747 Internat. J. Math. & Math. Sci. Vol. 8 NO. 4 (1985) 747-754 ON ORDERABILITY OF TOPOLOGICAL GROUPS G. RANGAN The Ramanujan Institute University of Madras Madras-5, India (Received October 15, ]984) ABSTRACT. A necessary and sufficient condition for a topological group whose topology can be induced by a total order compatible with the group structure is given and such groups are called ordered or orderable topological groups. A separable totally- disconnected ordered topological group is proved to be non-archimedean metrizable while the converse is shown to be false by means of an example. A necessary and sufficient condition for a no-totally disconnected locally compact abelian group to be orderable is also given. KEY WORDS AND PHRASES. Topological groups, orderable or ordered topological groups, non-archimedean metrizable, totally disconnected, locally compact abelian groups. 1980 AMS SUBJECT CLASSIFICATION CODES. 22A05, 54F05. I. INTRODUCTION. Topological groups whose topology can be induced by a total order are called top- ologically orderable groups and they are studied by Nyikos and Reichel [i] and Venkataraman, Rajagopalan and Soundarajan [2]. In this paper we give a necessary and sufficient condition so that topological group is orderable in the sense that it admits a total order which ind,,ces the topology of the topological group and which is also compatible with its group structure. We call such groups ordered topological groups. As a first step to this we give a necessary and sufficient condition that a group be orderable so that it admits a totoal order compatible with the group structure and such groups are called ordered groups. shown (Theorem 2.6, [2] Venkataraman, Rajagopalan, and Soundararajan have that a separable totally-disconnected topological group is a topologically orderable group if and only if it is metrizable and zero dimensional. It turns out that a separable totally-disconnected ordered topological group is non- archimedean metrizable (in the sense of Rangan [3]) while the converse fails to be true. It is interesting to note that the totally-disconnected non-archimedean metrizable locally compact abelian topological group (Qp,+) of p-adic numbers under addition admits an order that is compatible with the group structure (+) alone and another order that is compatible with its topology alone but admits no order that is compatible with G. RANGAN 748 + both its group structure and sufficient condition for a non-totally disconnected locally compact abelian group to be orderable. 2. ORERABILITY OF A TOPOLOGICAL GROUP. A group THEOREM 2.1. homomorphism f x G corresponding to each and a into the additive group of real numbers can be found (e e x C(x) can be ordered if and only if a subgrodp C(x) from G) which satisfies the fol- being the identity of lowing conditions and f (x) x xC(x) (i) (ii) for y (iii) for C(x), in x,y C(y) C(x) G in 0 for every C(y) C(x) e, e, y x aC(x)a -I (iv) for every a in G for every t in C(x) i.e. if C(x) and x taining Let PROOF. G ker f x C(x) group of C(x) a -I :x/axa then for each be an ordered group. x C(x)/C(x)* that and C(y) and f where f f x or y x axa z -I f (t) x and is the smallest convex subgroup con- C(x)* x e G in x. C(x) denote the let be the largest convex subgroup not [5]) that C(x)* is a normal sub- is order isomorphic to a subgroup of the reals and we identify this quotient group with the corresponding subgroup of the reals. fx C(x) be the natural map of C(x)* and C(y)* respectively C(x) C(y) C(y) C(x) to C(x)/C(x)* C(y) implies C(x)* C(y)* and hence groups f Hence (i), (ii) C(axa-1) * C(x)/C(x)* I x f aC(x)a C(z)/C(z)* and where z axa -I -I C(y) and If y C(x) I*a C(axa -! Let Since C(y) and (iii) of the theorem are easily verified. induces an order isomorphism a 0 C(x) then being convex subgroups of an ordered group either automorphism being order preserving it follows that aC(x)*a -I fx(X) Then clearly are the largest convex subgroups contained in C(x) -i f oI z a For each and f (ata z is the