Do Not Delete 11/30/2014 3:42 PM ARTICLE RULES AND STANDARDS IN COPYRIGHT Thomas B. Nachbar ABSTRACT In the last decade, calls to recalibrate the copyright system’s mix of incentives have become nearly ubiquitous in copyright scholarship. Most such proposals start from the point of identifying a failure (systemic or market) and then offer a reform that compensates (and hopefully remedies) that specific failure. But, starting from the principle that copyright should provide optimal incentives to create and ending with a particular failure (and its cure), most reform proposals fail to distinguish between the purposes of copyright writ large and the purposes of the legal system that implements copyright. While copyright encourages creative work, the copyright system does so through the limited means of allocation, both by providing a rule for initially allocating copyrights and by facilitating reallocation of those rights, either through transactions or by allowing use. Thus, copyright is essentially temporal in its focus, with important decision points at the time of both the creation of a work and the decision of a potential user of that work to reallocate part of the work through a use. Similarly, rules and standards operate primarily by altering the time at which information is needed in order to determine whether a particular action is legal. Most reform proposals (which can be classified as compulsory licenses, damages-only regimes, or requirements for additional showings) would alter the mix of rules and standards in the copyright system. The Article approaches the reform question by seriously considering the timing of copyright I would like to thank the participants at the 2014 University of Houston Law Center’s Institute for Intellectual Property & Information Law Symposium for their comments and suggestions, both during the symposium itself and in conversations before and after. 583 Do Not Delete 584 11/30/2014 3:42 PM HOUSTON LAW REVIEW [52:2 allocations and reallocations and the effect of reform proposals on when information is available to copyright’s decision-makers (promulgators, authors, users, and adjudicators). The Article provides a concrete example in the history of the Audio Home Recording Act (a compulsory license) to demonstrate how reform proposals that ignore the dimension of time are likely to derail the development of creative works and their associated technologies. A better understanding of how the copyright system uses rules and standards—and honestly confronting the limits of both—can inform present and future reform proposals. TABLE OF CONTENTS I. INTRODUCTION ............................................................... 584 II. REFORM IN COPYRIGHT .................................................. 585 III. COPYRIGHT AS A SYSTEM ............................................... 588 IV. RULES, STANDARDS, AND COPYRIGHT ........................... 593 A. Rules and Standards ............................................. 593 B. Rules and Standards in Copyright ....................... 596 V. RULES, STANDARDS, AND REFORM ................................ 601 A. Compulsory Licenses .............................................. 601 B. Damages-Only Regimes and Additional Showings ................................................................ 607 C. Taking Rules and Standards Seriously ................ 609 VI. CONCLUSION .................................................................. 611 I. INTRODUCTION Copyright law is a frequent object of reform proposals, many of which seek to enable increased access to works through either the certainty of rules or the increased sensitivity of standards. Few such proposals, though, take seriously the implications of shifting copyright in the direction of either rules or standards. I proceed first by describing several recent reform proposals in the terms of rules and standards. Although motivated by policy concerns over incentives and access, reforms do not modify “copyright” as a system of incentives and access but, rather, modify the specific system of copyright in which we operate—a system of allocations and reallocations of the social wealth embodied in creative works. Having described the system in which copyright rules and standards operate, Do Not Delete 2014] 11/30/2014 3:42 PM RULES AND STANDARDS IN COPYRIGHT 585 I discuss rules and standards in greater detail. The choice of whether to adopt a rule or a standard in a particular instance is one driven largely by concerns over the time at which a determination should be made, rules being ex ante determinations and standards being ex post ones. Understood as a question about timing, the rules/standards continuum presents three possibilities for when to make a determination: at the time of promulgation by a rule maker, the time at which an individual chooses to act, or the time of adjudication by a factfinder. Adapted to our system of copyright, proposals to shift to either rules or standards have effects on the decision-making of both authors and users of works—effects I consider in the penultimate section of the Article. When considered from the standpoint of rules and standards, many policy proposals that attempt to assist users in accessing works likely hinder users’ decision-making abilities with little countervailing gain to the policy of access. I summarize my findings in a brief conclusion. II. REFORM IN COPYRIGHT Copyright is widely understood to be justified by—and therefore serve—the distinctly utilitarian end of maximizing incentives to both create and distribute creative expression and access to that expression.1 Given its utilitarian justification, it is no surprise that copyright has garnered a steady stream of proposals to make it more useful.2 Social wealth maximization 1. See Wendy J. Gordon, Fair Use as Market Failure: A Structural and Economic Analysis of the Betamax Case and Its Predecessors, 82 COLUM. L. REV. 1600, 1604 (1982) (“[T]he copyright system creates private property in creative works so that the market can simultaneously provide economic incentives for authors and disseminate authored works . . . .”). Copyright seeks to optimize the superficially paradoxical use of restrictions on access in order to increase access through copyright’s incentive/access paradigm. See Glynn S. Lunney, Jr., Reexamining Copyright’s Incentives-Access Paradigm, 49 VAND. L. REV. 483, 498 (1996) (“[T]he incentives-access paradigm suggests that we can determine copyright’s proper scope by balancing the need for additional incentives against the need for access.”). Others have taken a more limited view, focusing much more on the incentives of authors than on the role played by access. See, e.g., Shyamkrishna Balganesh, Foreseeability and Copyright Incentives, 122 HARV. L. REV. 1569, 1571 (2009) (“Copyright law’s principal justification today is the economic theory of creator incentives.”). This particular view of incentives and access is distinct to common-law systems—it itself is contingent on the surrounding economic order. See Jane C. Ginsburg, A Tale of Two Copyrights: Literary Property in Revolutionary France and America, in OF AUTHORS AND ORIGINS: ESSAYS ON COPYRIGHT LAW 131, 131–33 (Brad Sherman & Alain Strowel eds., 1994). There are also other views that have much less to do with wealth maximization and focus on other social values, such as free expression. See, e.g., NEIL WEINSTOCK NETANEL, COPYRIGHT’S PARADOX 37–38 (2008). Although valid and interesting, such justifications are outside the scope of my particular inquiry. 2. See, e.g., David Fagundes, Efficient Copyright Infringement, 98 IOWA L. REV. 1791, 1836–37 (2013) (proposing eliminating certain damages remedies to make copyright infringement more efficient); Christopher Sprigman, Copyright and the Rule of Reason, 7 J. TELECOMM. & HIGH TECH. L. 317, 338–41 (2009) (proposing a rule of reason test for Do Not Delete 586 11/30/2014 3:42 PM HOUSTON LAW REVIEW [52:2 is a single-scalar metric that can be enhanced any number of ways, opening up the field to any number of proposals seeking to improve copyright.3 Doctrinal developments, too, especially the U.S. Supreme Court’s holding in eBay Inc. v. MercExchange, L.L.C. that injunctive relief in patent cases is not automatic, 4 have sparked renewed discussion over the possibility of adjusting the remedies available for infringement actions—to adjust the absolute “exclusive rights” approach5 to copyright— to more precisely tune the incentives/access tradeoff and thereby increase the wealth-enhancing effects of copyright.6 Reform proposals come in several flavors. The first is compulsory licenses, which substantially reduce transaction costs by denying copyright owners the ability to refuse to enter into licenses. The copyright statute itself includes several, albeit for very limited purposes,7 and several scholars have similarly proposed compulsory licenses for certain kinds of use.8 Compulsory licenses are prototypical rules—they are fixed at the time they are adopted, which is (ideally, as a matter of incentives) ex ante to the creation of any work and certainly to determining plaintiff’s right in copyright cases in order to make copyright law more efficient). 3. See Gregory S. Alexander, The Social-Obligation Norm in American Property Law, 94 CORNELL L. REV. 745, 748 n.8 (2009). 4. eBay Inc. v. MercExchange, L.L.C., 547 U.S. 388, 392–93 (2006). 5. I am not suggesting that copyright, in its “natural” state ever contained anything akin to an absolute right to exclude. No property system can be so described. Carol M. Rose, Canons of Property Talk, or, Blackstone’s Anxiety, 108 YALE L.J. 601, 631 (1998) (“[P]roperty as exclusive dominion is at most a cartoon or trope . . . .”). 6. See Jiarui Liu, Copyright Injunctions After eBay: An Empirical Study, 16 LEWIS & CLARK L. REV. 215, 222, 256–57 (2012). 7. See 17 U.S.C. § 111(d) (2012) (retransmission by cable systems); id. § 114(d)(2) (digital audio transmission); id. § 115 (nondramatic musical compositions); id. § 116 (jukeboxes); id. § 118(b)(4) (noncommercial broadcasting); id. §§ 119, 122 (secondary transmissions by satellite). 