3 9080 02898 0834 HB31 .M415 ' i;i:v|.' Hiii H 1 1 w ^ 1 i!^ Digitized by the Internet Archive in 2011 with funding from Boston Library Consortium IVIember Libraries http://www.archive.org/details/optimalsavingsdiOOfarh NBER WORKING PAPER SERIES OPTIMAL SAVINGS DISTORTIONS WITH RECURSIVE PREFERENCES Emmanuel Farhi Ivan Weming Working Paper 13720 http://www.nber.Org/papers/w 1 3720 NATIONAL BUREAU OF ECONOMIC RESEARCH 1050 Massachusetts Avenue Cambridge, MA 02 138 January 2008 We thank George-Marios Angeletos, Narayana Kocherlakota, Andy Atkeson and Martin Schneider for useful comments and insightful discussions. All remaining errors are our own. The views expressed herein are those of the author(s) and do not necessarily reflect the views of the National Bureau of Economic Research. © 2008 by Emmanuel Farhi and Ivan Weming. All rights reserved. Short sections of text, not to exceed two paragraphs, may be quoted without explicit permission provided that full credit, including © notice, is given to the source. Optimal Savings Distortions with Recursive Preferences Farhi and Ivan Weming Emmanuel NBER Working Paper No. 13720 January 2008 JEL No. HO ABSTRACT This paper derives an intertemporal optimality condition for economies with private information, focusing on a class of recursive preferences. a risk-free asset market, Our we By comparing it to the situation where agents can recursive preferences are homogeneous and satisfy a balanced growth condition, while allowing us to separate the role of risk aversion and intertemporal elasticity of substitution. quantitative exercises that disentangle the respective roles played optSimal distortions and the implied welfare gains. Emmanuel Farhi Harvard University Department of Economics Littauer Center Cambridge, MA 02138 and NBER efarhi@harvard.edu Ivan Weming Department of Economics MIT 50 Memorial Drive, E5 1-25 la 02142-1347 Cambridge, MA and NBER iweming@mit.edu freely save in derive the optimal savings distortions necessary for constrained optimality. We perform some by these two parameters play in With unfettered access to a risk-free asset, agents can perform the following variation to consumption plans. At any point their by one unit and increase it can lower their current consumption in time, individuals in all future periods and contingencies by a constant absolute amount, equal to the net rate of return. At a market equilibrium, individuals find themselves at an optimum within this class of variations. The corresponding optimality condition is the familiar intertemporal Euler equation. Instead, a planner may have on work must consider the response that any change effort, if the latter is in the consumption plan not fully under her control due to private information. In general, there exists a class of variations available to the planner on the agent's consumption such that incentives and work planner finds the The effort are preserved. optimum within At the constrained-efficient allocation, the this class of variations. variations available to the planner do not always, or even typically, coincide with those available to agents in a free market equilibrium. Difference in these sets of variations leads to optimality conditions that are potentially incompatible. Distortions on savings required to implement the constrained The first optimum with an point emphasized by this paper is may then be asset market. that the particular form that the set of allowable variations for the planner takes, depends critically on preferences. We begin by showing that there exists a particular class of preferences for which the set of variations available to the planner actually coincides with that available to agents in a free market. As a result, the constrained efficient allocation requires no distortions on agents' savings. The preferences required for this result feature no income effects on work effort and constant absolute risk aversion. This particular result demonstrates that the form of the discrepancy between the constrained-optimum and the market equilibrium is likely to depend, in general, on preference assumptions. Next, we propose a class of homogeneous preferences with a balanced growth condition on work effort that delivers consumption for the a simple and intuitive class of variations. The allowable variations on planner in this case are as follows. At any point in time, the planner can lower the agent's current consumption and increase by a constant proportional amount. it in all future periods This type of variation through the asset market, which opens up the possibility improvements. The optimal is and contingencies not available to the agent for the planner to find Pareto- savings distortions are dictated by the difference between the absolute and proportional variations on consumption available to the agent and planner, respectively. Proportional changes in consumption leave incentives unaltered precisely because preferences are homogeneous and satisfy a balanced growth condition. and plausibility of these variations is We believe that the simplicity a desirable feature of the preferences we propose. They lead to simple intuitions, transparent theoretical results and a tractable framework for quantitative analysis. Within this class of variations the resulting optimality condition is extremely simple. It requires that the ratio of current utility to lifetime utility always equal the ratio of current consumption to the expected present discounted value of simple optimality condition the Golden Ratio. It lifetime consumption. We term this can also be stated as a Modified Inverse Euler equation in a form that resembles the standard Inverse Euler equation that was derived as a necessary condition for optimality for the variations considered in Farhi and Werning (2006). These preferences have three advantages. First, they are flexible enough to allow us to study the respective impact of two crucial parameters: the coefficient of relative risk aversion and the intertemporal separability of consumption Second, although they feature non- elasticity of substitution. and work effort, these preferences call for no savings distortions - just as the separable preferences studied in the in the absence of recurring uncertainty lit- erature on the Inverse Euler equation. Third, they lead to a very clean separation result for welfare gains between an idiosyncratic part and an aggregate part. Towards the end of the paper, we perform some quantitative welfare exercises that compute the gains from optimal savings distortions. We follow Farhi and Werning (2006), where we developed a new approach to analyze the welfare gains from distorting savings and moving away from letting individuals save freely. consumption and work effort, and attention to the case of geometric main goal and the is The method forgoes a complete solution for both focuses, instead, entirely on consumption. We random walk consumption and constant work our restrict effort. Our to isolate and compare the effects that the intertemporal elasticity of substitution coefficient of relative risk aversion size of the intertemporal wedge and the Thus, although we borrow from Farhi and Werning welfare gains from optimal distortions. (2006), the focus in that paper have on the was on the generality in terms of the stochastic process the baseline allocation of consumption. Instead, our focus here is on a for set of stylized baseline allocations that allow us to clearly separate the impact of different preferences assumptions. Welfare gains depend crucially on four factors: the concavity of the production function, the coefficient of relative risk aversion 7, the intertemporal elasticity of substitution p~^ and the variance of consumption growth a^ As in Farhi . and Werning (2006), we find that gains are decreasing in the concavity of the production function. In partial equilibrium with a linear production function, gains can be extremely large. By contrast, for hypothesis of a geometric an endowment economy welfare gains are zero under our random walk consumption process. For the intermediate case of a neoclassical production function, welfare gains are greatly mitigated. The steady state of the optimal allocation with saving distortions feature lower capital and a higher interest rate then the corresponding steady state of the market equilibrium, where the precautionary savings motive is The at work. variance of consumption growth and the coefficient of relative risk aversion control the strength of this interest rate increase and the decrease motive and hence both the between the baseline steady state and the in capital optimal steady state. The intertemporal elasticity of substitution on the other hand controls the speed of the transition: the higher p~^, the faster the transition, and the higher the welfare The gains. configuration of these three parameters influences greatly the magnitude of the welfare gains. 