inner automorphism deter- x Then it i well known (see [4] and x e is the largest convex subgroup not containing smallest convex subgourp containing containing I x O, C(z) G in C(x) G Further for the order on a G in either fy(X) in which case mined by the element x or Inner and between the quotient If we identify these two sub- groups of the reals forgetting the order isomorphism between them we get that f f oI z a x which proves (iv) of the theorem. Conversely if G f (x) > 0 of all elements such that on For G 4=>f x -l(x x e x C(x G C(x) O<x -I) serves as the strict positive part of an ordering by (ii) and hence P. f x f -1 x x P>f x (x) 0 P We now observe a useful property of the subgroups perty P satisfies the conditions of the theorem we show that the set C(x)’s which we call the pro- ORDERABILITY OF tOPOLOGICAL GROUPS PROPERTY P. If a, b G, a ab C(a) e, b C(a) then = C(a) and C(b) and e 749 C(a) C(ab)= C(ba). tion to (i). a If + 0 C(y) + fy(y) C(z) 0. x e P Let where belongs to Similarly it can be seen that C(x) C(y) f f For x axa _ y xy C(x) -1 implies that f (x) > 0 Then f (axa z -1 y e C(x), f C(x) t c xy f (x) > x G C(x) that C(yt -I) C(yt C(x) Suppose C(yt impossible. For C(t) fyt-l(yt -I) f ft(t) 0 yt -1) -l(y) + f and e C(t) C(t -I CASE 2. Then f (x) X f xt f -l(t f (xt -I f (x) + e X x t C(x) C(t) C(xt -I) X -i e (xy) aC(x)a -I axa i.e. z f x f t f (t X -i yt is a convex C(x) and hence thereby proving C(yt fty-I fyt -I ft(t -I y C(x) ). Property P _ and 0 and so fyt-1 since C(yt Thus we get-that (y) -I 0 i.e. C(x) x For this x and let us assume that C(t) c_ C(x) f (x) C(xt 0 The convexity of -i and so since C fx fxt-! f (t -i X implies that We now discuss the two possibilities separately. by C(x). C(x) X -1 We will now show that this is ft This implies e and Property P imply that Hence f (t) C(t) -1 t xy is an ordered group. C(x) -I C(y) c_ C(x) -1) 0 is the smallest convex subgroup containing x, t t f C(x) C(x). -I yt y From the assumption implies yt C(x) can be and is impossible is any conves subgroup containing X -1 C(ty -l(t C(x) C C(x), t e C(t) -I C(t fxt-l(xt C(t In other words We now prove that let us suppose that CASE I. yt -I) a contradiction to the choice of (iii) of the theorem. x C(y-lyt -I) C(yt C(yt -I) C(y condition (ii) of the theorem we get that now implies that implies that C(x) This is done by proving that f If xy e P. f ol (x) z a t < y e C(x), C(xy) C(y) (the case and so To prove the second part of the theorem we first show that subgroup by showing that fxy(Xy)= and O, a contradiction. Now by Theorem 2, p. 13, [4] it follows that P. C(ba). C(y) By (iv) of the theorem we have X f (z) z and C(y) C(y) a contradic- C(a) xy oherwise since C(xy) 0 Now 0 a C(x) f (x) + f (y) y x f (xy) x 0 C(xy) then f (b) f a (b) since and x,y e P i.e. 0 C(ab). By Property P, a e G z + f a (b)f a (a) let us suppose that similarly dealt with). fy(X) f since C(ab) 0 a 0 and hence by (iii) C(x) however f (y) y 0 fy(y) C(y) C(x) C(a) Hence f (x) x f (b) and f a (a) f (ab) C(a) 0 C(ab) fx(X) C(a) C(b) For f (x) x 0 t Now in view of C. > fx(t) and G. RANGAN 750 fx (x) e fx(t) ==fxt-l(xt f (x) x C(x) fx(t) and f C(xt f (xt x Then == fx(t) f n -I x t x In either case CASE 3. f (x) > 0 x for some integer => f xn t -l(xnt -I) = 0 x n > t C(x) 0 n =>f x (xnt -I) e = f -I fx(t). f x C(x) z,y C(x) 0. x i.e. 2 > t _ fx2t-l(x2t-l) e The convexity of C(x) c_ C. x = fx (y) C(x) z > y C(zy Then -I C(x) fx (z) = f -1 x f x C(x) C. C(x) taining Ker f Then since x x 4 C, C(x)* C(t) C. i.e. -1 == 0 f -1 zy C C(x) fx(Xt -I) now implies -I C(x) which x. = -I For let f (zy x fx(Zy -1 0 -I fx(Z) Ker This proves that fx G. is the largest convex subgroup not contain- C is any convex subgroup not containing and so C(t) C x x C(x C(x) -l(zy + f (x) to the reals. fx(Z) _> fx(y) C c_ C(x) by (i) of the theorem and t, C(x) zy C(x)* For this let us suppose that Let C(zy and hence also of It remains for us to show that x C e C(x) C(x) In either case is a convex subgroup of C(t) For is the