Theory and Applications of Categories, Vol. 5, No. 5, 1999, pp. 91–147. DISTRIBUTIVE LAWS FOR PSEUDOMONADS F. MARMOLEJO Transmitted by Ross Street ABSTRACT. We define distributive laws between pseudomonads in a Gray-category A, as the classical two triangles and the two pentagons but commuting only up to isomorphism. These isomorphisms must satisfy nine coherence conditions. We also define the Gray-category PSM(A) of pseudomonads in A, and define a lifting to be a pseudomonad in PSM(A). We define what is a pseudomonad with compatible structure with respect to two given pseudomonads. We show how to obtain a pseudomonad with compatible structure from a distributive law, how to get a lifting from a pseudomonad with compatible structure, and how to obtain a distributive law from a lifting. We show that one triangle suffices to define a distributive law in case that one of the pseudomonads is a (co-)KZ-doctrine and the other a KZ-doctrine. 1. Introduction Distributive laws for monads were introduced by J. Beck in [2]. As pointed out by G. M. Kelly in [7], strict distributive laws for higher dimensional monads are rare. We need then a study of pseudo-distributive laws. The first step in this direction is quite easy: just replace the two commutative triangles, and the two commutative pentagons of [2] by appropriate invertible cells. The problem is to determine what coherence conditions to impose on these invertible cells. We should point out that, in [7], there is a step in this direction, keeping commutativity on the nose on the triangles and one of the pentagons, and asking for commutativity up to isomorphism in the remaining pentagon, plus five coherence conditions. The structure obtained from such a distributive law between two strict 2-monads is not, in general, a strict 2-monad, and since that article deals exclusively with strict 2-monads, what is obtained is a reflection result. In this paper, instead of working with 2-monads we work with the more general pseudomonads. We will see that the structure obtained from a distributive law between pseudomonads is a pseudomonad. We define a distributive law between pseudomonads as we said above, that is to say, asking for commutativity up to isomorphism of the two triangles and the two pentagons. We propose nine coherence conditions for these isomorphisms. See section 4 below. We observe that the coherence conditions of [7] and the ones proposed in this paper coincide if in our setting we ask for commutativity on the nose of the two triangles and one of the pentagons. Thus, the examples of distributive laws given there are examples here as well. But why exactly these nine coherence conditions? Received by the editors 1998 June 24 and, in revised form, 1998 November 22. Published on 1999 March 18. 1991 Mathematics Subject Classification: 18C15, 18D05, 18D20. Key words and phrases: Pseudomonads, distributive laws, KZ-doctrines, Gray-categories. c F. Marmolejo 1999. Permission to copy for private use granted. 91 Theory and Applications of Categories, Vol. 5, No. 5 92 A more conceptual approach to distributive laws for monads is given by R. Street in [11]. It is shown that for a 2-category C, a distributive law is the same thing as a monad in the 2-category MND(C), whose objects are monads in C. In this paper we introduce the corresponding structure PSM(A), of pseudomonads for a corresponding three dimensional structure A, see section 7. In M. Barr and C. Wells’ book [1], exercise (Dl) asks to prove that, for monads, a distributive law, a lifting of one monad structure to the algebras of the other, and a monad with compatible structure with the two given monads, are essentially the same thing. For pseudomonads we have already mentioned distributive laws. We define a lifting as a pseudomonad in PSM(A) in section 8. In section 6, we define what a pseudomonad whose structure is compatible with two given pseudomonads is. We show how to obtain a composite pseudomonad with compatible structure from a distributive law between pseudomonads, how to obtain a lifting from a pseudomonad with compatible structure, and, closing the cycle, how to obtain a distributive law from a lifting. We see then, that the nine coherence conditions can be shown to hold if we define a distributive law from a lifting. In turn, these coherence conditions allow us to define a lifting from a distributive law between pseudomonads. The situation for distributive laws between KZ-doctrines and (co-)KZ-doctrines is a lot simpler. We show that either one of the triangles commuting up to isomorphism (satisfying coherence conditions) is enough to obtain a distributive law. One such example is the following. It is well known that adding free (finite) coproducts to categories is a KZdoctrine over Cat, and adding free (finite) products is a co-KZ-doctrine. There is a more or less obvious distributive law of the co-KZ-doctrine over the KZ-doctrine. Observe however that even if we arrange for these KZ-doctrine and co-KZ-doctrine to produce strict pseudomonads, the distributive law obtained is not strict. This article is possible thanks to the definition of tricategories given in [6]. It is simplified by the fact that a tricategory is triequivalent to a Gray-category, a fact proved in the same paper. We thus work in the framework of Gray-categories, as in [6], continuing the development of the formal theory of pseudomonads started in [9]. This paper is organized as follows: In section 2 we provide a brief description of the framework that we use, namely that of Gray-categories. For more details we refer the reader to [6, 5]. In section 3 we recall the definition and some properties of pseudomonads given in [9], the definition uses the definition of pseudomonoid given in [3]. We also define the change of base 2-functors, change of base strong transformations and the change of base modifications that we will need in later sections. Change of base turns out to be a Graynatural transformation. In section 4 we define distributive laws for pseudomonads by replacing commutativity on the nose by commutativity up to isomorphism. We give here the nine coherence conditions that these isomorphisms should satisfy. The first step to obtain compatible structures is to define a composite pseudomonad Theory and Applications of Categories, Vol. 5, No. 5 93 from a distributive law. This is what we do in section 5. In section 6 we define what a pseudomonad with compatible structure is with respect to given pseudomonads. Furthermore, we exhibit the structure that makes compatible the composite pseudomonad defined in the previous section. We introduce the Gray-category PSM(A) in section 7, to define, in section 8, a lifting as a pseudomonad in the Gray-category PSM(A). In section 9 we show how to construct a pseudomonad in PSM(A), from given pseudomonads with compatible structure. In the following section, we go from a pseudomonad in PSM(A) to a distributive law. Section 11 deals with distributive laws of (co-)KZ-doctrines over KZ-doctrines. We refer the reader to [9] for the definition and properties we use of KZ-doctrines, but see [8] as well. We show that one triangle, plus coherence, is enough to produce a distributive law. Compare with [10], where it is shown that one of the triangles suffices for a distributive law between idempotent monads. The case of KZ-doctrines over KZ-doctrines is formally very similar. In this latter case, we show that the composite pseudomonad is again a KZ-doctrine. I would like to thank the referee for helping improve the readability of this paper, and for suggesting condition (12), after which all the conditions of section 6 were modeled. 2. Gray-categories As in [9] we will work with a Gray-category A, where Gray is the symmetric monoidal closed category whose underlying category is 2-Cat with tensor product as in [6]. A Graycategory is a category enriched in the category Gray as in [4]. We will briefly spell out what this means, and we refer the reader to [6] and [4] for more details. A Gray-category A has objects A, B, C, . . . . For every pair of objects A, B of A, A has a 2-category A(A, B). Given another object C in A, A has a 2-functor A(C, B) ⊗ A(A, B) → A(A, C). This 2-functor corresponds to a cubical functor M : A(B, C) × A(A, B) → A(A, C). We will denote M by juxtaposition, M (G, F ) = GF for F ∈ A(A, B) and G ∈ A(B, C). Given f : F → F in A(A, B) and g : G → G in A(B, C) we will denote the invertible 2-cell Mg,f by GF Gf GF gF / G F gf gF G f / G F . What the definition of being cubical means for M is the following: Given ϕ : f → f : F → F , and f : F → F in A(A, B), and γ : g → g : G → G , and g : G → G in A(B, C), we have that ( )F : A(B, C) → A(A, C) and G( ) : A(A, B) → A(A, C) are 2-functors, ( )f : ( )F → ( )F and g( ) : G( ) → G ( ) are strong transformations, ( )ϕ : ( )f → ( )f and γ( ) : g( ) → g ( ) are modifications, and the following three Theory and Applications of Categories, Vol. 5, No. 5 94 equations are satisfied gF γF * 4GF GF g F sk _ __ _ Gf gf Gf Gϕ GF GF Gf GF gF G f ks __ G f G ϕ + γF 3 G F , gF GF gF GF / G F G f gf / G F gf g F / G F gF gF GF Gf / G F gf Gf G f / G F g F gF GF = = G(f ◦f ) G f / G F , / G F G (f ◦f ) gf ◦f GF gF = GF and GF Gf GF gF gf gF g F / G F G f / G F / G F G f gf / G F Gf g F (g ◦g)F / G F G f GF (g ◦g)f / G F , (g ◦g)F and if either f or g is an identity, then gf is an identity 2-cell. Now, for every object A of A, there is a distinguished object 1A . The triangle in the definition of enriched categories means that the action of multiplying by 1A is trivial. Now, the pentagon means that for another object D in A, and κ : k → k : K → K in A(C, D) the following equations hold: (KG)F = K(GF ), (KG)f = K(Gf ), (Kg)F = K(gF ), (kG)F = k(GF ), (KG)ϕ = K(Gϕ), (Kγ)F = K(γF ), (κG)F = κ(GF ), (Kg)f = K(gf ), (kG)f = kGf , and (kg )F = kgF . We will use these properties freely, without further mention. 