MIT LIBRARIES 3 9080 02618 3548 Willlfl % ttto * \ * / LIBRARIES Digitized by the Internet Archive in 2011 with funding from Boston Library Consortium Member Libraries http://www.archive.org/details/annuitiesindivid00davi2 5 HB31 /j-. i*^t%\ .M415 4-5 2.oo5> Massachusetts Institute of Technology Department of Economics Working Paper Series ANNUITIES AND INDIVIDUAL WELFARE Thomas Davidoff Brown Peter Diamond Jeffrey Working Paper 03-1 May 7, 2003 Revised: March 17,2005 Room E52-251 50 Memorial Drive Cambridge, MA 021 42 This paper can be downloaded without charge from the Social Science Research Network Paper Collection at http://ssrn.com/abstract=405621 MASSACHUSETTS INSTITUTE OF TECHNOLOGY APR 2 6 AW5 LIBRARIES Annuities and Individual Welfare March 2005 17, Abstract: Advancing annuity demand theory, we present sufficient conditions for the optimality of full annuiti- zation under market completeness that are substantially less restrictive than those used by Yaari (1965). We examine demand with market incompleteness, finding that positive annuitization remains optimal widely, but complete an- nuitization does not. How timing of the ity uninsured medical expenses affect A new set of calculations with risk. income streams still shows a preference for demand for illiquid annuities depends critically on the optimal consumption trajectories very different from available annu- considerable annuitization, suggesting that limited annuity purchases are plausibly due to psychological or behavioral biases. (JEL Dll, D91, E21, H55, J14, J26) Since the seminal contribution of Yaari (1965) on the theory of a life-cycle consumer with an unknown date of death, annuities have played a central role in economic theory. His widely cited result is that certain consumers should fully annuitize all of their savings. However, these consumers were assumed to satisfy several very restrictive assumptions: they were von Neumann-Morgenstern expected utility maximizers with intertemporally separable utility, they faced no uncertainty other than time of death, they had no bequest motive, and the annuities available actuarially fair. While the subsequent literature these assumptions, the "industry standard" is for purchase were on annuities has occasionally relaxed one or two of to maintain most of these conditions. In particular, the literature has universally retained expected utility and additive separability, the latter dubbed "not a very happy assumption" by Yaari. While Yaari (1965) and Bernheim (1987a,1987b) provide intuitive explanations of why the Yaari result generality of this result has not been formally The first contribution of this paper those imposed by Yaari under which is may shown not depend on these strict assumptions, the in the literature. to present sufficient conditions substantially weaker than full annuitization is optimal. The heart of the argument can be seen by comparing a one- year bank certificate of deposit (CD), paying an interest rate r to a security that pays a higher interest rate at the end of the year conditional on living, but pays nothing if you die before year-end. second, annuitized, alternative assets, when is If you attach no value to wealth after death, then the a dominant asset. This simple comparison of otherwise matching articulated in a setting that confirms its relevance, dominance comparison of matching assets is lies behind the Yaari result. The not sensitive to their financial details, but does rely 1 on the identical and non-annuitized liquidity in the annuitized assets. demand This paper explores the implications of this comparison for asset in different settings, including both Arrow-Debreu complete markets and incomplete market settings. Debreu complete market In the Arrow- be optimal are that setting, sufficient conditions for full annuitization to consumers have no bequest motive and that annuities pay a rate of return to surviving investors, net of administrative costs, that is greater than the return on conventional assets of matching financial Thus, when markets are complete, risk. full annuitization is optimal without assuming exponential discounting, the expected utility axioms, intertemporal separability, or actuarially fair annuities. We also relate the size of the welfare gain to the trajectory of optimal consumption. A second contribution is to examine annuity some desired consumption paths are not annuity market, full annuitization demand available may no when in all some incomplete market wealth is settings. If annuitized in an incomplete longer be optimal. For example, an individual desires if a steeply downward sloping consumption path, but only constant real annuities are available, then annuitization full is no longer optimal. Thus, we explore conditions partial annuitization. We relative liquidity of annuities ance for medical expenditure shocks. The An optimum to include also consider partial annuitization with a bequest motive. Another example involves the risk. for the uninsurable risk early in life may effect and bonds in the absence of insur- on annuity demand depends on the timing of the reduce the value of annuities borrow against future payments of the fixed annuity stream but In contrast, loss of insurability of a shock occurring later in life if it is not possible to sell or it is possible to do so with bonds. may increase annuity purchases as a substitute for medical insurance that has an inherent annuity character. Thus, an annuity can be a better substitute than a bond Most practical questions for long-term care insurance. about annuitization (e.g., the appropriate role of annuities in public pension systems) are concerned with partial annuitization. The general theory to answer questions about the optimal fraction of annuitized wealth, literature has developed. a new Our third contribution "stress test" of annuity valuation. that differ substantially from what is We is itself is insufficient and thus a large simulation to extend the simulation literature by creating do so by generating optimal consumption trajectories offered by a fixed real annuity contract, and showing that even under these highly unfavorable conditions, the majority of wealth is still optimally annuitized. To generate the unfavorable match between optimal consumption and the annuity trajectory, we allow a person's utility to depend on how present consumption compares to a standard of living to which the individual has become accustomed, which model this "internal habit" as in These results Diamond and is itself We a function of past consumption. Mirrlees (2000). 1 imply that annuities are quite valuable to maximizing consumers, even utility under conditions that result in a very unfavorable mismatch between available annuity income streams and one's desired consumption path. Thus, while incomplete markets, when combined with preferences for consumption paths that deviate substantially from those offered by current annuity products, can certainly explain the lack of the full annuitization, it is difficult to explain near universal lack of any annuitization outside of Social Security and defined benefit pensions plans, at least at the higher one's portfolio and SSI insurance, which severe is is not relevant. This finding mismatch between life is a small part of strongly reminiscent of the literature on life insurance has documented a life insurance holdings of most households and their underlying financial Bernheim, Forni, Gokhale and Kotlikoff (2003); Auerbach and Kotlikoff Auerbach and Kotlikoff (1987), is a closely related product. 2 The literature on vulnerabilities (see e.g. ical or end of the wealth distribution where Social Security (1991)). These papers, taken together, are suggestive of psycholog- behavioral considerations at play in the market for life-contingent products that have not yet been incorporated into standard economic models. The We focus of the paper is on the properties of annuity demand in different market settings. do not address the more complex equilibrium question of what determines the set of annuity products in the market. In light of the value of annuities to consumers in standard models, think examination of equilibrium would have to include the supply response to that is not consistent with standard utility maximization. We we demand behavior do not develop such a behavioral theory of annuity demand, but rather clarify the mismatch between observed demand behavior and the value of annuitization in a standard utility maximization setting. The paper proceeds under which 1 DifTerent full as follows: annuitization is In section we provide a general set of sufficient conditions optimal under complete markets. models of intertemporal dependence (1990), Constantinides (1990), I, in utility arc discussed in, for Section II discusses of why example, Dusenberry (1949), Abel Deaton (1991), Campbell and Cochrane (1999), Campbell (2002) and Gomes and Michaelides (2003). "As discussed by Yaari (1965) and Bernheim (1991), the purchase of a pure the selling of an annuity. life insurance policy can be viewed as annuitization full may no longer be optimal with incomplete markets, paying particular attention Section III briefly discusses a bequest motive. to the role of illiquidity of annuities. IV we In Section report simulation results reflecting the quantitative importance of market incompleteness with habit formation, showing that even when the liquidity constraints on annuities are binding, individuals still concludes. Complete Markets I. Much V prefer a high level of annuitization. Section of the focus of the annuities literature has been an attempt to reconcile Yaari's (1965) "full annuitization" result with the empirical fact that few people voluntarily annuitize any of their private savings. 