smallest convex subgroup containing C(zy f (y) f (z) x fx (y) and is convex. C(x2t -I) Now is an order preserving homomorphism from x C since From Property P we get that fx2t-1 t Thus we see that in all cases f C t =>c(xnt -I) 0 C(t). i.e. f (x) x f (xt x since proves that i.e. C. t t e C. that t we conclude that C x. t C. t -I -I nf (x) x which in turn implies that ing by (i) of the THeorem since > 0 Again from the convexity of x. t -I C(x). t If f (t) x 0 x then being the smallest convex subgroup con- a contradiction. Hence f (t) x 0 i.e. This completes the proof of the theorem Even though possibly one can prove Theorem 2.1 in a different way using Theorem 11, p.51 of [4] or Theorem 2 of [5] we have prefered the above proof since it is elementary. The above form of formulating the theorem gives rise in a natural way for a criterion of orderability of a topological group as well. e is the first convex subgroup of REMARK. C, the intersection of all C(x), x e G, x G Hence when C (e) the above theorem gives a necessary and sufficient condition that G may be made into an ordered group without first convex subgroup. THEOREM 2.2. A non-discrete topological group G can be ordered so that the in- terval topology of the order coincides with the given topology and also simultaneously this order is compatible with the group structure of G if and only if G satisfies the following criterion (v) in addition to those of Theorem 2.1. (v) either the intersection of all which case the collection the C(x), x {C(x)} x G, x e is the singleton (e) in G form a neighbouhod base at the ORDERABILITY OF TOPOLOGICAL GROUPS C of e identity or the intersection G is an open subgroup of and for each 751 C of all the x in C f C(x), x e G, x e is an open continuous x homomorphism into the reals. In view of Theorem 2.1, it is enough to show that condition (v) above is PROOF. equivalent to the coincidence of the interval topology and the given topology of the G group Let now G be an ordered group. group (see 4.19 [6]). CASE I. Let a such that t I e in i.e. C f y -I e, t C(x) E I G, x x as in Theorem 2.1. e I are in C(x) t G Then since e and this proves that nC(x) Since t N y implies is not discrete there exists C(x), x (e) G there exists C(x) since is convex. G x Hence form a neighbourhood base of C z (e) oC(x) C is a convex subgroup and hence open in C(x) Hence for C ==f x,y for G CASE 2. Then and y y # C(x) such that C(x)* C(x) and We define be an open interval containing y > e with the interval topology is a topological (e) nC(x) I G f f x C(x)/C(x)* f y C is one-to-one on C, x,y xy f -i C(x) C = 0 f C(y) xy -l(xy For G and so -1 x e G f f(x) x f(y) being the cannonical map from x f C(x) f (say). y ==> f(x) C(x) being order isomorphic to a subgroup of the reals, ous homomorphism from it is clear that f to x x y, f(y) i.e. C(x)/C(x) and is an open continu- to the reals. To prove the converse also we consider two cases. CASE I. nC(x) From Case (e) {C(x)}, x e G {C(x)}, of the necessity part it follows that bourhood base for the interval topology. neighbourhood base at e By hypothesis x e, form a neigh- x e G, x e form a for the given topology and hence the two topologies coincide. CASE 2. oC(x) C z (e) For x,y C, it is clear from the convexity of C(x) and (ii) of Theorem 2.1 that f f f (say) Then f is a one-to-one open continuous homomorphism from C to y x the reals, the topology of of G Hence C C being the relative topology got from the order topology with respect to this (order) topology is homeomorphic to a subgroup of the reals with respect to its relative topology. continuous homomorphism from topology on G onto this subgroup of the reals. the two topologies on on G the two C conincide. topologies on COROLLARY 2.3. Let G But by hypothesis G C e is an open Now f is one-to-one implies that being an open subgroup in both the topologies themselves coincide. be an ordered topological group (i.e. the topology of is giben by a total order compatible with the group structure of ponent of the identity f