8. E.g., WILLIAM W. FISHER III, PROMISES TO KEEP: TECHNOLOGY, LAW, AND THE FUTURE OF ENTERTAINMENT 202 (2004) (levy on equipment using creative works combined with a license to use); Olufunmilayo B. Arewa, From J.C. Bach to Hip Hop: Musical Borrowing, Copyright and Cultural Context, 84 N.C. L. REV. 547, 641–42 (2006) (compulsory license to allow digital sampling); Mark A. Lemley & R. Anthony Reese, Reducing Digital Copyright Infringement Without Restricting Innovation, 56 STAN. L. REV. 1345, 1406–10 (2004) (levy to solve problems of secondary liability for facilitators of digital sharing); Glynn S. Lunney, Jr., The Death of Copyright: Digital Technology, Private Copying, and the Digital Millennium Copyright Act, 87 VA. L. REV. 813, 912, 916 (2001) (“limited tax on copying technology and storage media” combined with a compulsory license); Neil Weinstock Netanel, Impose a Noncommercial Use Levy to Allow Free Peer-toPeer File Sharing, 17 HARV. J.L. & TECH. 1, 21 (2003) (levy combined with compulsory license limited to peer-to-peer filing sharing); Robert M. Vrana, Comment, The Remix Artist’s Catch-22: A Proposal for Compulsory Licensing for Transformative, SamplingBased Music, 68 WASH. & LEE L. REV. 811, 850 (2011) (sampling compulsory license to allow “remix” of underlying works). Do Not Delete 2014] 11/30/2014 3:42 PM RULES AND STANDARDS IN COPYRIGHT 587 any use by another. They resolve not only the legal determination of whether a use is infringing but fix the level of compensation for that use.9 The second is damages-only regimes.10 By denying injunctive relief to copyright owners and relying exclusively on damages for infringement, damages-only regimes are similarly designed to reduce transaction costs because they eliminate the possibility that a copyright owner could “hold out” and deny a use that is wealth-enhancing.11 Damages-only proposals are extremely flexible and can be based on any number of concerns. Some are aimed at overcoming copyright owners’ ability to block new uses generally.12 Others are more finely tuned to specific problems, such as optimizing incentives,13 overcoming copyright owners’ irrational refusals to license,14 or solving transaction cost problems presented by particular uses15 and the changing nature of works and use more generally.16 In the language of rules and standards, these proposals shift copyright the opposite way from compulsory licenses—toward more of a standard because damages determinations would be made by judges at adjudication and would depend on all the information 9. FISHER, supra note 8, at 144–45. 10. Such proposals are frequently termed “liability rules” to distinguish them from “property rules,” but because “liability” is a distinct concept, I use the term “damages-only” to describe proposals to limit copyright remedies to damages alone. 11. See Mark A. Lemley & Philip J. Weiser, Should Property or Liability Rules Govern Information?, 85 TEX. L. REV. 783, 792, 796–97 (2007). 12. E.g., id. at 796–97 (covering both patent and copyright); see also Orit Fischman Afori, Flexible Remedies as a Means to Counteract Failures in Copyright Law, 29 CARDOZO ARTS & ENT. L.J. 1, 28–29, 37–38 (2011) (comparing generally the advantages of injunctive relief and damages-only rules for infringement). 13. See, e.g., Fagundes, supra note 2, at 1840–41 (proposing an “ex post compulsory license,” which would essentially operate identically to a damages-only regime with the measure of damages being the infringer’s profits). 14. See, e.g., Christopher Buccafusco & Christopher Jon Sprigman, The Creativity Effect, 78 U. CHI. L. REV. 31, 51–52 (2011) (discussing use of a damages-only regime for copyright infringement in order to overcome the irrationally high valuation that creators give to works they create); Christopher Buccafusco & Christopher Sprigman, Valuing Intellectual Property: An Experiment, 96 CORNELL L. REV. 1, 33–35 (2010) (discussing use of a damages-only regime for copyright infringement in order to overcome the irrationally high valuation that copyright owners give to works they own). 15. See, e.g., Thomas F. Cotter, Fair Use and Copyright Overenforcement, 93 IOWA L. REV. 1271, 1292–94 & n.58 (2008) (proposing damages-only regime for infringement of the derivative works right that falls short of fair use to maximize social welfare). 16. E.g., Molly Schaffer Van Houweling, Author Autonomy and Atomism in Copyright Law, 96 VA. L. REV. 549, 556–57, 640–41 (2010) (suggesting damages-only regime to solve the problem of increasingly atomistic works and uses of works). Not all scholars advance a damages-only regime on the grounds that it would increase social wealth. See Wendy J. Gordon, A Property Right in Self-Expression: Equality and Individualism in the Natural Law of Intellectual Property, 102 YALE L.J. 1533, 1573–76 (1993). Operating as I am in the realm of wealth maximization, such proposals are outside the scope of my inquiry. Do Not Delete 588 11/30/2014 3:42 PM HOUSTON LAW REVIEW [52:2 available up to the point of adjudication, including information not only about the work and the use but also about the effects of the use on the work. A third set of proposals would alter infringement determinations themselves by requiring, in addition to the traditional elements of copyright infringement, additional information about the nature of either the work or the use—for simplicity, I’ll call these requirements for “additional showings.” Thus, some would limit infringement to those uses that the author could have foreseen at the time the underlying work was created (because only such uses would have formed the incentive that induced that author to create the work),17 while others would insist on not only copying but some “anticompetitive” harm to the market for the work,18 or in the case of a derivative work, whether the copyright owner itself would be likely to enter the market for such a work.19 These proposals, like those for damages-only regimes, shift copyright toward the “standard” side of the rules/standards continuum, because they rely on additional ex post information in making determinations. Some aspects of copyright law, such as the fair use defense, arguably already incorporate similar, standard-like, limitations on copyright.20 Given these several types of reform proposals, the question is how do rules and standards inform our understanding of how these proposals (and indeed copyright itself) work. But in order to better understand how rules and standards work in copyright, we need to consider how the copyright system actually works to serve its wealth-maximizing ends. III. COPYRIGHT AS A SYSTEM Although it is a common habit to refer to the purpose of “copyright” or “copyright law” as being to provide incentives to 17. E.g., Balganesh, supra note 1, at 1571 (advancing “a test of ‘foreseeable copying’ to limit copyright’s grant of exclusivity to situations where a copier’s use was reasonably foreseeable at the time of creation—the point when the incentive is meant to operate”). 18. See, e.g., Christina Bohannan & Herbert Hovenkamp, IP and Antitrust: Reformation and Harm, 51 B.C. L. REV. 905, 905, 989–90 (2010) (“We propose a concept of ‘IP injury’ that limits IP remedies to situations in which the IP holder has suffered or is likely to suffer harm sufficiently linked to the purpose of IP law, which is to incentivize innovation.”); Sprigman, supra note 2, at 338–39 (suggesting a “rule of reason” approach that would require competitive harm to copyright owners in cases of nonliteral copying). 19. E.g., Thomas F. Cotter, Transformative Use and Cognizable Harm, 12 VAND. J. ENT. & TECH. L. 701, 751 (2010) (asking whether the market for the derivative work is a “phantom” market to the author). 20. See Christina Bohannan, Copyright Harm, Foreseeability, and Fair Use, 85 WASH. U. L. REV. 969, 977–78 (2007) (connecting fair use with competitive harms to authors). Do Not Delete 2014] 11/30/2014 3:42 PM RULES AND STANDARDS IN COPYRIGHT 589 create and distribute information (with a nod to the overall maximization of social wealth),21 it would be difficult to connect any rational policy interest to the bundle of rules that compose modern copyright protection. For instance, much of the value of copyrighted works lies not in their expression but in the ideas (or facts) they contain—and thus, it would seem rational to provide incentives for the creation and distribution of ideas and facts—yet ideas and facts themselves are unprotected by the copyright system.22 Thus, the copyright system is at least an imperfect implementation of a broad policy of incentives and access, and copyright lawyers are at some level constrained to confront that system rather than the policy justifications underlying it. The danger of ignoring the distinction is that it becomes easy to argue that the policy of incentives and access that the copyright system attempts to further should itself determine the rules of copyright. That is an attempt to remake copyright law, not understand it, although some areas of copyright law are certainly more amendable to the importation of policy than others.23 Copyright is hardly alone in this regard. Property law, for instance, has frequently been justified on the ground that it provides incentives for the productive use of resources, but no one would confuse the Rule Against Perpetuities with a policy of social wealth maximization. Recognizing the existence of a gap between copyright as a policy and our particular implementation of copyright (what I call the “copyright system”) frees one to consider what it is that the copyright system does, because it clearly does not provide anything anyone would call “a system of incentives and access to maximize the social wealth to be generated by creative effort.” Perhaps somewhat mundanely, the copyright system at its base does only two things: (1) allocates control over, and thereby maintains a claim to the wealth generated by, certain creative effort; and (2) enables reallocation of that control to others through a variety of mechanisms. The copyright system allocates control over certain creative content by awarding copyright protection to authors for their creative expression. The copyright system makes this initial allocation by vesting copyright in authors, which is a characteristic 21. E.g., Neil Weinstock Netanel, Copyright and a Democratic Civil Society, 106 YALE L.J. 283, 285 (1996) (“Copyright law strikes a precarious balance. To encourage authors to create and disseminate original expression, it accords them a bundle of proprietary rights in their works.”). 22. See 17 U.S.C. § 102(b) (2012) (ideas); Feist Publ’ns, Inc. v. Rural Tel. Serv. Co., 499 U.S. 340, 344 (1991) (facts). 23. Gordon, supra note 1, at 1604. Do Not Delete 590 11/30/2014 3:42 PM HOUSTON LAW REVIEW [52:2 of the system that many take for granted, but is itself a feature of our particular system of copyright.24 One could just as easily vest copyright in publishers, as the ancestor of our copyright system itself did.25 That the system conducts an initial allocation of this kind has great import because it directs all that follows. For instance, relying on an initial allocation of control over the work26 to the author determines that the entire system will be dependent on control and capturing wealth rather than some other means (such as bounties or patronage). The copyright system, perhaps even more importantly, also enables reallocation, which is necessary unless one assumes that the author of a work is also the party who most highly values the work. If the copyright system did not enable reallocation of the work (or aspects of the work), social wealth would suffer, because transfers of the work can themselves increase social wealth.27 The copyright system reallocates works in two primary ways: by making the initial allocation transferrable through transactions (a transactional reallocation—in our system through the use of licenses) and by allowing for use of the work by others. Use itself can be broken down to both consumptive28 uses of the work (including, for present purposes, distribution of the work to others for their consumption) and productive uses of the work. Either form of use constitutes a reallocation of the underlying work as well as a likely increase in social wealth, albeit in different ways and with different consequences. Consumptive use (enjoyment or use of the work in its own right) clearly increases social wealth (I am richer after I read a book than I was before, and therefore, so is society), but the increase in social wealth stemming from consumptive use is frequently completely internalized to the user.29 Productive use (the use of the work in creating another work) can result in either an increase or a decrease in social wealth 24. See 17 U.S.C. § 102(a)–(b). 