3 This issue model consumer behavior the shift in the US from of theoretical interest because is in the presence of uncertainty. it bears upon the issue of It is also how of policy interest because of defined benefit plans, which typically pay out as an annuity, to defined contribution plans that rarely offer retirees directly the opportunity to annuitize. Annuitization also important in the debate of the assumptions in the original Yaari formulation. model, and then show formally the generalization to The Optimality of Full Annuitization A. Analysis of intertemporal choice pletely commit all and all at once, that is, is all in a many full We annuitization if periods and states of nature, as optimal, relaxing with many No states. Aggregate Uncertainty resource allocation decisions are without additional, later trades. if, is begin with a simple two period Two Period Model greatly simplified to a fixed plan of expenditures time and is about publicly provided defined contribution plans. This section derives a general set of conditions under which many to Consumers made com- be willing to will at the start of time, they are able to trade goods across standard in the complete market Arrow-Debreu model. is Yaari considered annuitization in a continuous time setting where consumers are uncertain only about the date of death. Some results, discrete periods: the present, period 3 This assertion is however, can be seen more simply by dividing time into two 1, when the consumer consistent with the large market for what are is definitely alive and period example Brown and Warshawsky (2001). when called variable annuities since these insurance products do not include a commitment to annuitize accumulations, nor does there appear to be annuitization. See for 2, much voluntary the consumer By is wilting with probability alive U = we U(ci,C2), - 1 allow for a very general formulation of utility in a two-period setting with the assumptions that there uncertain. Lifetime utility that the consumer is is 4 q. is defined over no bequest motive and that only survival to period 2 first alive in period 2, C2- period consumption, We c\ , and consumption satisfy the axioms may depend on for U using a dual approach: We to be an expected value. the consumer second An is decision and the welfare evaluation of annuities can be determined minimizing expenditures subject to attaining at least a given measure expenditures securities available. is The a first is alive or not, in bond that returns exchange an annuity that returns actuarially fair annuity in units of first period consumption. Ra would for in period 2 yield Rb if we denote by there is A Ra = if the consumer i?s/(l — g). and expenditures is min cx,A,B We in Otherwise with B> Rb < Ra < Rb/(1 — violated, annuities is <?) The now and any However, future period, weak assumption that Ra > Rb- 5 E = B savings in the form of bonds, and is retired), ci +A+ then B. C2 = RaA + RbB, Thus, the expenditure 0, i.e., (1) that the individual not be permitted to die purchasing annuities and selling bonds in equal numbers would two period model with a single consumer good That this level. ci+A + BsX.U(cx,R A A + RB B)>U. Ra > Rb, a complete market setting, this 5 the 1. as: further impose the constraint that in debt. A we make consumption are simply minimization problem can be written whether and nothing otherwise. alive bonds may drive returns below in period 2 (e.g., the individual for lifetime 2, Adverse selection and higher transac- savings in the form of annuities and by no other income that there are two units of consumption in period because any consumer will have a positive probability of dying between thereby relieving borrowers' obligation, Assume level of each unit of the consumption good in period tion costs for paying annuities than for paying If the consumption. Additionally, this formulation does not require that preferences The optimal consumption utility. in the event drop the requirement of intertemporal separability, allowing for the possibility that the utility from second-period consumption level of first period is in each dated event precludes trade after the first period, but irrelevant. is supported empirically by Mitchell would be dominated by bonds. et al (1999). If the first inequality were 2 cost nothing and yield positive consumption when alive in period 2, but leave a debt if dead, leaving lenders with expected financial losses in total. This setup leads immediately to the optimality of annuitization. full able to reduce expenditures, while holding the consumption vector fixed, bond and purchasing one unit of the annuity (noting that expenditure minimization problem is is to set B = 0, i.e., R& > If by B > selling 0, then one Ra/Rb of the Rb)- Thus, the solution to to annuitize one's wealth fully. The is this intuition that allowing individuals to substitute annuities for conventional assets yields an arbitrage-like gain when when the individual places no value on wealth not alive. independent of assumptions about preferences beyond the lack of annuities be actuarially and for fair. Indeed, all that is required for is Such a gain enhances welfare utility from a bequest. Nor must consumers to have no bequest motive the payouts from the annuity to exceed that of conventional assets for the survivor. Equation (1) also indicates an approach to evaluating the gain from an increased opportunity to annuitize. Consider the minimization under the further constraint of an of annuities, A < A We know . upper bound on purchases that utility-maximizing consumers will take advantage of an arbitrage-like opportunity to annuitize as long as bond holdings are positive and can therefore be used to finance the purchase. With no annuities available, bond holdings will be positive period consumption is positive, as is if second- ensured by the plausible condition that zero consumption is extremely bad: ASSUMPTION 1: lim Ct -+o dU/dct — oo t : — 1, Allowing consumers previously unable to annuitize any wealth to place a small amount of their savings into annuities (increasing A from zero) leaves second period consumption unchanged the cost of the marginal second-period consumption consumption in both periods). Thus a small increase a given level of utility by available annuities for If the upper bound 1 — (Ra)/{Rb) < 0. This is unchanged, so too, is in A is made in the optimal level of from zero reduces the cost of achieving the welfare gain from increasing the limit on an optimizing consumer with positive bond holdings. 6 constraint on available annuities is large enough that bond holdings are then the price of marginal second period consumption (up to A) This point is (since falls zero, from 1/(Rb) to \/{Ra). With the context of time-separable preferences by Bernheim (1987b): a in the cost of marginal second-period consumption, its fall welfare gain from unlimited annuity availability is while financing the same consumption bundle as is made up when compensated of there level will rise. two parts. One part is is Thus the the savings no annuitization, and the second the savings from adapting the consumption bundle to the change in prices. We can measure the welfare gain in going from no annuities to potentially unlimited annuities from the expenditure function defined over the price vector (l,p 2 ) and the utility level U. Integrating the derivative of the expenditure function evaluated at the two prices E\ A=0 where c2 (p 2 ) is - E\ A=00 = E(l, 1/R B U) , £7(1, 1/Ra and 1/Rb'- 1/Ra, U) =- rl/R B c 2 (p 2 )dp 2 compensated demand arising from minimization of expenditures equal to subject to the utility constraint without a distinction between asset types. more (have larger second-period consumption) B. benefit more from the The Optimality of Full Annuitization with Many its simplicity, real Periods and many consumers face a more complicated decision periods of potential consumption and each period may have c\ + c2p2 Consumers who save ability to