2 Constrained Efficiency In this section we present a two period Free Savings vs. economy to introduce the basic concepts set the Against this background, in the next section we turn to an stage for the rest of the paper. horizon economy with recursive preferences. infinite Consider a simple economy with two periods but at the beginning of period values and and p{s) is — 1 in the second. Let = 0, 1. There is no uncertainty at 5 is si = s. cq denote consumption in the a state Si G the probability of outcome and consumes and works (ci(s), Yi(s)) t t realized; we assume S is finite, The agent consumes t with = #5 in the first period first period and denote consumption and output as a function of the realized state in the second period. We adopt a general specification of preferences and denote the agent's over allocations by f/(co, Ci(-),Fi(-)). Thus, As Yi{-) as inputs. special benchmark U case, utility functional takes a scalar qj and two functions Ci(-) and one can assume the state si determines the worker's productivity and that the worker has an expected utility function n(co,Ci,ei) over consumption in both periods and work effort 61(5) = Yi{s)/s. Then U{co,Ci{-),Yi{-)) = E[u{co,Ci{s),ei{s))]. Technology is linear Co for some q > 0. Here, R= 1/q + q^Ci{s)p{s) <q^ei{s)p{s) is the rate of return between periods (1) and 1. — Free Savings 2.1 First-best. At The first-best allocation simply maximizes utility subject only to technology equation (1). this allocation the first-order conditions for consumption are given by Uco{Co,Ci{-),Yi{-))= /i, = 9P(s)/i, ^ci(5)(co,Ci(-),Fi(-)) where /x is the multiplier on the resource constraint. The first-order conditions for consumption can be combined into the following generalized Euler equation: -^E g^ ^ci(5)(co,ci(-),Fi(-)) f/co(co,Ci(-),Fi(-)) In the expected utility case this equation specializes to the familiar Euler equation 1 = RE "uci(co,ci(s),ei(s))" (3) ' _Uco{co,Ci{s),ei{s))_ Competitive equilibrium with free savings. tains in a free market The Euler equation equation economy where individuals have For example, suppose that agents live in (2) also ob- access to saving at rate of return R. an incomplete market setting, facing the budget constraints Co Then the savings fci All < 0, ci{s) < Yi{s) + (4a) + Rki first-order conditions for the agent's utility delivers equation equation (2).^ More (4b) S. maximization problem with respect to Note that the budgets constraints equation (4a)- equation (4b) imply the resource constraint equation A general set-up. Vs G (1). under what conditions does equation generally, (2) hold? Consider the abstract optimization problem of maximizing utility U{co,ci{-),Yi{-)) subject to (co,Ca(-),Fi(-))e.F some constraint for with J^ ^ = set J-. This nests as special cases both the Tfh defined by the resource constraint equation planning problem —and the agent's optimization if we assume that there are some taxes and transfers that we impose Ci(s) < T{yi{s),s)-\-Yi{s) + Rki in the second period. Indeed, this result holds more generally, even are a function of output or the state, so that (1) first-best market setting in the free —with T = Tjra defined by the budget constraints equation (4a)- equation (4b). Suppose that starting from any aUocation define simple variations that maintain the allocation in (co-gA,ci(-) for all A in neighborhood of A = 0. ing (increasing) consumption in the That is, + y(s)/s, effort Property equation is (5) is maintained for Note that the same output allocation F(s), states all s. holds for both the first-best planning problem and the agent's op- More assume that Let r s E S = (2) By telling the truth is denoted by a*{s) = s for all s {ci{a{s)),Yi{a{s))) in state s. E E denote the set of S. An agent using strategy A E s S and assign con- loss in generality, one can <t The states of the world truth-telling strategy e S obtains is = {c'({s),Y^{s)) Incentive-compatibility can be expressed as The second-best planning problem corresponds (6). satisfied. mapping true all strategies. U{co,c,{-),Y,{-))>U{co,cU-),Y,^{-)) and equation an satisfied at optimal. a{s) denote a reporting strategy for the agent, S. Let is it the revelation principle, the best the second period accordingly. Without in the E must be E S from the agent regarding to request a report r into reports r whenever generally, Consider next a private-information setting, observed only by the agent. sumption and output (5) period, while increasing (decreasing) consumption in first Second-best with private information. planner can do possible to T: optimum, then the generalized Euler condition equation s is it is a feasible allocation can be perturbed by decreas- timization problem in a free-market setting. where the state ^ A,ri(-))e.F, parallel across all states s in the second period. and hence Y^-)) e (cq, ci(-), second-best VaeE. to the case where optimum maximizes (6) T = J-sb defined by equation (1) utility subject to selecting an allocation in Tsb- In this general context, typically property equation (5) with Tsb however, provides an example where Proposition 1. it Lei ?7(co,Ci(-), Yi(-)) ond argument. Then property equation The next fails. proposition, holds. = U{cq,Ci{-) — v{Yi{-),-)) where U monotone in its sec- (5) holds for J^sb for all feasible allocations {co,Ci{-),Yi{-)) ^sbProof. The result follows by noting that incentive compatibility equation if c{s) - v{Y{s),s) > c{r) - v{Y{r),s) Vr, s E S, (6) holds if and only E which is independent of cq and invariant to the operation of exchanging A c(-) for c(-) 4- for D any A. If it is property equation without (5) holds for A all (not just in a neighborhood around loss of generality to allow agents to freely save, in can allow the agent to select the value for of preferences identified A in this variation. of the quasi-linear specification c As a (co first Y^ v{Y\ s) is is -I- A,Yi(-)). 