25. Thomas B. Nachbar, Intellectual Property and Constitutional Norms, 104 COLUM. L. REV. 272, 320 (2004) (noting the copyright bestowed on the publisher, the Stationers’ Company). 26. Throughout, I will simply refer to allocation and reallocation of the “work” as a shorthand for “control over the work.” 27. See Thomas B. Nachbar, Judicial Review and the Quest to Keep Copyright Pure, 2 J. TELECOMM. & HIGH TECH. L. 33, 71 n.135 (2003). 28. Cf. Sprigman, supra note 2, at 335 (defining “consumptive infringement” as “forms of infringement involving the reproduction and distribution of copies that are either exact or near enough so that they are almost certain to compete with the original work for patronage”). I am relying on a differing conception of “consumptive,” one that focuses not on whether the use is similar enough to compete with the underlying work (because many transformative uses can compete directly) but, rather, on whether the use is part of the creation of a new work. 29. Fagundes, supra note 2, at 1809. Do Not Delete 2014] 11/30/2014 3:42 PM RULES AND STANDARDS IN COPYRIGHT 591 (an increase stemming from the new work or a decrease if the use results not just in wealth reallocation but also rent dissipation30). Unlike consumptive use, productive use frequently results in wealth gains both to the user and those who consume the newly produced (derivative) work.31 Consequently, productive uses have received tremendous attention from copyright scholars,32 although it is consumptive uses that tend to receive the bulk of the attention from legislators.33 Many uses are the result of transactional reallocations, but for my purposes, I will use the term “use” distinctly to describe a reallocation without regard to whether there is an underlying transaction. Uses can either be noninfringing (such as reading a book) or infringing (such as copying it), and thus it isn’t quite true that the copyright system “enables” infringing uses, although it permits them through imperfect enforcement.34 One might quibble with my description of a “use” like reading a book as a reallocation of the work because the copyright system does not initially allocate the right to prevent reading of a book in the author in the first place; if the author never has this particular right to the work, it cannot be reallocated through use. Rather, one might argue, that the copyright system allocates some rights (such as reproduction) in the author and other rights (such as reading) in the public. The problem with using the language of exclusive rights when considering allocations and reallocations is that the right to read a work does not pre-exist the creation of a work, but more importantly, neither does the social wealth to be gained from reading the work. While the exclusive right to read may never reside in the author, the social wealth to be gained by reading the work does, even if in latent form. The copyright system reallocates that wealth from authors to readers by refusing to protect an exclusive right to read. In this sense 30. For example, a T-shirt featuring a picture of Mickey Mouse shooting heroin might potentially reduce the value of Mickey as a character in creative works oriented toward children. 31. See Brett M. Frischmann & Mark A. Lemley, Spillovers, 107 COLUM. L. REV. 257, 285, 288–89 (2007). 32. See, e.g., LAWRENCE LESSIG, REMIX: MAKING ART AND COMMERCE THRIVE IN THE HYBRID ECONOMY 255–56 (2008); Frischmann & Lemley, supra note 31, at 285. Many scholars can be forgiven for their obsession with the role of productive uses given the copyright system’s emphasis on transformative uses as part of the fair use defense. See, e.g., Cotter, supra note 19, at 703–04. 33. Most modern changes to the Copyright Act (on the reallocation side rather than allocation side) have revolved around consumptive uses, such as compulsory licenses for cable television and rules to allow certain consumptive uses, such as digital transmission. 34. Because work is reallocated whether the use is infringing or noninfringing, the difference between infringing and noninfringing uses is irrelevant for the purposes of considering reallocations, although the difference is certainly not irrelevant to authors and users. Do Not Delete 592 11/30/2014 3:42 PM HOUSTON LAW REVIEW [52:2 the copyright system is not what allocates the social wealth from reading to the author—creation of the work does—but the system nevertheless operates on that wealth, even if in some cases only by reallocating it. My use of “reallocation” to describe that shift emphasizes that users cannot obtain that wealth until a point in time after the author creates it; my aim is to describe the temporal dimension of how value moves from authors to users, not to describe copyright doctrine. In the case of a right protected by the copyright system, such as the right to make copies of the work, the copyright system leaves the social wealth to be gained from copying with the author and permits, but does not force, reallocation. To state what the copyright system does in such simple terms is not to suggest it is a simple system. As described above, the copyright system does not reinforce the initial allocation of all the social wealth of a work to authors and does not cover every form of creative expression (not to mention noncreative works and nonexpression, both of which are completely outside the system35), and the various means through which the copyright system works reallocation are incredibly complex. But within its limited purview of creative expression, the copyright system itself can be described quite simply as a system of allocations and reallocations. It is wrong to view it as more from the perspective of policy; the system of initial allocations and reallocations is perhaps tuned to provide both incentives to create that expression and access to that expression—but it is not itself a system of incentives or access. It is similarly wrong to view it as less from the perspective of mechanics; the many features of the copyright system—detailed provisions regarding registration or renewal or statutory damages—exist to support these initial allocations and reallocations, but the end of the system itself is the initial allocation and reallocation of works. It is in the combination of initial allocations and reallocations that the copyright system so closely resembles the property system and is a likely reason for the resilience of the analogy to the “other” property system and the oft-maligned36 term “intellectual 35. Although patent is similarly a system of allocation and reallocations of created content, rules and standards operate very differently in the patent system, and so I have excluded it from consideration in this paper. The basic description here of the copyright system in terms of allocation and reallocation does apply equally to the patent system. 36. See, e.g., Floris Kreiken & David Koepsell, Coase and Copyright, 2013 U. ILL. J.L. TECH. & POL’Y 1, 32 (2013) (“[C]onstantly emphasizing the ‘property’ part of copyright makes copyrighted goods seem more exclusive than they really are or can be.”); Stefan Larsson, Metaphors and Norms: Understanding Copyright Law in a Digital Society, 36 LUND STUD. SOC. L. 5, 103–04 (2011) (noting metaphor of intellectual property forces legal debate over copyright into context of property). See generally DAVID R. KOEPSELL, THE ONTOLOGY OF CYBERSPACE: PHILOSOPHY, LAW, AND THE FUTURE OF INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY (2000) (comparing intellectual and tangible property rights). Do Not Delete 2014] 11/30/2014 3:42 PM RULES AND STANDARDS IN COPYRIGHT 593 property.”37 In a liability-based system (such as tort), initial allocations are either assumed (such as the initial allocation of the right against bodily injury or the property rights underlying a tort like conversion, which does not address itself the underlying ownership interest) or irrelevant, and the system is not designed to enable reallocation but is instead to compensate for admittedly wrongful reallocations; no one would say that tort law “enables” bodily injury through negligent conduct by insisting on compensation for it. IV. RULES, STANDARDS, AND COPYRIGHT Having described the copyright system as one of initial allocations and reallocations, the next question to consider is the role of rules and standards in the operation of that system. Before we can do that, though, we need a more detailed understanding of rules and standards. A. Rules and Standards Few concepts are as widely bandied about in legal scholarship as the familiar debates over rules and standards.38 I adopt here a fairly simple conception of rules and standards developed by Louis Kaplow in his seminal paper: Rules Versus Standards: An Economic 37. Thus, it is this allocation/reallocation structure of property regimes, and not the availability of injunctive relief, that distinguishes property regimes and liability regimes. Cf. Lemley & Weiser, supra note 11, at 783 (“The foundational notion of property law is that ‘the right to exclude’ is the essence of a true property right.”); Thomas W. Merrill, Property and the Right to Exclude, 77 NEB. L. REV. 730, 730 (1998) (“[T]he right to exclude others is more than just ‘one of the most essential’ constituents of property—it is the sine qua non.”). Lemley, Weiser, and Merrill cite Kaiser Aetna v. United States for this proposition. Lemley & Weiser, supra note 11, at 783; Merrill, supra, at 730. But the Court in Kaiser Aetna concluded that the right to exclude is a necessary part of a property right, not that the right to exclude distinguished property rights from other rights. See Kaiser Aetna v. United States, 444 U.S. 164, 179–80 (1979). Indeed, although the injunction-as-property meme has its intellectual origins in the Calabresi and Melamed approach to entitlements, see Guido Calabresi & A. Douglas Melamed, Property Rules, Liability Rules, and Inalienability: One View of the Cathedral, 85 HARV. L. REV. 1089, 1105–06 (1972), the view of property regimes as first allocating and then providing rules for reallocating entitlements is a more complete description of their approach. See id. at 1092 (“The state not only has to decide whom to entitle, but it must also simultaneously make a series of equally difficult second order decisions. These decisions go to the manner in which entitlements are protected and to whether an individual is allowed to sell or trade the entitlement.”). Thus, Calabresi and Melamed’s conception of entitlements is broad enough to capture the case of bodily integrity because the awarding of, and the ability to transfer, an entitlement to both our bodies and tangible property are economically—but certainly not legally—identical. See id. at 1091. 