annuitize completely. While a two-period model with no uncertainty other than length of from (2) , Jl/R A life Many States has a clarity that derives setting. In particular, they face several possible states of nature. For example, a 65 year-old consumer has some probability of surviving to be a healthy and active 80 year-old, some chance of finding herself sick and in a nursing of not being alive at we show that at age 80. Moreover, returns on some at age 80, and some chance assets are stochastic. In this section, the optimality of complete annuitization survives subdivision of the aggregated future defined by c 2 into A all home many future periods and states, as long as markets are complete. simple subdivision would be to add a third period, while continuing with the assumption of setting, we have bonds and annuities Ra 2 and period 3 with rates Rb3 and no other uncertainty. In keeping with the complete market that pay out separately in period 2 with rates Rb 2 and , Ra3- 7 If our That defining is, bonds and annuities purchased with the appropriate subscript: E = a + A 2 + A 3 + B2 + B3 (3) C2 = RB2B2 + RxiM (4) c3 = RB3B3 + RA3 A 3 (5) our assumption that the return on annuities exceeds that of bonds holds period by period, then full optimization result extends distinguishes between states standard Arrow security B2 in period 1 is Note that the standard trivially. when an individual is alive We an "Arrow annuity." This representative of a standard bond and when he or she have set up what we and B3) by combining matched pairs of events that occurred. definition of differ in not is call an Arrow security alive. can separate the Arrow bond into two separate Arrow is, a "Arrow bonds" (here whether the consumer's death has what becomes a dominated is That securities, one asset once and the consumer can choose to purchase only one of them. In a setting with additional sources of uncertainty, the combination of a matched pair of events to depict a non-annuitized asset particular In some consumer is settings there treat c\ as a scalar many may logical step, (t when the death of the not be such a decomposition of a bond because the recognition of and interpret future periods straightforward independent of other events and unimportant in determining equilibrium. important differences between different events To take the next is < strongly related to the survival of the individual. 8 is and assuming we can decompose Arrow bonds, we continue to c2 , B2 and A2 T), within arbitrarily as vectors with entries corresponding to arbitrarily many states of nature {u> < Q). Rj\% {Rb2) is then a matrix with columns corresponding to annuities (bonds) and rows corresponding to payouts by period and state of nature. Thus, the assumption of no aggregate uncertainty can be dropped. Multiple states of nature might refer to uncertainty about aggregate issues such as output, or individual specific issues beyond mortality such as health. the consumer is state of nature 7 sufficiently "small" where the consumer To extend the analysis, we assume that (and with death uncorrected with other events) that for each is alive, there exists a state where the consumer In keeping with the complete market setting, there is no arrival of is dead and asymmetric information about future life expectancy. 8 If the death of a consumer only occurs with other large changes, then there bond that in some differs from an Arrow annuity only future period if and only if in the death of a single consumer, an influenza epidemic occurs. is for no way to construct an Arrow example, if an individual will die the equilibrium relative prices are otherwise identical. bonds that represent the combination of two Arrow construct such bonds is Completeness of markets securities. Note, still has Arrow however, that the ability to not necessary for the result that a consumer without a bequest motive does not purchase consumption when not alive in the complete market setting. Annuities paying in only one dated event are contrary to conventional life annuities that pay out in every year until death. However, with complete markets, separate annuities with payouts in each year can be combined to create such conventional annuities. It is clear that the analysis of the two-period model extends to this setting, provided we maintain the standard Arrow-Debreu market structure and assumptions that do not allow an individual to die in debt since the consumer can purchase a combination of annuities with a structure of benefits across time and states as desired. In addition to the description of the optimum, the formula for the gain from allowing more annuitization holds for state-by-state increases in the level of allowed level of annuitization. Moreover, by choosing any particular price path from the prices inherent in bonds to the prices inherent in annuities, we can measure the gain in going from no annuitization to full annuitization. This parallels the evaluation of the price changes brought about investment (see Diamond and McFadden matter through optimal consumption; by a lumpy (1974)). Hence, with complete markets, preferences only this fact may clarify, for example, the unimportance of additive separability to the result of complete annuitization. Stating the result more formally, the THEOREM 1: // there is bequest motive and the payouts of some if there full annuitization result is a corollary of the following: no future trade once portfolio decisions have been made, is if there is no a set of annuities with payouts per unit of investment that dominate subset of bonds that are held, then a welfare gain is available by selling the subset of bonds and replacing the bonds with the annuities, so long as this transfer does not lead to negative wealth in any state. COROLLARY 1: motive annuitizes In a complete market Arrow-Debreu equilibrium, a consumer without a bequest all savings. Thus, with complete markets, the result of full annuitization extends to many periods, the pres- ence of aggregate uncertainty, actuarially unfair but positive annuity premiums, and intertemporally dependent utility that need not satisfy the expected so long as markets are complete. Thus, is if utility the puzzle of why to be solved within a rational, life-cycle framework, lie so few individuals voluntarily annuitize we have shown that the answer does not (beyond the issue of a bequest motive). in the specification of the utility function per se briefly consider the role of annuitization axioms. This generalization of Yaari holds with a bequest motive below. We However, the results do demonstrate the importance of market completeness, an issue that we turn to next. II. With complete markets, a higher Incomplete Markets yield of an Arrow annuity over the matching Arrow bond, dated event by dated event, leads directly to the result that a consumer without a bequest motive fully annuitizes. But markets are not complete. There are two forms of incompleteness that we consider. The that the set of annuities first is that exist. 9 The second is real world annuity highly limited, relative to the set of non- annuitized securities the incompleteness of the securities market. A. Most is Incomplete Annuity Markets markets require that a consumer purchase a particular time path of payouts, thereby combining in a single security a particular "compound" combination of Arrow annuities. Privately purchased immediate life annuities are usually fixed in nominal terms, or offer a prede- termined nominal slope such as a 5 percent increase per year. Variable annuities link the payout to the performance of a particular underlying portfolio of assets that way. CREF annuities are also participating, which and combine Arrow means that the payout actual mortality experience for the class of investors. To explore we a constant real annuity restrict some our analysis to a single kind of annuity of our results in a tinguishing whether bonds all more general vocabulary. - We issues raised examine the demand trade must occur at a single time or whether it is for securities in also varies by such - with the restrictions, although we state such an annuity, dis- possible to also purchase later. Trade Occurs All at Once Explaining necessarily why make use this of of this paper. Rather, is the case would take us into the industrial organization of insurance supply, which would consumer understanding and perceptions of insurance. These' issues are well beyond the scope we analyze rational annuity demand 10 in different market settings that are taken as given. For the case of a conventional annuity, we must revise the superior return condition for Arrow annuities that Rauj less > An RBt^tu:. appropriate formulation for a compound security is that it cost than purchasing the same consumption vector using bonds. Define by £ a row vector of ones with length equal to the number of states of