1/g. The economic invariant to A. is Proposition the case for 1 (5) is as follows. freely, interpretation (5) s, (5) holds. Any direct mechanism an ex-post menu In each state menu, {d[,Y^). Property equation guarantee that this 2.2 follows that, for the class that there are no income effects on work effort. An equivalent way of postulating property equation — 9A,ci(r) + A,yi(r)) essentially offers the agent this It period do not then affect the choice between work effort and earnings. to the loci of points (ci(-) on — R= then the sense that the planner they do not disturb incentive compatibility and property equation result, 0) by the proposition, the planner can allow the agent to save without distortions, at the technological rate of return Savings from the A= in each state s equal the agent selects an optimal point then amounts to assuming that this optimum then identifies the largest class of preferences that can all feasible allocations. Distorted Savings From the previous subsection, we know that the variations that result from free savings do not generally preserve incentive compatibility. In this situation, what can we say about the desirability of free savings? A Lagrangian approach. We approach The first is this question in two complementary ways. to attach Lagrange multiplier ii{a) on the incentive constraints equation (6), leading to an optimality condition that includes the effect that may have on the incentive constraints: -E/^('^)(-5^^o(co,Ci(a(-)),ri(a(-))) • if all + 5]t/,,(,)(co,Ci(a(-)),Fi(a(-)))) the incentive constraints are slack, so that this expression boils down jj,{a) to the Euler equation equation (2). tion equation (2) will typically not hold. Indeed, if are nonzero, then one can sign the intertemporal = for all <t € S, then Otherwise, the Euler equa- one signs the term —qUco{co, Ci(a(-)), '^ses^ci{s){co,c-i{a{-)),Yi{a{-))) for different strategies a and =0. J s&s \ o-ei; Note that A yi(cr(-)))-|- characterizes which multipliers wedge required in the Euler equation. Another Feasible variations. line of attack to find a different variation, that does pre- is serve incentive compatibility, without changing work This leads to an intertemporal effort. optimality condition that does not involve Lagrange multipliers. optimality condition with the Euler equation equation The idea is this (2). to find a variation function 5(A,s) on consumption in the second period that depends on the realized state s so that: (co in a One can then compare neighborhood of A= 0. + A,ci(-) + (5(A,-),ri(-))e^, (7) At an optimum we must then have that t/co(co, ci(-), ei(-)) + J2 ^ci(«)(^' ci(-), ei(-)) ^^(0, s) = (8) • s&S For example, with expected feasible is utility and u(co,ci,ei) = u{co,ci) — h{ei) a variation that is to set 5(A,s) so that fi{co where ^(A) is + A,ci{s) + 5{A,s))=u{co,Ciis))+A{A) Vs e 5 (9) such that ^(A + <5(A,5))p(5) = 0. (10) ses This variation shifts utility in a parallel way across states s E S. It preserves incentive compatibility because these parallel shifts cancel each other out on both sides of equation At an optimum A'{0) = so that uj^o^ d dA It (6). ' ' ' (11) Ue,(co,Ci(5)) then follows that 1 = E ?#^pw. (12) ^«ci(Co,Ci(s)) which is known as the Inverse Euler equation. compatible with the Euler equation equation By (3), Jensen's inequality, this condition except in the special case where there is inis no uncertainty in the marginal rate of substitution ratio Uco{cq, Ci{s))/uci{co-, Ci(s))- Without uncertainty the optimality of no intertemporal distortions follows from Atkinson-Stiglitz's (1976) result on uniform taxation, which requires separability between consumption and assumed in this case. effort, as Logarithmic balanced-growth preferences. esting special case with several advantages u(co,Ci) = + log(co) is Within this class of preferences, an inter- the logarithmic balanced growth specification /31og(ci). In this case the variations induce parallel multiplicative shifts over second-period consumption: S{A,s) for If some 5(A). Intuitively, incentives are consumption is = 6iA)c,is), provided by proportional rewards and punishments. down by a constant scaled up or (13) it does not change the incentives for work effort. In this case, unlike the preference class described in Proposition work effort are nonzero. 1, income effects for Proportional variations are feasible precisely because of the balanced growth condition, that implies that income and substitution exactly cancel each other. This logarithmic case seems economically appealing, because of the primitives and the simple proportional variations expected utility case permits. it condition. u(c) It is consumption, as = c^~"/(l — = u{co) + Pu{ci)h{ei) This class of preferences also a). easily verified that in simple generalization of this case, is to the where u(co, Ci, ei) and where One (14) satisfies a balanced growth once again the feasible variations are proportional in equation (13). In the next section we extend this class to an infinite horizon economy. Preferences that lead to the feasibiUty of proportional variations turn out to be very tractable. In particular, they lead to a very simple optimality condition. Within a class of baseline allocations, the optimum 3 is easily identified and its welfare improvements quantified. Recursive Preferences We now turn to an infinite horizon and introduce a class of recursive preferences that are homogeneous in the consumption process and separate elasticity of substitution as in (Epstein assumed and Zin, 1989). risk aversion from the intertemporal Consumption and work-effort are not to be separable, but satisfy a balanced-growth condition. For this class of preferences, we provide simple variations on consumption that maintain incentive compatibility. affect incentives. The variations involve proportional shifts in consumption that do not Both the homogeneity and the balanced-growth are crucial for this result. specification on preferences Based on these variations we derive the intertemporal optimaUty condition the section. this way, The condition is shown at the end of to be incompatible with allowing agents to freely save. In an intertemporal wedge on savings form of distortions on savings are required some is present at the optimal allocation. Thus, in any tax implementation of the optimum. In the next section we explore the welfare gains from adhering to this condition for some simple cases. Our preferences do not satisfy the separability condition required for Atkinson-Stiglitz's uniform taxation theorem. Despite this, it is optimal in the absence of uncertainty to set the intertemporal distortions to zero. Thus, for these preferences, optimal distortions in savings arise from ongoing idiosyncratic uncertainty, just as in the additively separable expected-utility case that leads to the Inverse Euler condition. Moral Hazard 3.1 We build on the following simple static moral-hazard model. At the beginning of the period, the agent s is first exerts effort a, which is not observable by the planner. The state of nature then realized from the distribution P{s\a). The planner observes s and gives the agent consumption c{s). The agent's expected utility is given by E[U{c{s)h{a))\a]. We suppose the agent's utility U{c) dard balanced- growth assumption, is a power function. This specification for which income and substitution equivalent reformulation of the agent's objective satisfies the stan- effects cancel out. An is U{Ch{a)) where C= CE[c{s)\a] = U-^{E[U{c{s))\a]) represents the certainty-equivalent obtained from the random consumption For our dynamic setting, we proceed analogously. chooses effort at-i, then the state sumption c(5*). Effort affects with = /i(0) 1. 5* is realized At the St and lowers Preferences are given by the recursion = Cis*)h{a{s'-')) 10 start of period and observed and the planner the distribution of state Va{s'-') c{s). utility t the worker allocates con- by a factor h{at) < 1 where C{s') = CE [W{c{s')Ms')) a{s'-'),s'-'] I (15) , represents lifetime-certainty-equivalent consumption, with CE = is (16) the certainty equivalent function and. = W{c,v) is R-^¥.R u-\{l-(3)u{c) + (5u{v)) (17) a time aggregator, mapping current consumption and future utility into a constant-consumption equivalent. With this representation of preferences, static setting. By in the following, c = one can easily see the analogy with the simple a change of variables, however, the same preferences can be represented more convenient, way. For any given effort plan a = {a(s*)}, an allocation {c(s*)} implies a process for lifetime utility {va{s*)} that solves Va{s') = W{c{s')Xnh{a{s'))va{s'+')\a{s'),s']) Incentive compatibility of c, \/t,sK (18) v and a* requires a* to maximize initial lifetime utility Va'iso) > Vo. Va{So) (19) Since preferences are recursive, this implies that a* maximizes continuation utility after any history Va'{s')>Va{s*) Otherwise, a plan that follows a* up to s* and That after s* would be preferable to a*. \/a,t,s\ (20) and then switches to the actions prescribed by a is. at Bellman's Principle of Optimality applies to the agent's