Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 9:239-256 (1994) © 1994 Kluwer Academie Publishers Observing Different Orders of Risk Aversion GRAHAM LOOMES Department of Economies, University of York, YorkYOl 5DD, UK UZI SEGAL Department of Economics, University of Toronto, Ontario, M5S lAI Cattada Abstract A decision maker's attitude towards risk is said to be of order /,; = 1, 2, if for every given risk e with expected value zero, the risk premium the decision maker is willing to pay to avoid the risk te goes with / to zero at the same order as;'. This article presents an experiment testing the order of decision makers' attitudes toward risk. Its major result is that both attitudes exist, eaeb in signifieant proportions. Moreover, two elasses of first-order behavior are defined. The rank-dependent model (Quiggin, 1982) belongs to one, the disappointment aversion model (Gul, 1991) to the other. We show that only the first of these two classes appears among our subjeets. Key words: risk attitude, decision theory, experimental economics Introduction One ofthe most interesting results of Machina's (1982) generalized nonexpected utility analysis is that under some smoothness assumptions, many analytical results of expected utility, especially comparative statics analysis and other results concerning optimization, carry over to nonlinear preferences (see also Machina, 1989). It turns out, however, that not all nonexpected utility models share these properties. In particular, smoothness of preferences with respect to outcomes, guaranteed in the expected utility model by the differentiability of the utility function, is not satisfied (at least not always) by some of these models. Let e be a nontrivial random variable such that E[e] = 0. Define T7(f) to be the risk premium the decision maker is willing to pay out of the nonstochastic wealth level w to avoid the random variable te. Formally, the decision maker is indifferent between w -\- te and w - j:(t). Segal and Spivak (1990) define the attitude towards risk associated with a preference relation as being of first- or second-order if for every w and such e and for sufficiently small /, the risk premium 'n-(?) is of the same order of magnitude as t or z^, respectively. Pratt (1964) proved that in expected utility theory (with a differentiable utility function), as t goes to zero, 'u(t) is proportional to t'^. There are nonexpected utility models—for example, Quiggin's (1982) rank-dependent and Gul's (1991) disappointment aversion, where, as t goes to zero, the risk premium is proportional t o ; (see also Montesano, 1988). 240 GRAHAM LOOMES/UZI SEGAL This seemingly technical definition has some strong economic implications. For example, under second-order risk aversion, some risk averse decision makers will always prefer random prices to the certainty of their average. On the other hand, for a decision maker who is first-order risk averse, random prices should be considered inferior to their sure average price, provided that these prices vary in a bounded neighborhood (Segal and Spivak, 1992). Also, some conclusions concerning efficient allocations of risk do not hold in the presence of first-order risk aversion. In particular, suppose that the economy is sufficiently large and has two types of decision makers, one type satisfying first-order risk aversion, the other type satisfying second-order risk aversion. Then the Pareto efficient allocations of the risk associated with a public project and the Pareto efficient allocations of risk in an insurance market may require that only the second-order individuals will share the risk. However, if everyone satisfies second-order risk aversion, then in both cases everyone should carry some risk (Segal and Spivak, 1992). This last observation is particularly relevant, since, as we show below, both types appear to exist in significant proportions. There are some other important implications in the area of insurance and finance. For example, second-order risk aversion implies that decision makers will buy full insurance if and only if there is no marginal loading (i.e., if the insurance premium, exactly equals the probability of loss). By contrast, first-order attitude implies that decision makers will buy full insurance even in the presence of some marginal loading, provided it is not too high (Segal and Spivak, 1990). In addition, Epstein (1992) argues that first-order risk aversion permits more flexibility in functional forms. He sbows that constant relative risk aversion under second-order attitude implies either enormous risk premiums for large gambles or almost zero premiums for moderate risks. By contrast, first-order risk aversion permits more realistic premiums. Epstein and Zin (1991) show that models of first-order risk aversion explain stock and bond returns data much better than do models of secondorder risk aversion. For other applications of this concept, see Epstein and Zin (1990). Since orders of risk aversion have such potentially widespread implications for economic analysis, it is natural to try to find out whether different orders exist. This article reports an experiment which attempts to observe the order of decision makers' attitudes to risk. Our major finding is that both first-order and second-order attitudes exist, and in significant proportions. Moreover, the design of our experiment also allows us to discriminate between two different classes of first-order risk behavior. The article is organized as follows. Section 1 sets out the theoretical predictions to be tested by the experiment. Sections 2 and 3 describe the experiment and its results, while section 4 contains some concluding remarks. Data related to the experiment are collected in tables 1 through 6. 