nature occurring in the annuity and so distinguished by bonds. Let the bonds continue to be represented by a vector with elements corresponding set of columns of the matrix of returns to the the scalar A Rb and let Ra be a vector of annuity payouts multiplying Then the to define state-by-state payouts. cost of the bonds exceeds the cost of the annuity under the assumption: ASSUMPTION RB B =» A< 2: For any annuitized asset A and any collection of conventional assets B, RaA = IB. For example, if there is an annuity that costs one unit of first period consumption per unit and pays Ra2 per unit of annuity in the second period and Ra3 per unit of annuity in the third period, then we would have 1 < Ra2/Rb2 + Ra3/Rb3- 10 By any consumption vector that may be purchased financed through annuities than linearity of expenditures, this implies that strictly when purchased by a through annuities set of is less bonds with matching expensive when payoffs. Consider a three-period model, with complete bonds and a single available annuity and no opportunity for trade after the initial contracting. min cx : ,A,B s.t. : The minimization problem U(c 1 ,RB 2B2 0, (6) + Ra2AR B3 B3 + RA3 A)>U is (8) feasible. Thus we can conclude that some annuitization The logic right then, hand is is if side represents the required investments in two 11 as long as this optimal and that the optimum the consumption pattern with com- worth changing by purchasing a bond. That period to replicate the annuity payout. we have an extends to a setting with more dates and However we would not get complete annuitization plete annuitization The alive, dominance of the annuity over the matching combination of bonds has zero bonds in at least one dated event. states. (7) B3 > Given our return assumption and positive consumption whenever trade now a + B2 + B3 + A B2 > arbitrage-like is is, purchasing a bond would be Arrow bonds that cost one unit each in the first R R worthwhile raises utility if it by more than the decline from decreased first period consumption. Thus, denoting partial derivatives of the utility function with subscripts, there will be positive bond holdings if we satisfy either of the conditions: U 1 (c 1 ,RA2 A,R A3 A) < RB2 U2 ( Cl ,R A2 A,R A3 A) (9) or Ui( Cl ,R A2 A, By A3 A) < R B3 U3 ( Cl ,R A2 A, A3 A). (10) our return assumption, we can not satisfy both of these conditions at the same time, but we might satisfy one of them. Additional Trading Opportunities The previous analysis stayed with the setting of a single time to trade. If there are additional may mean trading opportunities, the incompleteness of annuity markets are taken. Staying within the setting of perfectly predicted future prices for the same commodity purchased at different dates are bond purchase may increase the degree consistent, all that such opportunities and assuming that prices we can see that repeated of annuitization. If desired consumption occurs later than with consuming all of the annuitized benefit, then the ability to save by purchasing bonds, rather than consuming all of the annuity payment, means that annuitization is made more attractive. Returning to the three-period model with only mortality uncertainty, we can write this by denoting saving at the end of the second period by between the second and third periods The minimization is Z (Z > 0). We assume that the return on savings Z is consistent with the other bond returns (Rz = now: +A (11) {RBz/Rb2}Z) > U. (12) min ci d,A,B,Z s.t. The : U( Ci ,Rb2B2 + R A 2A - restriction of not dying in debt payments) if A Rbz/Rb2)- is Z, R B3 B3 + R A3 A + + B2 + B3 the non-negativity of wealth (including the value of future equals zero: RB2 B 2 + {R B2 /RB3 )R B3 B 3 > R B3 B 3 + (R B3 /RB2 )Z > 12 (13) 0. (14) Dissaving after annuitization full (if possible) would not be attractive if: RB2 U2 (cuRa2A,R A3 A) < R B3 U3 (c ,Ra2A,R A3A). (15) 1 Under Assumption To see this, note that 2, (15) is now sufficient for the result of full annuitization of initial savings. Assumption 2 implies that R B3 < Ra2^z + R-A3- dominated by the annuity with the second period return fully saved. Thus, holdings of B3 are Positive holdings of B2 are ruled out by Assumption 2 and condition (15) since they imply: R B2 U2 < RA2 U2 + which is is inconsistent with the part of the optimum) . FOC {R A 3/Rb3)Rb2U2 < RA2U2 for positive holdings of commonly used model In the full initial B. A illiquidity of an annuity consumption limits its attraction. that is B2 (and some annuitization is thus that 5(1 + r) > 1. If the than an individual wants, later We interest rate, a sufficient consider illiquidity below. Incomplete Securities and Annuity Markets: The Role of Liquidity widely recognized basis for incomplete annuitization in the future and and a constant annuitization in a constant real annuity available annuity (a constant real benefit) provides then the assumed A (16) , of intertemporally additive preferences with identical period utility functions, a constant discount rate condition for both + RazU3 is that there may be an which cannot be insured. This might be an individual need, like expenditure need a medical expense not insurable, or an aggregate event such as unexpected inflation, which lowers the real value of nominal annuity payments in the absence of real annuities. With incomplete markets, the arbitrage-like dominance argument used above will no longer hold annuities are not. 11 We assume We more than the life expectancy which would naturally reduce the liquidity of liquidity of non-traded bonds such show, however, that the presence of uninsured risks as certificates of deposit. may add optimal fraction of savings annuitized, depending on the nature of the of illiquidity by examining two bonds are liquid while total illiquidity of annuities without exploring the possible arrival of asymmetric information about annuities far if cases: uninsured medical expenditures, to or subtract from the risk. and the We illustrate the role arrival of asymmetric information combined with inferior annuity returns. 11 More generally, it is well face stochastic cash needs known that Huang lifecycle consumers may be unwilling to invest (2003). 13 in illiquid assets when they Annuities and Medical Expenditures For concreteness, length of To life. let this us start with the two period model above, where the only uncertainty model separately for each period. us add a risk of a necessary medical expense which let Assume has no effect on illness If it is possible to fully insure optimal plan is full we consider that this expenditure enters into the budget constraint as Assume a required expenditure, but does not enter into the utility function. occurrence of is life further that the expectancy. future medical expenses on an actuarially fair basis then the medical insurance and full Thus removing the annuitization. ability to insure medical expenses, while continuing to assume that annuity benefits can be purchased separately period-by-period, can only raise the in period if 1, but not if it the risk occurs early in demand occurs in period life, 2. for bonds and may do so That calls for shifting the medical risk occurs may be the illiquidity of annuities is, but not toward the end of relevant For example, contrast the cost of a life. hospitalization early in retirement with the need for a nursing former if home toward the end of life. The expenses to earlier and so increases the value of an asset that permits such a change. Since medical expenses only occur for the living, annuities are a better substitute for nonexistent insurance for medical expenses later in To the two-period problem considered of size, If M, there is with probability in (1), than are bonds. life we add the m and insurance at cost 7, paying a benefit of no additional trading medical expense risk of a first-period after the initial purchases, the problem f3 per dollar of insurance. is: ci+A + B + I min (17) ci,A,B,I s.t. (l-m)U(c 1 ,R A A + RB B) + mU{c 1 - M + /3I,RA A + RB B) > U. (18) In the case of no trading after the initial date, annuities continue to dominate bonds. actuarially fair, there will be complete medical insurance (and so insurance is same there were no risk and expenditures were reduced by as if mM) With . insurance, the presence of both risk and insurance generally so the level of annuitization, but savings are annuitized since bonds are To bring out the all role of liquidity, less A, and B The analysis still the are the favorable medical affects the level of illiquid savings assume that bonds can be sold early redemption penalty, but annuities can not be sold. c\, If and dominated. in the first period with an would be similar with liquid annuities that had a larger penalty for early redemption or the ability to reduce spending and add 14 a to bond holdings (at a lower interest rate) after a realization of no health risk. Then the problem becomes: min a,A,B,l,z {1-m) Ufa, R A A + RB B) + mU{c s.t. Z where is 1 d+A + B + I -M + pi + a B Z,RA A + RB (B-Z)) the value of bonds withdrawn early and a B (as < 1) is (19) > 17.