3. Pseudomonads For the convenience of the reader we will recall here the definition of a pseudomonad in a Gray-category A, for more details we refer the reader to [9]. We adopt the definition of pseudomonoid given in [3]. Theory and Applications of Categories, Vol. 5, No. 5 95 3.1. Definition. A pseudomonad D on an object K of a Gray-category A is a pseudomonoid in the Gray monoid A(K, K). We give now, in elementary terms, what this means. A pseudomonad D as above consists of an object D in A(K, K), and 1-cells d : 1K → D, and m : DD → D and invertible 2-cells dD Dd Dm / DD DDD D DD / DD Yao : z D ::: DD ~ β η zzz DD zz IdD DDm ! }zz IdD mD D µ DD m / D, m such that the following two equations are satisfied: / DDD EE DDm DDDD EE mDD EEDmD Dµ EE E" ⇐= DDD DDDEE µD mD E⇐= EE E" Dm EEDm EE E" / DD µ m ⇐= mD DD m Dmvv: DDDD JJDm JJ JJ $ mD m−1 m mDD DD ⇐= µ / ⇐= DDDLL Dm DDJJ = LLL LL mD LL% /D µ JJm J (1) m ⇐= JJJ$ DD m / D, DDDJ DD F FFm FF # DdD/ µ ⇓ ;D DD DDDH HH xx xxm H$ x mD vv / DDD JJ DDm DdD tt: ttt Dβ ⇓ JJDm JJ $ / DD m / D. DD J JJJ ηD ⇓ tt: J tttmD DdD $ = (2) DDD DD It is shown in [9] that the following three equations hold for any pseudomonad D: DD JJJm : JJ t t t IdD β ⇓ J$ d / / D D JJ η ⇓ tt: JJJ t tttm Dd J$ < D DD DDdD D" z zz −1 / 1KDD dd ⇓ DD m D, < DD z D zz d D" zz Dd d zzz dDttt 1K = DD DDEE dDD / DDD Dm EE βD EE EE⇐ mD µ ⇐= IdDD EE " DD m (3) D dDD / DD / DD dm m m / D = DDD ⇐= D EE Dm / DD EE dD EE β EE⇐ m IdD EEE E" D, (4) Theory and Applications of Categories, Vol. 5, No. 5 96 DDEE EE EEIdDD E Dη EEEE " ⇐ / DDD DD DDd Dm µ ⇐= DD m mD /D EE EE EEIdD md DDd Dd η EE ⇐= ⇐ EEE" DDD mD / DD m / D. m DD = m / D (5) We recall as well the 2-categories of algebras for a pseudomonad D. Let X be another object in A. An object in the 2-category D-AlgX consists of an object X in A(X , K), together with a 1-cell x : DX → X and invertible 2-cells X DD / DX DD ~ dX IdX DDX DD ψ x DD " mX X Dx / DX χ DX x x / X, such that the following two equations are satisfied DDDX EE / DDX EE DDx mDX EEDmX Dχ EE E" ⇐= DDX DDXEE Dx EEDx EE E" / DX χ x µX mX E⇐= EE E mX " ⇐= DX x Dx vv: = DDx / DDX JJ JJDx JJ JJ $ mX m−1 x mDX DX ⇐= χ / ⇐= DDXLL Dx DXJJ LLL LL mX LL% /X (6) x JJ x JJ ⇐= JJ$ / X, DX χ x DDXJ DX F FFxF F# DdX/ χ ⇓ DX DDXH ;X HH xx x x H$ xx mX vv DDDX = DdX tt: ttt Dψ ⇓ JJDx JJ $ / DX x / X. DX J JJJ ηX ⇓ tt: J tttmX DdX $ (7) DDX DX It is shown in [9] that for every object (ψ, χ) in D-AlgX , the following equality holds: dDX / DX II DDX Dx II βX II mX χ I Id II$ DX x / DX x /X = DX x dDX / DDX dx dX / Dx X II DX II II ψ x II Id II$ X. (8) Theory and Applications of Categories, Vol. 5, No. 5 97 A 1-cell (h, ρ) : (ψ, χ) → (ψ , χ ) in D-AlgX consists of a 1-cell h : X → X in A(X , K), together with an invertible 2-cell / DX Dh DX ρ x X x / X , h that satisfies the following two equations: X DD / DX DD ~ dX Id Dh / DX ρ DD ψ x DD " X = x h /X h / DX dX X dh Dh dX (9) / DX EE ~ ψ EE x Id EE" X EE X , DDXEE DDh mX EEDx EE E" / DDX EE Dρ ⇐= DX DXEE χ x E⇐= EE E" Dh EEDx EE E" /DX ρ X h DX ⇐= χ DXLL Dh / DX JJ ⇐= L = LLL x LLL% / X h JJDx JJ JJ $ mX m−1 mX x ⇐= x / DDX JJ DDh DDX (10) JJx x JJ J ⇐= J$ /X . X ρ h A 2-cell ξ : (h, ρ) → (h , ρ ) : (ψ, χ) → (ψ , χ ) is a 2-cell ξ : h → h such that the following condition is satisfied: Dh DX x * Dξ 4 DX Dh X ρ h x / X = DX x X Dh / DX ρ h ) (11) x ξ 5 X . h Given another object Z of A, and K ∈ A(Z, X ), we can define a change of base : D-AlgX → D-AlgZ . If ξ : (h, ρ) → (h , ρ ) : (ψ, χ) → (ψ , χ ) is in D-AlgX , 2-functor K is ξK : (hK, ρK) → (h K, ρ K) : (ψK, χK) → (ψ K, χ K). If then its image under K → K such that k : K k(ψ,χ) = k : K → K then we define the strong transformation −1 −1 (ψ,χ) = Xκ defines (Xk, xk ) and k(h,ρ) = hk . If κ : k → k : K → K in A(Z, X ), then κ a modification κ : k → k . We have actually defined a Gray-functor D-Alg : Aop → Gray. For every object Z, we have an obvious forgetful 2-functor D-AlgZ → A(Z, K). These 2-functors define a forgetful Gray-natural transformation Φ : D-Alg → A( , K). Theory and Applications of Categories, Vol. 5, No. 5 98 4. Distributive laws Let D = (D, d, m, βD , ηD , µD ) and U = (U, u, n, βU , ηU , µU ) be pseudomonads on the same object K of the Gray-category A. A distributive law of U over D consists of a 1-cell r : U D → DU in A(K, K), together with invertible 2-cells U U = DFF = DFF zz FFr FF F ω1 F# / DU uD zz D Ur UUD nD zz zz Du / U DU rU UD U / DU U ω3 r {{ FFr FF F ω2 F# / DU U d {{ {{ {{ dU Dn / DU O r UD O 4444 ω4 mU / DDU Um / DU U DD / DU D Dr rD subject to the following coherence conditions: (coh 1) / U K Ud / U D KK GGu} ssss KK GGd−1 KK y zzzz r u G K 2 d GG dU KKω % # / DU D 1 GG u = =U zz z z z 1 DD DD d ! u Du II U d II I$ ud U D LL r u: uu ω1 LLL% u u uD / DU. D Du (coh 2) U uD / UUD 44 nn 44 ηs{ D−1 44U 44 4 nD Id 44 44 44 44 U D4 UD Ur / U DU = U uD / UUD HH HH U ω1 U r H U Du HH$ U D HH rU px hh ω3 r U DU r DU U −1 ru DU u / Dn / DU DU HH rU DU U HH −1 HHDηU Dn H Id HH$ DU. (coh 3) / UUD U U LL LLL U ω2 LL Ur U dU LLL& U DU UUd dU U n ω2 U rU " DU U U dn dU Dn / DU = UU n UUd/ U U DJJ n−1 d Ud / nD JJ U r JJ JJ J% U II UD U DU II ω 888 ω 3 II 2 88 rU II 88 II II 8 r 88 DU U II dU III 88 II 8 II 88 Dn II 8 $ DU. Theory and Applications of Categories, Vol. 5, No. 5 99 (coh 4) U U r/ = U U U DU U/ rU U DU U U DU AA DD 55 DD AA DDU rU 55 AA DD A 55 U rU A DD 55 ! nU D U nD 5 U DU U AA nU D nDU 55 U DU AU AA U Dn AA 55 AA AAU Dn | U ω3 55 AA AA U ~ n−1 ω rU ~ r AA 3U / U DU UUD U U D 55 Ur U U DD U r / U DUDD DU UAU U DU 55 DD AA rU DD 55 u} ssss DD AA| −1 DDDnU 55 µU D DD AArn rU DD 55 D AA rU DU n D nD DD DU U D! nD 5 D 55 DD DU U DU U D 55 A u} rrrr ω3Dn nD DD AA 5 DD ~ A A|ADµU Dn DD ω3 / DU DD UD Dn AAA r D! / DU. UD U U U5 D r (coh 5) DD QQQ / U DD uDD QQQ QQQ rD Q ~ DuD QQQω( 1 D DU D ~ Dω1 DDu % / UD Um } ω4 Dr DDU r / DU mU = DDGG uDD GG GG m GGG # DDu DDU / U DD um D GG uD / U D GG G G ω1 r mu GG Du G# / DU. Um mU (coh 6) U U m/ U U DD DD U r DD DD " nDD nD = U U DDD n−1 m U DDG U m / U DD GG D U DUDD DD rU DD DD ! DU U DD ~ ω3 DD DD DD r Dn DU DDD DDDD DD ~ ω4 DD DD DD DD Dr DD" ! / DU DDU GG G rD GG# mU / UUD 33 33 33 33 3U3 r U DD U DU DD D 33 z DDU Dr z 3 DD zz uuuu ~ v z DD z U ω4 33 |zz rU D " / U DU ks __ rD ks __ DU U D U DDU −1 DD ω3 D U mU DD rr zz {{ DD zz {{ { z D { z }{{ DnD DU r D" |zz rDU ____ s k DU D DU DU rU Dω3 zz z z ~ ω4 U zz |zz DrU / DU U Dr DDU U mU U z {{ zz z {{ { z ~ mn { z }{{ DDn |zz Dn / DDU DU. U U DD DD {{ {{ { { }{{ nDD mU UUm DDU rD DD DD " Theory and Applications of Categories, Vol. 5, No. 5 100 (coh 7) Id U D QQQ U dD −1 U βD / U DD QQQ QQQ rD Q ~ dU D QQQω( 2 D Um & / U DU DU D r ~ dr DU dDU = idr . r ~ ω4 Dr / DDU β U D mU / DU 8 Um % / UD Id (coh 8) Id U Dd UD r U ηD / U DD ~ r−1 rD d / DU D DU QQQ DU d QQQ QQQ Dr Q ~ DdU QQDω Q( 2 DDU = idr . r } ω4 −1 ηD U / DU 9 mU Id (coh 9) U Dm / U DDNN PPP NNNU m PPP NN rDD P | U µD NNNN U mD PPP( ' DU DD U DD U m / U D U DDDPP DrD DDr rDD DU DD DrD DDU DPP | ω4 D PPP PPP P mU D PPP( DDDUPP DU m / U DD NNN NNNU m NNN { r−1 rD NN& m / DU D UD DDU D rD r DU D DDr Dr mU y zzzzω4 / DU { Dω4 y {{{{ω4 r / DDU NNN PPDmU NNNmU PPP { NNN PPP { { { y NN& µD U PP' mDU / DU. DDU DDDUPP PPP PPP Dr P | r mDU PPPm ( DDU U Dm = U DDD mU Observe that if the pseudomonads are strict (β, η and µ are identities), and ω1 , ω2 and ω3 are identities, then we obtain the coherence conditions of the “mild” extensions of the classical distributive laws given in [7]. Theory and Applications of Categories, Vol. 5, No. 5 101 5. The composite pseudomonad given by a distributive law Assume we have a distributive law of U over D as in section 4. The first question is how to produce a composite pseudomonad from U, D, and the distributive law. This is what we do in this section. Define V = (V, v, p, βV , ηV , µV ) as follows: V = DU ∈ A(K, K); v is defined as the composite 1K u /U dU / DU ; p is the composite DU DU DrU / DDU U DDn / DDU mU / DU ; βV is defined to be the pasting DU DU rr9 O MMMMMDrU MMM rr MM& rrr d−1 __uDU 3 + Dω U 1 U> DU U DDU LLL q8 }} DuDU qqq LLDDn } LLL q } q } q DDβ LL% q U } DDuU q } q uDU }} / DDU } II hhh3 DDU }} h h h } II mU } hhh h II h } h h h } II h h } hh dDU I$ βD U }}hhhhhhh / DU ; DU dU DUrrr Id ηV as the pasting Id / / DU ; l5 DU VVVVVV : l l v V l HH V v l V VVVV v DηU ηD U ll HH v l l V v V l H ll Dn vv DU u HH DdU VVVVVV # vv mU lll V* DU UFFXXXXXX DDU −1 r9 Ddn XXXXX r FF r XXXXX FF rr XXXXX FF rrrDDn XXXXX DdU U r FF r + FF U F Dω2 U −1 DDU DU dU FF qq8 FF q q FF qqq FF " qqq DrU DU HH Id DU DU Theory and Applications of Categories, Vol. 5, No. 5 102 and µV as the pasting / DU DDU U DU DDn / DU DDU DU mU Dr−1 Dr−1 DrDU U DrDU rU Dn / DDU DU U / DDU DU DU DrU DU DU DU DrU DU DDU U DU DDU rU DDU Dn DDDU U U DDnDU DDU DU DDrU m−1 rU DU DU mDU U / DDU U DrU DDDµU DDDn / DDDU DDDn m−1 Dn DmU U Dmn DmU mU DDn / DDU µD U mDU / DDU DDn DrU Dω4 U / DDU U DDrU / DDDU U DDDU n DDω3 U DDDnU / DDDU U mU DU DDrn−1 DDrU U / DU DU mU / DU. 5.1. Theorem. V = (V, v, p, βV , ηV , µV ), as defined above, is a pseudomonad on the object K. Proof. Observe that the pasting of µV and ηV V −1 is / / RR / EE RRR EE R RRDω EE RRR2 U DU EE −1 RRR R) Dη EE U DU EE EE EE EE " RDdnDU RRR RRR RRR RR RRR) −1 DrrU / −1 DrDn / DDrn−1 DDω3 U / m−1 rU / ηD U DU −1 + / / / DDDµU / m−1 Dn / Dω4 U Dmn µD U / / / . We must show that this pasting equals p ◦ V βV . Substitute the pasting of DdnDU and DηU DU −1 by the pasting of Dd−1 U uDU and DDηU DU . Then use (coh 2). With the help of (2) show that / −1 DDruU DDDηU / / U −1 - −1 DDrn DDDµU = / / 5 lll lll l l l lll lll RRR RRR RRR RR DDU DβU RRRR) / , DDrU DDDn Theory and Applications of Categories, Vol. 5, No. 5 103 and make the substitution. Make the substitution / / Dω2 U DU + = /: J : tt tt JJJ t t tt DU drU ttt DU dDn JJJ JJ tt tt tt / Ht /$ / HH H HH −1 HH −1 Dω2 DU H HDdU rU H HDdU Dn HH HH H$ H$ / /+ , = : J tt JJJ tDU t ω 1 U JJJ t JJ tt tt /$ / −1 DrrU / −1 DrDn / followed by the substitutions 8 N ppp NNNNN p p NNN ppp NN& −1 pppks _ __ _ DdU rU N NNN 8 −1 N p NNN DdU uDUppp NNN N p DDU ω U N NNN p 1 N p N p NN& NN& −1 ppp / NDd NNNU Dn N DDU DβU NNNN NN& . JJ JJ JJ JJ J$ . DU DβU , DdU DU and / / ηD U DU −1 + / m−1 rU / / = m−1 Dn DdrU / DdDn / / ηD DU −1 + , and / DdDn ηD / / Dmn DU −1 - µD U = / / 5 lll lll l l l lll lll RRR RRR RRR R Dβ DU U RRRR D R)/ . DDn mU Use (coh 7), and finish with the substitution / PPP PPP PDU PPPω1 U PPP ( / * DU DβU = DU drU / DU dDn / 8 ppp p p ppp ppp / / p8 NN NNN p DU d−1 uDU NNN pppDU Dω1 U p p N p ppp DU DDβU NN& / - Theory and Applications of Categories, Vol. 5, No. 5 104 In regards to