C, taken with the relative topology got from the given of G is either the trivial subgroup subgroup topologically isomorphic to the additive group of reals. G). (e) G Then the comor it is an open G. RANGAN 752 If (e) by Theorem 2.2 above G becomes a zero dimensional group. PROOF. If oC(x) (e) then C is the component of identity. For, each C(x) being an nC(x) C open and closed subgroup, contains the component of C e and so itself contains the But the component being a connected subgroup is also a convex subgroup (see component. Proposition 1.3(2), [2]) and hence contains C From Theorem 2.2 it follows easily that the component. C which proves that C is the same as is topologically isomorphic to the additive group of reals. 3. TOTALLY DISCONNECTED ORDERED GROUPS. A metric X on a set d is said to be a non-archimedean metric if d satisfies the stronger triangle inequality d(x,y) for X. x,y,z max(d(x,z), d(z,y) A topological group is said to be non-archimedean metrizable if there exists a right (or left) invariant metric on G (see G which induces the topology of G is such that its topology is given by Rangan [3]). LEMMA 3.1. Suppose a topological group d a non-archimedean metric invariant metric then there is an equivalent non-archimedean right (or left) G (i.e. a non-archimedean metric on 0 PROOF. When d z varies in easy to check that G Put G Then positive integers d’(x,y) V where n 0 p P(x,e) l/n} < k. W {x I/m d’ and choose z z o) < I/m z in Then with respect to the metric existence of a positive integer W is in U k V Hence and U U n d’(x,e) x n k Wz V M for all n d’. contains a l/n}. To prove U k for O, choose positive integers n,m such that O(x,e) d’(XZo,Z o + I/n. Let such that 0 is the open sphere with centre The continuity of such that d’(XZo,Z o) + I/n x WZo UkZ I/m + I/n xz o Let I/M x at x E z e U k. O and radius implies the Clearly x proving thereby that This completes the proof of the lemma. M THEOREM 3.2. Then group. 0(x,e) d’. G We will now G is finer than the topology induced by Corresponding to the Integer M 1/M V is clear that that the two topologies are the same we will show that each 1/n + 1/m It is is bounded. coincide. G, it x,y {x n d’ and for all i.e. the topology induced by some d’ d/l+d where supremum is is a right invaPiant non-archimedean metric on 0 Ox,y) sup d’(xz,yz) 0(x,y) is well-defined since 0 show that the topologies induced by Since then the metric d’ G is a non-archimedean metric on also defines the same topology on taken as which gives the same 0 d). topology as PROOF. O Let G be a separable totally disconnected ordered topological is non-archimedean metrizable. By Theorem 2.6 of [2], it follows that G is topologically orderable, metrizable, zero-dimensional group and so carries a non-archimedean metric inducing the topology of that G G (see proof of Theorem 7 of [I] or [7]). is non-archimedean metrizable. Now from Lemma 3.1 it follows ORDERABILITY OF TOPOLOGICAL GROUPS Vnkataraman, 753 Rajagopalan and Soundararajan proved (see Theorem 2.6, [2]) that a separable totally disconnected group is topologically orderable (i.e. the topology is given by a total order) if and only if it is metrizable and zero-dimensional. Non- archimedean metrizable groups are totally disconnected groups (see Rangan [3]). Hence in view of Theorem 3.2 above it is natural to ask whether the converse of Theorem 3.2 is also true. Is it possible to total order a non-archimedean separable topo- i.e. logical group in such a way that the order is compatible with both the group structure That the answer to this question is in the negative is shown by and the topology? Theorem 3.4 given below. For the counter example given in Theorem 3.4 we require the following definition. Each Let Q x in x’ I/p Ix-yl P and d(x,y) for and x,y Then Qp The completion of archimedean metric. where of Q d Qp does not divide Xlp is easily seen to be a non- with this metric (which can be made is called the field of Q into a field extending the addition and multiplication in We consider the