38. I recognize that, by focusing on the temporal dimension of rules and standards, I am considering an exceptionally narrow aspect of the dichotomy between rules and standards. On rules and standards generally, see H.L.A. HART, THE CONCEPT OF LAW 124– 35 (2d ed. 1994). Do Not Delete 594 11/30/2014 3:42 PM HOUSTON LAW REVIEW [52:2 Analysis. As Professor Kaplow explains, what separates rules and standards is not their relative complexity (there are some extremely complex rules and some very simple standards) but, rather, the degree to which they rely on ex ante or ex post determinations of legality.39 A legal directive is “rule-like” if the determination of legality is made before an act takes place and “standard-like” if the determination of legality can only be determined after an act takes place.40 Thus, a speed limit is an advance determination of a safe speed for a car to travel, and a driver could determine with certainty the legal limit on his or her behavior before setting out. Conversely, a directive to drive at a “reasonable” or “safe” speed would require (or allow) an adjudicator to factor in any number of considerations that might be relevant to a particular driver’s traversing a particular stretch of road at a particular time, and thus the actual legal limit on speed could not be decisively determined until after a particular act of driving took place. There are any number of considerations that moderate the rule/standard distinction. It is a commonplace in the rules/standards literature that most directives fall along a continuum between rules and standards.41 Most directives include a combination of both rule-like and standard-like elements (the tax code’s allowance of deductions for all “ordinary and necessary” business expenses comes to mind42), and the existence of legal precedent in applying a particular standard can give it a clarity and predictability approaching that of a rule.43 As a general matter, though, the distinction holds: rules rely for their determinations on information available before the act takes place, and standards require information that can only be obtained in the commission of the act. Because rules are based on information available ex ante and standards on information available ex post, the availability of such information is a key element in determining whether a rule or a standard is the most appropriate form of legal directive in a particular instance. Thus, if there is a great deal of information about the conduct available ex ante (such as observations of the likelihood of accidents at different speeds on roads similar to the one being regulated), rules are more appropriate. Where information can only be obtained ex post, standards work better. 39. Louis Kaplow, Rules Versus Standards: An Economic Analysis, 42 DUKE L.J. 557, 559 n.2, 588–90, 599 (1992). 40. Id. at 559–60. 41. E.g., Russell B. Korobkin, Behavioral Analysis and Legal Form: Rules vs. Standards Revisited, 79 OR. L. REV. 23, 30 (2000). 42. See 26 U.S.C. § 162 (2012). 43. Kaplow, supra note 39, at 564. Do Not Delete 2014] 11/30/2014 3:42 PM RULES AND STANDARDS IN COPYRIGHT 595 In slightly more granular terms, what matters is the cost of obtaining information relevant to the underlying legal determination: whether it is costlier to obtain information about a particular activity ex ante or ex post.44 According to Professor Kaplow, those relative cost determinations are relevant at three critical points in time: at the time of promulgation, at the time an individual must predict how the directive is going to apply to his conduct, and at the time of adjudication by a factfinder—costs incurred at the time of promulgation, choice, and adjudication.45 Generally, rules are expensive to determine at the point of promulgation and cheap to apply at the later points of choice and adjudication, while standards are inexpensive to promulgate but may be expensive for individuals to determine when they have to choose their behavior and result in costly trials at adjudication.46 Certain aspects of behavior may make them more amenable to either rules or standards. The cost of acquiring information about (unknowable) future acts is particularly high at the point of promulgation, and so rules generally make the most sense when applied to conduct that recurs frequently—speeding laws being a good example.47 The relative higher cost of promulgating the rule is offset by the low costs incurred at the moment of choice and during adjudication.48 On the other hand, it may simply not pay to invest in determining rules for all the possible ways a directive could be violated—as would be necessary in order to support a rule—if the directive is rarely violated. Consequently, heterogeneous behavior lends itself better to standards because, although the cost at the later stages of choice and adjudication is much higher than for the application of a rule, the frequency of either choice or adjudication is low, and so, the reduced cost of uncertainty is offset by the high cost of promulgating a rule.49 Of 44. Id. at 562–63. 45. Id. at 568. 46. Id. at 568–70. Professor Kaplow focuses on the choice the individual faces in deciding whether to acquire additional information (as from a lawyer), but I think it is actually better to focus on the individual’s choice of whether or not to act given his understanding of the directive, which is necessarily informed (and potentially determined) by the individual’s understanding of the directive, with or without legal advice. That is, the cost of determining the content of the directive is likely to affect equally not only the decision of whether to invest in learning about the rule but, also, the decision of whether to engage in the potentially illegal conduct (and have a greater deterrent effect if the individual is risk averse). 47. Id. at 563–64. 48. Id. at 577. And some rules may benefit from analysis of similar conduct in other contexts. Thus, a speeding rule may be inexpensively determined for a particular road because the safety of driving at different speeds on other similar roads is itself a frequent and readily observable event. 49. Id. at 563–64. Do Not Delete 596 11/30/2014 3:42 PM HOUSTON LAW REVIEW [52:2 course, the costs of applying rules and standards can vary at the different stages for reasons unrelated to whether information is known ex ante or ex post. For instance, if the information necessary for an accurate determination is in the parties’ control, the cost at choice may be very low, but the cost at adjudication may be higher (or the likelihood of an erroneous adjudication higher) because the adjudicator will need to obtain the information in the parties’ control before making an accurate determination. If a driver is the only one who knows how fast she was driving, it doesn’t matter whether the directive is stated as a rule (a speed limit) or a standard (reckless driving)—adjudication will likely be either expensive or unreliable (or both). B. Rules and Standards in Copyright It should come as no surprise that the copyright system utilizes both rules and standards in its operation. The copyright system’s regulation for determining initial allocation—fixation— is decidedly rule-like.50 One need know very little about an individual’s conduct ex post (except perhaps whether the expression was copied from someone else51 or is an unprotected idea52) in order to know whether a particular fixation satisfies the legal requirement for initial allocation of a work to its author. Other aspects of the copyright system look more like standards, such as the “substantial similarity” test for infringement53 (which has been clarified to the point of near-rule-dom through decades of precedent) and the notoriously indeterminate fair use defense54 (not so much). For an author, there remain three relevant points in time: promulgation (when Congress adopts a new provision of copyright law), choice (in this case, the choice to invest in creative activity that will result in allocation of the work to the author), and adjudication (an independent determination of the validity of the author’s copyright). When analyzing the behavior of authors (as opposed to legislators and adjudicators), the most relevant moment is the moment of choice. At that time, the author has to decide whether to invest in creative activity that will be protected by the copyright system or in some other behavior, and so at that 50. See 17 U.S.C. § 102(a) (2012) (“Copyright protection subsists, in accordance with this title, in original works of authorship fixed in any tangible medium of expression, now known or later developed, from which they can be perceived, reproduced, or otherwise communicated, either directly or with the aid of a machine or device.”). 51. Id. § 103(b). 52. Id. § 102(b). 53. See Nichols v. Universal Pictures Corp., 45 F.2d 119, 121 (2d Cir. 1930). 54. 17 U.S.C. § 107. Do Not Delete 2014] 11/30/2014 3:42 PM RULES AND STANDARDS IN COPYRIGHT 597 time, the author needs to know the content of the copyright law of allocation. For instance, it would be important for a potential author to know that if she invests in creating a compilation of facts, the facts themselves will not be protected by the copyright system because that information may affect her decision to invest in creating the compilation. The three-period approach, as confronted by an author deciding whether to invest in creation, can be displayed on a timeline that looks roughly like this: The nature of copyright, though, presents a complication to Kaplow’s three-period approach to the application of rules and standards. Because the copyright system enables reallocation through use, a potential user also faces a choice: whether to engage in a use of a work that has previously been allocated to an author.55 The points of promulgation and adjudication do not change (the user is interested in both the law of allocation and the law of reallocation, and those may be created at different times, but they are both likely to have predated the original allocation, and so for the parties’ purposes, they might as well be at a single point in time prior to any choice, and in virtually all copyright infringement cases, there will be a single point of adjudication to determine the validity of both the initial allocation and the legality of the reallocation), and so Kaplow’s three-period model can accommodate the allocation/reallocation structure of the copyright system by including not one but two points of “choice” relevant to a legal determination regarding use of any particular copyrightprotected work: (1) Promulgation (2) Choice by an author to invest in authorship (3) Choice by a user to engage in use (4) Adjudication 55. The copyright system also enables transactional reallocations, so it is possible that the point of choice for a reallocation will be when a potential buyer of the work will have to choose whether to purchase the work, and that point of choice similarly requires information about the legal content of the copyright system. While my analysis similarly applies to transactional reallocations, the informational problems facing buyers are considerably lower than those facing users, so I will focus on reallocation through use rather than transactional reallocation. Similarly, I will for the most part ignore potential reallocations to buyers that occur between the time of the original allocation to the author and the time of use, treating “author” and “rightsholder” as