(20) the fraction of value received net of the early withdrawal penalty. Since annuities still dominate any bonds that would never be cashed holdings would not exceed the amount cashed in early in, the level of bond and we can rewrite the problem as a+A + B + I min (21) v ' ci,A,B,I s.t. In this case, there it is -m) Ufa, RA A + RB B)+mU(ci-M + (31+ possible to generate preferences that have an B B,R A A) > U. (22) optimum with some bonds provided a small difference between annuity and bond returns, a small early withdrawal penalty for is bonds and We {I sufficiently actuarially unfair turn now medical insurance pricing. With medical insurance to a medical risk that occurs only in the second period. purchased at the start of period one, expected R B B) + mU(ci,RA A + R B B — M + (31). utility can be written as (1 — m) Ufa,RA A + Thus, medical risk in the second period does not change the dominance of annuities over bonds whatever the pricing of medical insurance. In the absence of the arrival of information, there are two equivalent ways of organizing medical insurance. purchase medical insurance at the start of period one (as with long-term care insurance). is One The is other to purchase an annuity with a plan to purchase medical insurance at the start of period two, alive. With both first-period into the if formulations, a worsening of the pricing of medical insurance will generally alter consumption and so total savings. In the second formulation, demand to for annuities. this translates directly In addition, there would generally be a change in the medical insurance purchased in the second period. In the first amount of formulation, unlike the second, a change in the level of medical insurance would also change the level of annuity purchase even if preferences were such that first-period consumption did not change. fair For example, going from medical insurance to no medical insurance would increase the spending on annuities by the amount previously spent on medical insurance if full preferences were such that first-period consumption 15 did not change. That for is, removing insurance that is effectively annuitized can increase the demand a standard annuity. Thus, we can conclude that the timing of the risk of medical expenses is key to understanding the interaction between the availability of medical insurance and the purchase of annuities. the absence of strong assumptions it is In thus impossible to sign the effect of liquidity needs on annuity demand. In one parameterization, Turra and Mitchell (2004) find that the optimal fraction of wealth annuitized remains large even possible when and are associated with truncated these uninsured expenditures tend to reduce We If However, these simulations also show that lifetimes. demand for annuities below 100 percent of savings. have assumed an absence of a relationship between medical expenses and a medical expense in period the value of liquid bonds. about out-of-pocket (uninsured) medical expenditures are life Since 1 implies a lower survival probability, then that The next expectancy. would strengthen subsection briefly considers a role of the arrival of information expectancy 12 we examine annuity demand do not explore the in different settings, rather illiquidity of annuities (relative to of annuities were an explanation for lack of pointed out that illiquidity is demand than a model of equilibrium, we bonds) that is present. for illiquid annuities, of the notation above, bonds would have a return as, with annuities characterized by might plausibly have Rb < Ra if illiquidity Bernheim (1987b) has if at any time. In terms held to maturity, Rg, and a return Ra and a a- Even is withdrawn with an early withdrawal option, we and as > a a- This could be the outcome since early withdrawal from an annuity has implications bond (where withdrawal may Even not a complete explanation for the near absence of annuity markets. Bernheim proposes the creation of annuities that are subject to cancellation early, life for the cost of providing the annuity, while this is less so of a just reflect available alternative investments). C. Inferior Returns to Annuities Another route to limited annuitization is if annuity pricing and the arrival of asymmetric infor- mation imply an advantage to delayed annuitization. For example, Milevsky and Young (2002) 12 If the medical condition is observable to the provider, it may be that bundling insurance for the cash need with the annuity could improve pricing for both forms of insurance by eliminating adverse selection that would exist for either product individually, as has been proposed by Warshawsky, Spillman and Murtaugh (forthcoming). 16 consider a cost to annuitization associated with illiquidity that renders the return on annuities essentially inferior to the return to wait to annuitize wealth Similarly, lier, if age 65, and yet it is may returns on investment in the future annuities purchased later in deferral of annuitization at, say, if on some bonds. In particular, they show that life are priced optimal. 13 may be If, it may be optimal exceed present returns. more favorably than those purchased ear- however, there are utility gains to annuitizing optimal to delay annuitization, then this implies that there are even larger utility gains to annuitizing later in life. Empirically, however, we do not observe households choosing to annuitize at later ages, suggesting that such an explanation cannot fully explain the demand near absence of Of course, assets, annuity if for private annuity returns, net of administrative costs, are inferior to those of conventional demand can go to zero. Mitchell et al (1999) show, however, that available pricing on annuities does not seem to be Dushi and Webb market annuities. sufficient to (2004), which builds render annuitization unattractive. Recent work by upon previous work by Mitchell et al (1999) and Brown and Poterba (2001) shows that a combination of low annuity returns, within couple-risk sharing that substitutes for a formal annuity market, and very high levels of pre-existing annuities can render additionally fixed annuities unattractive at any age. However, even these results suggest that we should observe frequent annuitization by surviving spouses, which we do not. III. Bequests Throughout the paper we have maintained the assumption that there was no bequest motive. While a bequest motive reduces the demand for annuities, it does not eliminate it in general. To see this, consider a model with two periods and uncertain survival to the second period as the sole Ignoring the role of inter vivos second. We gifts, there can be a bequest at the end of the model the bequest motive as an additive term depending on the two that might happen at the end of periods one and two. In this case, of own consumption and first the two possible bequest levels. Dennis (2004) also finds a gain to deferred annuitization 17 for With death some at the price patterns. period or of the levels of we can express risk. bequests utility in terms end of period two, the bequest is received in period min 3, : involving additional interest. Using the dual formulation, we +A+B ci have: (23) c\,A,B,C2 s.t. If : the utility of bequest is U(c 1 ,c2 ) + V(R B B,R B the expectation of a concave value of the bequest, start of period three (whether given then or earlier), V {R B B, Rb (RaA + R B B - Q2)) = where q is + R B B-c 2 ))>U. (R A A qv (R B R B B) we + (24) v, evaluated at the have: (1 - {RaA + RB B - q)v {R B the probability that the individual dies before period 2. c 2 )) , (25) For there to be no annuitization, the value of an annuity must be less than the value of a bond, evaluated at zero annuities: (1 With - q)RB RAv' {Rb {RbB c2 > enough to If 0, this is < R b Rb c 2 )) {qv' {RbRbB) + violated for an actuarially fair annuity (1 (1 - q)v' (RB {RB B - — q)RA = Rb, and c 2 ))) (26) for annuities close fair. the annuity v' This implies is actuarially {R B {RaA RaA = period consumption. c2 , then fair, + RB B - c2 )) = qv' {R B R B B) + a point implicit in Yaari (1965). Thus with (1 - q)v' That {R B {R B B - is, approach to bequests, the case this c 2 )) (27) annuitization equals second for significant annuitization survives the presence of a bequest motive. 