the other condition, observe that the pasting of V µV , µV V and µV is: / L / L / L LLL LLL LLL LLL LLL L L LLL L L L L L LL% LLL −1 LL −1 LL DU DrrU %/ DU DrDn %/ LL −1 LLDr L L L L L L LLLrU DU LLL LLL DU Dω4 U LLLL LLL LLL LLL LLL L LLL L% L% DU DDrn−1LLL% L% LLL / L / L LLL LLL LLL L LLL LLL LLL LLL LLL LLL L L L L −1 L LL DU DDω3 U LL DU DDDµU LL LLDr DU Dmn LL% % %/ %/ LLDnDU / L LLL LLL LLL LLL LLL LLL LLL LLL LLL LLL LLL LLL L L L L −1 LLDDr LL% LL% −1 LL DU µD U LL% LLL nDU LL% DU m−1 DU m % rU Dn / / / U LLL LLDDω LLL 3 LLL LLL LLL L% % −1 −1 DrrU DrDn LLLm−1 LDω LLL LLL4 U DU rU DU LLL LLL L LLL LLL LLL DDDµU DU L% % LLL / / LLL LLL LLL LLL Dω4 U −1 DDrn LLL L LLL −1 L% Dm / / LLmLDnDU LLL nDU LLL LLL DDDµU DDω3 U Dmn LLL LL % % / / / LLµ LLDLU DU LLL µD U m−1 m−1 rU Dn L% / / / Where we have only put the name of the corresponding 2-cell in each parallelogram. To show that this pasting is equal to the pasting of pp , µV and µV we do the following. First make the substitution / NN / NN NNN NNN NN NNN NNNDU m−1 NNNNDU m−1 NNNNN NN& rU NN& Dn NN& / / __ _ NNN ks _ Dω NNN4 U DU NNN NN& / = −1 Dr DrU / −1 / OO OOO OOO −1 OOO Dr DDn O' / −1 DDr Dn / OO / OO ks __ OOO OOODω4 DU O OOO OOO OOO Dm−1 OOO Dm−1 OOOO OOO U rU OOO U Dn OOO '/ . ' '/ DDrrU −1 DrDn / −1 DrrU / Then make the substitutions / L / L LLL LLL LL LLL L LLLDm−1 LLLLL LLLDm−1 LL% U Dn LL% L% U rU / / LLL ks __ Dm LLLnDU LLL L% / DDDµU DDω3 U −1 DDrn / / = / / L LLL LLL LLL / L DmrU % LLL DDDω3 U LL L DDDDµU L DmDn LL% / / LLL LLL LLL LLL LLL LLL LLL Dm−1 L LLL LLLDm−1 Dn L% rU L% %/ / −1 DDDrn Theory and Applications of Categories, Vol. 5, No. 5 105 and / NN / NN NNN NNN NNN NNN NNN −1 NN NNN DU DDr N n NNN NN& NNN N& / NN NNN NNN NNN NNN NNN NNN NNN −1 NNNDrDnDU NNDU DDω3 U NNDU DDDµU NNNN N N N N NN& NNN N& N& / / NNN NNN N NNN −1 −1 −1 NNN DrDrU DrDDn NNDDr NNN nDU NNNN / & NNN / NNN −1 −1 NNN DDrrU DDrDn NNN / & / = / / OO OOO OOO OOO O' −1 / / OO DrDrU OOO O OOO OOO −1 −1 DDrU DDr O OOO OOO rU U Dn OOO O O / / ' ' −1 −1 OOO DrDDn OOO OOO DDrrU OOO OOO OOO OOO OOO OOO DDDU r−1 OOO OOO OOO n OOO OO OOO OOO'/ ' −1 O' OOO DDr O O OOO Dn OOO OOO OO OO OOO DDDU DµU OOOO OOO ω3 U OOOODDDU OO' O O'/ O' / . −1 DrDU rU −1 DrDU Dn Now use (coh 4). Proceed with the following substitutions / M MMM MMM MMM MMM M MDDDU MMM Dµ MMM U MMM M M &/ & −1 DDDr MMM nU MMM −1 M MM DDDrn MMM DDDDµ UM& / MMM U MMM DDDDµU M MM MMM M& / = / N NNN NNN −1 DDDrU NNN n −1 NNN DDDr n & / N NNN N −1 NNN DDDDrn NNN DDDDµUNN& / MMM LLL MMM LLL LL MMM LLDDDDµ U MMM LLL M& & / , followed by / PP PPP PPP PPP PPP P PDDDU PPP rn−1 PPP PP( PP( / DDDω3 U U PPP PPP PPP PPP P( −1 DDDrU n −1 DDDDrn / / = DDDn−1 Dn / OO OOO OOO OOO O' / ODDDω NNN OOO 3 U NNN OOO −1 N NDDDr OOO NNN n OO' N' / , Theory and Applications of Categories, Vol. 5, No. 5 106 and then / NN / NN NNN NNN NN NNN N NNN Dm−1 NNN Dm−1 NNNNN rU Dn N N NN& N N& / / __ _ & NNN ks _ NµNDNU DU −1 −1 mrU mDn NNN NN& / / / = / NN NNN NNN NN __ N' / M s k MMM MMM µ DU MMM MD MMM m−1 MMMM m−1 rU Dn MM& M M& / / , m−1 DrU m−1 DDn / MMM MMM MMM MM& followed by the substitution / NN / NN NNN NNN NN NNN N NNNDDDrn−1NNNNN NNN NN& NN& NNN / NN NNN NNN NNN N N N NNN N N NNN DDDω U NN DDDDµNNNN NNNm−1 N NNN 3 U DnDU N N NN& NNN N& NN& / / NNN NNN −1 −1 m m NNN DrU DDn NN& / / = / / OO OOO OOO OOO O' / / −1 m OOO OOO OOO DrU OOO OOO OOO OOO OOO OOO DDr−1 OOO OOO OOO n O O OOO OOO OO' OO' ' −1 OOO / m O O OOO DDn OOO OOO O O OOO O O OOODDω3 U OOOOO DDDµU OOOOO O' O/' O' / . m−1 DU rU m−1 DU Dn Use (coh 9) to show that / OO OOO OO OOO OOO DU µD UOOOOO OO' OO' / = OOO Dω4 DU OOO OOO DmrU OO' OOO OOO OOO OO' Dm Dn OOO OOO OO µ DU OOO' D OOO OOO OOO OO' / OO OOO OOO OOO / ' −1 DrmU DDω4 U Dω4 U Dmn µD U / / / 4U / OO Dω OOO OOO DDmn Dmn OOO' / OOO OOO mmU OO µD U OOO' / OOO OOO OOO O OOO µD U OOOOO OO' OO' / Theory and Applications of Categories, Vol. 5, No. 5 107 and make the substitution. Next the substitution / NN / NN NNN NN NN NNN −1 NN −1 NN NNDU NNN DrrU NNDU NNNDrDn NNNNN −1 & /& /& DU NNN DrrU −1 −1 NNN DrDU rU DrDU Dn NNN NN& / / −1 DDrU rU DDω3 U DU NNN NNN NNN N −1 N& DU NNN mrU NNN NNN NN& / DDDn−1 rU −1 DrU DrU / DDDn−1 Dn / / m−1 DU Dn / / −1 DDrU Dn / m−1 DU rU / = / L LLL LLL LLL −1 / LDrrDU & LLL LL L LLL & −1 DrU DDn DDn−1 DrU DDn−1 DDn m−1 U DrU m−1 U DDn / L DDω3 DU LLL LL L LLL m−1 & / / rDU KK KK KKK KK KK K K KK K −1 KK −1 KK KK DrrU KKK KK DrDn KK K %/ % /% / , followed by the substitution / M / N NNN NNN MMM −1 NNN DrU NNN M mU M NNN M NNN M −1 NNN DrrDU NN& DU Dω4 U MMMM / MMM NNN NNN LLL LLL NNN N M NNN LLL LLL N NNN MMM −1 NNN N LLL LLL NNN NNN DrrU MMM NNN −1 LL& LL& DrDrU N NNN M& & DDU ω4 U & / NNN N N = NNN MMM LLL LLL NNN NNN N MMM LLL LLL NNN NNN NN LLL DU Dmn MMM LLL N N −1 NN N N N& N& DrDn N' −1 LL& LL& DrDDn MM& / NNN MMM / NNN N M N MMM −1 NNN DrmU MMMDDU mn NNNNN NNN N& M NN& & / . / −1 Substitute the pasting of DDU mn , DDω4 U , DDrDn and DDDrn−1 by the pasting of −1 DDω4 U U , DDrn and DDmU n . Then observe that the pasting of DDmU n , DDmn and DDDDµU equals the pasting of DDDµU , DDmnU and DDmn . Use (coh 6). To finish the proof, make the substitution / NNN NNN NNN −1 mrDU NN& LLL LLL LLL LL& / MMM MMM m−1 U mU MMM MMM DDω4 U / MMM NNN LLL NNN MMM LLL NNN MMM LLL NN& −1 MM& mDrU LL& / M = LLL LLL MMM LLL LLL LLL DDmn MMMMM LLL LL& LL& m−1 MM& DDn / NNN NNN m−1 mU NNN NN& / NNN NNN NNN NNN NNN NNN NN NNN NNN m−1 NNNN rU NN& NNN Dω4 U NNN NNN NNN NNN NNN NNN NN& NN& / MMM MMM MMM MM& NNN NNN NNN −1 mDn NN' NNN NN Dmn NNNN NN& / . Theory and Applications of Categories, Vol. 5, No. 5 108 6. Compatible pseudomonad structures We consider now the question of when can a pseudomonad be considered as the composite of two pseudomonads. Let D, U be pseudomonads on the same object K of the Gray-category A. Given another pseudomonad V = (V, v, p, βV , ηV , µV ) on the same object K, we say that V is compatible with the pseudomonads D and U if V = DU and there are invertible 2-cells: U B <<< < dU u θ1 |||| <<< z / DU, 1K DU DU DU DU JJ FF s9 w; s JJ p w F s p w F DU dU w DuDUss JJ F w F s JJ w w ss θ2 FF" θ3 J% ww ss / / DU, DU, DDU DU U Dn mU v subject to coherence conditions. To describe the coherence conditions introduce the following pastings: θ4 = / DU 5 DU θ−1 kkkDU 2 kkk kkk DU p DU Dn DU DU UTTT TTTT TT DU DU dU T) DU DU DU p pDU pU µV p−1 dU DU DU SSS 5 kkk SSS kkk θ k k p SSSS) k k DU dU 2 / DU, DU U Dn and θ5 = mU DU DDU DUTTT TTTT TT DuDU DU T) / DU DU 5 k k k kk k k k k pDU θ3 DU −1 DU DU DU Dp p DU p µ−1 Dup V DU DU 5 S SSS jj j j S j S j p SSSS) jjjjDuDU θ3 / DU. DDU mU The coherence conditions are: / DU, mm6 F m m m mmm mm99m m m m 99 θ2 5 −1 DU DU DU u 55 DU θ1 9 s 55 s ss 55 ss s s 5 ss DU dU Dn DU5 TTTT TTTT 55 TDU TTTvT 55 TTTT 55 T) 5 DU U Id ηV (12) p = DηU , Theory and Applications of Categories, Vol. 5, No. 5 (13) DU D ULL DuU 109 LLLDU dU LLL LL% Dn −1 DudU DU 9 DUQQQ ~ −1 ss QQQθ2 ss QQ s ssDuDU p QQQQQ s s ~ Q( s θ3 DdU / / DU DU DDU 7 mU −1 ηD U = DβU , Id (14) DDU LL D LLLDuDU mU LL duDU LLL% dDU / DU DU U DU QQQ ~ θ−1 dU DU ; v; QQQ 3 v v θ DU 1 v QQ v v p QQQQQ v Q( vv uDU ~ β V 1 DU DU = βD U, Id / DU U kk5 −1 k k θ U 3 k k kkkk pU mU U DDU U TTT TTTT TT DuDU U T) DU DU U DuDn DDn DU Dn (15) = DU θ−1 Dn 4 mn DU DU SSSS 5 j SSS jjjj j j j p SSSS) jj DuDU θ3 / DU DDU mU DnU DU U U SS SSS SSS DU dU U SS) / l5 DU U l l l lll lll pU DU DU U DU dn DU n (16) θ2 U −1 DU Dn θ4−1 = Dµ−1 U Dn DU DU SS SSSS jjj5 j j S j p SSSS) jjjjDU dU θ2 / DU DU U Dn / k5 DDU −1 k k Dθ k 3 kk kkkk Dp DmU DDDU TT TTTT TT DDuDU TT) DDU DU mDU m−1 uDU mU DU θ−1 5 (17) = µD U mU DU DU SS SSSS jjj4 j j S θ j p SSSS) jjjjDuDU 3 / DU DDU mU Some other equations we will need later are contained in the following: Theory and Applications of Categories, Vol. 5, No. 5 110 6.1. Proposition. Assume we have invertible 2-cells θ1 , θ2 , and θ3 , satisfying the coherence conditions. Then (Dn, θ4 ) : (βV U, µV U ) → (βV , µV ) (18) is a 1-cell in V-AlgK , and the following are 2-cells in V-AlgK : / (βV , µV ) p7 p DηU ppppp p ppp (Dn,θ4 ) Id (βV , µV )N NNN NNN NNN N' (DU u,p−1 u ) (19) (βV U, µV U ) (βV U, µV U ) (Dn,θ 4) V (DU n,p−1 )3 n gg gggg (βV U U, µV U U )W WWWWW + (DnU,θ4 U ) We also have that DµU VVVVV * (β , µ ), h4 V V hhhhh (20) (βV U, µV U ) (Dn,θ4 ) (p, θ5−1 ) : (βD U DU, µD U DU ) → (βD U, µD U ) (21) is a 1-cell in D-AlgK , and the following are 2-cells in D-AlgK : (DU p,m−1 Up) d2 ddddddd (βD U DU, µD U DUX) µV (βD U DU DU, µD U DU DUZ ) ZZZZZZZ , −1 (pDU,θ5 DU ) −1 ) XX(p,θ XXX5 X, (β U, µD U ), f2 D ffffff (βD U DU, µD U DU ) (p,θ5−1 ) (βD U5 DU, µD U DU ) SSS kk SSS(p,θ5−1 ) (DU dU,m−1 U dU kk)kk k kkkk k k k k (βD U U, µD U U ) θ2 (Dn,m−1 n ) (DU Dn,m−1 )2 U Dnd dddddd ZZZZZZZ ZZ, (pU,θ5 U −1 ) (23) SSS SSS SS) / (βD U, µD U ), (βD U DU, µD U DU ) θ4 (βD U DU U, µD U DU U ) (βD U U, µD U U ) −1 ) XXX(p,θ XXX5 X, (β U, µD U ), ff2 D fffff (Dn,m−1 n ) Furthermore, if we define σ1 as, U@ DU QQ QdU DU θ DU QQQQ( 1 uDU g3 DU DUOOO p gg ggg OOO g g g g OO' gggggggg vDU βV / DU Id (22) DU, (24) Theory and Applications of Categories, Vol. 5, No. 5 111 σ2 as PPP PPP P dU U DU PPP( d−1 U dU DU dnDU U DU dU DU / U DU dU DU DU DU dU DU/ DU DU DU RRR θ DU 2 RRR pDU R DnDU RRRR ( / DU DU DU U DURR nDU Up / U DU DU U dU DU U U DUPP d−1 Up DU p dU DU / DU DU µV p p / DU, γ as / U DU U U LL LLL LL dU DU d−1 U dU dU U LLL& DU dU n DU U OO / DU DU U dU OOO θ2 OOO p OOO ' / DU. Dn dn U dU then (σ1 , σ2 ) is an object in U-AlgK , and (dU, γ) : (βU , µU ) → (σ1 , σ2 ) is a 1-cell in U-AlgK . Proof. We show first that (Dn, θ4 ) is a 1-cell in V-AlgK . To show that (Dn, θ4 ) satisfies (9), start on the left hand side and make the substitutions: / JJ JJ βV U JJ JJ J$ / µV /9 , tt t t vDU dU tt tt t / / / / JJ JJβV DU JJ JJ J$ / O O = p−1 dU = / O O vp / βV DU / , t9 t t tt tt t / t βV and / θ2 $ = vDn . vDU dU / DU θ2−1 vp / v To show that (Dn, θ4 ) satisfies (10), start on the left hand side, cancel DU θ2 and its inverse, make the substitution / NN NNN NNN NNN NNN NNN NNN NN& DU p−1 dU &/ NNN NNN µV U NNN p−1 dU NN& / / OO OOO OOO p−1 OOO DU dU O' / N M = MMM NNN µV DU NNN MMM NNN MMM p−1 N' M& dU / . Theory and Applications of Categories, Vol. 5, No. 5 112 Then use (1), and conclude with DU DU θ2−1 / /$ p−1 DU dU p−1 p / / = / p−1 Dn /> AA AADU θ2−1 }}} AA } AA }}} } Next we show that DηU in (19) is a 2-cell in V-AlgK . To show that satisfies (11), start on the left hand side of (11). Use (12) to substitute the pasting of DU DηU and DU θ2−1 for the pasting of DU βV and DU DU θ1−1 . Then make the substitution DU DU θ1−1 / /$ p−1 u p−1 dU / / / = p−1 v / > . @@ @@DU θ1−1 ||| @@ | @@ ||| | Now use (5), and then use (12) once again. Next we show that DµU in (20) is a 2-cell of V-algebras. Start on the right hand side of (11). Use (16) to substitute the pasting of θ2 and DµU , by the pasting of DU d−1 n , DU θ4 and θ2 U . Make the substitution / OO OOO OOO p−1 n OOO O' / N MMM NNN −1 p MMM NNN dU MMM NNN MM& DU d−1 n N& / , / OO OOO OOO OOO OOO OOO OOO OOODU DU d−1 n O'/ ' O = OOO p−1 OOO dU U OOO p−1 Dn OO' / . Since we already know that (Dn, θ4 ) is a V-algebra morphism, we can substitute the pasting of µV , p−1 Dn , and θ4 , by the pasting of DU θ4 , θ4 and µV . By the definition of θ4 , we can substitute the pasting of µV U , p−1 dU U and θ2 U by the pasting of DU θ2 U and θ4 U . Finally, use (16). That (p, θ5−1 ) is a morphism of D-algebras, and that µV , θ2 , and θ4 are 2-cells of D-algebras are similar and left to the reader. Now we show that (σ1 , σ2 ) is an object in U-AlgK . Paste ηU DU −1 onto the left hand side of (7), and make a substitution on it to obtain / / OO OOO OOO −1 OOO d−1 d O OOO U uDU OOO U dU DU OOO OOO ' '/ / OOO OOOθ2 DU OOO OOO ηU DU '1 / d−1 Up µV (25) / / . Theory and Applications of Categories, Vol. 5, No. 5 113 Also paste ηU DU −1 on what turns out to be the right hand side of (7), and make the following two substitutions: E FF FF FF F# 5 FF k k U θ1 DUkk FF k k k FF kk U βV k F# k kk / dU DU = = C {{ CCC CC {{ { CC { {{ DU βV /! u: TTTTTT uu TTTT u TTTT uu u ) TT uu TTTT −1 : u TTTT v TdTUTTdU DU v uu d−1 TTTT v u U uDU v TTTT u TTTT v u TT) vv T* uu DU θ DU v 1 2 T e v e −1 T e TTTT dU p eeee vv e e e v e T e TTTT v eee DU βV vv eeeeee TTT) veveeeeeee / , / / = PPPP PPP η DU PPPV µV PPP p ' / / . Compare the pasting we arrive at with (25), and use equation (12). Now, the left hand side of (6) in this case, is the following pasting: / QQ / QQ QXQXQXXXX QQQ QQQ QQQ XXXXXX QQQ U d−1 QQQ XXXXX U d−1 QQQ Q QQQ U p U dU DU Q XXXXX QQQ QQQ QQQ XXXX+ Q/( QQQ /( RR QQQ QQQ RRR QQQ QQQ RRR QQQ QQQ U dU nDU RRR QQQ U µV U θ2 DU QQQ RRR Q Q( Q/( (/ QQQ QQQ QQQ QQQ QQQ QQQ d−1 d−1 QQQ Up U dU DU QQQ QQ( QQQ / / QQQ QQQ µU DU QQQ QQQ QQQ θ DU QQQ µV QQ2Q QQQ dnDU QQ( Q( / / . Make the following sequence of substitutions: / / µU DU / dnDU / U µV d−1 Up / µV / / = = t tt tt t t ztt Hµ HHV DU −1 HH HH HH $ / / = t tt tt t t ztt HH HdHU pDU HH HH H$ / DU µV t: KKKK tt KKK t t KKK tt d−1 U nDU tt / /% dnU DU DµU DU / 9 , HH t HH dnDU ttt HH HH tt H$ ttt / / J JJJ JJJ JJJ % / −1 dU p uu u u DU µV uu uu z u / , / J JJJ JJJ −1 pp JJJ / % µV uuu u µV uu uu z u / , d−1 U DU p Theory and Applications of Categories, Vol. 5, No. 5 / NN NNN NN NNN NNN U d NNNNN nDU NN& NN& / NNN −1 NdNNU nDU NNN d−1 U dU DU NN& / 114 / OO OOO OOO OOO O' / N M = MMM NNNd−1 U DnDU N MMM N MMM DU dnDU NNNN N& M& / , / d−1 U dU U DU / N NNN NNUNθ2 DU NNNNN NNN NNN NN& NN& NNN NNNdU pDU NNN NN& d U DnDU / = d−1 U DU dU DU / NNN NDU NNNθ2 DU NNN N& , and / NN / NN NNN NNN NNN NNN NNN NNN NNNU d N NNN NN& U dU DU NN& U d−1 Up &/ / NNNd−1 U DU NUNdU −1 NNN d−1 U DU p NNN dU DU dU DU / & / / / N NNN NNN d−1 NNN U U dU DU N& / / N N N = NNN NNN NNNd−1 U dU DU NNN NNN N NNDU NNN DU d−1NNNNN NN& d−1 N& N& Up U dU DU / / d−1 UUp On the other hand, the right hand side of (6) in this case is the pasting 8 N ppp NNNNN p p NNN ppp NN& ppp q8 qqq q q n−1 p qqq q q q 8 q q q qqq q q q q qqq n−1 qqq dU DU qqq qqq 8 qqq q q qq qqq q q eeee2 qqq eeeeee q e e e q e e qqq eeeeeeee qeqeqeeeeee / / / d−1 U dU DU d−1 Up / / MMM MMMθ2 DU µV MMM MM& d nDU / / . q8 p7 q p d−1 q p µ Up q V pp q qqq ppp q p q p / q / p pp8 pp87 d−1 p U dU DUppp p p ppp θ2 DU pppp p ppp pp ppp dnDU ppp pp ppp On this pasting make the following substitutions: / / N NNN NNN NNN N& / / NNN NNN NNN d NNN N NNN nDU NNN −1 NNNNN NNN NN& dU dU DU NN& d−1 NN& Up / / n−1 dU DU / Dn−1 dU DU / n−1 p / NN NNN NNN NNN & θ2 DU p Dn−1 p p p pp ppp p p / xp / NN / OO NNN OOO NNN NNN N OOO NNN −1 NNN −1 OOO d d N N N& U U dU DU N& UUp /' / = MMMM dnU DU MMM Dn−1 Dn−1 MMM p dU DU M& / / , = / NN / NN NNN NNN NNN NNN N NN NNN NNN NDU NN& DU d−1 NNNN& N& d−1 Up U dU DU / / θ2 U DU p pp pp p−1 ppp p−1 p p p dU DUppp p p p p ppp ppp ppp p p xppp p p x x / / Theory and Applications of Categories, Vol. 5, No. 5 115 and / p−1 dU DU / NN NNN NNN θ2 DU NNN .& = / PP APAPP PPP θ2 DU AAPPPDU PPP AA PPPP PPP AA PPP PP( ( P AA PPP AA PPµPV DU −1 AA PP AA θ4 DU PPPP A /( (definition of θ4 ). Compare both results, and use equation (16). The claim about (dU, γ) is left to the reader. Next we prove that the composite of two pseudomonads via a distributive law as defined in section 5, is compatible. 6.2. Theorem. Assume we have a distributive law as in section 4 and let V the composite pseudomonad defined in section 5. If we define θ1 = iddU ◦u , and θ2 as the pasting DU DUMM MMMDrU rr9 MMM MM& Dω U 2 / DDU U DU dUrrr rr rrr DU U Dn DdU U DDn Ddn / DDU DU UUUUU UUUU DdU ηD U −1 UUUU UUUU mU UUUU Id UU* DU, and θ3 as the pasting DU DUMM MMMDrU rr9 M Dω U MMMM & 1 / DDU U KK DDuU KK DDn KK DDβU KK KK % / DDU mU / DU, Id DuDUrrr rr rrr DDU then the pseudomonad V is compatible with U and D. Theory and Applications of Categories, Vol. 5, No. 5 116 Proof. Conditions (12), (13), and (14) are fairly easy and left to the reader. The remaining ones are also easy once we have shown that θ4 = DU DU U DU Dn / and DU DU mU DU / = θ5 DDU DU DrU Drn−1 / DDU U DrU U DDnU DDµU DDU U mU U DDn DU U Dn DDn mDn / DDU DDDn / DDU m−1 n DrU mrU / DDU U DDDU UmDU U DDn DDrU DDU U U DDU n DU DU DDDU DmU mU / DU, DDU mDU µD U mU mU / DU. To show the first equality above, start with the definition of θ4 and make the following substitutions: hh3 NNN hhhh NN h h h −1 NNN hhhh DU Dd h NNN n h h h hNhhh / /& 8 NNN DU Dω U −1 ppp 2 NNN p −1 DrDn NNN ppp −1 N& pppp DrrU / NNN Dr−1 p8 p NNN U dU p NNN ppp NN& ppppp / rr8 r r −1 r DrdU rrr −1 rrr Drn /8 , r8 p r p r p rr DDU d−1 n ppp p rrr p r p r r /8 pp NNN NNN DDU ω2 U −1 ppppp NNN p NN& ppppp = and 8 N ppp NNNNN p p NNN ppp −1 NN& ppp mU dU / −1 8 N N p m NNN p rU p p NNN p m−1 Dn NNN ppp Dω2 U Vppp &/ / VVVV p8 p VVVV p Dd n p VVVV VVVV ppp VVVV pppp + = {= DDD DD {{ { DD {{ {{ DDω2 U D/ ! QQQ QQQ QQQ QQQ QQQ QQQ QQQ QQQ DDd QQ( Q n Q( / QQQ −1 m n QQQ QQQ −1 mdU QQQ QQ( / . Now use (coh 3) on the pasting of DDU ω2 U −1 , DDω3 U , DDn−1 dU and DDω2 U . Next make the substitutions: / DDω2 U U ) = DDU d−1 n / −1 DDrn / DDd−1 Un / OO OOO OOO OOO ' DDω2 U pp p p p ppp xppp / , Theory and Applications of Categories, Vol. 5, No. 5 / OO OOO OOO OOO OOO OOO OOO OOO DDd−1 U n O'/ ' ?O?OO DDd ??OOO nU ?? OOOO DDDµU ?? OO' ?? o/7 ?? o o ?? DDdn oooo ?? ooo oo 117 / / DDµU DDdn = / , / and / DDdn m−1 dU / Dmn / µD U / ηD U −1 mU ◦ DDn ◦ DηD U U −1 . = / /; Finally, use (coh 8). The proof for θ5 is very similar, except that we need the equation: uU D / UUD 44 nn 44 βs{ D−1 44U 44 4 nD Id 44 44 44 44 U D4 UD Ur / U DU rU DU U px hh ω3 r Dn / DU = UD r / UUD uU D ur uDU / Ur DU LL U DU LLL ω1 U LL rU DuU LLL& DU U Id DβU ) Dn DU. To prove this last equation, observe that IdDU is isomorphic to Dn ◦ rU ◦ uDU , thus it suffices to show that the equation holds when followed by Dn ◦ rU ◦ uDU . And, since ur and ω3 are invertible, we can paste them below on both sides of the equation. This last equation is not hard to prove, using (coh 4) and (coh 2). The rest of the proof is left to the reader. 7. The Gray-category of pseudomonads in a Gray-category In this section we define the Gray-category PSM(A) of pseudomonads on a Gray-category A. The objects of PSM(A) are pseudomonads in A. Given pseudomonads D on K, and U on L, we denote the 2-category PSM(A)(D, U) as [D, U], and we define it as follows. The objects of [D, U] are pairs (G, G0 ), where G : U-Alg → D-Alg : Aop → Gray is a Gray-natural transformation, G0 ∈ A(L, K), such Theory and Applications of Categories, Vol. 5, No. 5 that Φ / D-Alg G U-Alg A( , L) 118 G0 ( ) Φ / A( , K) commutes, where Φ is the forgetful Gray-natural transformation defined in section 3. We can consider U-Alg and D-Alg as trihomomorphisms and G as a tritransformation. A 1-cell (G, G0 ) → (H, H0 ) in [D, U] is a pair (g, g0 ), where g : G → H is a strict trimodification, and g0 : G0 → H0 is in A(L, K), such that G U-Alg g + 3 D-Alg H = U-Alg Φ Φ A( , K) G0 ( ) , g0 ( ) 2 A( , K). A( , L) H0 ( ) What we mean by strict trimodification is, a trimodification in which all the invertible modifications required in the definition ([6],pg. 25) are identities. A 2-cell (g, g0 ) → (h, h0 ) in [D, U] is a pair (γ, γ0 ), where γ : g → h is a perturbation, and γ0 : g0 → h0 is in A(L, K), such that U-AlgX gX ⇓ γX + / ⇓ g D-Alg X X3 ΦX A(X , K) U-AlgX = ΦZ + γ0 ( ) A(Z, L) g0 ( ) ⇓ /⇓ h0 ( ) A(X , K). 