synonymous because such transfers, while frequent, are largely irrelevant to my analysis. Do Not Delete 598 11/30/2014 3:42 PM HOUSTON LAW REVIEW [52:2 Thus, a model of ex ante and ex post information as applied to the copyright system contains four rather than three stages, with two separate stages of choice: Stage 2, at which time the potential author chooses whether to invest in authorship that results in allocation of the work to the author and Stage 3, at which time the potential user chooses whether to engage in a use that results in partial reallocation of the work to the user. The author-choice three-period timeline thus adapted to include the possibility of use (and reallocation) looks more like this: Accounting for Kaplow’s recognition of the temporal dimension to rules and standards, then, the question is not whether the copyright system best functions using rules or standards but, rather, the appropriateness of each at each of the four time stages relevant to the creation and use of a particular work. Moreover, what information is known as “ex ante” and “ex post” at the point of choice is different for the author and the user because the author’s choice occurs before the user’s. Outlining the availability of information for the different parties on the list above, it looks something like this: Ex ante for information about both allocation and reallocation (1) Promulgation Ex ante for information about both allocation and reallocation (2) Choice by an author to invest in authorship Ex post for information about allocation (author) Ex ante for information about reallocation (user) (3) Choice by a user to engage in use Ex post for information about both allocation and reallocation (4) Adjudication Displayed along our timeline: Do Not Delete 2014] 11/30/2014 3:42 PM RULES AND STANDARDS IN COPYRIGHT 599 If information were costless, the copyright system would provide rules to both authors and users prior to their points of choice so that they could make the most informed investment decisions.56 Thus, all things being equal, the copyright system would utilize rules rather than standards for both allocation and reallocation.57 As described above, the copyright system provides rule-like legal directives regarding allocation (the fixation standard), thus minimizing the decision cost faced by potential authors at their point of choice. The question, then, is how rule-like the regulations regarding reallocation can be. Here, there is less consistency. Some reallocation directives are generally rule-like and require little information about the particular use (such as the exclusion of reading as one of the rights allocated to authors) while others require much more information about the particular use (such as the reach of the derivative works right and the fair use defense). Generally, reallocations involving consumptive uses tend to look more like rules and those regarding productive uses tend to look more like standards, which makes sense if the effect of productive uses on the underlying work is more highly variable than the effect of consumptive uses. Mandatory reallocation schemes, like compulsory licensing, provide rules for reallocation, reducing the decision cost faced by users, but again, tend to be for consumptive rather than productive uses. For instance, the mechanical license to cover a previously published sound recording expressly limits the degree to which the use can be productive (how much the cover can creatively alter the underlying song) and still qualify for the license.58 And here there is another point that requires some clarification of Kaplow’s rules/standards framework: The Kaplow framework is designed to describe how government creates law in terms of information about legal content.59 But the relevant information is information about how the legal directive will be 56. The situation is actually somewhat more complicated than even this simplified case suggests. An “author” in one context is a “user” in another—very few authors write on a truly blank slate (a feature I account for by including the case of productive uses). Thus, rather than a timeline, a more complete picture would be a cycle in which a use becomes the fodder for the next user/author’s creation. Introducing the complexity of a dynamic understanding does not alter the essential temporal nature of the decision points faced by each author or user and unnecessarily complicates matters, especially when one includes the points of promulgation and adjudication. Consequently, I have ignored (or at least limited myself to first-order) dynamic effects in my analysis. 57. See Korobkin, supra note 41, at 41 (discussing the advantage of rules for facilitating transactions). 58. See 17 U.S.C. § 115(a)(2) (“[T]he arrangement shall not change the basic melody or fundamental character of the work . . . .”). 59. Kaplow, supra note 39, at 568 (“[T]he problem of creating the law can be interpreted as one involving the government’s acquisition and dissemination of information.”). Do Not Delete 600 11/30/2014 3:42 PM HOUSTON LAW REVIEW [52:2 applied to any particular set of facts, and so Kaplow necessarily includes information about the underlying facts with information about legal directives in the abstract, as would any legislator attempting to formulate a rule to apply to future sets of facts, any lawyer providing advice to a client, or any judge rendering an adjudication.60 We can assume that everyone has roughly similar information about the underlying law throughout,61 but at Stage 3, when the potential user chooses whether or not to reallocate through use, there is, in addition to the information about the law of reallocation, a considerable amount of information about the original allocation itself—not necessarily information about the legal content of the allocation but information about the amount of wealth created by the allocation (and therefore, potentially available for reallocation through use). In the language of copyright law, because potential infringers can observe the value of previously created works, they can pick and choose among the universe of works in order to avoid wasting their time using (and possibly infringing) worthless ones. Returning to the language of rules and standards, the advantage of rules over standards is in allowing determinations to be made without much information about an action, but the universe of actions relevant to a use include not only the act of use but, also, information about the original allocation, which suggests that, as between authorship and use, use is more amenable to application of a standard because more information is available when the user chooses whether to use than was available when the author chose whether to create. The same point is doubly true after the use is made because, in addition to information about the value of the original allocation, we now have information about the value of the use itself. It is the increase in available information following both creation and use that underlies calls to push infringement towards a standards-based regime because a standard will allow adjudicators to include that additional information in their determinations.62 60. See id. at 585 n.71 (“The term ‘information’ is used here to include anything relevant to reaching a better decision, whether facts or understandings that can be improved through greater discussion and reflection.”). 61. The distinction between facts and law is more important in this case than in the case Kaplow examined because it is information about facts that constitutes the primary difference between the information that the author has at Stage 2 and the information the user has at Stage 3. 62. See Kaplow, supra note 39, at 616 (arguing that as information, conditions, and perceived values change over time, standards are easier to keep up to date than rules). Of course, the effect of this additional information (as discovered in work by some of the same scholars who advance an increased use of standards for infringement determinations) could be advanced as a reason to reduce the amount of information available to adjudicators. See Do Not Delete 2014] 11/30/2014 3:42 PM RULES AND STANDARDS IN COPYRIGHT 601 Thus, at the point that the potential user chooses whether to attempt a reallocation through use, whether a rule or a standard is (relatively) superior depends on whether one looks at it from the perspective of an author or a potential user. From the potential user’s standpoint, a rule is preferable in order to allow him to correctly evaluate whether to invest in use. From the author’s standpoint, a standard is preferable because a standard will better account for the wealth potential of the work as a whole and thus the magnitude of the effects of any future use.63 Even better for the author would be information about the future use itself because different uses will have different wealth effects. Information about the use doesn’t yet exist at Stage 3—we won’t know about the actual use and its wealth effects until Stage 4. What does exist at Stage 3 is information about the potential user’s future intent, but that information is held by the potential user and is not readily discoverable without the potential user’s cooperation. V. RULES, STANDARDS, AND REFORM Having a model of how rules and standards work in copyright, the question remains what rules and standards have to say for recent reform proposals. I take the three types of proposals in turn: compulsory licenses, damages-only regimes, and requiring authors to provide additional information, usually about the work, the use, or the markets for either.64 A. Compulsory Licenses Even a cursory understanding of how rules and standards work in the copyright system’s allocation and reallocation of works demonstrates that rule-based proposals for reform such as compulsory licenses are ill-advised. As rules, compulsory licenses can rely on information available only at Stage 1: when the rule is Shyamkrishna Balganesh, Irina D. Manta & Tess Wilkinson-Ryan, Judging Similarity, 100 IOWA L. REV. (forthcoming 2014) (arguing that, because experiments show that information about the nature of use and users can affect substantial similarity determinations, the substantial similarity test is itself inherently subjective). 63. One might argue that an author might also prefer a rule marginally less because she is not at a point of choice and so does not benefit from the determinacy of a rule as much as the potential user does, but that is not so. First, the author values determinacy for the same reasons the potential user does—to know what the overall allocation is, which is information necessary to engaging in transactional reallocation. Second, the author herself may be considering a future use (such as the creation of a derivative work) and will want to know the degree to which she can capture the additional wealth created by that work, much as would another user. For simplicity, I will assume the simple case as between authors and users, ignoring that authors may themselves be users of their own works. 