policy process is also unknown, taking on values of either ±1. If in this case a layman learns that ψ (0) = y he can rule out many possibilities but not all as he is unsure whether the true policy process is x = p + y or x = −p + y. Although relaxing full invertibility, a shortcoming of this specification is that the layman learns equally about policies that are close to the observed policy (≈ 0) and policies that are far away (as he knows they must be determined by one of two possible processes). In practice, however, the accuracy of beliefs depends on how “far” policy is moved from what is known. For example, as Congress observes the outcome produced by the current minimum wage level, it seems reasonable that they then possess more accurate information about the outcome that would arise from a reduction to $5 than if the wage were lowered all the way to $1.7 This is not the limit of the example’s unattractiveness as also retained from the canonical model are the restrictive assumptions that policy is linear, additive, and monotonic. In combination, these shortcomings confirm that partial invertibility is a necessary but not sufficient condition to accurately describe policy processes. An Analytic Representation To provide a richer description of expertise, I propose that the policy process ψ possess the properties of a Brownian motion. More specifically, I suppose that an issue be defined by the set of Brownian motions with drift µ and variance σ 2 . Thus, on any particular issue a layman knows that the process is a Brownian motion of parameters µ and σ 2 , with the nature of the issue varying in these parameters, but he does not know the realized path. 7 Similarly, the doctor’s advice on a minor cut is more useful to a patient suffering a larger cut than to one suffering from mental illness. 8 Although the application to policy formation is novel, Brownian motions have been applied productively in other areas of political science (Carpenter 2002, 2004) and are well suited to the policy environment. Moreover, the mathematical formulation of a Brownian motion is simple, tractable, and relatively intuitive. This parsimony aids considerably the analysis of the following section and should be equally helpful in other applications. A Brownian motion is a continuous stochastic process with stationary independent increments. Brownian motions are normally associated with movement through time, although time plays no role here. Rather, as with the canonical model, the policy instrument is the independent variable. To understand the Brownian motion, consider the movement of a stock price, a common application. Suppose the price of a stock is x at time t and we are interested in its price at time t + ∆. If the price follows a Brownian motion then we don’t know for sure what the price will be at t + ∆ — indeed it may be any price — but we do have beliefs over the possibilities. For a Brownian motion with drift µ and variance σ 2 , beliefs as to the time t + 1 price are distributed normally with mean (x + ∆µ) and variance |∆| · σ 2 . The drift measures the expected rate of change of the price and the variance the risk involved. Worthy of note for this process is that changes in the stock price — increments of the Brownian motion — depend only on the current price and are stationary (dependent neither on the value of t, the independent variable, nor the current value of the motion — the stock price). To understand how the Brownian motion is applied to policy expertise, it is useful to compare its construction with that of the canonical model. In both theories one can interpret the construction as follows: determine a point in the mapping by randomly choosing a point in the policy space (instrument and outcome), say ψ (p̃) = y, and from this point construct the rest of the mapping in either direction. The difference between the models is that the canonical model requires that the mapping proceed with slope one in either direction (and the randomly chosen point fully determines the process), whereas here the path is determined by a Brownian motion in either direction, allowing for much more variety. In both models the policy path is fully constructed prior to any interaction between policy makers, and an expert is fully aware of the realized path. The difference in construction between the theories leads to differences in the beliefs of a layman, and it is here that the Brownian motion approach bears fruit. If the layman learns that ψ (p̃) = y then he knows that the policy mapping passes through this point and is a Brownian motion with parameters µ and σ 2 . His beliefs over ψ (p), therefore, are dependent on the value y, the parameters µ and σ 2 , and the size of the policy adjustment p − p̃. Specifically, the expected value of ψ (p) is equal to: y + µ (p − p̃) . From the perspective of a layman, however, the true realization of ψ (p) is a random variable distributed normally with variance |p − p̃| σ 2 , which is increasing linearly in the 9 policy outcome x £ £ £ 6 ¢@ ¢ @ ­A ©¢ © ­ A ¡y A¡ ¢ 0 ¢ ¢ © © ¢ ¢ ££@ @¢ »P » P ψ (p) ¢ ¢ ³¢ slope = µ ³ -p policy instrument Figure 2: Partially Invertible Policy Process ψ (p): drift µ, variance σ 2 , and ψ (0) = y distance of the policy p from p̃. (As a point of contrast, the canonical model in this instance implies with certainty that θ = y − p̃ and ψ (p) = p − p̃ + y.) Figure 2 shows a Brownian motion that passes through ψ (0) = y, and depicts the drift line through this point. As depicted in the figure, the path of a partially invertible policy process need not be monotonic and may have many changes of direction (the drift line describes only the expected value of the path conditional on ψ (0) = y and not the actual path). The Brownian motion offers several advantages as an analytic representation of policy processes, several of which are listed in Table 1.8 The Brownian motion is both partially invertible and proportionally invertible, the latter capturing the idea that how much a layman learns about a policy instrument depends on how “close” it is to the policy for which the outcome is known. In particular, with a Brownian motion the accuracy of layman beliefs about a policy are proportional to the distance the policy is from a policy for which the outcome is known. The parameters of the Brownian motion (µ and σ 2 ) offer a measure of issue complexity. For fixed µ, an increase in the variance σ 2 reduces the information a layman can infer from expert actions; consequently, the larger is σ 2 the more complex is the policy issue. As the same property holds if σ 2 is held fixed and µ decreases, it is most useful to 8 Observations from the rich history of policy making (see, for instance, Carpenter 2001) are consistent with many of these properties yet they by no means provide an exhaustive account. Additional properties — such as non-stationarity or discontinuities — could be captured by using more general stochastic processes, such as a Levy process. 