1. Orders of risk aversion Let L be the set of simple lotteries over finite wealth levels in D = [0, M], a compact interval in St. The lottery (xi,p\;... ;x,,,p,,) yieldsx, with probability/?,, i = l,...,n. Forx G D, let 8^ be the degenerate lottery (x, 1). For random variable e = (e\,p\;...;e,,,p,,) OBSERVING DIFFERENT ORDERS OF RISK AVERSION 241 a n d / e 0i,\ette = (tei,pi;...; re,,,/p,,). For X e L, let F ^ be the cumulative distribution function ofX given by f";^'(x) = Pr(A'^ x). On L there exists a complete, transitive, continuous, and monotonic (with respect to first-order stochastic dominance) preference relation >. As usual, > and ~ denote strict preference and indifference, respectively. A function V: L -^ Si represents the preference relation > if for every X and Y in L, V{X) 5 V{Y) if and only if X > Y. For A' e L, let the certainty equivalent of A", denoted CE(X), be implicitly defined by (CE(AO, 1) ~ X. The risk premium -iT'*'(e) which a decision maker is willing to pay to avoid adding the random variable e to the nonstochastic wealth level w is defined by w - TT"'(e) = CE(M' + e). If E[e] = 0, then by definition, the risk premium is positive whenever the decision maker is risk averse. For the sake of simplicify, we often omit w from our notation. Consider now the risk premium •^(t; e) which the decision maker is willing to pay to avoid adding the random variable te to the current wealth level w. Of course, TT(O; e) = 0. Moreover, by continuify, lim,_^o T7(;; e) = 0. We assume that ^^{t; e) is a differentiable function of;, except maybe at; = 0.' Following Segal and Spivak (1990), define orders of risk aversion as the order of the first non-zero derivative of TT with respect to f at ? = 0 + for e such that E[e] = 0. Formally, Definition 1. The decision maker's attitude towards risk at w is of order one if for every e such that E[e] = 0, d-^{t; e)/af|,=o+ ^ 0. It is of order two if for every such e, ^ ^ o* ^ 0. Orders of risk aversion have a nice geometric interpretation. Consider the set of lotteries {(x,/?;_y,l - p):x,y G D}foragivenp G [0,1]. Define (p(x,3') = V(x,p;y,\ p) to be the utilify from this lottery and assume, without loss of generalify, that ip(x,x) = X. The preference relation > induces an indifference curves map in 9^-. The slope ofthe indifference curve through (x,y) is -<f)i(x,}')/92(jf,3')Suppose now thatp = q = \. Obviously, in this case, the function cp is symmetric, i.e., <3;,{x,y) = (p(y,x). Let the decision maker's current wealth level be w, and consider the random variable e = (1, j ; -1, \). The risk premium 'n-(;; e) satisfies ip(w — 17, W — IT) = (p(w + t , W — t ) ^ W — 77 = (p(w + t , W — t ) . Differentiate both sides with respect to t to obtain — == ( P 2 ( W ' + t,W - t) - ( p i ( w + t , W - t ) ^ If the decision maker is second-order risk averse, then, by definition, C)TT/(9;| , = o = 0, and therefore ipi(iv, w) = 92 (^, w)- Since the slope ofthe indifference curve through (w, w) is - (pi/'P2, it follows that this slope is - 1 . 242 GRAHAM LOOMES/UZl SEGAL Suppose, on the other hand, that the preference relation satisfies risk aversion of order one. Then, dTr/dt\,=o+ > 0. It follows that the limit from the left of the slope of the indifference curve through (w, w) is less than - 1, and since the function ip is symmetric, the limit from the right ofthe slope ofthe indifference curve through this point is greater than - 1 . In other words, indifference curves, as in figure 1, have a kink along the main diagonal (for similar pictures, see Segal and Spivak, 1990; Gul, 1991; Epstein, 1992). We now introduce a concept of orders of conditional risk aversion. Let A' and e be as before and define ;('|, + e to be the lottery (x,,/?,;. . . ; X , _ | , / ? , _ I ; A : , + e|,p,(7,;.. .;A:, + (^m,Pi<:ini',^i+\,Pi+\',--',x ,,,p,,). The lottery A'l, + e is obtained from A" by adding the "noise" e to the outcomex,. The conditional risk premium is defined as that amount of money which the decision maker is willing to pay out of x, in order to avoid this noise. Formally, We define orders of conditional risk aversion similarly to before. Let E[e] = 0. We say that the preference relation satisfies first-order conditional risk aversion if for every nondegenerate X, e and /, the first-order derivative of the conditional risk premium of X\ i + te with respect to f at f = 0 + is positive. It satisfies second-order conditional risk aversion if all these derivatives equal zero, but the second-order derivatives are positive (see also Segal and Spivak, 1988). Next, we briefiy consider some models. Throughout, we assume that the decision maker is risk averse. In this text, we simply summarize results. Proofs can be found in the references listed and in the appendix. Expected utility with a differentiable utility function u exhibits both second-order behavior and second-order conditional risk aversion. The same is true for a number of nonexpected utility models. For example, Segal and Spivak (1990) prove that Chew's \ \ X / / Figure I. A nondifferentiable Indifference curve. , / / OBSERVING DIFFERENT ORDERS OF RISK AVERSION 243 (1983) weighted utility satisfies second-order risk aversion. The proof that it satisfies second-order conditional risk aversion is similar. By contrast, the rank-dependent functional with nonlinear probability transformation function (see Quiggin, 1982; Yaari, 1987; Segal, 1989) and cumulative prospect theory (Tversky and Kahneman, 1992) represent first-order risk aversion (Segal and Spivak, 1990), Similarly, they represent first-order conditional risk aversion. However, Gul's (1991) disappointment aversion model satisfies first-order risk aversion, but secondorder conditional risk aversion (see appendix). Expected utility with (continuous but) nondifferentiable utility represents first-order (and first-order conditional) risk aversion around any point of nondifferentiability, 2. Experimental design Consider the following problem. There are three mutually exclusive and exhaustive statesof the world, 51, 52, and S3, with probabilitiesp + e,p - s, and 1 - 2/7, respectively, such that p G [0, 0,5] and e G [0, p]. The deeision maker has £7 to allocate between the first two events while winning £/v if ^3 happens. In other words, the decision maker will participate in the lottery (w + x,p + e;w + T - x,p - E;W + K,\ - 2p). We do not impose the constraint thatJC G [0, 7], This represents a simple problem of optimal portfolio selection. If p = 0,5 and we restriet x to be between 772 and T, then this problem has a clear interpretation in terms of insurance. Suppose that w = 0 (that is, the wealth level is T) and that the decision maker faces the possibility of a total loss in case ^3 happens. The decision maker can buy a partial insurance, the priee of which 50 pence (50p) for eaeh pound insured. For example, the total payment for a full insurance is 7/2, in which case the deeision maker will have £ r i n both cases less the insuranee premium 772, It follows immediately by first-order stoehastic dominance that if e > 0, then x ^ 7/2, We are interested in this seetion in the question: Under what conditions will the decision maker set X = 7/2? We start with the case where/? = 0,5 or/C = 7/2, Then by settings = 7/2, the deeision maker can guarantee the sure gain of 7/2, Suppose that p = 0,5, and eonsider again figure 1, The deeision maker is constrained to choose a point on the linex + y = T (not shown in the picture). Suppose indifference eurves are everywhere differentiable. If e = 0, thenx = y = 7/2 is the best point along thex + y = T line (reeall that the slope of the indifference curve at this point is - 1), However, if e > 0, then the slope of the indifference curve through (7/2, 7/2) is less than - 1 , and the best point along the budget line is to the right ofthe main diagonal. On the other hand, if indifference curves have kinks along the main diagonal (as is the ease under first-order risk aversion), then for a sufficiently small e > 0, the best point along the budget line is still atx = y. This intuitive analysis leads to Prediction 1, whieh follows from Proposition 1 in Segal and Spivak (1990), Prediction 1. Suppose that/? = 0,5 or that K = 7/2, Then 1, If the decision maker's attitude towards risk is of order two, then the optimal value of X is 7/2 if and only if E =0, 244 GRAHAM LOOMES/UZI SEGAL 2. If the decision maker's attitude towards risk is of order one, then there exists E* > 0 such that for e G [0, e*] the optimal value ofx is r/2. Ifp < 0.5 and K ^ T/2, then there is no way for the decision maker to avoid some risk, and the natural concept is therefore conditional orders of risk aversion. Similarly to Prediction 1, we now have Prediction 2. Suppose that/? < 0.5 and that K ^ T/2. Then 1. If the decision maker's attitude towards conditional risk is of order two, then the optimal value ofx is T/2 if an only if e = 0. 2. If the decision maker's attitude towards conditional risk is of order one, then there exists 8* > 0 such that for e £ [0, E*] the optimal value ofx is T/2. This optimization problem can thus be used in testing what kind of attitude towards risk decision makers have. We describe an experiment based on these results below. Assume w = 0, and consider again the optimization problem maXj. V(x,p + e;T - x, p - z;K,\ ~ 2p). Predictions 1 and 2 deal with the question: Under what conditions will a decision maker setx = ^ in this problem? There is, however, another issue which we wish to address, namely the connection between the value of e and the optimal value ofx. Of course, different functional forms may give specific answers to this comparative statics question, but we are interested here in general properties that follow by first-order stochastic dominance. Denote the solution of the above optimization problem by x(8). Suppose that for some p, X(E*) = T/2, but for some s < E*, X(E) > 772. Then, by first-order stochastic dominance and by the definition ofx(E), it follows that (x(z),p + E*; T - x(e),p - B*; K, I - 2p) > {x(e),p + B;T - x(e),p - e; /f, 1 - 2p) > (T/2, 2p; K, 1 - 2/7). ThereforeX(E*) ^ 7/2, a contradiction. This leads to Prediction 3. Let the preference relation satisfy the first-order stochastic dominance axiom, and assume that for some/?, K, and s* > 0, x(e*) = 7/2. Then for the samep and A:,X(E) = 772 for all E E [0, E*]. The aim of the experiment was to use variants of the simple optimal portfolio selection problem described at the beginning of this section to observe the extent of second-order, first-order unconditional, and first-order conditional risk aversion in a sample of individual decision makers. One can, of course, argue, following Mas Collel (1974), that no experiment can prove nondifferentiability of preferences. However, our aim is not to prove differentiability or nondifferentiabilify of indifference curves, but to check what models fit observed behavior better. Figure 2 gives two examples of the form in which such decision problems were presented in the experiment. Columns represent states ofthe world whose respective probabilities, expressed as chances out of a hundred, are shown at the base of each column. The mechanism for determining which state of the world occurs is a single random draw OBSERVING DIFFERENT ORDERS OF RISK AVERSION 1 245 60.61 60 : 42.4.3 100 40 80.81 ! 