64. See supra text accompanying notes 7–20. Do Not Delete 602 11/30/2014 3:42 PM HOUSTON LAW REVIEW [52:2 promulgated. When it comes to industries developing as rapidly as content industries (and the associated technologies for creating, distributing, and consuming content), there is simply too much information that develops (a great deal of it between Stage 1 and Stage 2, much less between Stage 1 and Stage 3, when users must make use decisions) to countenance the rigidity of a rule.65 History is strewn with examples of attempts to engineer rulebased reallocation regimes that have either failed or succeeded in pushing creative industries in completely unforeseen and unintended directions.66 For instance, the Audio Home Recording Act (AHRA)67 established a technology-based levy engineered to allow the use of a wondrous, new technology—digital recording media—to make nearly perfect copies of music without destroying the recording industry—a regulatory model that was essentially dead-on-arrival because of the limited demand for the media subject to the AHRA levy.68 The recording media subject to the AHRA levy have almost completely disappeared from the market in favor of computer-based recording technologies, which are not covered by the AHRA.69 The error represented by the AHRA is doubly disconcerting because it is impossible to determine whether the shift to computer-based recording is independent of the AHRA’s levy (representing a mistaken prediction by Congress in 1992 about the technological direction of audio home recording) or is partially the result of it (that the AHRA levy itself has harmed the ability of non-computer-based audio home recording to compete with its un-taxed cousin). This second, endogenous, 65. Cf. Korobkin, supra note 41, at 33–34 (describing the heterogeneity that generally militates in favor of standards, including the “chronological heterogeneity” of technological change). 66. E.g., Robert P. Merges, Compulsory Licensing vs. the Three “Golden Oldies”: Property Rights, Contracts, and Markets, POL’Y ANALYSIS, Jan. 15, 2004, at 1, 9; see also Robert P. Merges, Contracting into Liability Rules: Intellectual Property Rights and Collective Rights Organizations, 84 CALIF. L. REV. 1293, 1308–16 (1996) [hereinafter Merges, Contracting into Liability Rules] (describing the durability of the sub-optimal mechanical license, which was intended to permit a diverse market for piano rolls, but now serves as a below-market-price source of content for record companies). 67. Audio Home Recording Act of 1992, Pub. L. No. 102-563, 106 Stat. 4237 (codified at 17 U.S.C. §§ 1001–1010 (2012)) (requiring implementation of a system that prevents serial copying of works recorded on digital audio recording media and a royalty payment system). 68. See, e.g., Lemley & Reese, supra note 8, at 1407 (explaining that the AHRA has not been used “because the digital audio recording systems covered by the Act never caught on”); Netanel, supra note 8, at 33 (“The AHRA might serve as useful precedent for the NUL, but its levy provisions have largely remained a dead letter because the market for digital cassette recorders and other single-purpose devices for digitally recording music never developed.”). 69. See Recording Indus. Ass’n of Am. v. Diamond Multimedia Sys. Inc., 180 F.3d 1072, 1078 (9th Cir. 1999). Do Not Delete 2014] 11/30/2014 3:42 PM RULES AND STANDARDS IN COPYRIGHT 603 potential effect of the AHRA highlights just how ill-conceived government price-setting in innovation markets really is. In terms of rules and standards, the problem is that, at Stage 1, legislatures may have no idea that the use at Stage 3 will even exist, making it likely that compulsory licenses will necessarily favor uses that already exist at Stage 1 and privilege those existing uses over the creation of new uses.70 The failed lessons of compulsory licensing as an innovation strategy are frequently lost on compulsory license proponents; some who advocate a levy system not only mention the AHRA as a model but, also point out that it is essentially defunct because of the limited demand for the media subject to the AHRA levy,71 apparently without appreciating that the AHRA’s failure is itself reason to reconsider the approach it embodies. The wide variety of both works and uses means that while rule-based regimes are likely to either be irrelevant, or worse derail progress, they are certain to incur tremendous cost at the point of promulgation. There is no better example of the incalculable costs of government rate-setting in copyright markets than the recent experience of the webcasting compulsory licenses.72 In 1995 and 1998, respectively, Congress passed the Digital Performance Right in Sound Recordings Act (DPRA)73 and the Digital Millennium Copyright Act (DMCA),74 which, in combination, established an exclusive right to perform sound recordings by digital transmission75 as well as a compulsory license available to webcasters who wish to perform those sound recordings over the Internet.76 The new statute also established a 70. See Thomas B. Nachbar, Monopoly, Mercantilism, and the Politics of Regulation, 91 VA. L. REV. 1313, 1374–75 (2005). 71. See supra note 68. 72. As I use the term, “webcasting” is the transmission over the Internet (usually the World Wide Web) of sound recordings. The sound recordings are sent piecemeal over the Internet and reassembled on the user’s computer for playing, but they are not stored on the user’s computer and cannot (theoretically) be copied to other media or played again at a later time. 73. Digital Performance Right in Sound Recordings Act of 1995, Pub. L. No. 104-39, 109 Stat. 336 (codified at 17 U.S.C. §§ 106, 114–115 (2012)). 74. Digital Millennium Copyright Act, Pub. L. No. 105-304, 112 Stat. 2860 (1998) (codified in scattered sections of 17 U.S.C.). 75. See 17 U.S.C. § 106(6). There is no exclusive right to perform sound recordings by analog transmission. Analog radio stations, for instance, are not required to pay any royalties to the owners of copyrights in the sound recordings they play; they need a license from, and consequently pay royalties to, only the owners of the copyrights in the underlying compositions. See id. § 106(4). 76. My exposition is a dramatic oversimplification of the provisions, which are several pages long. See id. § 114. My discussion touches upon only one form of webcast service: noninteractive, nonsubscription webcasting. Subscription services and interactive services (which allow the user to specify the selection and order in which the songs are played) are treated differently under the statute. See id. Do Not Delete 604 11/30/2014 3:42 PM HOUSTON LAW REVIEW [52:2 mechanism for determining the compulsory license rates: First, it provided the recording industry with an exemption to the antitrust laws that allowed the major record companies to negotiate and set prices as a single block.77 Second, the Act provided for a period of negotiations, and in the event of their failure, the establishment of a Copyright Arbitration Royalty Panel (CARP) to set license rates for a two-year period based on the rates it imagined “a willing buyer and a willing seller” would agree to in a wellfunctioning market.78 As the (statutorily required) negotiation began, the (statutorily created) cartel’s negotiating strategy was to unfailingly insist on a license rate for small webcasters of $.004 per performance (almost six times the final license rate) in an attempt to generate high-priced agreements as precedent for the CARP proceedings certain to follow.79 As anticipated by all, the negotiations fell through, and the first CARP was quickly called.80 To approximate the hypothetical willing-buyer/willing-seller rates, the CARP looked to the twenty-six agreements that the (statutorily created) cartel of record companies had successfully negotiated as part of its plan to influence the outcome of the CARP proceedings.81 Of the twenty-six existing agreements, the CARP disqualified all but one,82 effectively setting the rates to be charged all webcasters based on a single agreement between the Recording Industry Association of America (RIAA) and Yahoo!, one of the 77. Id. § 114(e)(1). 78. Id. § 114(f)(1)(A), (2)(B), (C)(ii) (2000). Of course, the very need for a compulsory license establishes that the as yet nonexistent market contained neither willing buyers nor willing sellers. 79. Rate Setting for Digital Performance Right in Sound Recordings and Ephemeral Recordings, Docket No. 2000-9, CARP DTRA 1 & 2, Interim Public Version at 47–50 (Feb. 20, 2002) (U.S. Copyright Office, Report of the Copyright Arbitration Royalty Panel), available at http://www.copyright.gov/carp/webcasting_rates.pdf [hereinafter CARP Report]. 80. Digital Performance Right in Sound Recordings and Ephemeral Recordings, 64 Fed. Reg. 52,107, 52,107–08 (Sept. 27, 1999); CARP Report, supra note 79, at 10–11. The CARP was supposed to set the royalty rates for the period 1998–2000, but that CARP took so long in constituting itself that those proceedings were consolidated with the proceedings for 2000–2002. See CARP Report, supra note 79, at 105. 81. CARP Report, supra note 79, at 45–46. 82. Twenty-one of them were disqualified because the webcasters either had paid little or no actual royalties under the agreements or had ceased operating. Id. at 51–54. Two more were disqualified because the webcasters had agreed to the licenses under exogenous, idiosyncratic time constraints that prevented them from waiting for the results of the CARP proceeding itself. Id. at 54–56. One was disqualified because it was in settlement of litigation and contained a most-favored-nation clause that made pricing dependent on the lowest prices the RIAA eventually gave to others (both defects in some degree of the agreement the CARP eventually used as a model, see infra note 88), and one was disqualified because the CARP found it was superficially irrational for the webcaster to agree to the license in the first place. CARP Report, supra note 79, at 56–59. Do Not Delete 2014] 11/30/2014 3:42 PM RULES AND STANDARDS IN COPYRIGHT 605 largest and most heavily capitalized Internet companies in the world.83 Based on that agreement, the CARP chose a rate of $.0014 per performance for “Internet-only” digital transmissions and $.0007 for webcasts that were retransmissions of radio broadcasts (“radio retransmissions”).84 The CARP justified the difference as representing the increased “promotional value” enjoyed by copyright owners whose songs are played over the radio at the same time they are webcast,85 even though it found elsewhere in the report that the very existence of the separate rates in the Yahoo! agreement was the product of collusion between the RIAA and Yahoo! in yet another attempt to generate inflated license rates to serve as precedent for the CARP proceeding.86 When the CARP’s final report was reviewed by the Register of Copyrights, she injected a grain of much-needed reason by rejecting the two-tiered approach,87 but the single rate she chose was still based on the price stipulated by the single Yahoo! agreement without any regard to the agreement’s other terms.88 Instead, the Register Solomonically chose $.0007 per song, a rounded average between the two different license rates paid by Yahoo! under the agreement,89 a rate roughly ten times the rate charged by performing rights societies for use of the underlying musical works in over-the-air radio broadcasts.90 83. CARP Report, supra note 79, at 60–61. 