dynamic program. We now bility. consider variations in the consumption process that maintain incentive compati- After history s'^ the consumption sequence not affect incentives. At affected in period r and s'^ we shift is just shifted proportionally, and this does consumption to compensate, so that incentives are not earlier periods. The key property we use is homogeneity of W(c, v') and of CE. Proposition 2. Assume u{x) = x^'P/ {I — p) and R{x) 11 = x^~'' / {1 — j) with p,j >0. Suppose that c, V and a* satisfy conditions (18) and (19). Fix a history A c{s'^) c{s') = for there exists a A = fort> { A'c(s*) . Consider the variation: s^ T and s* y- s'^ otherwise c(5*) Then for any A' s* s'^ such that v and a* satisfy conditions (18) and (19). c, Proof. Let v be such that Va{s^) = A'va{s^) for i > T and 5* >- s'^ Va{s*) = Va{s*) foT t > s* ^ s'^ so that condition equation (18) with c is met T and for all 5* with t > t with s* ^ s'^. Now set A so that va'isn so that Va' at s'^ {s'^) = = Va' {s'^). W {Ac{s'),A'CE[h{a*{s-'))v,,{s^-^') Using recursion equation \ a*{s^),s^]) (18), the inequality . equation (20) evaluated implies CE [h{a*{s^))va'{s^^') > CE a*{s^),s^] I [h{a{s^))va{s^+') \ a{s^),s^] , so that Va'is^) = W{Acis'),A'CE[h{a*{s^))va^{s^^') a*{sn,s^]) I >W {Ac{s'),A'CE[hia{s^))va{s^^') \ a{sn,s^]) = i).(s^). Hence, we have that Va{s'') a* is < Va'is'') = Va'{s'') for all a. optimal from period r onward and delivers the same continuation utility as previously. For any plan a define an alternative plan a that switches to a* from period r onward: a(s*) = a(5*) for i < r and a{s^) Va{So) That is is, < = > t. ^a(-So) < a*(s*) for Va{So) = a dominates a and yields the same dominated by the recommended action a* t The result ^a* (^o) utility as = above implies that Va'{so)- without the variation, which in turn which also yields the same variation. This estabUshes that a* remains incentive compatible. 12 (21) utility as after the D A Private Information: 3.2 Here we build on Mirrlees' Dynamic Mirrleesian Economy static private information model. the agent privately observes productivity consumption gives the agent At the beginning of the period, The agent then makes a 0. c{r) as function of the report. The report r and the planner agent's expected utility is ¥.[U{c{r)h{r,e))\a]. where r = a{6) is We the agent's reporting strategy. a power function. This specification which income and substitution suppose the agent's utility U{c) is the standard balanced-growth assumption, for satisfies effects cancel out. For our djoiamic setting, we assume the following structure of uncertainty. At the beginning of the period a state 9t is a it realized finite and publicly observed by the agent and planner. Then of values. After observing the shock to the planner. by realized and observed only by the agent. To simplify we assume that number histories St is z* = We collect the variables Sj and the agent makes a report dt observed by the planner by zt = r^ {st,rt) 9t take on regarding and their (s*,r*). For any reporting strategy a v,{z\9') where Zt+i We let = = W {c{z')XE[h{z'^\e,^,)v,{z'-^\e'+') a* denote the truth- telling strategy of the next result Proposition (c, h, 3. is Assume u{x) = v) satisfying (22) and cr^{z* x^~''/{l — = { A'c(2*) c{z*) Then for any A' there exists a on s\ the realization of We 9t p) , 9^) = is 9t. Incentive compatibihty requires Va. and R{x) (23), fix a history z^ c(2*) = (22) , (23) in the appendix. A c{z-') u{x) at+,,z\e']) (5^+1,0-^+1(2;*, 61*+^)). Va'{zo,9o)>v,{zo^9o) The proof \ A such that for = x^~"'/{l and consider 2* = — 7). For any allocation the following variation: r fort>T and z* >- z'' otherwise (c, h, v) satisfy (22) and (23) independent and identically distributed; or if: (h) (a) Conditional p — I so that \ogx. do not impose restrictions on the stochastic process 13 for the observable state St- Re- garding the unobservable shock, the requirement in part and can, for productivity, requirement does ensure in particular, is (a) does not restrict the process accommodate any degree What of persistence. that the states that affect the evolution of shocks are observable, that there are no hidden states. Although this implies that the observable state the sense that Pr(s*+",6I*+"|5*,6'*) ficient statistic for (s*,6'*), in allocations typically depend on the history may False past reports vant. this 9^ = s* is Pr(s*+",6'*+"|s*), optimal In this way, the history of reports r* . a suf- is rele- then affect the allocation the agent receives, but do not affect the planner's capacity to predict the agent's future productivity. This tractability allows us to find variations that maintain incentive compatibility. = In the logarithmic case, p 0, the crucial property H/(Ac, = Hence, setting A^~^(A')^ reporting strategy. As a 1 in result, that Ai-^(A')^H/(c,t;'). the variations does not affect the utility delivered by any no assumption on the structure of uncertainty is required. The Intertemporal Optimality Condition: The Golden Ratio or The Modified Inverse Euler Equation 3.3 Let us say that an allocation E Yl'tLo 9*Q any AV) = is and is efficient if it minimizes the present value of consumption delivers a given lifetime utility level in efficient allocation an incentive compatible way. Then cannot be improved by the variations above. That is, these variations cannot reduce the discounted value of consumption. Fix a node at all s'^ . Increase consumption at s^ proportionally by A, and increase consumption nodes that follow it, s* >- s'^, proportionally by A'. This variation propositions above. Indexing the variation by A' and solving for constant, we permitted by the A = 5(A') that keeps utility consider the minimization min j (5(A')c(r ) first-order necessary and + A' ^ q'c{s') Pr[5*|a*, J"] t>T,S^ \ The is J sufficient condition for optimality is ct (1-/3Mq) Y.7=o'i'^A(^+s] u{vt) Thus, optimality requires the ratio of current to lifetime equated to the ratio of current consumption with 14 (24) . j its simply utility (25) (1 — (3)u{cf,) / u{vt) expected present value to be q/ X^^q 9*^Et['^+s]- Rearranging, the ratio of current consumption and utility must be equated to the ratio of the present value of consumption with lifetime utility: Ct (26) {1-I3)u{ct) u{vt) Both conditions formalize the optimality of a form of consumption smoothing. We call them the Golden Ratio conditions. The next for result reexpresses the optimality condition above in a way that is more suitable comparison with the optimality condition - the Euler equation - that results when agents can save freely at the interest rate q~^ We . call this condition the Modified Inverse Euler equation. Proposition 4. Define ht+iVt+i Xt+l (27) CEt[ht+iVt+iY At the optimum in (24) the following condition (a) holds: i-p u'{ct) %. 1 u'{(h+\) /? (h) If agents (28) '-t+i can borrow and save freely at the interest rate q then the allocation must satisfy ^, the following Euler equation: x: '^' (29) u'[c,) Savings will generally be distorted at the optimal allocation, since the Modified Inverse Euler equation and the Euler equation are incompatible. Thus, in any implementation of the planner's optimum, agents cannot be allowed to borrow and save freely at the interest rate l/q. Suppose that the optimality condition equation T by solving for the factor (1 replaced with (1 — — (28) holds. Define the intertemporal r) required so that the Euler equation (29) holds wedge when \/q is r)/g: 1 - T = E; „P-7 u'{ct+\ 't+\ % 1-p (30) u'{ct+x) u'ict) so that r = —Gov u'{ct.+1) u'{c,) 1-p -X.