10 Properties of Policy Issues: 1. 2. 3. Properties of Policy Processes: 4. 5. 6. Partial invertibility. Proportional invertibility. A continuum of simple and complex issues. Full support. Continuity. Non-monotonicity. Table 1: Properties of Brownian Motions 2 represent issue complexity by the ratio σµ , which may vary continuously. It is then the 2 2 case that issue complexity is increasing in σµ . The limiting case σµ → ∞ represents issues of extreme complexity (non-invertible expertise) such as medical expertise. The 2 opposite extreme of σµ → 0 represents increasingly simple issues (invertible expertise), such as days of the week, with the broad range of intermediate values capturing the full gamut of policy issues and expertise between these extremes. Properties 4-6 in Table 1 reflect a policy process that is more complicated than the linear and additive processes in the canonical model. The Brownian motion offers full support over policy outcomes, is continuous (but not differentiable), and is non-monotonic. Full support captures the idea that laymen are ill informed about the impact of a policy change with beliefs dispersed over wide support rather than focused on two possibilities as in the simple generalization offered earlier. Continuity ensures that small changes in policy lead to small changes in outcomes (unlike for non-invertible processes). Finally, non-monotonicity implies that for a change in policy laymen can not be sure of not only the outcome that would result but even the direction of the change, a possibility precluded in the canonical model.9 The possibilities offered by the family of Brownian motions can be seen when applied to two issues that have presented classic examples of policy making in the United States: the minimum wage and environmental policy. Expertise on both of these issues is partially invertible, although to different degrees. As argued above, Congress is less than certain about how a change in the minimum wage would affect the economy. Despite this uncertainty, members of Congress (most likely) agree that an increase in the wage would produce a more liberal outcome and a decrease a more conservative outcome. This agreement on ordering is significant (just as it was important that the absent minded professor knew that Tuesday followed Monday), and consequently the minimum wage 2 issue represents a relatively low degree of complexity (and a low value of σµ ). 9 This requirement is not simply that a layman is unsure of the sign of the true process’ slope, but that the processes themselves are nonmonotonic. One may, of course, rearrange the policies such that the function is monotonic, but this merely transfers the uncertainty to knowledge of which orderings deliver monotonic processes. 11 In contrast, environmental policy is significantly more complex. For example, knowing the outcome from command-and-control regulation in the 1980’s informed Congress only minimally (if at all) about the outcome to expect from, say, a market for tradeable pollution permits. In fact, members of Congress may be so lacking in expertise as to not even be sure whether this change would lead to a more liberal or a more conservative 2 outcome.10 Consequently, environmental policy corresponds to a high value of σµ .11 Although these two issues are substantively different, technically they differ only in degree. Significantly, Congress has historically treated the two issues differently, delegating significant environmental policy making power to the EPA, whereas the minimum wage is decided within the legislature. In the following section I show that the difference in complexity between the issues provides an explanation for this pattern of real policy making. ISSUE COMPLEXITY AND DELEGATION A prominent and successful line of research in political science, beginning with the seminal work of Gilligan and Krehbiel (1987), has been the study of expertise and delegation in policy making. One stream of this work — and the one I will take as my leading example — is legislative-bureaucratic policy making. The central problem in this relationship is the legislature’s ability to take advantage of bureaucratic expertise while avoiding what is known as bureaucratic drift. Weber described the problem as follows (Gerth and Mills 1958, page 235):12 “Here an early concern of the ruler was how to exploit the special knowledge of experts without having to abdicate in their favor but preserve his dominant position.” Underlying every paper in the literature on delegation is a model of the policy process, and the process typically employed is the canonical model of expertise (Gilligan and Krehbiel 1987, 1989; Epstein and O’Halloran 1994, 1999; Huber and Shipan 2002; Bendor and Meirowitz 2004; Huber and McCarty 2004; etc.). As argued in the introduction, this conception of expertise leads to a commitment problem. I consider here a classic version of the delegation game and show how the commitment problem arises and how it depends critically on the invertibility of the policy process. 10 Esterling (2004, ch. 6) provides a case study of this legislation. While most interested parties agreed that tradeable permits would provide an efficiency gain, there was substantial uncertainty over the distributive impact of the policy (as well as the magnitude of the efficiency gain). 11 At least given the policy instruments under consideration. If more radical policy proposals were to be taken seriously — indentured servitude, perhaps — then consideration of wage laws may become more complex. 12 An analogous problem exists in the floor-committee relationship in legislatures studied by Gilligan and Krehbiel (1987). 