84. Id. at 75–78. 85. Id. at 74–75. 86. Id. at 64–67 (noting that because most of Yahoo!’s webcasts were radio retransmissions, they were willing to take a sharply inflated Internet-only rate in exchange for a slightly decreased radio retransmission rate to achieve the lowest overall effective rate). 87. See Determination of Reasonable Rates and Terms for the Digital Performance of Sound Recordings and Ephemeral Recordings, 67 Fed. Reg. 45,240, 45,243 (July 8, 2002) (codified at 37 C.F.R. pt. 261) [hereinafter LoC Rate Determination]. The scheme to determine rates calls for review of the CARP determination by the Librarian of Congress upon recommendation by the Register of Copyrights. Id. at 45,242 (citing 17 U.S.C. § 802(f) (2012)). 88. See id. at 45,255. The existence of similar (if not identical) terms to those in the Yahoo! agreement were cause for the CARP to disqualify another one of the twenty-six agreements as precedent. See supra note 82. 89. LoC Rate Determination, supra note 87, at 45,255. 90. See Copyright Royalties: Where Is the Right Spot on the Dial for Webcasting?: Hearing Before the S. Comm. on the Judiciary, 107th Cong. 145 (2002) (statement of Jonathan Potter, Executive Director, Digital Media Association). While analog radio stations are not required to obtain rights from the owners of copyrights in the sound recordings they play, they are required to get permission from the owners of copyrights in the underlying musical works, a process coordinated by three major “performance rights organizations” (ASCAP, BMI, and SESAC), which grant blanket licenses to radio stations to play their members’ music. Mr. Potter’s comparison is based on the rates charged radio stations by the performance rights organizations for the right to broadcast those underlying musical works. See id. Do Not Delete 606 11/30/2014 3:42 PM HOUSTON LAW REVIEW [52:2 The chosen rate proved to be so unworkable that it took Congress less than six months to devise and execute an alternative scheme that pushed the interested parties to negotiate a more realistic set of rates based on the size of each webcaster.91 But for an infusion of rationality from Congress (from Congress!), the CARP’s administrative rate setting would have wiped out Internet webcasting in its infancy at an estimated administrative cost of $25 million.92 Of course, there is no way to estimate the lost value to the economy of the more than four years (encompassing both the inflation and burst of the “Internet bubble”) the process ate up before it was effectively scrapped for a solution based on a decadesold rate scheme adopted by private parties under the supervision of no one but the antitrust enforcers.93 Although it received a great deal of attention due to its rocky first few steps, the path to the digital distribution of music over the Internet, which is governed by nothing more publicly minded than strong intellectual property rights and unabashed market pricing, has been a comparative walk in the park.94 Whether the disastrous experience of the CARP was a product of incompetence or greed is irrelevant. Attempts to generate ideal markets by altering the basic rules of exchange through compulsory licensing are equal invitation to both. Government interference with the operation of free pricing is always tempting 91. Small Webcaster Settlement Act of 2002, Pub. L. No. 107-321, 116 Stat. 2780 (codified at 17 U.S.C. § 114(f)–(g)). 92. See Copyright Royalty and Distribution Reform Act of 2003: Hearing on H.R. 1417 Before the Subcomm. on Courts, the Internet, and Intellectual Prop. of the H. Comm. on the Judiciary, 108th Cong. 31 (2003) (statement of Michael J. Remington, Attorney-At-Law & Partner, Drinker Biddle & Reath, LLP); Brian Flavin, A Digital Cry for Help: Internet Radio’s Struggle to Survive a Second Royalty Rate Determination Under the Willing Buyer/Willing Seller Standard, 27 ST. LOUIS U. PUB. L. REV. 427, 453 (2008) (noting that Congress rescued internet webcasters from being driven out of business by enacting the Small Webcaster Settlement Act of 2002). Over one million dollars went to the arbitrator’s expenses alone. Paige Albiniak, CARP is Thrown Back, BROADCASTING & CABLE, May 27, 2002, at 14. 93. See Am. Soc’y of Composers, Authors & Publishers v. Showtime/The Movie Channel, Inc., 912 F.2d 563, 564–65 (2d Cir. 1990) (describing antitrust court’s supervision over performing rights organizations under consent agreement); Lemley & Weiser, supra note 11, at 828–29 & n.223, 836 (noting the new system implemented by Congress is similar to system that the CARP decision replaced and that federal antitrust court is final overseer of pricing structures). 94. After the rights of copyright owners to control digital distribution of their works were confirmed in A&M Records, Inc. v. Napster, Inc., it was only a matter of months before music became widely available for licensed download on the Internet and less than two years before the launch of the wildly popular iTunes, which celebrated in 2013 its 25billionth download. See A&M Records, Inc. v. Napster, Inc., 239 F.3d 1004, 1027 (9th Cir. 2001); iTunes Store Sets New Record with 25 Billion Songs Sold, APPLE (Feb. 6, 2013), http://www.apple.com/pr/library/2013/02/06iTunes-Store-Sets-New-Record-with-25-Billion -Songs-Sold.html. With 15,000 songs downloaded per minute, Apple appears to have stopped publicly announcing new “billion” marks of accumulated music downloads. Id. Do Not Delete 2014] 11/30/2014 3:42 PM RULES AND STANDARDS IN COPYRIGHT 607 for those who do not like the outcomes generated by unregulated markets, but a solution so amenable to rent-seeking is likely to lead to a “vicious circle” of increasing regulation as interested parties demand tighter restrictions in order to correct for the injustices created by previous ones.95 Congress’s structural response to the webcasting debacle has not been to eliminate the market restrictions that naturally and inexorably caused it but, rather, to replace the CARP with a panel of “Copyright Royalty Judges,” collectively the “Copyright Royalty Board” (CRB), whose roles are extended to cover the full array of copyright compulsory licenses.96 It is not clear the CRB’s deliberations have been any more successful, although their docket is balanced out with licenses covering more static industries, such as cable television. If the hope of relying on royalty “judges” was to insulate compulsory license determinations from political pressure, that hope appears to have been either hopelessly naïve or simply extremely formalist. From the standpoint of industry participants, the CRB is a direct substitute for lobbying Congress for protectionist legislation.97 From the standpoint of rules and standards (as well as fundamental political economics), compulsory licenses are decidedly lacking, partly because they must price both the author’s initial investment decision and the user’s use decision at a time when neither the work nor the use (nor, necessarily, even authors or users themselves) exist. The question, then, is whether reforms coming in the form of standards can do any better. B. Damages-Only Regimes and Additional Showings Although they are distinct proposals, damages-only regimes and additional showings are identical from the perspective of rules and standards because both enlist ex post information in making determinations. The difficulty in evaluating such proposals is that they seek to not only incorporate additional information, they generally seek to shift the identity of the decision-maker from the author at Stage 3 (deciding whether or not to license a use) to a 95. See Anne O. Krueger, The Political Economy of the Rent-Seeking Society, 64 AM. ECON. REV. 291, 302 (1974). 96. Copyright Royalty and Distribution Reform Act of 2004, Pub. L. No. 108-419, 118 Stat. 2341 (codified as amended at 17 U.S.C. §§ 801–805). 97. See, e.g., Glenn Peoples, TKO or Split Decision?, BILLBOARD, Nov. 30, 2013, at 5, 5 (“Pandora has given up its efforts to seek legislation that would help reduce the royalties paid to rights holders, a source knowledgeable with the decision tells Billboard. Instead of pursuing legislation, Pandora will focus its efforts on lobbying the Copyright Royalty Board (CRB), the three-judge panel that sets statutory rates for webcasters like Pandora. The current rates run through 2015.”). Do Not Delete 608 11/30/2014 3:42 PM HOUSTON LAW REVIEW [52:2 factfinder at Stage 4 (deciding the outcome of a copyright lawsuit). For some proposals, the shift in identity of decision-maker is as important as the shift in time, premised as they are on the possibility of economically irrational conduct on the part of authors.98 Concentrating solely on the temporal shift, what these proposals do is deny certainty at Stage 3 in order to obtain a better result at Stage 4. Few such proposals seem to be concerned about the harm to certainty on the author’s part (none that I have read, and some are indifferent to authors at any time after Stage 2 by design99), but there is an equal harm to users’ certainty at Stage 3 because both author and user will have to wait until Stage 4 to find out the legal consequences of the use. This delay likely impacts users more than authors because users will have to potentially make substantial investments in use at Stage 3 (while authors will have already made their investment in creation back at Stage 2). Rather than concern over ex ante versus ex post determinations, such proposals seem to be aimed at a straightforward policy goal: lowering the expected cost users will face from an infringement lawsuit either by reducing their likely economic harm (it will be capped at the judge’s determination of damages) or by reducing the likelihood of being found to infringe (by adding elements to the infringement determination).100 Authors could just as irrationally (but consistently) argue that their losses to infringers have been too high, and therefore, Congress should treble all copyright damages or eliminate one of the elements of infringement (any one will do!). In order to understand such proposals from the perspectives of rules and standards, one would need to evaluate proposals that provide the same expected value of litigation but differ only on the time of determination. Such measurement is not possible for the current crop of decidedly one-sided proposals for which the intended goal of reducing the expected cost of litigation likely swamps the effect of having additional information at the time of determination. 98. See supra note 14. 99. See supra note 17. 