8.65 ! 20 I 42 ! 38 100 Figttre 2. Two examples of the form in which decision problems were presented in the experiment. from a box containing one hundred cloakroom tickets numbered 1 to 100 inclusive. So, in the lower of the two examples shown in figure 2, S\ occurs if the randomly drawn ticket bears a number between 1 and 42 inclusive, ^2 occurs if the ticket is between 43 and 80, and S3 occurs otherwise. In terms of the notation used in the previous section, the first example in figure 2 is the case where/? = 0.5 and e =0.1; the second example involves/? = 0.4, e = 0.02 andK = 8.65. Participants in the experiment were randomized between four subsamples. Each subsample was presented with a series of 16 variants of the formats shown in figure 2. For eight ofthe 16 problems, the total sum to be distributed between S\ and 52 was £22.40. For the other eight problems, T = £17.30. In cases where there was a third state of the world, K was set either at 0 or at T/2 (the second case in figure 2 is an example of the latter.) The values ofp and E varied extensively, with 0.1 ^ p ^ 0.5 and 0.005 ^ e ^ 0.3. Full details of the parameters used in all four subsamples are given in tables 1-4. Each subsample was presented with five, six, or seven problems where either there were only two states of the world or else the payoff in S3 was T/2. In these cases, individuals could, if they wished, opt for certainty by settings = T/2. Alternatively, by settings > T/2, they could raise the expected value of the portfolio by accepting some level of risk. In these cases, second-order risk averse individuals will always set x > T/2. By contrast, individuals who are first-order risk averse will setx = 772 if e is less than or equal to their critical value E*. Since the value of e* may vary from one individual to another and from one value ofp to another, the number of observations of x = T/2 in these cases will tend to decrease as E increases. However, if there are individuals who are first-order risk averse, we should expect to observe them setting x = T/2 in problems where e is sufficiently small. Those whose attitude to risk is w«conditional first-order (e.g. disappointment aversion) should be expected to set x = T/2 only in (some of) the five, six, or seven cases where p = 0.5 or K = T/2. However, those who exhibit first-order conditional risk 246 GRAHAM LOOMESAJZl SEGAL aversion may also be expected to setx = T/2 in a number of cases where/7 < 0.5, K = 0 and e is sufficiently small. The experiment discussed in this article was conducted in two stages, in February and in June 1991. In February a letter was distributed widely among students and nonacademic stafi" at the University of York describing the general nature of the experiment, giving examples of two- and three-state problems, explaining the incentive system, and inviting potential participants to sign up for whichever session was most convenient for them. As a result, a total of 196 individuals participated in groups of up to 16 at a time. On arrival at their session, individuals were randomly allocated to one of the four subsamples and seated at a separate computer terminal, not adjacent to anyone in the same subsample. Each session began with two practice rounds (common to all subsamples) during which the instructions were reviewed and any questions were answered. The two practice problems and the 16 incentive-linked problems all followed the same pattern. The first screen displayed five alternatives, all with the same values oip, e, and K (if/? <0.5), but with T divided difi:erently between S\ and S2. For example, the first screen for the second example given in figure 2 offered the five possible allocations: v4: {15.00, 2.30} 5 : {13.50, 3.80} C: {12.00, 5.30} D: {10.50, 6.80} £: {9.00, 8.30}. (The pairs of numbers were filled into the empty boxes in figure 2). Subjects were asked to consider the alternatives and choose the one they most preferred. After they had confirmed their choice, a second screen presented four more alternatives, which differed from the first five only in thatx and T - x were now clustered more closely around the distribution chosen from the first screen. For example, someone who chose alternative C in the first screen, would now be presented with the following pairs of \x, T - x}\ ^ : {12.75, 4.55} fi: {12.25, 5.05} C: {11.75, 5.55} D: {11.25, 6.05}. After the most preferred second screen option had been chosen, a third screen appeared. This displayed six alternatives, clustered around and including the option selected from the second screen, and now with the values ofx differing by only 5p from one alternative to the next. Having chosen one of the six alternatives, a fourth (and final) screen displayed only that chosen option. This gave subjects an opportunity to refiect on the portfolio which they had arrived at, and make any final adjustments to the OBSERVING DIFFERENT ORDERS OF RISK AVERSION 247 distribution of T if they wished. This could be done by using two of the cursor keys: pressing the left arrow key moved money from ^2 to 51 in 5p increments; pressing the right arrow key moved money in the opposite direction. When completely satisfied with the distribution, subjects confirmed their decisions, and the computer moved to the next decision problem, repeating the same four-screen sequence,^ The idea behind this procedure was to use a series of choices to enable subjects to iterate towards their most preferred portfolio in each case. It might seem more straightforward simply to present the (fourth) screen with arbitrary {x, T - x) pairs already inserted and then ask