14 IV. The theory shows that while by some annuity, an many in 1 in settings. The use full annuitization unrealistic assumption, The theory Simulations not guaranteed unless every bond is also clear that partial annuitization it is itself is insufficient for of a "guarantee" with annuities is common. This a lower monthly annuity for a given purchase price. We is dominated is optimal answering practical policy questions that are often involves a minimum number of payments, resulting note that this generates a random bequest compared with purchasing the same lower annuity without the guarantee and bequeathing (or giving before death) the reduced purchase price. In the case of issues, the fair annuities, demand depends on pricing the guarantee is a pure gamble and implausibly optimal. With selection and the guarantee may be part of addressing 18 selection issues. what fraction of savings often centered on is optimally annuitized in different market settings and with different preferences. Thus, a large simulation literature has arisen to address review this literature, and then extend results it by conducting a this. We briefly "stress test" of the annuity valuation by considering cases that are intentionally designed to create a more extreme mismatch between desired consumption and the annuity income stream than we would expect to see practice. By showing to be extreme cases, that the optimal level of annuitization remains high even in we conclude in what we consider that the virtual absence of voluntary annuitization cannot be easily explained the standard set of reasons that come from the life-cycle framework. Friedman and Warshawsky (1990) and Mitchell, Poterba, Warshawsky and Brown (1999) are examples of the simulation literature that calculate assumptions. These papers, like preferences can be represented many by a utility gains from annuities under alternative an individual a retired individual whose others, consider constant relative risk aversion, utility function that exhibits exponential discounting, and intertemporal separability. They accept a substantial reduction in wealth in exchange for access to actuarially Numerous subsequent papers have explored the fair (Brown and Poterba and Mitchell (2004), Sinclair Webb are constrained in (2001)), and higher some way (i.e., levels of pre-existing annuities annuity markets are incomplete), the most fixed in real terms. is findings, these papers find that there are substantial gains to is due to mortality het- (2004)). In nearly every case, the annuity products considered in these papers being that the annuity's payment stream nuitization and Young (2002)), (2003)), uninsured medical expenditures (Turra (2004)), actuarially unfair prices Palmon and Spivak erogeneity (Brown (2003), (Dushi and and Smetters annuity markets. 15 gains from annuitization under a wider range of assumptions, including: uncertainty about future asset returns (Milevsky risk pooling within couples consumers would find that these not always optimal. can be interpreted: when full Our some theoretical results provide a annuitization is common assumption Consistent with our theoretical annuitization, but that full an- framework in which such results sub-optimal, the settings were such that incomplete markets led to a mismatch between desired consumption trajectories and available annuity income paths. 15 Even in these cases, Another strand however, the optimal level of annuitization was generally high. of the literature examines the "probability of a shortfall" when a consumer rather than using formal annuity markets. Milevsky (1998) 19 is a good example of this approach. tries to self-insure A A Relaxing Additive Separability: A. "Stress Test" of key practical message from our theoretical results that the welfare gains from annuitization is depend on preferences mainly through the consumption Annuity Valuation trajectory. Thus, if one is seeking to recon- the theory with the empirical smallness of voluntary annuity markets, one ought to be looking cile for situations in which there is a severe mismatch between the desired consumption trajectory and the income path provided by a limited set of annuities in an incomplete markets setting. In this section, we extend the simulation literature by modeling preferences that lead to a severe mismatch with the goal of seeing whether such mismatches can plausibly explain the small market. We do this by exploring a are not intertemporally additive class of models that have the and have the feature that realistic size of the property that preferences different parameterizations, meant to the heterogeneity of household financial positions at retirement, lead to very different time reflect shapes of optimal consumption. We consider a 65 year-old male with survival probabilities taken from the U.S. Social Security Administration for the year 1999, modified (to ease computation) so that death occurs for sure by age 100. His utility function is: 100 r tf=£(l + ( 4 1 ( Ci / Si ) -7 /(i-7) (28) t=65 When the parameter St is constant, this is the frequently modeled case of Following this literature, we set the real interest rate and discount rate the utility gains from annuitization. We set 7 = 2 and find the (S) CRRA preferences. equal to .03 and calculate consumption vector that solves the expenditure minimization problem numerically using standard optimization techniques. 16 We begin by simply verifying that our model matches the results of the previous literature in the case in which setting, fixed at a value of one, corresponding to the which we denote as "Case annuitize A St is all 1" in wealth. Moreover, with r Table = 5, real rough estimate of the magnitude of trajectories between the unconstrained 1, find that (circles it is optimal utility case. an individual to for Results for other levels of risk aversion are available fully and x's 1) obtained by observing the difference in in figure 1, case 1) consumption plan and consumption plan. When optimal consumption sharply decreasing, the constraints bind consumption away from the optimal path. 16 In this annuities provide the optimal annuity stream. EVs can be the constrained real annuity (triangles in figure is we CRRA in 20 some of the papers listed above. In these cases, the benefit of annuitization is relatively small relatively small and the gain annuitization) consumption and the constraints impose What differentiates our (1) so that is is offset further more general set-up from behind our prior work is utility function, is greater. we can then markedly from the usual differ unconstrained (zero we can vary that the utility function exhibits an "internal habit," which optimal consumption trajectories that taken from Diamond and Mirrlees (2000), CRRA that is equation adjust to create case. it is St in The intuition not the level of present consumption, but rather the level relative to past consumption, that matters for For example, life in a studio apartment is surely is less steeply decreasing, there are greater benefits the net benefit to annuitization less costs, so consumption of future When optimal by the constraints. hump shaped and sum because the more tolerable for someone used to utility. living in such circumstances than for someone who was bedroom house. In choosing how to allocate resources across periods, "habit consumers" trade off immediate gratification by a negative income shock to abandon a from consumption not only against a lifetime budget constraint, but against the effects of consumption early in Following forced Diamond and life Mirrlees (2000), st = on the standard-of-living we model the (st-i (29) is the parameter that governs the speed of adjustment of the habit habit is constant and we are back in the additively separable case. of the habit (q=1). Away from zero, we life. + act-i)/(l'+a) We select also evolution of the habit as follows: a habit approaches last period's consumption. later in four- level. When a As a approaches is zero, the infinity, present an intermediate speed of habit adjustment find that changes to a make no substantive difference to our results, and therefore do not report results for a range of a values. 17 When the habit evolves (a > 0), present consumption increases the future standard-of-living. This increase in the standard-of-living reduces the the future. With later level of utility and increases marginal utility in consumption, there are fewer future periods that are adversely affected by an increased standard-of-living. While some researchers have attempted to measure parameters of alternative habit formation models, largely involving "external habit" formation in calibration exercises, there edge no empirical study that provides estimates of the initial Additional results are available from the authors upon request. 