*+i u'ict) Importantly, the intertemporal wedge r 1-7 ^t+\ is (31) xl-fu'{c,^,) zero whenever there is no uncertainty. For the case of certainty, Atkinson-Stiglitz's uniform-taxation result requires preferences to be separable 15 between consumption and However, in our recursive specification preferences are not leisure. Interestingly, despite this, the absence of resolution of uncertainty separable. between two periods implies that there should be no intertemporal distortion on savings there. In other words, although the separibility conditions required by Atkinson-Stiglitz are violated, their uniform commodity taxation result holds under certainty with our preferences. Thus, optimal distortions can be entirely attributed to ongoing idiosyncratic uncertainty, just as in the additively separable expected-utility case that leads to the Inverse Euler equation (Golosov et al, 2003). Note that on savings is = 7 if positive. > 0. We shall 0, guaranteeing that the intertemporal distortion Another interesting case = baseline allocation, so that q+i r > one gets that r 1 £t+iCf when q is is a geometric random walk at the then follows that It study this case in more detail in the Vf is proportional to q, and next section. Constant Absolute Risk Aversion Preferences 3.4 In this subsection, risk aversion the we show that for a particular class of preferences optimal distortion on savings convenient specification of preferences is zero. with constant absolute In a static moral-hazard setting, a is E[Uic-h{a))\a] where U{x) = — e"'*^ is (32) exponential. Equivalently, one can express ex ante utility as CE[c-h{a)\a] In our R{x) — dynamic —e'''^ setting, we v') — u~^ {{1 5. = W {c{s')XEK{s'+') - hia{s')) — P)u{c) + Pu{v')) and CE = R~^ER. inequalities (19) as before. Proposition generalize this specification as follows. Let u{x) = — e~^^ and and consider the recursion v^{s') where W{c, (33) Assume The next proposition u{x) = is —e~^^ and R{x) 16 proved \ a{s'),s']) Incentive compatibility requires in the = — e~"*'^. (34) appendix. Suppose we have c, v and a* . satisfying conditions (18) and (19). Fix a history c(s^) = c(5*) { c{s^) +A for + fort A' A there exists a As above, we say that an Consider the variation: . = s* > 5^ T and s* s^ >>- otherwise c(s*) Then for any A' s'^ such that c, v and a* satisfy conditions (18) and (19). is efficient if it minimizes the present value of con- Y,q'c{s')Y>x[s'\a*] (35) allocation sumption required to deliver a given lifetime utihty level in an incentive compatible way. efficient allocation cannot be improved by the variations above. That is, Then any these variations cannot reduce the net present value of consumption. Indexing the variation at any node by A' and solving for can write the minimization subproblem as freely at a market Proposition and save 6. The optimum in (24) corresponds to the u'[ct) tion CARA the worker could save and borrow = economy where agents can borrow The following Euler equation ^u'(CE(ct+i - holds: (36) ht)). coincide. Welfare Gains; Quantitative Explorations In this section, Section 3. The we investigate the welfare gains from the optimal savings distortions derived in analysis proceeds along the lines of Farhi case where the baseline allocation features a geometric work and preferences under consideration, the constrained-optimality condi- and the Euler equation 4 if we interest rate q~^ freely at the interest rate q~^. Hence, for the that keeps utility constant in (24). In this case, the first-order necessary with the condition obtained sufficient condition coincides A effort is constant. The settings. Assumption The baseline allocation {ct.ht] geometric random walk Ct+i (2006). We focus on the random walk consumption process while analysis in this section covers both to the private-information and moral-hazard 1. and Werning = is such that ht = h is constant and Ct is a Qet+i with St+i identically and independently distributed over time. 17 — Partial equilibrium 4.1 Let us first assume that there R= with a gross rate of return The if the baseline allocation random also a pure geometric a pure geometric random walk. Suppose that Assumption 7. is then the cost minimizing allocation attainable through our variations ht is constant, Proposition is q~^. following proposition shows that walk and is a linear technology to transfer resources from period to period is obtained by multiplying {q} 1 holds. Then the cost minimizing allocation {q} by a deterministic drift g~^: ct = ag~% with g = ' ^-') (qp-'E[s] (E [c^"^]) and a 1 where 3 = is such that q attainable from the baseline allocation through our varia- Ct also follows a geometric random walk, but with a stead of E[£:] for the baseline allocation. This condition — a necessary and when h^ = Cj. Note that > 1 and vice drift /3 p = dh}~f. ensures that the constrained-optimality within our class of variations factor. It is This roles in this compounded with effect is also useful to note that if ^ > 1. versa. Increasing g while maintaining the value of qE[e\ effective discount factor /3 different drift ^~^E[£:] in- and h}~P play exactly similar his constant, h acts as a discount to produce an effective discount factor then a new sufficient condition for optimality holds at the optimal allocation formula: qg-p^e] pih}'^. Hence the optimal allocation tions - (3. is exactly equivalent to decreasing the In other words, the higher g, the lower the effective discount factor that makes the constrained-optimality condition hold. Note also that given qE\£\ elasticity of substitution discount factor /3 and parameter g, p. the intercept The a depends only on the intertemporal risk aversion parameter 7 only shifts the effective required for the constrained-optimality condition to hold. Economists are used to thinking of the discount factor as a primitive of the model, and as the equilibrium interest rate as an outcome. However, contrary to interest rates, discount factors are not directly observable. In fact, comes from equilibrium values of Q, we most of the evidence concerning discount factors interest rates. Therefore, in the formula for the intercept prefer to think of the equilibrium interest rate q as the primitive effective discoimt factor (3 and to solve for the that makes the constrained-optimality condition hold given g and qne\. 18 We Intertemporal wedge. can compute the optimal wedge in closed form: — Cov{£,£~^) ^ ^ Note that the wedge and is is E[e]E[£-T] always positive. by entirely determined that the origin of the wedge 7, that is magnitude Its example by the agent's attitude toward is independent of p is This highlights risk. the combination of two factors: the riskiness of tomorrow's consumption from today's perspective and the agent's would be no reason to in this distort savings Absent shocks, there risk aversion. and the Euler equation would hold. Similarly, if the agent were risk neutral, there would be no reason to distort savings and the wedge would also be zero. We can re-express the wedge using the formalism of cumulants: generating function of log (e) of log(e) is moments, as we see from the notation is standard, with be the moment : m{9) The nth cumulant m let = given by = «;„ = ^^(0). log E[s'] Cumulants are = ^2, «3 = denoting the conditional mean of log(£) first four: /xi = log £;[exp(^ log (e))] ki ^1, K2 A*3) 1^4 closely related to = fJ-4 — and ^„, The 3(//2)^- n > for 1 , denoting the nth central conditional moment. Using this notation we derive a formula that ties the wedge to the higher order moments or cumulants of log(e): 00 - log(l - r) = m(l) + m(-7) - m(l - 7) = J^ «„/n! (1 + (-7)" - (1 - 7)") n=2 In the lognormal case, which n > 3 log(e): we explore below, the higher cumulants and we obtain a closed form -log(l -r) = for the «;„ of log(£:) are zero for wedge which depends only on the variance a"^ of 7a2. Outside of the lognormal case, higher cumulants are non-zero and higher moments of the distribution of consumption growth rates affect the wedge. For example, impact of skewness K3. The contribution negative skewness - K3 - decreases the wedge Welfare gains. computed The costs k term to the wedge of this if 7 < 1 is we can analyze the given by K3 and increases the wedge Hence "'' ^ if 7 > 1. and k of the baseline and the optimal allocations are to be - k = ac l-qg-'ne\ 19 easily and k ^— = - 1 qE[e] Combining these two expressions, we can derive the cost allowed relative reduction in expected discounted by our variations. Proposition 8. Suppose that Assumption holds. 