12 A useful reference point for the following results is the foundational work of Bendor and Meirowitz (2004). In addition to providing a broad and thorough treatment of delegation models, Bendor and Meirowitz consider many variants and extensions of the canonical formulation. Two of these are particularly pertinent here. First, they allow generalized functional forms for policy processes and do not restrict attention to linear additive models. Second, they allow for both the endogenous acquisition of expertise and for Congress to ignore agency recommendations and pass overriding legislation. Critically, however, the power of override is withheld from Congress when the agency acquires expertise, which is exactly the case of interest here. The Model The players are a Legislator and an Agency, denoted shorthand by L and A, respectively. For simplicity the players are treated as unitary actors. Policy is chosen once and the players can either retain the status quo sq or choose a new policy instrument, where the set of alternative instruments is the real line; thus, I = {sq, R}.13 The outcome space is the real line, P = R. The legislator and agency possess ideal points in the outcomes space given by 0 and a, respectively, where a > 0. Both players have quadratic loss utility functions; the utility from outcome x is: uL (x) = −x2 , uA (x) = − (a − x)2 , where the subscript denotes the player. Risk aversion is not necessary for the results to follow but represents the default case in the literature (Bendor and Meirowitz 2004). I consider a simple delegation game that explicitly allows for the full Congressional power to override agency action. The structure of the game is consistent with classic models of delegation in the literature (modulo various extensions and generalizations; Bendor, Glazer, and Hammond 2000; Bendor and Meirowitz 2004; Huber and Shipan 2006). The sequence of play is given in Table 2. Policy instruments are mapped into outcomes via the function ψ ∈ Ψ, where the issue Ψ is either invertible, non-invertible, or partially invertible. For non-invertible issues I assume only that processes are onto functions, and for comparison suppose invertible issues are as specified in the canonical model.14 For partially invertible issues I restrict attention to the family of Brownian motions of drift µ and variance σ 2 , which with probability one are onto functions. Thus, regardless of the complexity of expertise, both 13 Assuming that the status quo is an element of R adds technical difficulty to the following analysis without substantively changing the underlying intuition. 14 An onto function (also known as a surjective function) requires that for each y ∈ R an x exists such that ψ (x) = y. 13 Stage 1: The legislator chooses whether to delegate. If not jump to stage 4. Stage 2: The agency decides whether to acquire expertise. Stage 3: The agency proposes a policy instrument & the legislator updates beliefs. Stage 4: The legislator chooses whether to acquire expertise. Stage 5: The legislator decides whether to override the agency proposal; if so it chooses a policy instrument. Stage 6: The selected policy instrument is implemented and mapped into a policy outcome; payoffs are determined. Table 2: Timing of the Delegation Game the legislator and agency possess induced ideal policy instruments (that map into their ideal outcomes), although such policies may not be unique.15 The legislator and the agency both begin the game as laypeople with equal knowledge of ψ, knowing µ and σ 2 but not the realized path. Expertise is a binary variable and, if obtained, the bearer gains perfect knowledge of the policy process (expert beliefs φ are degenerate). The cost of expertise to each player is cL , cA ≥ 0. I focus on the case cL = cA = c > 0, ensuring that the emergence of agency expertise is due to issue complexity and not cost asymmetries; I consider the asymmetric cost case as an extension in the appendix (including the commonly studied case of cA = 0). If, from a layman’s perspective, ψ maps the status quo with certainty into the legislator’s ideal outcome there is no need for delegation (nor the acquisition of expertise). Therefore, I consider issues in which the status quo delivers an outcome that is uncertain and distributed uniformly around 0 with support [−i, i].16 For other policies, as one may expect, uncertainty about outcomes is greater than for the status quo. I adopt the standard assumption in the literature that prior beliefs for all p ∈ R are distributed uniformly over the outcome space (Gilligan and Krehbiel 1987, 1989, Epstein and 15 As Brownian motions are stochastic processes, a player’s most preferred policy corresponds to their ideal policy with probability one. 16 This uncertainty arises naturally with the evolution of technology or the arrival of an exogenous shock, such as an election that changes the composition of the legislature. An alternative formulation would be to assume the status quo delivers a known outcome that differs from 0. 14 O’Halloran 1994).17 As discussed in the introduction, the focus here is on Type 2 rather than Type 1 agency agenda control (Bendor et al 1985), and I assume the legislator can costlessly override an agency recommendation. This assumption impacts the nature of communication between the agency and legislator, with policy recommendations now taking the form of costless messages. I restrict the channel of communication to be the proposal of a policy instrument and, by the revelation principle, I study equilibria in which policy recommendations reflect the information they convey.18 The equilibrium concept is Perfect Bayesian Equilibrium (PBE). I restrict attention to equilibria in which delegation occurs only when it is strictly preferred. That is, the legislator delegates only if the agency acquires expertise and the legislator benefits from this information. Informally, this restriction says that delegation is used only when it is “value added.” Utility is written as uL (y|J) when the policy outcome is y and player J ∈ {L, A, ∅} has paid the cost of expertise, where ∅ represents the null set; uA (y|J) is analogous (in equilibrium at most one player develops expertise). Note finally that utility is independent of the policy instrument chosen and the identity of the expert (other than through the cost of expertise c). Results I begin by establishing two simple properties that serve as outside options for the players. First, consider the optimal policy choice of either player in the absence of expertise. In this case the optimal action is to either choose a policy at random or retain the status quo. By construction, it is always optimal to retain the status quo, which delivers reservation utilities: 1 uL (sq|∅) = − i2 , 3 1 2 uA (sq|∅) = − i − a2 . 