21 standard S65 m is to our knowl- our model. This is not a major limitation, however, as our objective is not to carefully calibrate a realistic model of a representative lifetime optimizing consumer, but rather to create optimal consumption trajectories that create an intentionally more severe mismatch with the available annuity structure than and to recognize the wide diversity actually observe in available consumption data in we wealth at retirement relative to lifetime income. Doing so allows us to "stress test" the annuity valuations in order to see if one can plausibly explain the paucity of voluntary annuity purchases within a rational model. strictly We do so by considering initial standards of living that generate consumption paths that are both extremely friendly and extremely unfriendly to annuitization. The first four columns of Table Column are varied across cases. number and the indicate the case 1 the fraction of wealth that (5) reports constant real annuity instead of bonds. In column (6), we report relevant parameters that is optimally placed in a the equivalent variation ("EV") associated with this optimal amount to hold utility constant while moving from having the optimal amount annuitized to having for all of real annuitization. This Column of wealth in bonds. the case in which the individual is (7) the increase in wealth required is permitted to choose an optimal payout trajectory, the "complete markets" result, although strictly speaking, by EV) reports the gains from annuitization (again as an are no longer constrained to purchase a constant real annuity. For shorthand, of annuities that are desired in a real annuity, be this individual all that is i.e., they we refer to this as is that the subset necessary available. Because an internal habit introduces a new cost to early consumption, one might expect that the fixed real annuity will be even more desirable with an internal habit (a However, the accuracy of this intuition hinges on the resources at retirement. If the initial habit 0) than without. level of the initial habit S65 relative to small, then is > it correct that the presence of a is potentially increasing habit leads to deferred consumption and increased valuation of the annuity. However, if the initial habit is so large as to be unsustainable, so that the habit level must fall over time, then the presence of the habit will push optimal consumption earlier, because of the desire to smooth the ratio of consumption to habit across time. If the habit decreases with time, then smoothing likewise requires that consumption decrease with time. Hence a very high initial habit relative to resources provides a mechanism beyond heavy discounting whereby the deferred consumption required by a constant To calibrate the model, and real annuity to build some may be intuition, 22 very burdensome. we first consider an individual who has reached retirement with resources that, level of consumption when annuitized, are sufficient to exactly satisfy their habit for the rest of their lifetime. In this scenario, labeled "Case 2" in Table the individual enters retirement with a habit level S65 that value of their wealth. consumption, When i.e., 18 As expected, the presence of a is 1, precisely equal to the annual annuity potentially increasing habit leads to deferred and upward sloping consumption path in the early years (see Figure only real annuities are available, the optimal allocation 1, Case 2). to fully annuitize, because doing is so provides the individual with the highest possible return without imposing any binding liquidity constraints. still if While the the individual utility is gain is even higher than in our base case, the able to purchase annuities in a complete market, utility gains are higher and thus exactly match the desired consumption trajectory. In this latter case, the ability to choose an optimal annuity trajectory is equivalent in utility terms to nearly doubling of non-annuitized wealth. Reaching retirement with precisely the resources required to maintain one's past is living standard not the empirical norm, however. Indeed, given the wide range of retirement resources across the population, it would not make sense to consider a common Hurd and Rohwedder relative to retirement resource across the entire population. new evidence on the They find a level of pre-retirement consumption (2004) provide distribution of the percentage change in spending from pre to post retirement. mean consumption drop of 13 - 14 percent. At the 20th percentile, they find a 30 percent decline in consumption, whereas at the 95th percentile they find a 20 percent increase in consumption. 19 We choose to examine even more extreme points in the consumption distribution by evaluating the case in which the habit amount that can be sustained by is double the to fully annuitize all initial wealth. consumption 1, habit level in retirement. Doing so As in cases 1 and 2, it is still optimal in a constant real annuity generates a utility gain that upward sloping consumption trajectory More 50 percent and 200 percent of the the individual has sufficient wealth to purchase a real annuity equivalent to a 67 percent increase in non-annuitized wealth. desired is one's retirement wealth. In Case 3 of Table 1 and Figure stream that level of is The ability to to the even more valuable. interesting for purposes of our "stress test" is to examine the case in which the individual only has half of the level of wealth that would be required to sustain their initial ls Given our mortality assumptions, the annual annuity value of $100 of starting wealth 19 Hurd and Rohwedder do not report points in the distribution 23 match annuities is is below the 20th percentile. habit consumption $8.59. level. As can be seen in Case leads the individual to want to sharply reduce consumption 4, this early in retirement, in order to rapidly bring down the level of habit to a more sustainable As level. such, the optimal fraction of wealth held in a real annuity declines to 90 percent, as the individual uses the 10 percent of non-annuitized wealth to supplement consumption in the then consumes the annuity Pushing the habit ratio. By trajectory, as for the "stress test" remainder of life after bring the habit in Case 5, is the real annuity income stream is to a lower level. is .10, the optimal consumption even more heavily front-loaded, and thus the mismatch with Even so, the individual would optimally In results not reported, we have found that even when particularly severe. annuitize three-quarters of their wealth. the individual's habit 10 years, and even further, Case 5 adds a high discount rate to the low wealth-to- holding r fixed at .03 and raising the discount rate to shown down first so high that retirement wealth can provide for an annuity that is one-sixth of the initial habit level, the optimal fraction of wealth invested in a real annuity only is still nearly two-thirds of initial retirement wealth. These simulations indicate that it is extremely difficult to such that the optimal fraction of wealth annuitized drops at retirement without appealing to many generate optimal consumption profiles much below additional factors. two-thirds of initial wealth This suggests that the absence of annuitization outside of Social Security and defined benefit pensions cannot be easily explained within a rational life-cycle model, even with preferences that lead to a severe mismatch between desired consumption and available annuity paths. V. With complete markets, the Conclusions and Future Directions result of standard, but restrictive assumptions. complete annuitization survives the relaxation of several Utility need not satisfy the von Neumann-Morgenstern axioms and need not be additively separable. Further, annuities need not be actuarially fair, but only must offer positive net premia over conventional assets. With incomplete markets, the full annuitization result can break down when mismatch between the optimal consumption path and the income stream offered market. In the much-studied case of a world where only individual mortality that there may there is is a sufficient by the annuity uncertain, we find be considerable individual heterogeneity in the value of annuitization. Heterogeneity 24 in annuity valuations is for early consumption. driven by heterogeneity in the willingness to substitute late consumption We find that even for preferences that stretch the impatience, a large fraction of wealth In our simulations, is bounds of plausible optimally placed in a constant real annuity. we have retained the abstractions of no bequest motive, no risks other than longevity and no learning about health status or other liquidity concerns. Exploring the consequences of dropping these assumptions in the context of non-separable preferences and unfair annuity pricing would be an important generalization, but obtaining results will require strong assumptions on annuity returns, on the nature of bequest preferences and liquidity needs, and on the stochastic structure of bond returns. It is sometimes argued that the lack of annuity purchase This raises the question of what sort of bequest motive would there is no annuitization, then a bequest is random in is evidence for a bequest motive. an absence of annuities. call for both timing and measured as a present