subjects to use the cursor keys to achieve their optimal portfolio. The potential danger with such a procedure is that the starting point, the "initial endowment," may in some way bias the results, especially since subjects have to do different amounts of work to achieve different final portfolios. The procedure that we adopted was arguably more neutral and gave people time to absorb the parameters of the prob lem and "home in" on a final decision. Moreover, since the first three screens required the same number of keystrokes whichever portfolio was eventually chosen, no portfolio involved more time or effort to select than any other. By setting T at either £22,40 or £17,30, we attempted to counteract a tendency of subjects to give responses in "round" numbers. In the experiments reported in Loomes (1991), subjects were given the task of dividing £20,00 between two states of the world. In more than 90% of cases, the responses that they gave were in whole pounds. Under these circumstances, it would be very difficult to tell how often setting x = T/2 is due to first-order risk aversion, and how often it is primarily due to rounding. In the design of the present experiment, we selected values of 7 which made T/2 neither more nor less round than adjacent values of J:. It may at this stage be worth noting other respects in which the present experiment differs from the one reported in Loomes (1991), That earlier experiment was primarily concerned with testing the independence axiom of expected utility theory rather than orders of risk aversion, and the data could not be used for this latter purpose. Besides the problem of rounding, the parameters were generally not appropriate for the task. For example, in cases where/? = 0,5, E was never lower than 0,1; and in all cases where there was a third state of the world, K was set at 0, In the earlier experiment, only 12 sets of parameters were used, and E never fell below 0,05 in any of them. So, although the earlier experiment yielded a number of responses where x = 772, it was clear that we needed to reduce the propensity for rounding, and greatly extend the range of parameters, especially the number of cases where 0 < E ^ 0,05, if we wished to try to discriminate between difTerent orders of risk aversion. Subjects were asked to work through the 16 decisions at their own speed, answering each one as accurately as they could, on the understanding that when they had completed all 16, one and only one would be selected at random to be played out for real. The procedure was that when subjects indicated that they had finished, a supervisor came to their terminal and asked them to roll a 20-sided die until it came to rest with a number between 1 and 16 face up. The subject's decision in that problem was retrieved from the computer's memory and displayed on the screen. The subject then picked a 248 GRAHAM LOOMES/UZI SEGAL ticket at random from a box of 100 cloakroom tickets, and was paid whatever amount was due under the relevant state of the world.-' Throughout the February experiment, subjects did not know that they would be invited to make the 16 decisions again at a later date. But, in June, they were each sent a letter inviting them to participate again. This letter was accompanied by a sheet which displayed—in the format shown in figure 2—all 16 decision problems which had been presented to them in February. On this occasion, subjects were asked to decide on the distribution of T in each case in advance, write their most preferred values ofx and T - x into the appropriate columns on the sheet, and then come to the laboratory at any convenient time during two fivehour periods to enter their decisions into the computer. This time they were not asked to go through the three-screen iterative choice procedure, but to enter their decisions directly via the "fourth" screens. Our reason for inviting subjects to make the 16 decisions again was to check whether the opportunity to see all 16 decision problems together and to consider all their responses at their leisure would markedly change the observed patterns of behavior, either at an individual or at an aggregate level. 3. Results Altogether, 136 of the original 196 subjects took part again in June. In reporting the results, we shall focus on the responses of these 136 individuals.'' Tables 1-4 present the aggregate patterns. (The individual data are available upon request.) In each table, the sixteen decision problems are listed in ascending order of E. In cases where e is the same in two or more questions, these are listed in descending order of p. In each subsample, there is a pair of problems with the same values of both E and p: in these cases, the problem where K = T/2 is listed above the one where K = Q. Problems where either/? = 0.5 ox K = T/2 are marked with an asterisk. The columns headed February and June show the numbers of individuals who setx = T/2 on each occasion, with the numbers in brackets reporting cases where individuals setx < T/2. All four tables exhibit patterns in both February and June which are consistent with an appreciable degree of first-order risk aversion. There is clear evidence of some differences in responses between February and June. Judging by the frequencies of violations of stochastic dominance^—which fell from 45 cases committed by 29 individuals down to 25 cases committed by 13 individuals—the opportunity to consider decisions more carefully helped to reduce aberrant responses. It also served to markedly increase the observability of first-order risk aversion in all four subsamples. Since respondents were randomized between subsamples, a convenient way of conveying the overall pattern is to combine the data as in table 5, which shows the average percentages of cases where x was set equal to 772 for different levels of E. TO ensure representation from all four subsamples within each cell, responses to certain pairs of adjacent E'S have been pooled. It is clear that for 0.005 $ E ^ 0.025, the February pattern 249 OBSERVING DIFFERENT ORDERS OF RISK AVERSION Tabte I. Subsample 1 responses (n = 33) Problem Number 10 6* 4* 16 12* 8* 2 3 9 14* 7 13 11 5 1* 15 e P February June .005 .01 .01 .01 .02 .02 .075 .075 .075 .10 .10 .125 .125 .20 .30 .30 .475 .50 .20 .20 .40 .10 .375 .225 .125 .50 .15 .375 .275 .44 .50 .45 8(2) 6 4(2) 5(2) 3(1) 12(2) 8 12(1) 12(1) 5(2) 1(1) 2 7(1) 1 1 3 1(1) 2 1(2) 1 1 1 2 1 1 1(1) 3(1) 2(1) 1 1 1 1 One respondent set.