1 Then the relative expected discounted cost reduction achieved by going from the baseline allocation to the optimal allocation k ~k By is _ fl-qg-PE[s]\^^ fl-qg-'E[e]y-^^ 1-9E[5] V ; V 1-qE[£] homogeneity, the ratio of the cost of the optimal allocation to the cost of the baseline does not depend on the current or in other words, given gE[e], ^ the variations. It is consumption level of is c. Given the cost of the baseline allocation, a sufficient statistic for the welfare gains attainable through some comparative therefore instructive to perform statics with respect to 9- Given qE[e] and g, the relative expected cost reduction depends only on the intertemporal elasticity of substitution parameter p. that given g and gE[£], the intercept = At ^ 1, the reduction in cost This a direct consequence of the fact noted above is a does not depend on is 0. This the risk aversion parameter. because in this case, the constrained-optimality is condition holds at the baseline allocation. Moreover, a Taylor expansion around g that the cost reduction When zero at the first k 1 ^ order in g and increasing in g qE[e] is like taking the effective discount factor to 0. reveals : Yir^Ekl- Taking g to In that case, the optimal allocation for 1 is In the limit where p goes to Ct = 1, we for i > 1 and cq = cq. get ,= -E[e]and. = ^3r^, which I ,,2 , g goes to infinity on the other hand, the cost reduction goes to infinity A_i = is = is .-. exactly the expression derived in Farhi and Werning (2006). Euler at the baseline. in the interesting case Given the importance of ^f we now investigate , where the Euler equation holds 20 its main determinants at the baseline allocation. That the . Euler equation holds at the basehne means that -7 which can be re-expressed as The fiq-^h'-P^. [£-^] (E [e^-^] effective discount factor /3, = /3 /3 Knowing ^ 7-£ = 1 = (38) can then be determined: ^ (5h} ) 5(E[£^])-^(E[ei-^])^ the sufficient statistic g for the welfare gains in formula (37) can be derived using the formula in Proposition (7). Proposition holds 9. // Assumption 1 and the Euler equation holds at the baseline allocation, then J g=lE[e]E[e-^]{E[s'-''])-y. The optimal change wedge in drift g is reflects the strength of the for inceased more agents r: = g {1 — t)~^^'^. The precautionary savings motive: the higher the wedge, the The higher the intertemporal larger the gains from frontloading consumption. substitution, the wedge positively related to the elasticity of are willing to accept reductions in consumption in the future consumption today. The two combined determine the optimal change effects in drift g. When e is ~ lognormally distributed loge N{fi,a'^), then the wedge from the baseline allocation g and the welfare gains can be computed and the variance CoroUciry 1. cr^ of in r, the change in drift terms of the mean /x consumption growth: Suppose that £ is lognormally distributed loge ~ N{^,al), then r and g are given by T = I — r ^. ,^ E[e]E [e-f] , = — 1 exp ^ L — 7(T.ej ~ 70", i ' e and = exp ( As we already discussed, the magnitude of the shocks cr^. When shocks are lognormal, wedge is ~ —a^ \P I V — 1 H <T^. P increasing in the degree of risk aversion 7 Moreover, 7 and a'^ affect the wedge in a in the complementary way. the formula takes the remarkably simple form r 21 and = 1 —exp [— 7(t^] . The crucial parameter g associated with is -cr^. The higher the variance and of the shocks, the higher risk aversion, the higher the required change in drift g between the baseline and p~\ the the optimum. Similarly, the higher the intertemporal elasticity of substitution higher 9- Intuitively, this different dates can be seen by taking the limit as p goes to become perfect substitutes. Note however the limit, since the required change in drift g goes to )~^ that in this case, the intercept a converges to 1 — g (E [£""'•'] E [e^~^]. when p goes Intuitively, it is to 0, best to deliver lim - is it optimal to front-load consumption more and more. The is non trivial. ~ + -~ 1 - + (l-27)f - l-q 3Xp 'p + 1 Indeed, we have: 7cr; qe^' i_ gains are increasing in the intertemporal elasticity of substitution p~^: intuitively, as consumption at different dates become more substitutable, it becomes easier to compensate the agent for a decrease in the drift in consumption in order to lower his exposure to fact, we can k this risk. In derive a simple formula for small a^: '-1 + From In in the first period so that agents are entirely cost reduction 1-- qexp p = 0, consumption all shielded from consumption risk. The so that consumption at The Euler equation and the optimality condition are incompatible in the limit where p goes to infinity. 0, formula it 77^^-4 p apparent that at the is first (39) ' qei^)^ (1 relevant order, risk aversion and the in- 2 tertemporal elasticity of substitution enter the formula for the gains only through ^. Quantitative exploration. Figure 1 and 2 plot the reciprocal of the relative cost reduction using equation equation (37) as a measure of the relative welfare gains as a function of a|. The figures use 0.007. The an emxpirically relevant range for value of gE[e] In figure 1, cr^ which is taken to vary between and set to 0.97. is the intertemporal elasticity of substitution p~^ is set to 1 and the different curves correspond to different values of the relative risk aversion coefficient 7 ranging from 1 to 3 in increments of 0.5. The gains are increasing in 7; 10% Increasing 7 by is exactly equivalent to increasing a^ by 10%. In Figure 2, the relative risk aversion coefficient 7 is set to 1, and the different curves correspond to different values of the intertemporal elasticity of substitution p"^ ranging from 0.5 to 1 in increments of 0.1. equivalent to increasing a'^ The gains are increasing in by 5%. 22 p~\ Increasing p~^ by 10% is roughly Figure and 1: Welfare gains as a function of a^. Baseline consumption The Euler equation a ranging from 1 to 3. ht is constant. values of Two lessons holds. emerge from our simple The is a geometric random walk correspond to different different curves First, welfare gains exercise. range from small to potentially large. Second, they depend a lot on three parameters of the model: 7, p and The play an coefficient of relative risk aversion 7 and the variance of consumption growth cr^ a'^. especially important role over the range consistent with the available empirical evidence con- cerning these two parameters. but its The intertemporal influence over the empirically relevant range because the range for this parameter than 7 and a^ as can be seen from 4.2 Up to elasticity of substitution p^^ is is somewhat less is important, dramatic. This is both smaller and because p~^ enters with a smaller power (39). General equilibrium now we have of the results restricted the analysis to partial equilibrium. Alternatively, one can think we have derived of return to capital. In Farhi so far as applying to an economy facing some given constant rate and Werning (2006), we argue that neglecting general equiHbrium effects magnifies the welfare gains from reforming the consumption allocation. Here we explore the joint influence of risk aversion and the intertemporal elasticity of substitution on general equilibrium welfare gains. Planning problem. problem, it allocations is q Consider a baseline allocation {ct,ht}. useful to introduce the following notation: let In order to setup the planning T{{ct,ht},A_i) be the attainable through our variations from the baseline allocation {A_iCi, that the shifted allocation {A-iCt,ht} utility increased is incentive compatible by a multiplicative factor A_i to the agent. 23 and /i^}. set of Note delivers a value lifetime In general equilibrium, the Figure 2: Welfare gains as a function of walk and h-t is constant. The from 0.5 to 0.9. cr? when baseline consumption is a geometric random correspond to different values of p~^ ranging different curves planning problem can be set-up as W{Ko) = max vq (40) {ct,Kt^i} subject to ht {{1 Vt i-p r,i.