size, discounted value. Assuming one cares about the risk aversion of recipients, this by giving the heirs a fixed sum at a fixed time and annuitizing the rest. If may be dominated More generally, partial annuitization can reduce the variation in the bequest. The near absence of voluntary annuitization is puzzling in the face of theoretical results suggest- ing large benefits to annuitization. While incomplete annuity markets may a large fraction of wealth suboptimal, our simulation results show that this render annuitization of is not the case even in a habit based model that intentionally leads to a severe mismatch between desired consumption and the single payout trajectory provided by an incomplete annuity market. These results suggest that lack of annuity tion may be demand demand may arise from behavioral considerations and that mandatory annuitiza- welfare increasing. It also suggests the importanace of behavioral modeling of annuity to understand the equilibrium offerings of annuity assets. References Abel, Andrew, "Asset pricing under habit formation and catching up with the Joneses," American Economic Review, Papers and Proceedings, 1990, Auerbach, Alan J. and Laurence J. 80, 38-42. Kotlikoff, "Life Insurance of the Elderly: 25 Adequacy and Determinants," in "Work, health, and income series, _ and _ , (3), among the elderly" Studies in Social Economics Washington, D.C.: Brookings Institution, 1987, pp. 229-67. "The Adequacy of Life Insurance Purchases," Journal of Financial Intermediation, 1991, 1 215-41. Bernheim, B. Douglas, Z. Bodie, J. Shoven, "Dissaving After Retirement: Testing the Pure Life Cycle Hypothesis," in and D. Wise, eds., Issues in Pension Economics, Chicago: NBER-University of Chicago Press, 1987a, pp. 237-282. _ , "The Economic Effects of Social Security: Toward a Reconciliation Journal of Public Economics, 1987b, 33 _ , "How Strong are Bequest Motives? Evidence and Annuities," Journal of _ , (3), Political Based on Estimates of the Demand Economy, 1991, 99 and Financial Vulnerabilities: Study," American Economic Review, 2003, 93 Brown, Jeffrey Theory and Measurement," 273-304. Lorenzo Forni, Jagadeesh Gokhale, and Laurence Life Insurance Holdings of (1), (5), for Life Insurance 899-927. J. Kotlikoff, "The Mismatch Between Evidence from the Health and Retirement 354-365. R., "Redistribution and Insurance: Mandatory Annuitization with Mortality Hetero- geneity," Journal of Risk _ and James M. Poterba, and Insurance, 2003, 10 (1), 17-41. "Redistribution and Insurance: Mandatory Annuitization with Mortality Heterogeneity," Journal of Risk and Insurance, 2003, 70 (4), 527-553. _ and Mark J. Warshawsky, Market and Regulatory Campbell, John, Woodford, "Longevity-Insured Retirement Distributions from Pension Plans: Issues," Working Paper 8064, NBER "Asset Pries, Consumption and the Business Cycle," in John B. Taylor and Michael eds., Handbook of Macroeconomics, Amsterdam: North-Holland, 2002. Campbell, John Y. and John H. Cochrane, "By force of habit: of aggregate stock market behavior," Journal of Political Constantinides, George, "Habit Formation:A Resolution Political 2001. Economy, 1990. 26 A consumption-based explanation Economy, 1999, of the Equity 107, 205 Premium - 251. Puzzle," Journal of Deaton, Angus, Understanding Consumption, Oxford, 1991. Dennis, Michael, "A Theoretical and Empirical Comparison 2004. Mimeo, UC papers in and Immediate Annuities," Berkeley. Diamond, Peter A. and James A. Mirrlees, els," in P. J. of Deferred Hammond Honour of Sir and G. D. Myles, James "Adjusting One's Standing of Living: eds., Incentives, Organization, Mirrlees, Oxford: Dusenberry, James, Income, 3, and Public Economics, Oxford University Press, 2000. Diamond, Peter and Daniel McFadden, "Some Uses nomics," Journal of Public Economics, 1974, Two Period Mod- of the Expenditure Function in Public Eco- 3-21. Saving, and the Theory of Consumer Behavior, Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1949. Dushi, Irena and Anthony Webb, "Household Annuitization Decisions: Simulations and Empirical Analysis," Journal of Pension Friedman, Benjamin M. and Economics and Finance, 2004, 3 Mark J. (2), Warshawsky, "The Cost 109-143. of Annuities: Implications for Saving Behavior and Bequests," The Quarterly Journal of Economics, February 1990, 105 (1), 135-154. Gomes, Francisco and Alexander Michaelides, "Portfolio Choice A Life-Cycle Model With Uninsurable Labor Income Risk," 6 (4), Internal Habit Formation: Review of Economic Dynamics, 2003, 729-766. Huang, Ming, 109 With (1), "Liquidity shocks and equilibrium liquidity premia," Journal of 104-129. Hurd, Michael and Susann Rohwedder, "The Retirement-Consumption Actual Declines in Spending at Retirement," Working Paper 9586, Milevsky, Not _ and Economic Theory, 2003, Moshe A., "Optimal Asset Allocation Towards the to Annuitize?," Journal of Risk End and Insurance, 1998, 65 Puzzle: Anticipated NBER 2004. of the Life Cycle: (3), and To Annuitize or 401-426. Virginia R. Young, "Optimal Asset Allocation and the Real Option to Delay Annuitization: It's Not Now-or-Never," 2002. Working Paper, York 27 University. Mitchell, Olivia, of the 89 James M. Poterba, Mark Warshawsky, and Jeffrey R. Brown, "New Evidence Money's Worth of Individual Annuities," The American Economic Review, December 1999, (5), 1299-1318. Palmon, Oded and Avia Spivak, "Information and the Market for Annuities," Working Paper, Bank of Israel 2001. Sinclair, Sven H. and Kent A. Smetters, "Health Shocks and the Demand for Annuities," Technical Paper Series 2004-9, Congressional Budget Office 2004. Turra, Cassio M. and Olivia S. Mitchell, "The Impact of Health Status and Out-of-Pocket Medical Expenditures on Annuity Valuation," Working Paper, Pension Research Council 2004. WP 2004-2. Warshawsky, Mark J., Brenda Spillman, and Chris Murtaugh, and Long-Term Care Insurance: Theory, Evidence, Practice and Bodie, Brett Hammond, and "Integrating the Life Annuity Policy," in Olivia Mitchell, Zvi Steve Zeldes, eds., Financial Innovations in Retirement Income, forthcoming. Yaari, Menahem E., "Uncertain Lifetime, Life Insurance, and the of Economic Studies, April 1965, 32, 137. 28 Theory of the Consumer," Review Table Case • Simulated Utility Gains From Access To Annuitization 1. Habit Ratio of Adjustment initial Speed a Discount % rate Welfare gain Welfare gain whei annuitized when optimal annuity markets S65 to real with real % complete annuity annuities annuitized habit of savings of savings (1) (2) (3) (4) (5) (6) (7) 1 n/a n/a 0.03 100 56 56 2 1 1 0.03 100 71 96 3 1 0.5 0.03 100 67 74 4 1 2 0.03 90 51 54 5 2 1 Notes: Risk aversion 7 is 75 0.1 throughout. set at 2 Column equation (28) to the annual payout of an actuarially through 100. Welfare gains in columns (6) and fair (3) 25 30 compares the habit level (565 in annuity with equal payouts in years 66 (7) are calculated as the amount of of initial wealth that a 65 year old male unable to annuitize any savings would have to be given to attain the same level of utility as if he were allowed to annuitize an optimal fraction of savings. Column (5) is the optimal fraction of savings placed in a real annuity, corresponding to the equivalent variation in column Figure (6). 1 Complete annuitization is optimal when the trajectory of payouts is plots optimal consumption trajectories with no annuities, real annuities designed annuities for each of the five sets of parameters. 29 unconstrained. and optimally Figure 1. Optimal Consumption Trajectories Under Different Annuity Availability Case 1 G i Optimal Hoal Annuitization " Optimal Unconstrained Annuitization No Ann uiliza lion O No a Oplimal Real Annuitization Oplimal Uncoftslrainad Annuilizaltot » |2 | O 1 Case 2 --.... 10 , ° A A A * Aa ago 15 20 Annuitization , - ••-.... 15 20 25 30 10 Years past 65 Years past 65 Case 3 Case 4 O No i Oplimal Roal Annuitizalion Annuitization Opll mat C A U n cons tra inod Annuttizalior No Annuitizalion Opt imal Re al Ann u Hizal Ion Optimal Unconstrained Annuitrzatiof g« ro 10 liiiiiiajaf 1 & A £ A A £. £ i " o i 15 20 25 30 10 Years past 65 15 20 a a A a a 25 ^ 30 35 Years past 65 Case 5 O No Annuitization fi Oplimal Real Annuitization Oplimal Unconstrained Annui'izafioi i« $AA4.i£.Aiiil.a£.aAia£.iaafli 15 20 25 30 35 Years past 65 Notes: The five cases case, circles plot optimal shows correspond to the parameter values consumption Triangles plot optimal consumption for a consumer when only who is expenditures annuity is is the available minimum to hold utility equal to the and expenditures are equal to 100. 30 is solely maximum ^4 Table 1. In each unable to annuitize any wealth. a constant real annuity consumption when any consumption trajectory can be funded listed in 8 36 available, x 's plot optimal by annuities. utility 02 k The level of when a constant real Date Due Lib-26-67 MIT LIBRARIES 3 9080 02618 3548