*: = 4 for all 16 questions in both February and June. Table 2. Subsample 2 responses (;j = 32) Problem Number 8* 16 11 14* 4* 3* 2 6 13 7 5* 10 12 1 15 9* E P February June .005 .005 .015 .015 .02 .025 .05 .05 .05 .075 .10 .10 .125 .15 .15 .25 .125 .125 .475 .375 .50 .125 .20 .13 .10 .175 .50 .40 .325 .35 .30 .50 9(1) 6 6(1) 5(2) 5(2) 3 14 12(2) 4(1) 10 6(1) 4(1) 4 2 4 3 3 3 3 1 2 1 2(1) 4(1) 2 2(2) 2 3 3(1) 3(1) 3 2 One respondent setA- = y for all 16 questions in both February and June. 250 GRAHAM LOOMESAJZl SEGAL Table 3. Subsample 3 responses {ii = 39) Problem Number E P February June 6* 16* 12 8 14 2* 4* 10 9 7 1* 5 3 11* 15* 13 .005 .01 .01 .01 .02 .02 .05 .05 .10 .15 .20 .20 .20 .25 .30 .30 .225 .45 .45 .10 .20 .14 .50 .35 .25 .25 .50 .40 .30 .50 .50 .45 10(1) 4(1) 6(1) 4(3) 4(4) 1(1) 2 2 2 0(1) 1 1 1(2) 1 1 1 14 13 13(1) 8 5 6 5 3 1 2 1 2 2 2 1 1 Table 4. Subsample 4 responses (n = 32) Problem Number E P February June 16* 10 4* 8 12* 2 14 1 5 9* 11 15 7 6 3* 13 .005 .005 .015 .015 .025 .025 .05 .05 .05 .10 .10 .10 .125 .125 .25 .25 .325 .325 .225 .135 .375 .225 .45 .25 .15 .50 .30 .20 .225 .175 .50 .45 9(1) 6(1) 6(2) 5 2 18 21(1) 11(1) 8(2) 4 8 5 1 1(1) 3(1) 4 1(1) 1 0 0 0 0 0(1) 0 1(1) 1 2 0(1) 2(1) 1(1) 0 0(1) 251 OBSERVING DIFFERENT ORDERS OF RISK AVERSION _ Table 5. Percentages of cases where J: = T ~ 2 .005 .01/.015 .02/.025 .05/.075 .10 .125/.15 .20/.25/.30 February 23.9 15.0 7.4 6.8 3.7 4.3 2.8 June 45.9 28.7 16.7 8.2 5.4 5.3 2.9 E Table 6. First-order behavior in pairs of problems with same {p, E) Only when February (June) Subs. 1:4* & 16 Subs. 2: 8* & 16 Subs. 3: 16*&12 Subs. 4: 16*& 10 2(2) 6(4) 0(1) 5(1) Both Only when K=0 2(10) 3(10) 4(12) 4(17) 3(2) 3(2) 2(1) 2(4) is reproduced in June, but on approximately twice the scale. There is rather less difference for 0.05 ^ e ^ 0.15, and virtually no difference for e ^ 0.2 where (apart from the two individuals who set x = T/2 for all 16 problems on both occasions) there are very few observations and little discernible pattern about them. In short, aggregate behavior is consistent with the existence of first-order risk aversion, and with our hypothesis (based on the assumption that E* is liable to vary among individuals) that the number of observations ofx = T/2 will tend to decrease as e increases. In our experiment, such behavior does not seem attributable to "rounding," or to casual unconsidered responses, and we take our results to suggest that, for at least some decision makers, first-order risk aversion is a characteristic of their preferenees. Several other points of interest emerge from the data. Across the four subsamples, there were a number of sets of questions whieh allowed us to check Prediction 3. In February there were a total of 40 cases where individuals chose x = T/2 in at least one question in those sets, of which only five violated Prediction 3. In June there were four violations out of 67 cases. Secondly, although first-order behavior was exhibited by many in our sample, it is also evident that a substantial minority of respondents weversetx ^ T/2, either in February or in June. Inspection of the individual data shows this to be the case for 33 (24.3%) of the sample of 136. Third, recall that disappointment aversion entails unconditional, but not conditional, first-order risk aversion, i.e., entails setting x = T/2 only in (some of) the problems marked with an asterisk. In our experiment, there was little evidence of such behavior. Perhaps the most straightforward indication of this comes from examining the pairs of problems involving the same values oip and e, but with K = T/2 in one case and K = Oin the other. Table 6 shows the data by focusing attention only on those responses where some sort of first-order risk aversion (conditional or unconditional) is exhibited. Even in February, with less time to refiect upon their decisions, the cases which conform with disappointment aversion never outnumber those that do not; and in June, when given the opportunity to consider their deeisions in advance, the great majority who set x 252 GRAHAM LOOMESAJZI SEGAL = 7/2 do SO for both problems in each pair, in disagreement with disappointment theory. This strongly suggests that models which entail first-order risk aversion should be able to accommodate first-order conditional risk aversion, and should not be restricted to the unconditional case. 4. Conclusion Rather than focus on some specific axioms of decision theory, we have concentrated in this article on a more general characteristic, namely, the order of risk attitude. In addition to the existing distinction between unconditional first-order and second-order risk aversion, we extended the analysis to encompass order of conditional risk aversion and showed how this extended analysis enabled us to distinguish among several different decision models. We then reported an experiment designed to discover