3 Observe that these values differ as for the agency the outcome is both uncertain and has an expected value different from its ideal point. The legislator, in contrast, suffers 17 A uniform prior over the real line is known technically as improper. It is a common assumption in both statistics and formal models in the social sciences. For invertible issues it is equivalent to the assumption that θ is distributed uniformly over R. For partially invertible issues uniform beliefs can be constructed from θ by setting ψ (0) = θ and generating from this point the true mapping in either direction. 18 That is, if the agency reveals that ψ (p) = x it is conveyed by a recommendation of instrument p (rather than, for example, recommending p − ε and L knowing to adjust upwards). The restriction to this equilibrium is without loss of generality and is also efficient if the legislator incurs a cost to override (including to change) the agency’s proposal. 15 only from uncertainty. Gilligan and Krehbiel (1987) refer to these as informational and distributional costs, respectively. Second, the value of uL (sq|∅) implies that the legislator, if acting in isolation, acquires expertise only if the cost is less than the disutility of the status quo; that is, the legislator acquires expertise rather than accept the status quo if and only if c < 13 i2 . Denote this critical value by ciL = 13 i2 , and the analogous value for the agency by ciA (a) = 13 i2 + a2 . Delegation With Commitment Before analyzing the full model, I first solve for optimal delegation if the legislator can commit to the delegation of authority. This case is analytically simpler than the full model and, when contrasted to the full model, clearly exposes the role of commitment. The invertibility of expertise is immaterial in this environment as even if the legislator is able to invert the agency’s expertise it is unable to benefit from this knowledge. Consequently, if delegated to, the agency acts independently of oversight and implements its own ideal point (conditional on acquiring expertise). Formally, ignoring the commitment problem in delegation is equivalent to the following change to Step 3 of the delegation game: Step 3alt : Agency selects a policy instrument. Proceed to Step 6. Define the “Commitment Game” as that produced when Step 3alt is substituted for Step 3. Lemma 1 characterizes delegation in this environment. Lemma 1 Commitment game. If delegation occurs the agency acquires expertise and implements its own ideal point (the outcome is a). The domain of delegation is as follows. 2 (α) For c < ciL = i3 , the legislator delegates if and only if a < a1³, where´(a1 )2 = c. (β) For ciL < c < 2ciL , the legislator delegates if and only if a ∈ a2 , √i3 , where (a2 )2 + 1 2 i 3 = c. Proof. L delegates only if A acquires expertise, which requires c < ciA (a). This delivers: uL (a|A) = −a2 and uA (a|A) = −c. Comparing uL (a|A) to uL (sq|∅) and uL (0|L) implies L delegates only if a2 < min [c, ciL ]. The result follows by simple algebra. If granted authority the agency acquires expertise and, without the threat of oversight, chooses its ideal policy. Anticipating this response, the legislator is left with a stark choice: determine policy independently or receive the agency’s ideal outcome (a). These incentives lead to delegation of two types. In the domain of case α both the legislator and agency would acquire expertise. The agency’s ideal point is sufficiently close to 0, however, that the legislator prefers to 16 delegate and free-ride off the agency’s investment in expertise. Delegation in this case satisfies the famous ally principle (Bendor, Glazer, and Hammond, 2000). The delegation of case β is somewhat different. The legislator delegates to more extreme agencies as it is not prepared to acquire expertise itself. In this situation, the legislator’s point of comparison is the status quo, rendering attractive any agency up to a = √i3 . Of course, the legislator would like to delegate to any agency more centrist than this bound, but it is only the more extreme agencies in this set that are prepared to acquire expertise. If c > 2ciL both conditions cannot be satisfied simultaneously and no delegation occurs. Delegation of type β exploits the different willingness to pay of the players (and that the agency’s willingness to pay is an increasing function of a), and fails the ally principle.19 Delegation and Oversight In the absence of commitment the agency operates in the shadow of legislative oversight. Its ability to influence policy in this setting depends on its ability to control any advantage in expertise it obtains. The invertibility of expertise, therefore, is critical to successful delegation, and the following results are demarcated accordingly. In all subsequent results I return to the original delegation game without commitment. Invertible Policy Processes: A useful starting point is to ask: does the equilibrium behavior of the commitment game hold up in the absence of commitment? For invertible policy processes, the answer is a simple no. If the agency acquires expertise and reveals the policy that delivers outcome a (as occurs in the commitment game), the legislator can invert the agency’s expertise and use its power of override to implement its own ideal point.20 This implies immediately for simple issues that a lack of commitment changes the nature of delegation. In fact, Theorem 1 shows delegation is not only altered by the removal of commitment, but that it is fatally undermined. 