-Tni-' - ,3)cl-' + 13 for f {E[vl--;']) = 0,1,.. {ci}GT({Q,M,A_i), Kt+i + E[q] < F{Kt, Nt) + (1 - S)Kt for t = 0, 1, ... Ko = Ko. Necessary and c? sufficient conditions for this course, allocation Et FK{Kt.Nt) + {l-5) and A_i is the maximand in ( = E[ct], where the superscript i -^Kt+i for i = 0, 1, [Uviri])'-' we have W{Kq) — A-it-F where W is the welfare achieved at the baseUne 40). Note that we can always decompose q Cf are: Vt+l = (ih'-" Of problem = (^^Ct with the property that stands for idiosyncratic. deterministic parallel shifts in consumption, we have 24 that E[cJ] = 1 and Since our variations allow for {q} G T({ct, /?t}. A_i) for some A_i if and only The if {5j} G T({cJ, ht}, A_i). analysis of this planning problem tackled in is full generality in Farhi where we also explore non geometric random walk baseline (2006), and Werning allocations: we provide cases where (40) can be separated into two different planning problems, one involving only the idiosyncratic part of the allocation instead, we focus on the cj and the other only the aggregate part Ct- special case were the baseline allocation features geometric walk consumption with constant Here random ht- Geometric random walk with constant hf Suppose that the baseline allocation features geometric random walk consumption with constant ht and constant aggregate consumption: = Ct+i where St+i Ct£t+i and ht = h, independently and identically distributed across agents and time and with is E[£i+i] =1. In other words. Assumption holds and E[e] =1. 1 Define l3e Proposition 10. Suppose = f3{E [e^-^])^ and that = Ctc\ where Ct and A_i CRRA preferences: Assumption 4 = h'-^P,. holds and E[e] =1. 1 The solution to (40) is are the solutions of the standard neoclassical growth model with Ct 1 - = (l-4) ^ P max ^ {Ct,Kt+i} TPl^ (41) subject to Kt+i + Ct< F{Kt, Nt) + (1 - 5)Kt for t = 0, 1, ... Ko = Ko. The property relies crucially we saw that the idiosyncratic component of the baseline allocation on the assumption of geometric random walk with constant above, the planner only wants to affect the drift of {c]}, which case of an is endowment economy where 1 = is ht- Intuitively, as impossible in the E[cJ]. In the case where the baseline allocation is a geometric random walk with constant can therefore restrict welfare gains come from modifying the aggregate component our attention to the aggregate part of the allocation: Euler equation at the baseline. already optimal Suppose that we the potential of the allocation. in addition, the baseline allocation repre- sents a steady state where the Euler equation holds. 25 all ht, p-i p-i 0.5 = p-' 0.75 = l 6WpE SWge fss SWpE 5Wge rss 5WpE SWge rss 0.09% 0.34% 1.07% 0.10% 0.69% 6.53% 12.33% 0.38% 0.79% 3.82% 5.28% 7.03% 0.10% 0.37% 0.75% 3.82% 4.55% 3 3.82% 4.55% 5.28% 1.56% 2 2.02% 3.62% 7=1 7 = 7 = = 5.15% 9.85% Table Let qss = — (1 we can that case, S + 5.28% Welfare Gains. 1: FpciKss, Nss))~ 5.28% be the inverse of the steady state interest rate. In derive as above an expression for P^: 4 = qss (E [s-^])-' E [e^-] (E [s]r' = qss (E [e])' J^_ E E [e] That the baseline allocation is [£-T] a steady state implies in particular that E[£] =1. We can therefore simplify the formula for $^: Pe The optimal rate qss When terms of e is // lognormally distributed logs and E [g^-^] E [e] E [e-r] ' = 4- a^. We ~ N{fj,,a'^), then we can compute P^ and qss in get the remarkably simple formula: qss is, qss allocation will eventually reach a steady state where the inverse of the interest given by qss is = = Pe = qss exp (-70"e) Equation (42) shows that the new interest rate is Kss < Kss) by The a factor given by exp (70-^). (42) higher than the initial interest rate (that higher risk aversion and the variance of consumption growth, the higher the increase in steady state interest rates, and the higher the reduction in steady state capital stock. Because the baseline allocation has no trend, the intertemporal elasticity of substitution does not affect the level of the The only thing our variations allow in this case is 7 and the variance As we of consumption growth is a'^ by the controlled only by the relative risk a'^. just discussed, the coefficient of relative risk aversion sumption growth interest rate q^g. to correct the externality created precautionary savings motive, the intensity of which aversion new 7 and the variance of con- control the decrease in capital between the baseline steady state and the optimal steady state. The intertemporal elasticity of substitution, on the other hand, controls the speed of the transition: the higher p~^, the faster the transition, and the higher the welfare gains. 26 We now F{K,N) = K^N^-"" + function of compute the welfare gains consumption growth computations: a^ rss = Qss ~ ^ ~ = (1 - in general equilibrium for the neoclassical 5)K. at the highest We a = set 0.36, S end of the values we used 3.07%. — 1, 2 — 0.5, 0.75 and our partial equilibrium fixed at rss, the welfare gains in general equilibrium and SWpE SWge and if — and three different the interest rate were the interest rate fss at the state for the optimal allocation. important general lesson from this exercise, as pointed out is 1 For each configuration of these 3. parameters, we report the welfare gains in partial equilibrium (2006), in set the variance We take the initial interest rate at the baseline allocation to be We perform the computations of welfare gains for three different values for the relative risk aversion coefficient 7 An We .09. 0.007. values of the intertemporal elasticity of substitution p~^ new steady = production in Farhi that taking into account the concavity of the production function into account general equilibrium effects and Werning — that is, taking — greatly mitigates the welfare gains. This because of the consumption process —the optimal policy is in general equilibrium, reducing the drift under partial equilibrium —yields lower and lower gains as consumption and capital go down over time and the equilibrium interest rate increases. As a consequence, it is optimal to reduce the drift differential. Eventually, under the optimal allocation, the drift differential goes to and the economy reaches the new steady state with a higher interest rate and a lower capital stock. Even though the partial equilibrium welfare gains can equilibrium welfare gains never go above 0.79%. The 7 = 3. the general = 1 and the highest value of the For those parameter values, the new interest rate substantially higher than the initial interest rate: rss this large difference in interest rates , highest gains are reached for the highest value of the intertemporal elasticity of substitution p~^ relative risk aversion coefficient be as high as 12.33% and therefore = 5.28% whereas rss = is 3.07%. Despite in steady state capital stocks, the general equilibrium welfare gains are moderate at 0.79%. 5 Conclusion This paper studied constrained focused on how efficient allocations in private information economies. We the optimal savings distortions featured in those allocations depend on indi- viduals' preferences. We introduced a recursive class of preferences that allowed a separation of risk aversion from intertemporal substitution, and derived general results on the nature of optimal distortions. We then performed a quantitative investigation consumption allocations. We for a class of geometric random walk showed that savings distortion depend only on 27 risk aversion and . the variance of the shocks to consumption. However, the welfare gains from these distortions depend on both parameters, although we found greater The purpose of the quantitative exercise was to limited in terms of the consumption allocations we undertake a comprehensive exploration it sensitivity to risk aversion. illustrate the role preferences, but it was In Farhi and Werning (2006) considered. of savings distortions and welfare gains for general consumption processes. Appendix Proof of Proposition 3 Part (a). The proof parallels the proof of Proposition 2 closely. First note that since prefer- ences are recursive an incentive compatible allocation satisfies yz\e\a, Va>{z\9')>v,{z\9') (43) so that truth-telling maximizes continuation utility after any history of reports. Let v„{z\ e*) = A'v^iz*, e') for t > r and 2* ^ z" Va{z\ e^) = Va{z\e') iox t > T and 0* ^ F so that condition equation (22) with c met is for all 0^ with t > r with = w{^c{z^),^'<CE[h{z^^\er+iW{z^^\d^+') v,.