3 Vertical and horizontal compositions are the obvious ones. The rest of the operations are defined as follows: (H, H0 )(G, G0 ) = (HG, H0 G0 ) (H, H0 )(g, g0 ) = (Hg, H0 g0 ) (h, h0 )(G, G0 ) = (hG, h0 G0 ) (τ, τ0 )(G, G0 ) = (τ G, τ0 G0 ) (H, H0 )(σ, σ0 ) = (Hσ, H0 σ0 ) 8. Liftings 8.1. Definition. A lifting is a pseudomonad in the Gray-category PSM(A). in PSM(A) has to have domain a In more detail, observe that a pseudomonad D pseudomonad U = (U, u, n, βU , ηU , µU ) in A, with domain some object K of A. Observe is of the form that D d), (m, β), ( = ((D, D), (d, D m), (β, η , η), ( µ, µ)). Theory and Applications of Categories, Vol. 5, No. 5 119 Taking the second entries, we obtain a pseudomonad D = (D, d, m, βD , ηD , µD ) in A on X , and the same object K. Furthermore, given an object X of A, we can define DX = D dX = dX etcetera, to obtain a pseudomonad DX = (DX , dX , mX , βX , ηX , µX ) in Gray, on the 2-category U-AlgX . D and the family DX X behave well with forgetful 2-functors and change of base. 9. From a pseudomonad with compatible structure to a pseudomonad in PSM(A) Assume we have a pseudomonad V that is compatible with pseudomonads D and U as in on the object U of PSM(A). Let X be an section 6. We want to define a pseudomonad D object of A. We begin by defining a 2-functor DX : U-AlgX → U-AlgX . Given an object (ψ, χ) in U-AlgX , with U XDD {= DD x uX {{{ D { { DDD! { ~ { ψ / X, X Id UUX nX UX Ux χ x / UX x / X, Define the first entry of DX (ψ, χ) as U DX F NN NNNU DuX NNN NNN & dU DX U DU XOO OOOdU DU X d−1 OOO uDX U DuX OOO θ1 DX ' __ / DU DU X DX ks __DU NNN DU DuX s9 oo7 NNNpX sss ooo NNN o v ssss DuX o o β X NN& V ss vDX ooo vDU X / DU X / DX DU X II DuX II Dx II II Dψ I$ Id . DX, Theory and Applications of Categories, Vol. 5, No. 5 120 and the second entry of DX (ψ, χ) as U U DX nDX U DU X U dU DU X U Dx / U U DU X / U DU DU X U pX / U DU X / U DX MMM 22 MUMMDuU X 22 U DuX MMM U Du−1 22 x M& 22 ks ____ / U DU X Id U DU U X 22dU U DU X U DβU X x q dU DUUUDU dU DU DU X q 22 X q q 22 dU DU X qqUqDnX q d−1 q 22 xq __ U DU x / DU DU X 22 nDU X U DU X ks __ DU DU U X d−1 DU DU x dU DnX qq U dU DU X 22 q 22 p pU X dU DUq X qqq p−1 d−1 x U pX 2 qq DU DnX q x DU dU DU X / DU DU DU X / DU DU X ks __ DU U X / DU X DU U DUNX DU pX DU x NNN θ4 X −1 rr r θ DU X NN 2 rr pDU X µ X pX Dx n−1 dnDU X DnDU XNNNN Dχ rrrDnX V r DuX N r ' xr / U DU X / DU DU X / DU X / DX. U U DuX U DuX pX dU DU X Dx If (h, ρ) : (ψ, χ) → (ψ , χ ) in U-AlgX , then define the first entry of DX (h, ρ) as Dh, and the second as the pasting U DX U DuX U DU X U Dh / U DX U DuX U Du−1 h / U DU X U DU h dU DU X d−1 U DU h / DU DU X dU DU X DU DU X DU DU h p−1 h pX DU X Dx DX DU h Dρ Dh pX / DU X Dx / DX Given ξ : (h, ρ) → (h , ρ ) in U-AlgX , define DX (ξ) = Dξ. 9.1. Proposition. The above definitions make DX : U-AlgX → U-AlgX a 2-functor. is a : U-Alg → U-Alg as DX at every object X of A, then D Furthermore, if we define D D) ∈ [U, U]. Gray-transformation, and (D, Proof. The hardest part of the proof is to show that DX (ψ, χ) is indeed an object in U-AlgX . This is what we do, and we leave the rest to the reader. We must show that (6) and (7) are satisfied. To show (7), pass ηU DX to the left hand side, and perform the following sequence of substitutions: / ηU DX −1 + / / n−1 DuX dnDU X / = / / / N rr8 rr8 rr8 NNNN r r r r r r NN r r r rrrU uDuX rrrrrd−1 rrr Dη DU X −1 NNNN U uDU Xrrr U &/ , rrr r / / Theory and Applications of Categories, Vol. 5, No. 5 / NN / NNNθ2 DU X NNN DηU DU X −1 NNN& 2 8 rrr r r rrrDU θ1 DU X rrr = / 8 ppp p −1 p p dU dU DU X pp−1 ppp dU uDU X /; 8 p p ppp pppDU θ1 DU X p p p / µV X ηV DU X −1 0 / = / = d−1 U pX /; / J JJ JJU uDuX JJJ JJ JJ JJ JJ J$ J$ / = JJ JJ JJ U θ1 DU X JJJ 1$ U DuX / NN NNN NNN NNN & U DβU X p p p pp ppp p p xp /; 7 , d−1 U vDU X }> }} } }}DU βV X }} r8 rrr r r rr U βV X rrr (see (12)) /C , pX /; , dU DU X / NN 8 N NNN ppp NNNNN p N p N p N p NNN −1 NNNNN p p U θ DX 1 p U d &/ U DuX /& VpVVV VVVV pp8 p VVVV p VVVV U vDuX pppp VVVV V+ ppp / NN NNN NNN NNN NN NNN NN& U Du−1 NNNN& uX / NN NNN NNN NNN U DηU X −1 & 0 , = / NN 8 N NNN ppp NNNNN p NNN p NNN p p NNN p −1 N p d U Dη X N U DnX p U p &/ &/ / NN NNN pp8 NNNNN p p N NNN NNN pp p p −1 −1 NN N p DU Dη X θ X N N& p 4 U p &/ / / ; NN NNN NNN N ηV DU X −1 NN& / , 8 rrr r r rrr U θ1 DU X rrr = / p8 ppp p p pp−1 ppp dU vDU X 8 ppp p p ppp DU βV X ppp 121 = / NN 8 N NNN ppp NNNNN p NNN p N p N p N p Dχ NNN& DηU X −1 NN& ppp / / = JJ −1 / JJ JJdU DU uX JJ JJ JJ JJ JJ J$ J$ / JJ JJ JJ DU DηU X −1JJJ % 0 , JJ −1 / JJ JJ puX JJ JJ JJ JJ JJ J$ J$ / J JJ JJ J DηU X −1 JJJ % 0 , = v: vv v v vv DU ψ vv /> (see (19)) Dx / , Theory and Applications of Categories, Vol. 5, No. 5 and / / U Du−1 uX U Du−1 x d−1 U DU uX d−1 U DU x p−1 uX p−1 x / / = /: U Dψ U DuX / / 122 / / /; . dU DU X pX DU ψ To get from the left hand side of (6) to the right hand side, make the following sequence of substitutions: / NN NNN NNN NNN NNN NNN −1 NNN NNU & nDuX &/ NNN NNµNU DX NNN n−1 DuX NN& / / / µU DU X dnDU X / = / TTT SSS T SSS SSS U dnDU XTTTTTT S) T)/ d−1 U nDU X 1 θ4 DU X / / / NN NNN NNN d−1 U DU dU DU X NNN / / & NNN NNN NNN d−1 NNN NNU pX N DU θ2 DU X NNNN DU µV X NNN &/ &1 / (definition of θ4 ) d−1 U DU pX / p−1 dU DU X / d−1 U DnDU X / = / = d−1 U dU U DU X d−1 U pX d−1 U DnDU X t: JJJ JJ tt t JJ tt JJ t tt DU θ2 DU X /$ DµU DU X /5 , 6 l k l k d l nDU X k kk lll kkk llll / kk / OO OOO (see (16)) OOO OOO OOO OOO OOO OO' DU d−1 '/ nDU X θ2 U DU X p p p p p p θ4 DU Xpp pp pp ppp p p ppp p x xpp / , / / = dnU DU X d−1 U dU DU X / , l6 −1 k5 lDU k l k l d k nDU ll kk kkX llll / kk / NN / NN NNN NNN NNN NN N U θ2 DU X NN& U µV X NNNN& / 1 / TTT SSS TTTT SSS SSSd−1 SU) nDU X TTTT)/ = / / NN NNN NNN NNN & DµU DU X θ2 DU X p p p pp ppp p p / xp / K KK KK KK n−1 U DuX KK K% / JJ = HHH µ DU X J U JJ HH JJ HH JJ HH n−1 DuX $ / % , / µV DU X θ2 DU X /6 , Theory and Applications of Categories, Vol. 5, No. 5 / NN NNN NN NNN NNN DU µ XNNNNN V NN& NN& / NNN µ DU X NNVN NNN µV X NN& / / PP / PP PPP PPP PPP PPP PPP PPP PPP P PPP PPP PPP −1 −1 PP( U d U d P P ( ( U pX U dU DU X −1 / / PPPdU dU U DU X PPP −1 PPP dU DU pX d−1 PPP U DU dU DU X P( / / θ2 U DU X ) / K KK KK KK KK K% / H J = HH JJ µV X J HH HH µ X JJJJ HH V J% $ / , p−1 pX DU d−1 U dU DU X DU d−1 U pX p−1 dU DU X p−1 pX / J JJ t: JJJ JJ JJ tt t JJ JJ t t J t U d J$ U DnX JJ$ tt U U DβU X / / / / / QQ QQQ QQQ QQQ QQ( / / PPP OOO OOO d nDU X P OOO OOO PPP OOO OOO PPP OOO OOO PPP d−1 O' d−1 O/' (/ , U pX U dU DU X = = 8/ NNN 8 NNN rrr rrrU d−1 r r U DuU X r r NNN r r r r r r NN& rr U DU DβU X r rrr / , / / / d−1 U DU DuU X d−1 U DU DnX p−1 DuU X p−1 DnX = dU DU DU X / / pDU X = / / / ; , / PP PPP PPP PPP PP' / O N = NNN OOdO−1 OOdU NNN U UX OODU NNN OOO −1 DU d NN' U DuU X O' / , d−1 U U DuU X DU d−1 U DuU X p−1 DuU X / DU DβU X / OO OOO OOO OOO OOO OOO OOO OOUO d−1 U DuU X O'/ ' OOO −1 dOUOdU DU X OOO d−1 OOO U DU DuU X O' / / n−1 pX n−1 dU DU X : J tt JJJ JJ tt t tt U DU Dβ X JJJ t U t /$ / K KKK KKK KKK % Dn−1 pX θ2 DU X tt t tt tt t y / , t Dn−1 dU DU X / / PP / PP PPP PPP PPP PPP PPP PPP PPP P PPP PPP −1 PPP −1 PP( d d P P ( ( U U pX U U dU DU X / / PPP dnU DU X PPP PPP Dn−1 Dn−1 pX PPP dU DU X P( / / ) / = / / / QQ QQQ QQQ QQQ QQ( / / PPP d−1 OOO OOO PPP U dU DU X OOO OOO PPP OOO OOO OOO OO −1 −1 PPP ODU ' dU dU DU X OO'/ DU dU pX P(/ , d−1 U U pX d−1 U U dU DU X / θ2 DU X / = / / 123 Dn−1 DuU X / OO OOO OOO OOO ' θ2 DU U X p p p p p ppp xppp / , Theory and Applications of Categories, Vol. 5, No. 5 / OO OOO OOO OOO OO OOO −1 OOdOU U DuU X OOOOO ' '/ OOO OOdOnDU X OOO Dn−1 DuU X OOO ' / = 124 / / n−1 DuU X dnDU U X / U DβU X , / dU DnX / , DU DβU X , / OOO OOO OOO OOO OOO O OOO U θ4 X −1 OOOOO ' '/ OOO −1 d OOUODU DnX OOO d−1 U pX OOO ' / / OO OOO OOO OOO OO OOO OOODU θ4 X −1 OOOOO ' '/ OOO OOOp−1 DnX OOO µV X OOO ' / U DnX / PP PPP PPP µV U X PPP PP' / O N = NNN OOO θ X OOO 4 NNN NNN −1 OOO θ X OO' 4 NN' / , / NN NNN NNN NNN & U DβU X pp p p p ppp xppp / J JJ t: JJJ JJ JJ tt t J t d JJU DnX JJJ tt J J$ t t $ /: U DµU X t: JJ JJ t−1 tt t t JJ t t JJ tt dU DnXttt J$ ttt t t / / J JJ t: JJJ JJ J tt t JJ θ4 X −1 JJJ t t J JJ t J$ tt /$ DU DµU X t: JJ t: JJ t t JJ tt θ4 X ttt JJ tt t J$ ttt tt / t = t: KKKK tt KKK t t KKK U Dχ tt tt / /% U Du−1 nX U Du−1 x d−1 U DU nX d−1 U DU x p−1 nX p−1 x / / / / PP PPP PPP d−1 PPP U pU X PP' / OOO = NNNN −1 O d OO U DnX NNN NNN DU θ X −1OOOO OO' 4 NN' / , = = / OO OOO OOO OOO OO OOO OO' U Du−1 OOOO' nX / U DβU U X p pp ppp p p p p p U DµU Xppp ppp pp xppp / , xp / t: t: JJJ JJ tdt−1 tt t t JJ t t JJ tt U DU nX tt t t t $ t / DU DµU X JJ JJ : JJ JJ tt t JJd J t JJU DnU X JJJ tt J$ J$ ttt / / t: t: JJJ JJ tt p−1 ttt t JJ nX tt tt JJ t t tt $ tt / DµU X JJ JJ t: JJ JJ t JJ J tt JθJ4 U X −1 JJJ tt J$ J$ ttt / = / , / / U Du−1 Ux U Du−1 x d−1 U DU U x d−1 U DU x p−1 Ux p−1 x / / / / (see (18)) / / / 9 , / HH t HH HH DU χ tttt HH HH tttt $ t (see (20)) Theory and Applications of Categories, Vol. 5, No. 5 / OO OOO OOO OOO OO OOO OOO DU χ OOOOO ' '/ OOO OOODµU X OOO Dχ OOO ' / / PP PPP PPP Dn−1 PPP x PP' / O N = NNN OOO OOO Dχ NNN OOO NNN Dχ OO' NN' / , / NN NNN NNN NNN NN NNN NN& U Du−1 NNNN& Ux / U DβU U X p pp p −1 p dU DU U x ppp xppp dU DnU X / p p ppp p−1 Ux ppp −1 p p xp θ4 U X / p p p p p p −1 Dnx ppp pp ppp ppp xppp / xpp /8 / 8 pp8 ppp U d−1 ppp U p−1 x ppp p p U DU x p p p p ppp ppp pppd−1 U DU x ppp / pp / pp p8 ppp −1 p p d d−1 U pU X U dU DU U X ppp / / pp / OO OOO OOO OOO OOO OOO OOO OOO DU p−1 x O'/ ' OOO OOOµV U X OOO p−1 x OOO ' / / θ2 DU U X ) and 125 = / / 8 ppp p −1 −1 p dU pX dU dU DU X ppp ppp d−1 U U DU x / /8 8 pDU p8 −1 −1 ppp p p d p p DU px pp U DUp xp pp p ppp ppp p p ppp p p p p p p / / / PP PPP PPP p−1 PPP DU x PP' / O N = NNN OOO µ X OOO V NNN NNN −1 OOO p OO' x NN' / , = = DU d−1 U DU x / p−1 DU x / / J JJ JJ JJ JJ $ U DβU X t t t tt tt ztt dU DnX t tt tt d−1 t U DU x tt −1 / zt θ4 X t tt tt p−1 t x tt / zt Dn−1 DU x / OO OOO OOO OOO ' θ2 DU X p p p pp ppp p p / , xp / OO OOO OOO OOO OO OOO −1 OOO dU U DU x OOOOO ' '/ OOO OdOnDU UX OOO Dn−1 OOO DU x O' / / PP PPP PPP PPP PP' / OOO = NNNN d O X OOnDU NNN OOO NNN −1 NN' dU DU x OOO' / , / OO OOO OOO OOO OOO OOO OOO OOO U U Du−1 x O'/ ' OOO −1 OOnODuU X OOO n−1 DU x OOO ' / / PP PPP PPP n−1 PPP Dx PP' / P O = OOO PPP n−1 PPPDuX OOO PPP OOO PP' OO' U Du−1 x / . n−1 DU x Theory and Applications of Categories, Vol. 5, No. 5 126 We are now ready to define dX : 1 → DX , and mX : DX DX → DX . The first entry of (dX )(ψ,χ) is dX, while the second is the pasting / U DX ;; VVVVV VUVuX ;; VVVVV U DuX U duX ;; VVVVV V+ ;; ; U U X U dU X / U DU X dU X ;; ;; ;; dU U X dU DU X d−1 d−1 U dU X U uX ; DU dU X / DU DU X DU X DU uX / DU U XQQ Q Q θ QQQ 2 X DηU X −1 pX QQ DnX QQQ( / DU X Id U X; VVVVVV x U dX dx X Dx / DX, dX and (dX )(h,ρ) = dh . Define the first entry of (mX )(ψ,χ) as mX, and the second as the pasting U DDX SS U DuDX / U DU U mX SSSS SSSS S U DDuX SSSS) U DuX U muX / U DU X U DU DXSS U DDU XSS U mU X SSSS U Du−1 SSSS dU X SSSS SSDDU DuX S SSSS U DuDU X dU DU DX S U DU DuX SSSS) SS) d−1 U mU X s k _ _ dU DU X DU DU DX U DU DU X dU DuDU X DU DDURX SSSS k R k RRR SSSS d−1 kk k DU mU X R k U DU DuX R k SSS RRR DU θ X pDX dU DU DUkk Xkk RRR 3 DU DU DuX SSSS) ukkkk DU DuDU X ) _ _ s k / DU DU X DU DX p−1__ DU DU DU X DU pX DuX kkk kkkk k k DU DuX k k ukkkk pDU X DU DU X YYYYYY YYYYYY YYYYId YYYYYY pX DdU DU X µV X YYYYYY ηD U DU X YYYY, / DU DU X DDU DU X RRR mU DU X RRR RRR DpX θ5 X pX RRRR) / DU X DDU X mU X DDx DDX mX mx Dx / DX. Define (mX )(h,ρ) = mh . 