19 Delegation of variety α but not β is produced if, as is standard, the issue is invertible and the status quo is modeled as a point in R. This difference reflects another peculiarity of the canonical model as when expertise is invertible a layman is able to “bias” the policy outcome even without acquiring expertise. For example, if sq ∈ R delivers an expected (but noisy) outcome of 0 then by simply choosing the policy a units to the right of the status quo a non-expert agency moves the expected outcome to its ideal point. The agency can, therefore, remove distributional uncertainty without acquiring expertise, reducing its willingness to pay for expertise to the same as the legislator (as then only informational uncertainty is relevant for both) and precluding delegation of type β. This path of play is unlikely to arise in practice as Congress would never accept the recommendation of an uninformed agency. (Restoring delegation of type β requires that the legislator possess veto power over agency proposals, such as is supplied by the closed rule in Gilligan and Krehbiel (1987), and that the acquisition or not of expertise is perfectly observable by the legislator.) 20 Gilligan and Krehbiel (1987; page 308) were aware of this property of the canonical model, although it has received little subsequent attention. 17 Theorem 1 Delegation does not occur if the policy process is invertible. Proof. If c < ciL necessary conditions for the agency to acquire expertise and the legislator to delegate are a > a1 and a < a1 , respectively, and delegation is not possible. Consider then c > ciL such that payoffs in the absence of delegation are uA (sq|∅) and uL (sq|∅). Suppose L delegates and the distribution of policy outcomes has mean x and variance γ (with quadratic preferences these are sufficient statistics to determine utility). Equilibrium requires that L sets x = 0, which is possible as ψ is invertible, and thus uA (.|A) = uL (.|A) − a2 − c. Successful delegation requires uA (.|A) > uA (sq|∅), 2 2 which implies uL (.|A) − c > − i3 , and c < i3 = ciL as uL (.|A) ≤ 0. This establishes a contradiction and the result follows.21 Delegation fails in this environment precisely because the agency cannot protect its expertise. In proposing a policy the agency reveals some of its expertise, and on simple issues the agency has such a small informational advantage that the legislator is able to appropriate all of the information for its own advantage. Put another way, the agency must use its expertise to influence policy, but doing so allows the legislator to steal it. This logic applies even if the agency offers less precise policy proposals — such as recommending only whether the legislator choose a “high” or a “low” policy, as in the partition equilibria of Crawford and Sobel (1982) — as the legislator is equally capable of appropriating noisy information. Surprisingly, the legislator’s inability to delegate in this environment is a direct result of its own power. Because the legislator is able to invert agency expertise, the agency is unwilling to invest in expertise, leaving the legislator worse off. The contrast between Lemma 1 and Theorem 1 captures how the commitment problem affects delegation under the canonical model. This failure of delegation implies that for Congress to benefit from delegation on simple issues it must find ways to “tie its own hands” and endow agencies with Type 1 agenda control. Non-Invertible Policy Processes: The difficulties with invertible expertise do not arise for more complex issues. In this case the agency recommendation reveals nothing about other policy instruments, even if the outcome from the proposed policy can be inferred precisely. Consequently, if the legislator were to override the agency with a different instrument, it would be doing so with only its prior beliefs to guide it. Delegation, therefore, presents the legislator with a stark choice: accept the agency’s ideal point or decide policy independently. This is the exact same choice the legislator faced in the commitment game and, not surprisingly, equilibrium behavior is closely related — but subtly different — to that in Lemma 1. 21 This result does not depend on cL = cA and applies directly to at least a range of values in which cA < cL ; see the treatment of asymmetric costs in the appendix. 18 i i Theorem ³ 2 For´ non-invertible policy the legislator delegates if and only if cL < c < 2cL and a ∈ a2 , √i3 , where (a2 )2 + 13 i2 = c. If delegated to, the agency develops expertise, recommends its ideal policy, and is not overridden by the legislator. Proof. Consider two cases. (i) c > ciL . If a < a2 the agency ³ does´not learn, and if i a > √3 L would ignore A. Thus, delegation occurs only if a ∈ a2 , √i3 . In this domain L accepts A’s ideal point rather than pay c and Lemma 1 establishes that it is in A’s interest to learn. (ii) c < ciL . L delegates to A only if a < a1 (Lemma 1), and if A acquires expertise uL (a|A) = −a2 and uA (a|A) = −c. However, if A instead does not acquire expertise, L has the final move and acquires expertise itself, giving: uL (0|L) = −c, and uA (0|L) = −a2 . As for any potential delegate a2 < c, the agency prefers L to acquire expertise and delegation does not occur. Delegation in this environment is driven purely by the complexity of expertise. The complexity of the issue enables the legislator to make a virtual commitment to not override agency decisions, and this commitment induces the agency to acquire expertise, leading to delegation that otherwise would not occur. To be sure, the legislator would like to move policy towards its own ideal point, but its hands are tied by its own ignorance. Surprisingly, the legislator benefits from its ignorance as otherwise the agency would not acquire expertise (fearing an override) and the legislator would be left to determine policy on its own. Legislator ignorance of this sort is apparent on many real issues, as observed by Moe (1989, p.271): “And, due largely to experts’ specialized knowledge and the often intangible nature of their outputs, [Congress] cannot know exactly what its experts are doing or why.” Theorem 2 shows that although such ignorance may be normatively unappealing, it in fact assists in the efficient formation of policy. Theorem 2 is notable also by what is missing. In the absence of commitment delegation only occurs if c > ciL and the legislator prefers the status quo to paying for expertise; thus, delegation of type β from the commitment game survives whereas that of type α does not. In α delegation (c < ciL ) both players prefer the acquisition of expertise to the status quo, and in the commitment game the legislator is able to free-ride off the agency’s investment in expertise. In contrast, the full game reverses the positions as the legislator moves last and the agency is the one able to free-ride.22 The type of delegation that does survive (when c > ciL ) does so precisely because the legislator prefers the status quo to paying for expertise. Critically, the agency is still 22 The timing of legislative-bureaucratic interaction is in practice more fluid than modeled here and some bargaining over the cost of expertise may occur. Regardless of the outcome of any such process, however, the message remains that the legislator’s independent incentive to acquire expertise fundamentally changes the agency’s incentives and the practice of delegation. 