whether different attitudes could be detected. We asked a substantial number of individuals to participate twice, presenting each person with the same set of decision problems on both occasions, with a four-month interval in between. On the second occasion, each participant had the opportunity to contemplate his/her decisions at leisure, the idea being to check whether behavior which departs from conventional expected utility theory diminishes when individuals have ample opportunity to consider their responses, make calculations, etc. While the frequency of violations of stochastic dominance was effectively halved on the second occasion, evidence of first-order risk aversion became more pronounced; at the same time, it was also clear that a substantial minority of respondents conformed with second-order risk aversion on both occasions. The patterns of behavior exhibited by our sample at an individual and at an aggregate level suggest that first-order risk aversion, conditional as well as unconditional, may be a significant phenomenon, and that the implications of first-order attitudes for many areas of economic activity deserve serious consideration. Such steps were taken by Epstein and Zin (1990,1991) and by Segal and Spivak (1992). Appendix This appendix discusses some of the claims presented at the end of section 1. As stated there, we assume throughout that the decision maker is risk averse. Expected utility with a differentiable utility function u exhibits second-order behavior. Let V(X) = Jou(x)dFx(x). Risk aversion implies that u is concave. Consider the lottery 8^ + te with the expected utility /DM(W -I- te)dFe(e). If E[e] = 0, that is, if JoedFi.(e) = 0, then dtrQ; e)/af|, = o = -lDeu'(w)dFi(e) = 0 hut d^'rr(t; e)/dt^\,=ii+= -Soe^u"(w)dFe(e) > 0. Similarly, expected utility (with a differentiable utility function ii) satisfies second-order conditional risk aversion. The rank-dependent functional (see Quiggin, 1982; Yaari, 1987; Segal, 1989) is denoted RD(A^ and is given by OBSERVING DIFFERENT ORDERS OF RISK AVERSION 253 =£ (1) u{x)df{Fx{x)) for some strictly increasing and continuous function/, satisfying/(O) = Oand/(1) = 1. Call this functional/jroper rank-dependent if it is not expected utility, i.e., if the probability transformation function / is not linear. This functional represents risk aversion if and only if M and / are both concave (see Chew, Karni, and Safra, 1987). In that case, a proper rank-dependent functional represents first-order risk aversion. Consider the lottery 8^ + tt with E[e] = 0. Then RD(8H, + te) = JDM(W + te)df{Fi(e)). Hence dTv{t; e)/*|,=()+ = -J[)Xu'(w)df{F^(e)) > 0 (see Segal and Spivak, 1990). Similarly, a strict rankdependent functional (with concave u and / ) represents first-order conditional risk aversion. Gul (1991) suggested another model for decision making under uncertainty, called disappointment aversion. We show below that this functional satisfies first-order risk aversion, but second-order conditional risk aversion. Let X = (x\, p\;...; Xf,, p,,), and assume that x\ ^ . . . ^ x,,. An elationdisappointment decomposition (EDD) of A' is a triple (a, Y, Z) such that the possible outcomes o f y = (y\,qh ... ;>»,„,(?,„) are those outcomes^ of Xsatisfyingx ^ CE(A^,the possible outcomes of Z = {zi,r\;... ;z^,r^) are the outcomes^ of A'such t h a t x ^ CE(A^, and Fx = aFy + (1 - a)Fz. Let 7 : [0,1] -^ &lhe given by y(a) = a/[\ + (1 - a)|3] for some p G ( - 1 , 00). According to the disappointment aversion theory, the preference relation ?= can be represented by the functional 7(a) X q,u(yi) + (1 - ^(a)) t nu^z,) (2) for some EDD of X It represents risk aversion if the function u is concave and p > 0. However, if p = 0, the functional at Eq. (2) is reduced to the expected utility form. Consequently, we call this functional proper disappointment aversion if p > 0. Lemma 1. Suppose that the decision maker is risk averse and that the preference relation > over the lotteries can be represented by a proper disappointment aversion functional. Assume further that the risk premium 'n-(/; e) is difTerentiable from the right at f = 0 +. Then the deeision maker's attitude towards risk is of order 1.^ Proof: Lete = (e\,p];... ;£„,/?„)withE[e] = Owhereei < . . . <en,andlet^(Obethe certainty equivalent of the lottery 8^; + te. There are two possible cases: 1. There exists f* > 0 and /Q sueh that \ft £ (0, t*), i,(t) G. [w + /e,,,, w + tei^^+ \]; or 254 GRAHAM LOOMES/UZI SEGAL 2. There exists /'o and two sequences {^j, such that for) = 1 , 2 , (a)lim^.^^ 4 = O;and (b) For every/c,4(/'^) < w + t^i^ei^^hut ^{t\) >w + t\ei^y Consider case 1, and assume first that for every / £ (0, t*), ^{t) G (w + /e,,,, w + ,,i+1). Then, the EDD is unique, and by Eq. (2) we get that where a = 2"=,,|+i A-Therefore, «(w - T7(/)) = V{^w + te) implies „ pieju'{w + tej) '• = ' 0 + 1 MO dt = 0+ ' = '0+1 (Recall that E[e] = 0 and p >0). Similar calculations for case 2 show that jr(t) is not differentiable a t ; = 0 + , a contradiction to our assumption that T:{f, e) is differentiable from the right at f = 0 +. Finally, if ^{ti^) = w + t^en) for some ('o and a sequence tk -^ 0, then either the risk premium is nondifferentiable as in case 2, or its derivative is positive as in case 1. • Consider now the issue of conditional orders of risk aversion. Let X and e be as in the definition of conditional orders of risk aversion, and suppose that the certainty equivalent of A" is (strictly) betweenx,,, andx,,,+1. For a sufficiently small t, adding te tox, leaves the certainty equivalent between x,,, andx/,|+1 (thus a and therefore ^(a) do not change) and, moreover, will add outcomes only on one side of the