additive group of this field p-adic numbers. p We define is an integer. s Q in be a fixed prime number. p pSx’ can be written uniquely in the form Q the numerator and denominator of s Let denote the field of rational numbers. Qp and denote it by It is a separable totally disconnected group (see section 2, [8] for itself. details). (see van Rooij [8]). LEMMA 3.3. PROOF. ln!l P Since En! follows that A B which proves that THEOREM 3.4. Qp PROOF. topology. In.n,l P En.n! and tend to zero as B Then There is no order A + B Qp Suppose Let 0 Qp (Qp,+) on En! + En.n! E(n+l)! which is compatible with both From the compatibility of the group structure under this order. s n k=l 0 k.k! and from the compatibility of the order -i lim s This proves that simultaneously with the group structure Since + + alone. + 0 which is a contradiction. Qp and the topology. admits no order compatible However by Theorem 2.6 of [2] it follows that it admits an order which induces the topology of Qp Qp (see also is a torsion-free abelian group it admits a total order compatible with the group structure 4. A admits a total order compatible with the group structure and is also impossible. Remark 5.7 of [2]). -I. even though it admits an order compatible with the topo- and topology it follows by Lemma 3.3 that 0 converges to tends to infinity, it n alone and an order compatible with the group structure and order it follows that Similarly Z n.n! the series -i. and the usual topology of logy of and Qp In + alone (Corollary 5, p.36, [4]). NON-TOTALLY DISCONNECTED ORDERED GROUPS. In this section we consider only abelian non-totally disconnected groups. In what follows we refer the reader to Wright [9] for the deinitions of radical-free, maximal G. RANGAN 754 radical free etc. A non-totally disconnected locally compact ableian topological group THEOREM 4.1. is orderable if and only if it is maximally radical free and its component is an open subgroup of PROOF. topologically isomorphic to the reals. G Suppose is a mon-totally disconnected locally compact abelian group G whose topology is given by a total order which is compatible with the group structure of G Then by Corollary 2.3 its component C is an open subgroup topologically Now by Theorem 5.1 of Wright [9] it follows that isomorphic with the reals. G is maximally radical-free in its interval topology. Let now G satisfy the conditions of the Theorem. Theore 5.2 of Wright [9] orderable. G G is connected then by G is If not since the component of the identity is open and topologically iso- morphic to the reals G is one-dimensional free by Theorem 5.3 of Wright By Theorem If is topologically isomorphic to the reals and so of Isiwata [I0], G/C is discrete and maximally radical [9] and hence torsion-free by Theorem 4.1 of Wright [9]. G can be totally ordered so that the order topology coincides with the given topology of G and this order is compatible with the group structure as well. ACKNOWLEDGEMENT. I thank Professors M. Rajagopalan and R. Venkataman for the many use- ful discussions I had with them while preparing this paper. REFERENCES I. NYIKOS, P.J., and REICHEL, H.C. 5(1975), 195-204. 2. VENKATARAMAN, M., RAJAGOPALAN, M., and SOUNDARAJAN, T. Genii Topology App. (1972), Topologically orderable groups, Gen. opology Appl. Orderable topological spaces, I-i0. 4. RANGAN, G. Non-archimedean metrizbility of topological groups, Fund. Math. (1970), 179-182. FUCHS, L. Partially .Kdred a!ebraic sstems, Pergaman Press (1963). 5. 6. IWASAWA, K. On linearly ordered groups, J. Math. Soc. Japan I(1948), I-9. HEWITT, E. and ROSS, K. A. Abstract Harmonic Analysis, p.l, Springer-verlag 7. GROOT de, J. 8. ROOIJ van, A. C. M and SCHIKHOF, W. H. (3) 19(1971), 120-160. 3. (1963). Non-archimedean metrics in topology, Proc. Amer. Math. Soc. (1956), Non-archimedean analysis, Nieuw Arch. Wisk. WRIGHT, F. B. Topological abelian groups, Amer. J. lath. 59(1957), 477-496. 10. ISIWATA, T. Linearisation of topological groups and ordered rings, Kodai Math. Sem. Reports (1952), 33-35. 9.