19 prepared to acquire expertise despite the high costs, and it is this different willingness to pay that drives delegation in the absence of commitment. As the willingness to pay is increasing in a, delegation to allies is not possible and the ally principle fails. Partially Invertible Policy Processes: For partially invertible issues the legislator is able to extract some but not all information from agency recommendations. Lemma 2 establishes a preliminary result for this environment describing when the information extracted is sufficient to induce the legislator to override the recommendation. This calculation is dependent on two factors: the benefit of moving the expected value closer to its ideal point versus the cost of uncertainty. The critical value such that the cost exceeds the benefit of moving at all is the following. Lemma 2 Suppose expertise is partially invertible and prior beliefs are updated with the knowledge that ψ (p̃) = t > 0. A non-expert legislator prefers p̃ to any other policy q ∈ R σ2 if and only if t ≤ 2µ . Proof. Without loss of generality set µ ≥ 0, which implies all policies p > t are dominated by t. For p = p̃ − ∆, where ∆ ≥ 0, we have: uL (p) = − (t − ∆µ)2 − ∆σ 2 . Optimizing: ∂uL (p) = 2µ (t − ∆µ) − σ 2 ∂∆ ∂ 2 uL (p) = −2µ2 < 0. 2 ∂∆ Thus, L implements p iff ∂uL (p) ∂∆ ≤ 0 at ∆ = 0, which requires t ≤ σ2 . 2µ The possibility that the legislator does not override provides the foundation for successful delegation. Theorem 3 describes when delegation occurs for partially invertible expertise. Theorem 3 invertible the legislator delegates if and only if ciL < c < 2ciL , ³ ´ If ψ is partially σ2 a ∈ a2 , √i3 , and a ≤ 2µ . If delegated to, the agency develops expertise, recommends an ideal policy, and is not overridden by the legislator. Proof. As the agency may have multiple ideal policies, let its recommendation rule for µ ≥ 0 be p0 = max Ω, where Ω = {p|ψ (p) = a} (analogously, p0 = min Ω for µ < 0; if max Ω does not exist let the agency recommend any element of Ω, a zero probability event for µ 6= 0). For the legislator, all p > p0 are dominated by p0 and the payoff for all 20 p < p0 are as in Lemma 2. The result then follows as a direct implication of Theorem 2 and Lemma 2. The equilibrium for partially invertible expertise is of the same take-it-or-leave-it form as when expertise is non-invertible, the only change being the addition of the condition from Lemma 2. Combining Theorems 1 through 3 together produces the conclusion that, in the absence of commitment, delegation is possible only if expertise is sufficiently complex. 2 Theorem 3 specifies only that profitable delegation is not possible if a ≤ σ2µ and is silent on how the legislator would react in this case if delegation occurred and the agency recommended its most preferred policy. Simple algebra establishes that the legislator would not move the policy so much that the expected outcome is zero (instead trading off lower risk for some remaining divergence). This “partial override” does not allow for additional delegation as if the agency knew that the legislator would partially override, it would adjust its initial policy offering accordingly, but anticipating this the legislator would increase the amount of override, and so on.23 That the legislator would not fully appropriate agency expertise does offer, however, the opportunity for mutual gain and the players have an incentive to create institutions that allow this benefit to be accessed (in ongoing work I consider the possibility that Congressional hearings fill this role). DISCUSSION The preceding results show that successful delegation is possible only for complex issues and when it does occur, agency proposals have the form of take-it-or-leave-it ultimatums to the legislator. Behavior of this sort arises also in models that endow the agent with Type 1 agenda control, such as the famous setter model of Romer and Rosenthal (1978), the intra-legislature models of Gilligan and Krehbiel (1987, 1989) and legislativebureaucratic policy making (such as in Epstein and O’Halloran 1994). The novelty of the current paper is that this behavior arises in an environment with frictionless legislative oversight. The agency ultimatum presents the legislator with a stark choice: accept the status quo or go with the agency’s proposal. With unencumbered oversight power this begs the question: why does the legislator limit itself to only two alternatives despite holding full power over policy? The answer offered here is expertise, or lack thereof. On issues of sufficient complexity the absence of expertise creates a fear of the unknown, and this fear renders the many other alternatives undesirable. Walker (1969, p. 890) provides evidence that such a fear constrains policy making in practice, concluding that: “Uncertainty and the fear of unanticipated consequences has always been a formidable barrier to reform.” 23 It is for the same reason that the legislator cannot delegate to extreme agencies and hope for them to compromise on policy. 