{z\e^) I So that ity Va'^z^.O'') = Va'{z'^,9'^) for all equation (43) evaluated at z'^ 9'^. 6^ ^ 6'^ I (22), the inequal- a,V,^^e^ CE[h{z^+\er+,)v^{z^+\e^+') I i;<,.(^^r) = solve (j,Vi,r,^i) Using the recursion equation > ^^"""^ A implies CE[A'{s^+')h{z^+\er+i)v,^{z^^\e-^') for all histories Let . and reporting plans a. at+uz\0^] Hence, W{Ac{z^),Cn^'{s^^')h{z^+\er+,)v,4z^'-\e^^') I <l,^^r]) >W{Ac{sn,A'is^-'')CE[h{z-+\er+x)v,{z^^\e^+')\at+,,z\e^])=v,{z\9^). 28 Collecting the inequalities, we have shown that < Vc{z\e^) Thus, a* = Va'{z\e^) in period ^;^.(^^^*) r z\9\a, for all optimal from period r onward and delivers the same continuation utility as pre- is viously. For any plan a define an alternative plan a that starts at a and then switches to a* from period r onward: result is < at{z'',e*) for t r and = 0-4(2^,^*) a;{z^ ,B^) for t > r. The above implies that t'a(2o,^o) That = at{z'' ,9^) is, < = Vf,{zo,eo) a dominates a and va{zo,6o) same yields the < = v^^{zo,9o) utility as dominated by the recommended action a* which v„^{zo,9o)- (44) without the variation, which in turn same also yields the utility as after the variation. This establishes that a* remains incentive compatible. Part (b). Note that 9*) = A'v„{z\9*) v^{z*, 9') = v^{z\ v^{z\ Set A= for i > r and iovt>T and 9^) 2* >- F ^ z^ z* (A')"'^ so that v,{z\9^) = h{z\9r)W{Ac{zn,^'CE[v,,{z^+\9^+') \ <l,^^r]) = h{z^,9r)W{c{z^),Cnv^'{z^^\0^+')\a;^,J\9^])=v,{z\9n. It follows by backward induction that v„{z*, 9*) In particular, 1)^(20,^0) = = v^{z\ 9^) for all s*, t < r. ^^(^05^0)) so that the result follows from incentive compatibility of the original allocation. Proof of Proposition 5 Let V be such that Va{s*) = Va{s^) {;^(s*) = Va{s*) + A' > T and for i for t>T 29 and s* y s'" s* ^ s^ so that condition equation (18) with c is met for all s* with t > r with 5* 7^ s'^ . Now set A so that v,,{s^) so that Va' at {s'^) = W -W = Va' (s'^). (c(5*) + A,CEK.(s^+i) + (c(s*) + A, A' A' - + CE[w„.(s^+^) - Using recursion equation h{a*{s^)) \ h{a*{s^)) \ a*(5"), s"]) a*(s"), (18), the inequality 5^) . equation (20) evaluated implies s"^ - CE[w„.(s"+i) h{a*{s^)) > a*{s^),s^] CE[va{s^+^) - h{a{s^)) \ a{s^),s^], I so that Va'{s^) = W (c(s*) + A, A' > + W - CE[i;„.(s^+i) {c{s') + A, A' h{a*{s^)) + a*{s^), s^\) \ - CE[^;,(s^+l) /i(a(sO) a{s^),s^\) | = ijais^. Hence, we have that Va{s'') a* is < Va'{s'') = Va*{s'') for all O, optimal from period r onward and delivers the same continuation utility as previously. For any plan a define an alternative plan a that switches to a* from period r onward: a(s*) = a(s*) for t < T and a{s*) < l^a(-So) That is is, = > t. Va{So) < a*(s*) for t Va{So) = a dominates a and yields the same dominated by the recommended action a* The result fa* (So) utility as = above implies that Va'{So)- (45) without the variation, which in turn which also yields the same utility as after variation. This establishes that a* remains incentive compatible. Proof of Proposition 6 The equation that defines -(1 From this equation as a function of A' /3)«(Q)(e-''^ - 1) get that at A' = 0: - we A dA _ p = is: (3u{CE{vt^^ u{CE{vt+i 30 - - h,)){e-P^' ht)) - 1). the At the optimum, we must have that at A =0: dA _ where r = defined by r is — g~^ 1 Therefore, the following optimahty condition must hold: 1. {l-/3Hct)=/3ru{aKivt+,-h,)). — Noting that u{c) —u (c), this condition {l-[i)u'{ct) which is = equivalent to: (5ru\€E{vt+i-}H)) the optimality condition in the problem where the agents can borrow and save freely is at the interest rate in the text is r. Transforming these two equivalent conditions into the Euler equation straightforward. Consider the constrained as a function of A efficient allocation. in the following -A This defines —A We can rewrite the equation that defines A way: = -log(l + r(l-exp(-pA))) A > — rA. Now as a concave function of A. Therefore, agents the constrained efficient allocation and allowing strategy but also to borrow and save between history them consider giving the to not only choose a reporting and subsequent periods. The following s'^ variations are then available to the agents: c(s^) c(s*) = { c{s*) c(s*) Since A > — rA, +A for 5* + rA for = t> s^ T and 5* >- 5^ otherwise whatever reporting strategy the agent chooses when these variations are permissible, he will always achieve lower utility than under the were given the variations allowed is for the planner. same reporting strategy if he Since the constrained efficient allocation incentive compatible, he cannot achieve higher utility than under the constrained efficient allocation without history s'^ , any additional saving or borrowing. Generalizing that argument to any this proves the proposition. 31 Proof of Proposition 7 When consumption is a geometric random walk and constant, is ht it is possible to derive lifetime utility in closed form: Lemma 1. Suppose that Assumption 1 holds. Then Vt = Ahct with 1 i-p (3 A i-p .l-/3/ii-^(E[ffi-^])T The key feature that delivers this result is the homogeneity of agents' preferences. For a given h, a proportional shift in consumption today moves consumption in every future period by a proportional factor, thereby shifting lifetime utility in the same multiplicative factor. Hence a discount factor. The constant disutility consumption equivalent units by h on the other hand, acts exactly consumption equivalent units utility in to consumption and to the disutility from effort or work. settings in section 2.1 It is and This directly proportional Vt is reminiscent of the static is 2.2. then easy to guess an verify that the solution proposed the level of utility and like in Proposition 7 both preserves the constrained-optimality condition. satisfies Proof of Proposition 10 Before proving this proposition, Lemma 2. it is useful to establish the following Consider the allocation in Proposition lifetime utility derived from {c\, h} : vl~ Ahc\ 10. with We A= ( can write ^^ '" Lemma. Vt = Vtvl where v\ is the and j iL = (i-A)EA-'f Let us now prove Proposition 10. We only need to check that E, Ph^-p FK{Kt,Nt) holds. Decomposing — r^ Vt+l zP c\ ^ + {\-5) into the product Ctdj. (E*[Ci1) and using condition as PeQt+\ FKiKt,Nt) + {l-5) 1 32 i-7n 1 Lemma 2, we can express this This sical is the standard Euler equation that growth problem (41). is trivially verified by the solution of the neoclas- This concludes the proof of Proposition 33 10. References Diamond, Peter A. and James A. Mirrlees, "A Model of Social Insurance With Variable Retirement," Working papers 210, Massachusetts Institute of Technology, Department of Economics 1977. Epstein, Larry, and Stan. Zin, "Substitution, Risk Aversion and the Temporal Behavior of Consumption and Asset Returns: A Theoretical Framework," Econometrica, 1989, 57, 937-968. Far hi, Emmanuel and Ivan Werning, "Capital Taxation: Quantitative Explorations of the Inverse Euler Equation," 2006. Mimeo. Golosov, Mikhail, Narayana Kocherlakota, and Aleh Tsyvinski, "Optimal and Capital Taxation," Review of Economic Studies, 2003, 70 (3), 569-587. Ligon, Ethan, "Risk Sharing and Information Studies, 1998, 65 (4), 847-64. Rogerson, William P., in Village Economics," Review of Economic "Repeated Moral Hazard," Econometrica, 1985, 53 34 Indirect (1), 69-76. n^i'M^ I Mi* li lllllll ''''llliijlilililli! '^iiiiiiiiiili 41111 .:: illiiiiilill iiill iiill ill ijl'! iMi'Sliiiliiiigjiiiiiliiiiii!!!!:!;;!! li ' ''' I W''