certainty equivalent of X The analysis of this case is therefore similar to that of expected utility, and the disappointment aversion model satisfies second-order conditional risk aversion, although it is of unconditional order one.' OBSERVING DIFFERENT ORDERS OF RISK AVERSION 255 Acknowledgments We gratefully acknowledge the financial support of the Economic and Social Research Council (U.K), Award No. R000231194 and of the Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council of Canada. Notes 1. For a discussion of the differentiability of the risk premium in expected and nonexpected utility models, and especially the issue of nondifferentiability of the utility function in the expected utility model, see Segal and Spivak (1990, 1992). Note that since a monotonic function is almost everywhere differentiable, nondifferentiability is the exception, not the rule, within the expected utility model. 2. We also checked tbe conjecture that some subjects migbt have tended to repeatedly pick alternatives near tbe middle of tbe screen, somebow figuring that tbis is probably a reasonable thing to do. Tbere is, bowever, no evidence for such behavior. Tbe only people who consistently picked alternatives from around tbe same area of the screen were those (few) who opted for an equal or near equal division of tbe money in all cases. But since those people mostly exhibited the same pattern of answers under a quite different procedure (discussed later in this section), tbere is no reason to think tbat their responses were an artifaet due to the screen displays. 3. Following Holt (1986), there has been some question about wbether tbis "random lottery selection" procedure may distort tbe way individuals report their preferences. Subsequently, Starmer and Sugden (1991) examined tbis question directly and found no evidenee of any systematic distortion. 4. No significant difference was found between the February responses of tbe 136 individuals who took part on both occasions and the 60 individuals who did not return in June. 5. Most of tbese cases involvedx being set only slightly lower than 7/2 i.e., the potential cost of such errors was generally very small. 6. Epstein (1992) has already indicated, without a formal proof, tbat the disappointment aversion functional implies first-order risk aversion. 7. The only case where the first-order derivative is not zero is when tbe certainty equivalent of A" equals some x,|| and the noise is added to tbis outcome. We ignore tbis case bere because for every/;, the set of lotteries of length n having this property has measure zero in the set of all lotteries of length /;. Also, in tbe experiment reported above, the noise was added to tbe certainty equivalent only when X = 8,. References Chew, Soo Hong. (1983). "A Generalization of tbe Ouasilinear Mean with Applications to tbe Measurement of Income Inequality and Decision Tbeory Resolving the Allais Paradox," Ecoiiomelrica 51, 1065-1092. Cbew, Soo Hong, Edi Karni, and Zvi Safra. (1987). "Risk Aversion in the Theory of Expected Utility with Rank Dependent Probabilities," yoi/ma/o/Ecottom/c Theoiy 42, 370-381. Epstein, Larry G. (1992). "Behavior Under Risk: Recent Developments in Theory and Applications." In J.J. Laffont (ed.). Advances in Economic Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Epstein, Larry G., and Stanley E. Zin. (1990). " 'First-Order' Risk Aversion and the Equity Premium Puzzle," Joumal of Monetary Eeonomies 26, 387-407. Epstein, Larry G., and Stanley E. Zin. (1991). "The Independence Axiom and Asset Returns." NBER Technical Working Paper No. 109. Gul, Faruq. (1991). "A Theory of Disappointment Aversion," Eeonomeliiea 59, 667-686. 256 GRAHAM LOOMES/UZI SEGAL Holt, Charles. (1986). "Preference Reversals and the Independence Axiom,"/l/?!CT7Cfl/i Econotnic Review 76, 508-515. Loomes, Graham. (1991). "Evidence of a New Violation ofthe Independence Ax\om," Jottnial of Risk ami Uttcetiaittty 5, 9\-\0S. Machina, Mark J. (1982). " 'Expected Utility' Analysis Without the Independence Axiom," Econometrica 50, 277-323. Machina, Mark J. (1989). "Comparative Statics and Non-Expected Utility Pvtfercnces," JotitiutI of Economic Theory 47, 393-405. Mas Collel, Andreu. (1974). "Continuous and Smooth Consumers: Approximation Theorem," Jotimal of Economic Theoiy 8, 305-336. Montesano, Aldo. (1988). "The Risk Aversion Measure without the Independence Axiom," Theoiy and Decision 24, 269-288. Pratt, John. (1964). "Risk Aversion in the Small and in the Large," Econometiiea 32, 122-136. Ouiggin, John. (1982). "A Theory of Anticipated \J\i\ky," Journal of Economic Behavior attd Orgattization 3, 323-343. Segal, Uzi. (1989). "Anticipated Utility: A Measure Representation Approach,"y4;»!a/i' of Operation Research 19, 1989, 359-373. (Correction: 1993, "The Measure Representation: A Correclion," JottnutI of Risk and Uncertainty 6, 99-\01.) Segal, Uzi, and Avia Spivak. (1988). "Local Risk Aversion." University of Toronto Working Paper No. 8806. Segal, Uzi, and Avia Spivak. (1990). "First Order Versus Second Order Risk Aversion," Journal of Economic Theory5l, 111-125. Segal, Uzi, and Avia Spivak. (1992). "Univariate and Multivariate Uniform First-Order Risk Aversion and Some Applications." Manuscript. Starmer, Chris, and Robert Sugden. (1991). "Does the Random-Lottery Incentive System Elicit True Preferences? An Experimental Investigation," ylmerica/i Economic Review 81, 971-978. Tversky, Amos, and Daniel Kahneman. (1992). "Advances in Prospect Theory: Cumulative Representation of Uncertainty," Jottmat of Risk and Uneeriainty 5, 297-323. Yaari, Menahem E. (1987). "The Dual Theory of Choice Under Risk," Econometrica 55, 95-115.