21 The conception of expertise offered here is purely informational, and in this sense shares a lineage with the canonical model. An alternative — and complementary — view of expertise is offered by Page (2006, 2007; see also Hong and Page 2001). In Page’s framework, expertise is best thought of as an ability (or a strategy) rather than a difference in knowledge, and manifests as a superior ability to solve problems. The focus of Page’s work also differs from here as he studies the use of expertise in problem solving (and the intriguing question of whether group heterogeneity aids in problem solving) whereas I focus on the strategic interaction between experts and laymen. In practice, of course, both facets of expertise are important. Indeed, the duality of information and skill was present in mankind’s first ever attempt at documenting knowledge. In their famous Encyclopedie (1751-1772), Diderot and D’Alembert describe, among other things, the tools and techniques of the mechanical arts, yet they were under no illusion that knowledge of their book alone would be sufficient to establish expertise (see Pannabecker 1994 for an account).24 Models of delegation in political science are closely connected to models of communication in economics. Indeed, as frictions disappear the policy recommendations of bureaucrats reduce to policy advice and the model can be equivalently viewed as a cheap-talk game with endogenous information acquisition. In that light, my informational theory is a generalization of that in Crawford and Sobel (1982) and subsequent work. To understand the nature of this generalization, it is best to interpret Crawford and Sobel in a non-standard way. In Crawford and Sobel the sender and receiver prefer different actions, the problem being that these actions are subject to a shock (the state of the world). Crawford and Sobel assume that the state of the world is a single variable and that the same state is applied to all actions. Alternatively, one may interpret Crawford and Sobel’s model as containing a state variable for each possible action (a continuum of states), with the assumption that the state variables are perfectly correlated and thus describable by a single piece of information. Viewed in this light, my contribution is to relax this final assumption on correlation. My theory supposes that different actions are affected by different states and that these shocks are correlated less than perfectly. In the language of Crawford and Sobel, then, my main result is to show that if the correlation is weak enough, perfect (but partial) information revelation is possible in communication equilibria. With this interpretation in hand, several open questions emerge, the most prominent 24 From a modern informational perspective, a striking feature of Diderot and D’Alembert’s enterprise is that they encountered considerable difficulties in obtaining the necessary information for their book due to the desire of the guild members to maintain their informational advantage. This reluctance anticipates the reticence of modern bureaucrats to relinquish their informational advantage to their political overseers. Further anticipating modern subterfuge, Diderot contemplated the response of enrolling his associates as guild apprentices to spy on the artisans! 22 being whether the partition equilibria of Crawford and Sobel exist when the conditions for delegation in Theorem 3 fail? We know that such equilibria exist in the limit of perfect invertibility, thus whether they also exist for σ 2 > 0, and what the threshold is for existence, are questions of interest. Another open question regards Battaglini’s (2002) result that in a multidimensional policy space with multiple experts the canonical model allows a policy maker to achieve her ideal outcome by exploiting differences in the agents. The techniques underlying this result do not obviously extend to policy processes that are less than perfectly invertible, leaving open the interesting question of whether in this environment, as in the single dimension studied here, issue complexity restores agency power. Further extensions include partial learning (of the policy mapping), repeated interaction and, perhaps most interestingly, endogenizing the degree of issue complexity. If the agency is given freedom over the complexity of policy then it is easy to see that the agency has an incentive to choose a policy that is sufficiently complex to ensure its informational advantage is protected, even if this choice trades-off policy outcomes. This possibility offers an endogenous explanation for the often lamented inefficiency and complexity of modern bureaucracies, and resonates with Fiorina’s famously cynical theory that the labyrinthine federal bureaucracy is the product of intentional design.25 The canonical model has, for several decades now, provided a parsimonious and insightful tool to understand policy making. The broader theory introduced here captures elements of reality omitted from the canonical model, and in so doing provides a deeper understanding of issue complexity and offers a solution to the commitment problem in delegation. Perhaps most importantly, the simplicity and generality of the framework should prove useful to the study of policy formation and decision making in many environments. APPENDIX: ASYMMETRIC COSTS OF EXPERTISE The legislative-bureaucratic relationship is dynamic, and expertise obtained on one issue may be usefully applied to the same or different issues in the future. As such, many policy making situations are more accurately modeled under the condition cA < cL . I briefly consider this extension here and present two results, one for each extreme of invertibility. These results reinforce the conclusion that it is only on complex issues that delegation arises of the sort observed in practice. 25 To interpret Fiorina’s thesis through the informational lens offered here, members of Congress become expert at navigating the bureaucracy where the nature of bureaucratic decision-making is intentionally non-invertible, thereby creating an incumbency advantage over less skilled challengers. 23 Corollary 1 considers non-invertible expertise and shows that the delegation region of Theorem 2 is expanded when cA < cL as the agency possesses a greater willingness to acquire expertise. However, the ally principle is only restored in the limit case of cA = 0. The proof is a simple generalization of that for Theorem 2 and is omitted; Note that a01 , a001 , and a02 are analogues of a1 and a2 defined in Lemma 1. Corollary 1 For non-invertible policy and cA < cL , the legislator delegates if and only if: i´ ³ h (i) cA < ciL and a ∈ a01 , min a001 , √i3 , where (a01 )2 = cA and (a001 )2 = cL . ´ ³ (ii) ciL < cA < 2ciL and a ∈ a02 , √i3 , where (a02 )2 + 13 i2 = cA . Delegation of type (ii) is a continuous generalization of that in the equal cost case, whereas type (i) is new. This delegation occurs despite the agency knowing that L will develop expertise should it not. The agency develops expertise in this situation as cA is sufficiently low to warrant moving the policy outcome from 0 to a, and the legislator does not override as the cost of it obtaining expertise exceeds the benefit of moving policy from