9.2. Proposition. With the above definitions, dX : 1 → DX and mX : DX DX → DX are strong transformations. Furthermore, defining d as dX , and m as mX at every object Theory and Applications of Categories, Vol. 5, No. 5 127 d) : 1 → (D, D) and (m, D)(D, D) → (D, D) are X of A, we have that, (d, m) : (D, 1-cells in the 2-category [U, U]. Proof. The size of the diagrams obtained is what makes it hard to prove that (mX )(ψ,χ) satisfies (10). To get from the left hand side of (10) to the right hand side make the following three substitutions: TTTT TTTT TTTT T ) TTTUTDu−1 TTTpX TTTT T ) TTTdT−1 U DU pX TTTT TTT) T TTTTp−1 TpX TTTT TT) T −1 TTTTDdU pX TTTT TTT) T TTTT DµV X TTTT TTT) / TTT TTTT TTTT T)/ U θ5 X TTTT TTTT TTTT TTTT TTTT TTTT T TTTT TTTT TTTT TTTT TTTT U mx TTTT TTTT TTTT T T TT) TTTT T −1 T) / T T U Du TTTT Dx TTTT TTTT TTTT TTTT TTTT TTT) TTT) TTTT T TTTTd−1 TTTT T HHTTT −1 U DU Dx T U Du TTTT TTTT DuX TTTTTTT HH TTTT HH TTT TTTT TTTT TTTT T HH ) ) ) T HH TTTTTT p−1 −1 T d TTdTUTDU DuX U DuDU X jjj TTTTDx j HH j T j TTTT j HH TTTT T) ujjjjj $ T DU DβU X −1 ) −1 DU Du T j j x T j j p TTTT j jj DuX TTTT jjjj jjjj T) Yujjjjj ujjjjDdU DnX T −1 YYYYYY j TTTDd YYYY TTUTTDU x jjjj j j ηD U DU X YYYYYYYYY j T T j YYYYY, j T T) ujj Dθ4 X −1 T / Dp−1 T j x T j T j T j T j T j TTTT jj T) YujjYjj YYYYYY DDχ YYYYYY YYYYYY YYYYY, TTTT TTTT TTTT U muX )/ TTTT d−1 X TTUTmU TTTT T/) DU θ3 X TTTT µV X TTTT TTTT θ5 X )/ mx / = [[[[[[[[ [[[[[[[[ [[[[[[[[ [[[[[/ U θ3 DU X d−1 U pDU X / VVV VVVV VVVV VVV U DβU X hhh+ h h hhh shhhhhh −1 / VVV d d U DnX hhh U pX VVVV h h h VVVV h VVV+ shhhhhhh / U Du−1 x / d−1 U DU x / V VVVV p−1 x VVVV θ4 X −1 V V ηD U DU DU X VVV/+ V µV DU X / µV X VVVV hhh h VVVV h h h Dχ VVVV hhhh [[ V/+ θ5 DU X /3 shhh [[[[[[[[ h h/3 h θ5 X hhhh mx [[[[[[[[ hhhh h h h h h [[[[[[[[ h hhh [[[- hhhhh / hhh Theory and Applications of Categories, Vol. 5, No. 5 NNN NNN NNN NN& NNNd−1 NUNpDX NNN NNN & NNN µV DX NNN NNN NN& / NN NNN NNN NNN −1 U pDuX /& NNN NNN NNN U Du−1 U DuX NN& / U DβU DX p pp p −1 p dU DU U DuX ppp xppp / dU DnDXp p p p p ppp xppp −1 θ4 DX −1 p NN pU DuX NNN p p p NNN p NNN ppp p p xp & NNN NNN NNN NNN NNN Dn−1 NNN DuX NNN NN& 128 NNN NNN NNN U ηD U DU X UVDu−1 NN& VVdU NNN VVDU VVVXV N θ3 DU X VVVV NU VVVNVNNNN VVVVN& V + VVVV VVVVd−1 U DU dU DU X VVVV VVVV VVVV + p−1 dU DU X / NNN NNN NNN DdU dU DU X NN& / NNN NNN2 DU X Dθ NNN NN& DdnDU X / / N NNN NNN NNN NNN NNN U µV X NNN NNN N& / /8* < p < p p < p < p << ppp << ppp << d−1 U pX −1 << dU pDU X << < / / NNN NNN NNN µV DU X ηD U DU DU X NN& / NN NNN NNN NNN θ DU X 5 /& = / / d−1 U DU DU DuX / p−1 DU DuX / p−1 DuX / NN 8/ NNNηD U DU X ppp p NNN p NNN ppppp & p d−1 U DU pX / / d−1 U pX / p−1 pX / NN µ X NNN V NNN NNN µV X &/ and g3 OOO ggggg OOO g g g g OOO gg g g g g gg U U muX OOO '/ gOgggg / WOOWWW NNN OOOO OOOWWWWW NNN W O O W W O O W NN WWWWW OOO OOO −1 W O O WWWW+ U D−1 NNNNN OU' U DuDuX O/' N U mU W OOOU dU DuDU X WWWW X OO WWWWW NNNNN OOO OOOO WWWWW NNN OOO OOO OOO OOOU d−1 U DU θ3 X WWWWWNWNW n−1 N+'/ DuDX ' ' U DU DuX −1 / OOdOU dU DU DX OOO OOO OOO −1 OOO OOO d−1 U DU pX OOO dU DU DU DuX OOO / ' ' WW d / WWnDU θ2 DU X WWWDX WWWWW WWWWW p−1 p−1 pX DU DuX WWWWW W+* / / µV X / Theory and Applications of Categories, Vol. 5, No. 5 = 129 / PP PPP PPP PPP PP( PXPXPXXXX n−1 mX PPP XXXXXX X PPP PPP XXXXXXXXXX P XXX+ / ( Q −1 PPP PPP n−1 QQQ dU dU DU X PPP PPP DuX QQQ PPP PPP QQQ PPP PPP QQQ U m uX P( P/( ( PPP PPP U Du−1 PPP PPP DuX PPP PPP PPP PPP PPP θ2 DU X PPP P PPP P( dU DuDU X PPP( PPdPnDU X −1 X PPPd−1 PP nn XXXXXdXUXmU PPUPDU DuX XXXXXX PPPPP nnn PPP n X n XXXXX PPP PPP nn XXXXXPP( ! DU θ3 X P' wnnnn X/+ . The fact that the three equalities above are indeed satisfied and the rest of the proof are left to the reader. and µ It is easily seen that, defining η, β, at every X as (ηX )(ψ,χ) = ηD X, (βX )(ψ,χ) = β), and ( η , η), (β, µ, µ) in [U, U]. We thus βD X, and (µX )(ψ,χ) = µD X, we obtain 2-cells ( have: d), (m, β), ( = ((D, D), (d, 9.3. Theorem. D m), (β, η , η), ( µ, µ)) is a pseudomonad in PSM(A), on the object U. 10. From a pseudomonad in PSM(A) to a distributive law Assume that we have a pseudomonad in PSM(A) as in section 8. We produce a distributive law as follows. Consider DK : U-AlgK → U-AlgK . Since the diagram U-AlgK ΦK DK A(K, K) / U-Alg ΦK D( ) K / A(K, K) commutes, we have that DK (βU , µU ) is of the form (σ1 , σ2 ) with U? DU@ @@ @@s @@ uDU DU U U DU | σ1 Id nDU / DU, DK U DU U U-AlgK DK / U-Alg K U / U-Alg / U DU σ2 Furthermore, since the diagram U-AlgK Us K s s / DU. Theory and Applications of Categories, Vol. 5, No. 5 130 is the change of base 2-functor defined in section 3, then DK (n, µU ) : commutes, where U DK (βU U, µU U ) → DK (βU , µU ) is of the form (Dn, σ3 ) : (σ1 U, σ2 U ) → (σ1 , σ2 ) with σ3 of the form U Dn / U DU U DU U σ3 sU DU U s / DU. Dn Similarly, it can be shown that (dK )(βU ,µU ) is of the form (dU, σ4 ), with UU U dU / n σ U U DU 4 dU s / DU. If we apply DK to (σ1 , σ2 ) we obtain another U-algebra (σ1 , σ2 ), with U DDU < FF x xx uDDU xx x x xx U U DDU DDU FF FsF F σ1 F# / DDU, nDDU U s / U DDU σ2 U DDU s s / DU. Applying DK to (s, σ2 ) : (βU DU, µU DU ) → (σ1 , σ2 ), we obtain a morphism (Ds, τ1 ) with U DU DU sDU U Ds / U DDU τ1 DU DU s / DDU. Ds We also have that (mK )(βU ,µU ) is of the form (mU, γ1 ), with U DDU s DDU U mU / U DU γ1 mU s / DU. Define σ5 as the pasting U DuDU / U DU U mU U DDU Id U Dσ1−1 OOO OOO sDU U Ds OOO' DU DUOO τ1 U DDU OOO OOO s Ds OOO' U DU DU OO DDU s γ1 mU / DU. Theory and Applications of Categories, Vol. 5, No. 5 131 It is with the help of σ1 to σ5 that we define the distributive law as follows: Define r = s ◦ U Du, ω1 as the pasting U D NN s9 NU NNDu ss NN' s ss u Du D JJJ U 8 DUNNN s JJJ NN ppp p p J σ1 NN& pp uDU Du $ / DU, DU uD Id ω2 as the pasting U dsss9 U D NN NU NNDu NN' U d u pU 8 DUNNN NN pp p p s NN& pp U dU DU, U U NN σ4 NNnN pp8 p p NNN p −1 ηU & ppp dU Id 1U s sss U JJJ JJUJu J$ ω3 as the pasting UUD U U Du/ U U DU nD Us / U DU U DuU/ U DU U sU / DU U LLL LLL LU DβU U Dn Id LLL% U DUKK nDU n−1 Du / U DU UD σ2 s U Du Dn KKK σ3−1 KK s KKK % / DU, and ω4 as the pasting UD O U Du / U DU O //// U mu U mU / U DU DU U DDU QQQ o7 U DuU−1DuDU nn6 o QQQsDU n o n o n o Du QQQ n s−1 oo nUnDU Du o QQQ n o n U DDu Du nn oo ( / / / DU DU U DD U DU D DU D Um U DuD / DU O s sD DU Du //// σ5 Ds mU / DDU. The proof that we obtain a distributive law in this way is based on the behavior of the 2-cells σ1 -σ5 . Aside from the obvious conditions that come from the facts that (σ1 , σ2 ) is a U-algebra, (Dn, σ3 ) and (dU, σ4 ) are homomorphisms of U-algebras, we have the following conditions. 10.1. Proposition. The following are 2-cells in U-AlgK : DηU : Id → (Dn, σ3 ) ◦ (DU u, s−1 u ). (26) Theory and Applications of Categories, Vol. 5, No. 5 132 DµU : (Dn, σ3 ) ◦ (DU n, s−1 n ) → (Dn, σ3 ) ◦ (DnU, σ3 U ). dn : (Dn, σ3 ) ◦ (dU U, σ4 U ) → (dU, σ4 ) ◦ (n, µU ). (27) Furthermore, the following equations are satisfied: DDULL / U DDU U mU / U DU uDDU LLLDuDU LLL LL% uDuDU U DuDU mU = DU DUNNuDU DU/ U DU DU Id NNN N NσN1 DU sDU NNN ' Dσ1 σ5 s DU DU $ DDU Ds DDU mU uDDU/ DU KK U DDU umU uDU / U mU U DU KKK σ1 KKK Id KK% s DU, / DU / NN NNN NNN NNN NNN NNN NNN & N NNN NNN NNN NNN NN& NNN N??NN NNN NNN ??NNN N ?? NN NNN ?? NNN NNN N ? NNN N ? N −1 N U σ5 ⇓ ⇐ ? n NNN NNN N DuDU Uo DβU DU ? N NNN NNN UNN Du−1 NN⇐ s '/ ' NNN NN⇐ σ2 DU N NNN N NNN &N ⇐ N& NNN σ3 DU −1 −1 NNN s s ⇐ O e NN& eeeeeee OO ⇐ OOO re NNN OOO NNN OO NNN NNN Dσ2 ' NNN σ5 N⇐ NNN ⇐ NNN ' / = / U U DU LL LL LL −1 nDDU nDU LL nmU LL LL LL / LL U DDUOO U mU U DULL LL OOO LL LLU s LL OOO LL L LL O L LL U DuDU OO' LL LL LL LL LL L U DU DU LL LL NNN LL LL NNN LL L LL NNN LL L s LL NN' LL sDU & LL LL L DU DU U DU L LLL LL LL σ2 LLL σ5 L s LL L LL Ds LLL% & / DU DDU U U DDU U U mU mU (28) Theory and Applications of Categories, Vol. 5, No. 5 133 / U DU U = U DDU UU mU U / U DU U K JJ K OOO KKKU Dn JJU Dn JJ OOO KKK U DuDU U JJ O KK% U mn U DDn OO' J$ / U DU DUOOU U−1 DDU U mU U DU U DU DU U U DU OOO U DuDn O OOO sDU U U DuDU sDU U sU U DU Dn OO' U DDU OUO U mU U DU DU OUO U DU DU DU DU U OOO s−1 OOO Dn sDU DsU OOO DU Dn ' DDU UOO DU DU OOO Dσ3 OOO Ds σ5 DDn OOO' DDU U DUMM U DuU MMM MM U DdU MMM& U DU UMM s σ5 U DDU UNN mU U / DU UJJ σ3 NNN JJ Dn JJ NNN JJ N m n N DDn J$ N& / DU. DDU s DsU / DU mU = U DDU −1 U mU MMM U DudU MMM U DuDU U DU dU MM& DU UMM U DU DU MMM s−1 MMM dU sDU Dn MM& DU dU DU MM DU DU MMM Dσ4 MMM Ds σ5 DdU MM& U DU U uDU mU LLLId LLL U DuU −1 LL% U DβU / U DU U DU U # / U DU U Dn sU U DU s DU / DU, : vvvv v DdU vv vv mU Id ηD U = U DULL rr LLLU dDU LLL LL% Id s k s k _ _ _ _ U U DULL ηU DU U βD U Ur DDU LLL rr LLL rrr r L r nDU L% yrr U mU U uDUrrr rr ry rr U DU dU DU dDU / DU / DU sDU σ4 DU / DU DU Ds Dn s DDU / U DDU MMM MMUMmU U duDU U DuDU MMM M& / U DU DU U DU σ3 s U dDU ds DU U U U DU U dU DU nDU (30) U DULL sU DDU mU Id U ηD U (29) σ5 s / DDU MMM MMmU MMM MM& βD U 0 DU Id s DU, Theory and Applications of Categories, Vol. 5, No. 5 134 U mU / U6 DDU U DU n nn n U DmU n n U DuDU nnn nnn _ _ U DDDU Uks Du−1 Un6 DU DU mU nn nnn n U DuDDU sDU n n nnn U DU mU U DU DDU ks s__−1 nDU DU 6 mU nn n n n s sDDU σ5 nnn nnn DU mU DU DDU DU DuDU Ds DU DU DU DsDU Dσ5 / DU DDU 8 6 mU qq nnn q nnn n qqq DDs µ U n D q n q n nn DmU qq mU / DDU DDDU DDU DU mDU = U mU / U6 DDU U DU m m qq8 q U DmUmmmm q q m U µD U qqqqU mU mmm q mmm Ul DDDU U mDU / U DDU l l U DuDDU U DDuDU lll U DuDU lll l l U muDU vll __ _ ks _ U DU DDU U DDU DUU mU DU / U DU DU RRR U Du−1 RRR DuDU RRR s sDDU U DuDU DU RR U DU DuDU RR( __ DU DDURR sks−1 U DU DU DU RRRDuDU RRR R sDU DU σ5 DU sDU DU DuDU RRRR( (31) DU DU DU DsDU DDU DU DDs DDDU DU. 8 q qqq Ds qqq qqq mU mU DU / DU DU mDU / DDU ms σ5 Observation: The equations that appear in the proposition can be written as condi- Theory and Applications of Categories, Vol. 5, No. 5 135 tions in U-AlgK . For instance, it can be shown that the pair of pastings: ϕ = U DDU B NN NNNU DuDU NNN NNN ' uDDU uDuDU U DU DU 7 NNN pp NNsDU uDU DUppp NNN p p p p NNN' pp DuDU σ1 DU / DU DU / DU DU DDU LLL Id LLLDs LLL L% Dσ1 Id . DDU, and ϑ U U DuDU = nDDU / U sDU nDU DU / U Ds QQQ QQUQDuU DU QQQ } U Du−1 s QQQ Q( ks ____ Id U DβU DU mmmm U DU s m mmm m m U DnDU vmmm sU DU } s−1 / / U DuDU sDU s sDU | n−1 DuDU U DuDU | σ2 DU / sDU ks __ n n σ3 DU −1 nnn nn nnnDnDU n n / vn / DU s | Dσ2 Ds / , Ds define an object in U-AlgK . Thus, the first two equations say that (mU, σ5 ) : (ϕ, ϑ) → (σ1 , σ2 ) is a U-algebra morphism. Similarly the rest of the equations. We leave the details for the interested reader. Proof. The fact that DηU and DµU are 2-cells in U-AlgK follow from applying DK to ηU and µU , respectively. The statement about dn follows from pseudonaturality of dK . As for the equations, the proof of the last equation is fairly typical, and it is the only one we do. We begin by introducing some notation and deducing some equations we will need. The notation is DK ( (βU DDU, µU DDU ) DK ((σ1 DU, σ2 DU ) DK ((σ1 , σ2 ) (s ,σ2 ) / (σ , σ )) 1 2 (Ds,τ1 ) / (σ , σ )) 1 (mU,γ1 ) 2 / (σ1 , σ2 )) = (Ds ,τ2 ) (σ1 DDU, σ2 DDU ) 1 (DDs,τ3 ) / (σ , σ ), = (σ1 DU, σ2 DU ) = (DmU,γ2 ) / (σ , σ ), (σ1 , σ2 ) 1 2 and (mK )(σ1 ,σ2 ) = (mDU, γ3 ) : (σ1 , σ2 ) → (σ1 , σ2 ). / (σ , σ ), 1 2 2 Theory and Applications of Categories, Vol. 5, No. 5 136 Now the equations. Since U-AlgK DK DK , mK 2 U-AlgK = U-AlgK DK ΦK A(K, K) ΦK DD( ) , m( ) 2 A(K, K), A(K, K) D( ) we have that ms = (mK )(s,σ2 ) is a 2-cell (σ1 DU, σ2 DU ) (DDs,τ3 ) (mU DU,γ1 DU ) / (σ1 DU, σ2 DU ) ms (σ1 , σ2 ) (Ds,τ1 ) / (σ , σ ) 1 (mDU,γ3 ) 2 in U-AlgK . From this we obtain the equation / PP PPP PPP / PPP PPP τ1 ( PPP m PPP PP( s PP( / / QQ PPP QQ PPP PPU( ms QQQQ( / PPP τ3 PPP γ3 PP' / . = γ1 DU (32) Similarly, (µK )(βU ,µU ) is a 2-cell (σ1 , σ2 ) (mDU,γ3 ) (σ1 , σ2 ) (DmU,γ2 ) / (σ , σ ) 1 µD U 2 (mU,γ1 ) / (σ1 , σ2 ). (mU,γ1 ) We thus obtain the equation / PP PPP PP PPP PUP( µD U PPPP( / PPP γ3 PPP γ1 PP( / / QQ QQQ QQQ / OOO γ1 ( OOO O OOO OOµ' D U OOOO' / , = γ2 Observe that (βU DU DU, µU DU DU ) (sDU,σ2 DU ) (σ1 DU, σ2 DU ) (U Ds,n−1 Ds ) τ1 (Ds,τ1 ) / (βU DDU, µU DDU ) (s ,σ2 ) / (σ , σ ) 1 2 (33) Theory and Applications of Categories, Vol. 5, No. 5 137 is a 2-cell in U-AlgK . Since DK behaves well with change of base, then DK (U Ds, n−1 Ds ) = ). Thus, applying D , we have that (DU Ds, s−1 K Ds (σ1 DU DU, σ2 DU DU ) (DsDU,τ1 ) (DU Ds,s−1 Ds ) / (σ1 DDU, σ2 DDU ) Dτ1 (σ1 DU, σ2 DU ) (Ds ,τ2 ) / (σ , σ ) 1 (DDs,τ3 ) 2 is a 2-cell in U-AlgK . From this we obtain the equation / / τ1 DU τ3 / nn6 QQQ nnnU Dτ −1 QQQQQ n n n (/ / 1 = / −1 (34) τ 2 sDs / /6 . PPP PPP Dτ1 nnnnn PP' nnn We also have that (U mU,n−1 mU ) (βU DDU, µU DDU ) (s ,σ2 ) γ1 (σ1 , σ2 ) / (βU DU, µU DU ) (s,σ2 ) / (σ1 , σ2 ) (mU,γ1 ) is a 2-cell in U-AlgK . Applying DK to it we obtain that the equation / PP PPP PPP PPP P U P( Dγ1 PPP(/ PPP τ2 PPP γ2 PP( / = / QQ QQQ QQQ / OOO τ1 ( OOO OOO OOO OO' OODγ ' 1 / , s−1 mU (35) is satisfied. We are ready to show (31). Start with the second member of the equation, and use (32). Next make the substitution / = U muDU −1 −1 / JU Dσ1 JJ J JJ J JJ U ms JJJ JJ JJ J$ J$ / U DDσ1 II II II II I$ U mDU / . Use now (33) and (34). Make the substitutions 6 mmm O mmm m m m −1 mmm mmm U Dσ1 DU / / O U Dτ1−1 / , = U Du−1 Ds / M MMM MMM MM U Dσ1 −1 MM& / / , Theory and Applications of Categories, Vol. 5, No. 5 138 and / = U Dσ1 −1 JJ JJ JJ JJ J$ U Du−1 mU U DmU / / IU Dσ1−1 HH II HH HH U Dγ1 IIII HH II H$ /$ , using that (Ds, τ1 ) : (σ1 DU, σ2 DU ) → (σ1 , σ2 ) and (mU, γ1 ) : (σ1 , σ2 ) → (σ1 , σ2 ) are 1-cells in U-AlgK . Then the substitution NNN NNN U DDσ−1 NNN 1 NN& −1 NUNDu NNNDuDU NNN U Du−1 Ds NNN & NNNs−1 NDuDU NNN s−1 NNN Ds N& = / U DuDDU /# / sDDU MMM MMM DU Dσ−1 MMM 1 MM& /$ . Finally, use (35). We show now that we do have a distributive law. 10.2. Theorem. With the above definitions, r : U D → DU and the invertible 2-cells ω1 , ω2 , ω3 , and ω4 , define a distributive law of U over D. Proof. We show (coh 3, 6 and 8), leaving the rest to the reader. Start on the left hand side of (coh 3) and make the following substitutions: / J JJ JJ JJ −1 ηU U JJ 1$ / NN NNN NN NNN NNN σ4 U NNNNN NN& NN / µU & NNN NNN NNN dn NN& / = / n / NN NNN NN NNN NNN U duU NNNNN NN NN& U βU & / U dn / U σ4 σ4 / = U dU µU / , using (27), / NN NNN NNN NNN ' U Dβ U / = / / / NN NNN NNN U dn NNN / ' NNN NNN σ3−1 NNN NNN σ4 NNN NNN NN' NN' / = $ / MMM MMM MMUMβU MM& & , ww ww w w {ww FF µ−1 FFU FF FF F" n−1 dU σ4 / H HH HH HH HH # σ2 / w w ww ww w / , {w Theory and Applications of Categories, Vol. 5, No. 5 139 using that (dU, σ4 ) : (βU , µU ) → (σ1 , σ2 ) is a 1-cell in U-AlgK ; / NNN NNN −1 NUNηNU NN& and / µ−1 U = / O O n−1 u / / NN NNN NN NNN NNN U U du NNNNN N NN& N& / NNN n−1 u NNN NNN n−1 dU NN& / = / / , qq8 q q −1 qq ηU qq qqq / NN NNN NNN NNN / ' NNN n−1 MMM NNN Du MMM MMM U du NNN NN& MM& / . n−1 d To prove (coh 6), start on the right hand side, and make the following substitutions: / pp p p p U U Du−1 Du ppp xppp n−1 / DuD p p p pp U s−1 Du ppp p p p x / NN NNN 33 NN NNN 33 NNNU Du−1 NNNNN 33 NN& U Du NN& 33 / U DβU D p 33σ2 D pp p −1 p 33 sU Du pp 33 ppp σ3 D−1 p x / 33 pp Dn−1 pppp p 33 p Du pp 33 ppppp ppp p xpp p x / / = t t t tt tt t zt JJ Dσ3−1 JJ JJ JJ J$ σ5 U / mn = t tt tt t t tt ytt JJ U Du−1 Dn JJ JJ JJ JJ J −1 % NNN sDn NNN NNN NN& / / NN NNN NNN U Du−1 DuU NNN / & du−1 NNU NNN Dn NNN s−1 DuU NNN / & NNN s−1 Dn NNN DU DβU NN NNN &- / pp pp n−1 p p p p p DDu pp ppp ppp xppp / wpp−1 nDuDU ppp pp U Du−1 Du ppp p p / 3wp NNN 22 33 NNN 22 3 NNN 33 22 NN' 3 22 DU βU DU p 3 σ DU 2 3 22 pp 33 22 ppp p 33 p 22 wppp 33 22 s−1 Du 33 σ3 DU −1qqqq 22 33 qq 22 3 qqqq q x / , U mn / K KKK KKK KKK KK / % using (29) σ3−1 σ5 / , = / NN NN U DDβU NNNN NNN -' U DuDU sDU , Theory and Applications of Categories, Vol. 5, No. 5 140 and / NN NNN NN NNN NNN U muU NNNNN NN& NN& / U mU = U DDβU ) U mn / NN NNN NNN NNN ' U DβU / ) . Now use (28). Conclude with the substitution / NN NNN NN NNN NNNU U mu NNNNN NN& NN& / NNN n−1 DDu NNN NNN n−1 mU NN& / / NN NNN NNN NNN / ' NNN n−1 MMM Du NNN MMM MMM U mu NNN NN& MM& / . = n−1 m To prove (coh 8), start on the left hand side, and make the substitutions: / NN NNN NNN U Du−1 d NNN / & NNUNDu−1 Du N NNN s−1 NNN d N& / −1 NNN NNN sDu NNN N NNN DU du NNNNN NN& NN& / = NNN NNN NNN U ηD NN& NNN U Ddu NNN NNN NN& = / NN NNN NN NNN NNN U Ddu NNNNN NN& NN' / NNNU Du−1 u NNN −1 NNN U DudU NN −1 & / MMM su MMM MMM s−1 dU MM& / , and /( U mu / U Du MMM MMM MMMU ηD U MM& (/ . Now, use (30), then the equation obtained from (26). It is easily seen that what remains equals the identity. 11. (Co-)KZ-doctrines over KZ-doctrines Distributive laws for KZ-doctrines over KZ-doctrines are formally very similar to distributive laws of co-KZ-doctrines over KZ-doctrines. We start this section by recalling the definition and some aspects of KZ-doctrines [9] (see [8] as well). Then we define distributive laws of co-KZ-doctrines over KZ-doctrines, and we show that such a distributive law induces a distributive law between the induced pseudomonads, as defined in section 4. Finally, we show that the composite pseudomonad given by a distributive law of a KZ-doctrine over a KZ-doctrine is again a KZ-doctrine. Theory and Applications of Categories, Vol. 5, No. 5 141 11.1. We are still working in a Gray-category A, and K is an object of A. 11.2. Definition. A KZ-doctrine D on K consists of an object D, 1-cells d : 1K → D, and m : DD → D in A(K, K) and a fully-faithful adjoint string η, * : Dd m; and α, β : m dD : D → DD such that DD JJJm : JJ t t t IdD β ⇓ J$ d / / D D JJ η ⇓ tt: JJJ t tttm Dd J$ < D DD DDdD D" z zz / 1KDD (dd )−1 ⇓ DD m D. < DD z D zz d D" zz Dd d zzz dDttt 1K = DD (36) D The 2-cell δ : Dd → dD is defined as the pasting IdD / t: D JJJ Dd JJ β −1 ⇓ttt JJ J J t $ ⇓ J$ tt m dD J$ / DD, DD D JJJ IdDD and it satisfies the equations δ ◦ d = dd and m ◦ δ = β −1 · η −1 . In a co-KZ-doctrine U, with u : 1 → U and n : U U → U , the fully-faithful adjoint string is of the form uU n U u. Proposition 10.1 of [9] says that D induces a pseudomonad D = (D, d, m, β, η, µ) if µ is defined as the pasting IdDDD / DDD @ == == αD ⇓ = mD == = dDD DDD == DD m / DD @ === == m == dm ⇓ dD = β ⇓ = /D /D Dm IdD 11.3. Assume we have a KZ-doctrine D = (D, d, m, αD , βD , ηD , *D ), and a co-KZ-doctrine U = (U, u, n, αU , βU , ηU , *U ), with Id / DD, III αDuuu: m $ uu dD DDII D DD JJ m dD uu: D uuu JJ βD J$ / D, D II Id III Dd $ / D, : ηD uuu uu m DD Id : D JJJDd JJ $D $ / DD, muuu DD uu Id and / U, U HH HHH αU vvv: vv n uU # UU Id ; U HHHuU HH v v βU $ / U U, UU Id n vvv / U U, HHH ηUvvv: n # vv U u U U HH Id U U uuu: U uuu U U II n $U III $ / U. Id Since we are assuming D to be a KZ-doctrine, and U to be a co-KZ-doctrine, then βD and ηD , and αU , and *U are invertible. Let δ : Dd → dD and υ : uU → U u be the corresponding induced 2-cells. Theory and Applications of Categories, Vol. 5, No. 5 142 11.4. Definition. A distributive law of U over D consists of a 1-cell r : U D → DU in A(K, K), together with an invertible 2-cell U DFF {= FF r FF { F { ω 1 F" {{ / DU, D Du uD {{{ such that the pasting DU PP pp8 DuU −1PPPPuDU PPP −1 PPP udU DαU ω U 1 ' ' * pp / / U NNN υ 4 U U U DU DU U rU U dU nn7 NNN mm6 m n m n UNu −1 −1 nn mm NN D$U ru mmmmmDU u U dunnnnU Du U d NNN& nn mm / DU UD dU ppp pp p pp uU /* DU 7 Dn r is invertible. We denote the inverse by ω2 . We further require the pasting Id / U U D U r / U DU rU / DU U ; HH 9 v: HH HH Dn tt −1 v ηU D vvv U ω1 HH HH tt ru t H HH t v v nD HH$ H$ tt DU u D$U t vv U uD U Du / / DU UD DU ω3 = U U DH H r Id to be invertible, and the pasting ω4 = r Id / DU JJ : U D II DdU v II JJDU d U m vvv JJ U $ IUIIDd JJ vv r I d Dω2−1 v D I J v $ % v / U DD / DU D U DD rD Id Dr / DU v: v ηD U vvvv v $ vv mU / DDU to be invertible. We also require the following two coherence conditions: UD r / DU JJ JJDuU J U uD ks __ uU D uDU ω U −1 JJJ 1 υD J% −1 ur Dn / U U D U r / U DU rU / DU U DU = / DU DuU IIUIDu U uD U ω −1 III ru Dυ II 1 $ DuU )/ / U DU UUD DU U Dn / DU DdU D JdU JJ U dD ω D−1 JJdJ−1 r 2 J% dDU δU */ / U DD DU D DDU mU U D II r Ur rU / DU, and UD r / DU JJ JJDdU J __ _ U Dd DU d U dD ks _ −1 JJ Dω JJ U δ 2 % rd mU / / U DD rD DU D Dr / DDU DU = U D JJ r rD Dr / DU. Theory and Applications of Categories, Vol. 5, No. 5 143 Using the equations υ ◦ n = ηU · βU and δ ◦ m = αD · *D , and the coherence conditions, it is not hard to see that the inverse of ω3 is r Id / DU / DU, ;U D HH III : DuU v v Dα HH uU D v nD vvv HH U vv −1 IIuDU III v v H v HH ur v vv II ω1 U −1 βU D vv # $ # vv Dn / / / U U D U r U DU rU DU U UUD Id and the inverse of ω4 is / U DD rD / DU D Dr / DDU II ; 9 v: II II mU tt Uα d vv ω2 D II II tt r D vv t I II t v β U I t v D Um U dD dDU I$ I$ t v t v dU D / / DU. UD DU Id U DDII r Id Looking at the definition it seems possible to define a distributive law in terms of ω2 , defining ω1 with a similar pasting as ω2 was defined above. It can be shown that if we start with ω1 , define ω2 as above, and then use a similar pasting to define a new ω1 we have that ω1 = ω1 . And similarly if we start with ω2 . 