100. Compare supra notes 17–19 (discussing the many proposals for additional showings), with Sara K. Stadler, Copyright as Trade Regulation, 155 U. PA. L. REV. 899, 899, 939, 954, 957 (2007) (arguing for several changes to the copyright statute, including no liability for personal copying, preempting overreaching licensing rules, and a reinvigorated fair use defense on the grounds that “only acts of public distribution are behaviors that threaten to cause the sorts of competitive harms that Congress should seek to redress”). Do Not Delete 2014] 11/30/2014 3:42 PM RULES AND STANDARDS IN COPYRIGHT 609 Ignoring the intended distributive effects of these proposals, the question from the perspective of rules versus standards is whether the decrease in certainty (to both author and user) at Stage 3 is outweighed by the increase in information between Stage 3 and Stage 4. That is a question that has gone unanswered by those arguing for either more damages-only regimes or additional showings. C. Taking Rules and Standards Seriously Most copyright reform proposals seem to be concerned with increasing access (rather than incentives),101 and if one is serious about facilitating access, the real question is how to reconcile the conflicting needs of authors and users at Stage 3, when potential users must choose whether or not to attempt a reallocation through use. A rule of forced reallocation at Stage 3—such as a compulsory license—ignores the information available at that point about the value of the underlying work. Proposals for the application of standards for reallocation are premised on the availability of this additional information (and more) but necessarily argue for the application of those standards at Stage 4—by a court in an adjudication102—which ignores the value to the user of having a reliable determination at Stage 3. The key to finding the right balance is to focus on the nature of the information available at Stage 3, or, rather, the change in available information between Stage 2, when the author chooses whether to create, and Stage 3, when the user chooses whether to use. 101. See Stadler, supra note 100, at 916, 942 (arguing copyright holders should be given exclusive public distribution rights but not exclusive reproduction rights so public can “gain increased access to copyrighted works”); see also Glynn S. Lunney, Jr., Fair Use and Market Failure: Sony Revisited, 82 B.U. L. REV. 975, 1026 (2002) (arguing courts should consider increase in access private copying achieves as opposed to assuming private copying has same economic consequences as copying by competitor). 102. Some proposals for standards attempt to reconstruct at Stage 4 the reasonable expectations of authors at Stage 1. See, e.g., Balganesh, supra note 1, at 1571 (“[T]his Article proposes a test of ‘foreseeable copying’ to limit copyright’s grant of exclusivity to situations where a copier’s use was reasonably foreseeable at the time of creation . . . .”). This is a call for something akin to a standards time machine—applying a standard (foreseeability) at Stage 4 but discarding the information accumulated at Stages 2 and 3, the availability of which provides the primary advantage of a standard over a rule. Perhaps meritorious as an attempt to avoid hindsight bias, see id. at 1631–32, such a proposal represents (in terms of rules and standards) the worst of both worlds. On the problems inherent in the application of such an approach in the specific case of copyright, see Wendy J. Gordon, Response: Trespass-Copyright Parallels and the Harm-Benefit Distinction, 122 HARV. L. REV. F. 62, 75–76 (2009); Wendy J. Gordon, An Inquiry into the Merits of Copyright: The Challenges of Consistency, Consent, and Encouragement Theory, 41 STAN. L. REV. 1343, 1387 (1989). Do Not Delete 610 11/30/2014 3:42 PM HOUSTON LAW REVIEW [52:2 It is important to remember that the act of use is specific to a particular underlying work (and therefore, the original allocation). This has two important consequences from the perspective of rules and standards: First, the likelihood that the potential user will be materially harmed by wrongly being denied reallocation through use at Stage 3 is very small because the potential user has not yet invested in use and therefore, is free to use other works.103 Second, and much more importantly, the marginal benefit of using a standard rather than a rule for determining whether to allow a reallocation by use is itself specific to the underlying work. The relative increase in information between Stage 2 and Stage 3 is limited to information about the work, and thus, any shift along the continuum from rule toward standard should also be limited to information about the underlying work.104 The best information about the value of a particular work is more likely to be held by the work’s author (or current rightsholder, whom I’ve previously combined with the author for the purpose of analysis) than anyone else, and so, in a world where information is costly, optimal determinations about whether to allow a particular reallocation are most likely made through the application of standards by authors. I am hardly the first person to propose such a regime.105 Indeed, it is the regime we currently operate under because broad reproduction, derivative-use, and public-performance rights (all of which are allocated by the copyright system to authors) limit the availability of reallocations by use, pushing many potential users to negotiate with authors in order to obtain transactional reallocations instead. Nor is there any lack of criticisms of such a regime—most reform proposals originate in exactly such a 103. In economic terms, at Stage 3, the user has not yet made any asset-specific investments in use of the underlying work, and so he suffers no stranded costs if he is refused use. See generally Oliver E. Williamson, Transaction-Cost Economics: The Governance of Contractual Relations, 22 J.L. & ECON. 233 (1979) (discussing the economics of transaction costs). The wrongly refused potential user likely suffers some opportunityrelated harm because he will have to move on to a use that he likely values somewhat less than he values use of this particular work. The amount of that harm is measured by the marginal market power that any particular work possesses over other similar works (and thus the cost imposed by a wrongful denial likely approximates zero). See Edmund W. Kitch, Elementary and Persistent Errors in the Economic Analysis of Intellectual Property, 53 VAND. L. REV. 1727, 1729–34 (2000); see also Liu, supra note 6, at 256–63 (explaining the relative lack of holdup in modern copyright markets). 104. Moreover, because the use will be specific to a work, any rule of reallocation should also be specific to the work. Because reallocation of a particular work is likely to be a very infrequent event, the high cost of setting a rule is unlikely to be regained through repeated application of the rule. See supra text accompanying notes 47–49; see also Kaplow, supra note 39, at 621 (“The central factor influencing the desirability of rules and standards is the frequency with which a law will govern conduct.”). 105. See, e.g., Merges, Contracting into Liability Rules, supra note 66, at 1308–16. Do Not Delete 2014] 11/30/2014 3:42 PM RULES AND STANDARDS IN COPYRIGHT 611 criticism. There may be good reasons to criticize the current regime, but reform proposals cannot ignore the implications of rules and standards for how they would alter the existing regime. From the perspective of rules and standards, the main difference between the current regime and most proposals106 is the time at which the determination is made—they shift the reallocation determination to Stage 4. In terms of available information, the only real change in available information between Stage 3 and Stage 4 is about the value (positive and negative) of the use. Most proposals are, unsurprisingly, premised in the assumption that uses are systematically undervalued, and so they seek to incorporate more information about use in reallocation determinations. That increase in information is offset (either partially or completely) by the decrease in the factfinder’s ability (relative to the author) to obtain information about the value of the work.107 In the end, it’s not clear that there are any information advantages to be gained. What is certain is that the loss of certainty at Stage 3—a loss felt largely by users—is not offset in any meaningful way. As a result, the effect on authors is indeterminate and the effect on users is likely negative. VI. CONCLUSION Few copyright reformers are likely consumed with the question of where their reform proposals fit in the continuum between “rules” and “standards.” But the rules/standards debate, being at its essence one about the timing of decisions, highlights the structure of the copyright system in ways that most reform proposals ignore. Looking at the copyright system through the lens of rules and standards helps us recognize the nature of the copyright system as a system of allocations and reallocations and emphasizes the various stages in time over 106. Here I am excluding compulsory licenses, to which I’ve provided ample attention above. 107. One set of reform proposals is premised on the possibility that authors/rightsholders might be irrational in making value determinations. See supra note 14. There is, of course, no reason to think copyright rightsholders are marginally more irrational than either owners of tangible property (one could use an identical argument to support a damages-only rule applied to all property rights) or users, whose own self-serving biases are also likely at play. See Korobkin, supra note 41, at 46–47 (describing self-serving bias in the application of rules and standards). Even putting such concerns aside, though, that authors may exercise their rights irrationally doesn’t change the fact that authors have much better information about the value of a work than either the user or a neutral factfinder. In the end, there’s no particular reason to think the increased cost of the information to the neutral factfinder offsets the gain in their rationality, or at the very least, the case has not been made. For those proposals not predicated on the irrationality of authors, of course, there is no benefit to offset the cost of placing the reallocation decision in hands other than the author’s. Do Not Delete 612 11/30/2014 3:42 PM HOUSTON LAW REVIEW [52:2 which the copyright system operates with regard to any particular work: the time at which rules are promulgated, the time at which the author chooses whether to invest in creation, the time at which a user chooses whether to reallocate some aspects of a work through use, and the time at which a disputed reallocation is adjudicated. Critically, for the incentives/access paradigm, there are two separate decision points that are necessary in order to realize the full value of a work: the point at which the author chooses whether to invest in creation and the point at which a user chooses whether to use the work. Only by taking seriously the ex ante and ex post nature of decisions at both of these decision points can we understand the full impact of copyright reform proposals seeking to enlist the certainty of rules or the additional information allowed by standards. When looked at through the lens of rules and standards, some proposals, such as compulsory licensing, are despairingly problematic; seemingly contrary to virtually all we know about choosing between rules and standards. Increased reliance on standards also has its costs. Notably, proposals to move to damages-only regimes, or to require additional showings, exact a price in the form of decreased certainty at precisely the time potential users must choose whether or not to invest in using a work. If we are truly interested in increasing access, adopting a more standards-based approach to copyright is likely to do more harm than good.