a back to 0. Thus, the asymmetry in costs creates an asymmetry in willingness to pay, facilitating successful delegation where it otherwise would not occur. The more interesting case of asymmetric costs arises when expertise is invertible. Theorem 1 continues to hold for cA < cL as long as the asymmetry is not too great, although it breaks down for cA sufficiently small. In this case the agency is prepared to acquire expertise as it is better off letting the legislator appropriate the expertise than having the legislator remain uninformed and choose the status quo. The use of expertise in this case, however, is not straightforward as the agency can only imperfectly transfer its information to the legislator. Crawford and Sobel (1982) show that equilibria must be of a particular partition form. The following remark describes the main properties in this environment should delegation occur. Krehbiel (1991, page 93) reports a similar result, referring to it as the “Procedural Commitment Principle.” Remark 1 If delegation occurs for an invertible policy process when cA < cL , outcomes possess the following properties: (i) The expected value of the outcome is 0 and there is no bureaucratic drift. (ii) The realized outcome is not certain and the agency strictly prefers the certain outcome of 0. In this case the agency would like to give all of its expertise to the legislator but is unable to accomplish even this. These properties are inconsistent with the Weberian view of bureaucratic power, suggesting that this environment does not represent much of the delegation that is observed in practice. 24 References [1] Aghion, Philippe, and Jean Tirole. 1997. “Formal and Real Authority in Organizations.” Journal of Political Economy 105 (February): 1-29. [2] Austen-Smith, David. 1990. “Information Transmission in Debate.” American Journal of Political Science 34 (February): 124—152. [3] Battaglini, Marco. 2002. “Multiple Referrals and Multidimensional Cheap-Talk.” Econometrica 70 (July): 1379-1401. [4] Bendor, Jonathan, Serge Taylor, and Roland Van Gaalen. 1985. “Bureaucratic Expertise versus Legislative Authority: A Model of Deception and Monitoring in Budgeting.” American Political Science Review 79 (December): 1041-1060. [5] Bendor, J., A. Glazer, and T. Hammond. 2001. “Theories of Delegation.” Annual Review of Political Science 4: 235-269. [6] Bendor, Jonathan, and Adam Meirowitz. 2004. “Spatial Models of Delegation.” American Political Science Review 98 (May): 293-310. [7] Carpenter, Daniel P. 2001. The Forging of Bureaucratic Autonomy. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. [8] Carpenter, Daniel P. 2002. “Groups, the Media, Agency Waiting Costs, and FDA Drug Approval.” American Journal of Political Science 46 (July): 490-505. [9] Carpenter, Daniel P. 2004. “Protection without Capture: Product Approval by a Politically Responsive, Learning Regulator .” American Political Science Review 98 (November): 613-631. [10] Crawford, Vincent P. and Joel Sobel. 1982. “Strategic Information Transmission.” Econometrica 50 (November): 1431-51. [11] Diermeier, Daniel. 1995. “Commitment, Deference, and Legislative Institutions.” American Political Science Review 89 (June): 344-355. [12] Epstein, David and Sharyn O’Halloran. 1994. “Administrative Procedures, Information, and Agency Discretion.” American Journal of Political Science 38 (August): 697-722. [13] Epstein, David and Sharyn O’Halloran. 1999. Delegating Powers. New York: Cambridge University Press. 25 [14] Esterling, Kevin M. 2004. The Political Economy of Expertise. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press. [15] Fiorina, Morris P. 1977. Congress: Keystone of the Washington Establishment. New Haven: Yale University Press. [16] Gerth, H.H. and C.W. Mills (Eds. and trans.). 1958. From Max Weber: Essays in Sociology. New York: Oxford University Press. [17] Gilligan, Thomas, and Keith Krehbiel. 1987. “Collective Decision Making and Standing Committees: An Informational Rationale for Restrictive Amendment Procedures.” Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization 3 (2): 287-335. [18] Gilligan, Thomas, and Keith Krehbiel. 1989. “Asymmetric Information and Legislative Rules With a Heterogeneous Committee.” American Journal of Political Science 33 (May): 459-490. [19] Hong, Lu, and Scott E. Page. 2001. “Problem Solving by Heterogeneous Agents.” Journal of Economic Theory 97: 123-163. [20] Huber, John D. and Nolan McCarty. 2004. “Bureaucratic Capacity, Delegation, and Political Reform.” American Political Science Review 98 (August): 481-494. [21] Huber, John D. and Charles R. Shipan. 2002. Deliberate Discretion: The Institutional Foundations of Bureaucratic Autonomy. New York: Cambridge University Press. [22] Huber, John D. and Charles R. Shipan. 2006. “Politics, Delegation, and Bureaucracy.” Working paper. [23] Krehbiel, Keith. 1991. Information and Legislative Organization. Ann Arbor, MI: University of Michigan Press. [24] Miller, Gary J., and Terry M. Moe. 1983. “Bureaucrats, Legislators, and the Size of Government.” American Political Science Review 77 (June): 297-322. [25] Moe, Terry. 1989. “The Politics of Bureaucratic Structure.” In Can the Government Govern? eds. John Chubb and Paul Peterson. Washington D.C.: Brookings Institution. [26] Pannabecker, John R. 1994. “Diderot, the Mechanical Arts, and the Encyclopedie: In Search of the Heritage of Technology Education.” Journal of Technology Education 6 (Fall): 45-57. 26 [27] Page, Scott E. 2006. “Uncertainty, Difficulty, and Complexity.” Working paper. [28] Page, Scott E. 2007. The Difference: How the Power of Diversity Creates Better Groups, Firms, Schools, and Societies. Princeton NJ: Princeton University Press. [29] Ringquist, Evan J. 1995. “Political Control and Policy Impact in EPA’s Office of Water Quality.” American Journal of Political Science 39 (May): 336-363. [30] Romer, Thomas, and Howard Rosenthal. 1978. “Political Resource Allocation, Controlled Agendas, and the Status Quo.” Public Choice 33(1): 27-44. [31] Walker, Jack L. Jr. 1969. “The Diffusion of Innovations Among the American States.” American Political Science Review 63 (September): 880-899. [32] Weingast, Barry R., and Mark J. Moran. 1983. “Bureaucratic Discretion or Congressional Control? Regulatory Policymaking by the Federal Trade Commission.” Journal of Political Economy 91 (October): 765-800. 27