11.5. Theorem. If D and U are the pseudomonads determined by the KZ-doctrine D and the co-KZ-doctrine U respectively, then r together with ω1 , ω2 , ω3 and ω4 define a distributive law of U over D. Proof. Since U is a co-KZ-doctrine, we have that βU = αU−1 and ηU = *−1 U . With this in mind, we must show that the coherence conditions (coh 1) to (coh 9) of section 4 are satisfied. We show that (coh 1), (coh 3) and (coh 4) are satisfied and leave the others to the reader. Consider the inverse of the left hand side of (coh 1). To get the inverse of the right hand side make the following four substitutions υ ◦ u = u−1 u , 9 K ss KKKK s s K% ss / du / / u−1 d −1 u−1 uu / dU / 9 KKK −1 KKKU du ssss s % s O /% O ω1/ U −1 O u−1 Du / −1 ru / = / O = u−1 Du * O Du−1 u ω1−1 / / , / /!, and 9 KKK KKDα sss s K% U s s KKK Du−1 9 u s s KKK s D$U s s % s = / $: idDu Theory and Applications of Categories, Vol. 5, No. 5 144 To prove (coh 3) start with the inverse of the right hand side and make the following substitutions: υ ◦ n = ηU · βU , βU 7 P ooo PPPPP o o PP( u−1 ooo /: , 6( n υU −1 = U αU / / / U dn / / rn 9 MM sss −1 MMMM s s M& s / dn / = / / J JJ JJ JJ u−1 Dn J / ω1 U −1 J/ $ / JJ JJU α−1 JJ U JJ J$ u−1 n / u−1 dU u−1 dU U A OOO OO Du−1 OOOO OO' n 8 O / O r rrrr rn rrr −1 rrr ω1 U U / / , = / O O = U d−1 uU / / J JJ JJ JJ Du−1 n JJ / DαU /$ u−1 Dn / , JJ JJ U dn rrr9 JJ rr $ r / −1 ruU / r8 O rrr r r rr rrr DαU U/ = / O / , nn6 n n nnn nnn n n / n DU α−1 U / O Dµ−1 U / , and / NNN −1 NNDU NNNαU NNN & / = Dµ−1 U / : I uu II uuD$ U III u u U /$ Dn / . Comparing the pasting obtained with the left hand side of (coh 3), we see that we must show that /: /9 K /9 JJ = Dn ◦ rU ◦ U ω2−1 . KK η ttU d−1 ss r −1 ss J u s u s KKK JJ Utt J$ tt / sss / sss D$U / 9% 4 −1 s nd jjjjj ω s 3 jj sss jjjjj / s / Now, pass every 2-cell of the left hand side to the right hand side, except for ηU . It is not hard to see, with the help of (coh 1), that the resulting equation is satisfied. Start with the inverse of the left hand side of (coh 4), and make the following sequence of substitutions: / O /= / / HH O = β D { H {{ {{ { { / { µU D−1 U HβHU U D HH HH H$ u−1 n / , Theory and Applications of Categories, Vol. 5, No. 5 / O /: U βU D ttt t u−1 tt n tt / t O = / {{ { { u−1 r {{ }{{ / CCuuU D CC −1 CC CC U ur ! / = / / JJ JJβU U D −1 JJ uU r JJ J$ / / J JJ JJ uuDU JJ −1JJ / U ω1 U /$ = = / / AA AAβU D AA uuU D AA / , / E EE EE EE u−1 r E" / u uDU z z zz u−1 Ur zz z / , }z / O / , O βU DU tt9 t t nr tt tt t / A OOO OO uDuU OOOO OO' 8 O / O r rrrr u−1 rU rrr −1 rrr ω1 U / / , / O rr8 O r r r u−1 Dn rrr DαU rrr / , / / J JJ JJ uDuU JJ J / U DαU J/ $ / J JJ JJ −1 JJ uDn J / ω1 U −1 J/ $ = = A OOO OO Du−1 OOOO OO' n / O rr8 O rrr rn rrr −1 rrr ω1 U U / / , / J JJ JJ JJ JJ / DαU /$ = 8 O rrr r r rrr rrr DαU U/ and 145 Du−1 n / O Dµ−1 U / , 11.6. Assume now that D is a KZ-doctrine as before, but that U is also a KZ-doctrine. The data for D is unchanged, and the data for U is now: U U HH n Id HHH # U / U U, αU vv: vvvuU U U HH n uU vv; U vvv Id βU HHH $ / U, / U, U HH HHH ηU vvv: vv n Uu # UU Id U Uu n uu: IIII uuu $U I$ / U U. UU Id We have υ : U u → uU . Copying almost exactly the definition of a distributive law of a co-KZ-doctrine over a KZ-doctrine, we obtain the concept of a distributive law of the KZ-doctrine U over the KZ-doctrine D. If U and D are the pseudomonads induced by U and D respectively, we obtain, in a very similar way, a distributive law between the pseudomonads U and D. Let V be the composite pseudomonad obtained from this last distributive law, as in section 5. Theory and Applications of Categories, Vol. 5, No. 5 146 11.7. Theorem. The composite pseudomonad obtained from a distributive law between KZ-doctrines is again a KZ-doctrine. Proof. We follow the notation introduced before the statement of the theorem, and the notation for V is the same as in section 5. According to theorem 11.1 of [9], it suffices to show that p vV with counit βV . Define ϑ : V v → vV as the pasting 2 DU = UFF FF FF FF FFDU dU DuU FF DU FF DdU FF DudU FF δU FF ! " dDU , / DU DU. DDU 5 DuDU lll ll duDU lll ldU l uDU l DU lll , DU u ----Dυ U DU It is not hard to see that ϑ ◦ v = pp and that p ◦ ϑ = βV−1 · ηV−1 . Using these two equations, an easy calculation shows that p vV with unit Id V vV , V βV−1 ⇓ & /VV V V OO ϑV ⇓ 2 V V V V p oo7 OOvV o OO V vp ⇓ oooo p OOOO o vV o OOO o ooo ' V and counit βV . References [1] M. Barr and C. Wells. Toposes, triples and theories. Springer-Verlag, 1985. [2] J. Beck. Distributive laws. Lecture Notes in Mathematics 80, Springer-Verlag, 1969. pp. 119-140. [3] B. Day and Ross Street. Monoidal bicategories and Hopf algebroids. Advances in Math. Vol. 129, Number 1, 1997, pp. 99-157. [4] S. Eilenberg and G. M. Kelly. Closed categories. In: Proceedings of the Conference on Categorical Algebra, La Jolla 1965, ed. S. Eilenberg et. al., Springer Verlag 1966; pp. 421-562. [5] J. W. Gray, Formal category theory: Adjointness for 2-categories. Lecture Notes in Mathematics 391, Springer-Verlag, 1974. [6] R. Gordon, A. J. Power and Ross Street. Coherence for tricategories. Memoirs of the American Mathematical Society 558, 1995. [7] G. M. Kelly. Coherence theorems for lax algebras and for distributive laws. Lecture Notes in Mathematics 420, Springer-Verlag, 1974. Theory and Applications of Categories, Vol. 5, No. 5 147 [8] A. Kock. Monads for which structures are adjoint to units. Journal of Pure and Applied Algebra 104(1), 1995, pp. 41-59. [9] F. Marmolejo. Doctrines whose structure forms a fully faithful adjoint string. Theory and applications of categories, Vol. 3, No. 2, pp. 24-44. 1997. http://tac.mta.ca/tac/volumes/1997/n3/n3.dvi [10] R. Rosebrugh and R. J. Wood. Distributive adjoint strings. Theory and applications of categories, Vol. 1, No. 6, 1995, pp. 119-145. http://tac.mta.ca/tac/volumes/1995/n6/v1n6.dvi [11] Ross Street. The formal theory of monads. Journal of Pure and Applied Algebra 2, 1972, pp. 149168. Instituto de Matemáticas Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México Area de la Investigación Cientı́fica México D. F. 04510 México e-mail: quico@matem.unam.mx This article may be accessed via WWW at http://www.tac.mta.ca/tac/ or by anonymous ftp at ftp://ftp.tac.mta.ca/pub/tac/html/volumes/1999/n5/n5.{dvi,ps} THEORY AND APPLICATIONS OF CATEGORIES (ISSN 1201-561X) will disseminate articles that significantly advance the study of categorical algebra or methods, or that make significant new contributions to mathematical science using categorical methods. The scope of the journal includes: all areas of pure category theory, including higher dimensional categories; applications of category theory to algebra, geometry and topology and other areas of mathematics; applications of category theory to computer science, physics and other mathematical sciences; contributions to scientific knowledge that make use of categorical methods. Articles appearing in the journal have been carefully and critically refereed under the responsibility of members of the Editorial Board. Only papers judged to be both significant and excellent are accepted for publication. The method of distribution of the journal is via the Internet tools WWW/ftp. The journal is archived electronically and in printed paper format. Subscription information. Individual subscribers receive (by e-mail) abstracts of articles as they are published. Full text of published articles is available in .dvi and Postscript format. Details will be e-mailed to new subscribers and are available by WWW/ftp. To subscribe, send e-mail to tac@mta.ca including a full name and postal address. For institutional subscription, send enquiries to the Managing Editor, Robert Rosebrugh, rrosebrugh@mta.ca. Information for authors. The typesetting language of the journal is TEX, and LATEX is the preferred flavour. TEX source of articles for publication should be submitted by e-mail directly to an appropriate Editor. They are listed below. Please obtain detailed information on submission format and style files from the journal’s WWW server at URL http://www.tac.mta.ca/tac/ or by anonymous ftp from ftp.tac.mta.ca in the directory pub/tac/info. You may also write to tac@mta.ca to receive details by e-mail. Editorial board. John Baez, University of California, Riverside: baez@math.ucr.edu Michael Barr, McGill University: barr@math.mcgill.ca Lawrence Breen, Université de Paris 13: breen@math.univ-paris13.fr Ronald Brown, University of North Wales: r.brown@bangor.ac.uk Jean-Luc Brylinski, Pennsylvania State University: jlb@math.psu.edu Aurelio Carboni, Università dell Insubria: carboni@fis.unico.it P. T. Johnstone, University of Cambridge: ptj@pmms.cam.ac.uk G. Max Kelly, University of Sydney: maxk@maths.usyd.edu.au Anders Kock, University of Aarhus: kock@imf.au.dk F. William Lawvere, State University of New York at Buffalo: wlawvere@acsu.buffalo.edu Jean-Louis Loday, Université de Strasbourg: loday@math.u-strasbg.fr Ieke Moerdijk, University of Utrecht: moerdijk@math.ruu.nl Susan Niefield, Union College: niefiels@union.edu Robert Paré, Dalhousie University: pare@mscs.dal.ca Andrew Pitts, University of Cambridge: ap@cl.cam.ac.uk Robert Rosebrugh, Mount Allison University: rrosebrugh@mta.ca Jiri Rosicky, Masaryk University: rosicky@math.muni.cz James Stasheff, University of North Carolina: jds@charlie.math.unc.edu Ross Street, Macquarie University: street@math.mq.edu.au Walter Tholen, York University: tholen@mathstat.yorku.ca Myles Tierney, Rutgers University: tierney@math.rutgers.edu Robert F. C. Walters, University of Sydney: walters b@maths.usyd.edu.au R. J. Wood, Dalhousie University: rjwood@mscs.dal.ca