(P à Q) Therefore, evil god's creation is good.

advertisement
1
I
INTRODUCTION
This essay is written in response to an article by Stephen Law entitled “The Evilgod Challenge.” In the article, Law makes the case that the theistic belief of an all-good
god is no more rational than an all-evil god.1 Law’s goal is to say that the theistic concept
of God is irrational because of the existence of evil. Law’s hypothesis is described as
symmetrical with basic theistic claims about God. That is, evil god is omnipotent and
omniscient. Yet, instead of being maximally good, this god is maximally evil. Just as
Christianity has the problem of evil, Law’s hypothetical world is confronted with the
problem of good. Thus, Law posits a problem of evil – problem of good equivalency. I
will challenge his claims based on flaws within his argument because of a lack of
coherence between his world and the actual world.2 I will argue this in three primary
premises. First, I will present ontological and metaphysical asymmetries between God
and Law’s evil god. Second, I will show problems with his understanding of libertarian
free will. Finally, I will present that the notion creation is inherently good. Further, if
Law’s thesis is taken to its rational end, the evil world is not sustainable. A world of pure
evil, by definition, would destroy itself. Thus, all three of my arguments will be upheld
with an overarching theme of annihilation that the evil world presents.
Law defends his hypothesis with the formulation of reverse-theodicies. The
reverse-theodicies are formulated parallel to theistic theodices; they are supposed to
uphold the evil world despite the problem of the good. Reverse-theodies that Law uses
are: (1) free will; (2) evil used for character building; (3) and theodicies of second-order
1
Stephen Law, "The Evil-god Challenge," Religious Studies 46, no. 4 (2010), 369.
It should be noted that Law argues against a general theistic belief. However, throughout this paper I will
support my thesis by referring to the Christian God as the good god in Law’s argument.
2
2
goods from first-order evils. It should be noted that Law himself admits that his reversetheodicies are weak.3 Yet, Law states that the weaknesses of his reverse-theodicies are no
worse than actual theodicies for the existence of God.4
Law supports two major arguments against God from evil. He affirms the logical
(or deductive) problem which states that if evil exists in the world, then it is illogical to
affirm a belief in an omniscient, good God. The logical problem is simple. Evil clearly
exists, thus a perfect God does not exist.5 Law also affirms the evidential problem. The
same two propositions from the logical problem can be extrapolated and transferred to
the evidential problem. That is, the sheer amount of evil within the world provides strong
empirical evidence against a rational belief in God. Thus, God does not exist.6 Law finds
both the logical and evidential arguments valid and he therefore adapts the evidential
problem for his hypothesis.
Law describes evil god as one whose “depravity is without limit. His cruelty
knows no bounds. There is no other god or gods – just this supremely wicked being.”7
Likewise, Law’s symmetry continues with the problem of evil – problem of good
equivalency. Contrary to evil god’s malicious nature, evil god gives:
(i) immense health, wealth and happiness
3
Law seems to confuse his understanding of theistic terms. By proposing reverse-theodicies, Law is really
providing a “defense.” While there are some shared components between a “theodicy” and a “defense,” the
main difference is that a theodicy is put forward as true. A defense, on the other hand, is nothing more than
a possibility. Further, a theodicy gives reasons why an all-good God allows evil. A defense is more vague
insofar as defenses say that it is reasonable to believe in God despite the allowance of evil even if humanity
does not know the reasons for evil. Essentially, Law’s reverse-theodicies fall under the category of a
defense. For a more detailed explanation, please see Peter Van Inwagen, "The Argument From Evil," in
Christian Faith and the Problem of Evil (Grand Rapids: Wm. B. Eerdmans Publishing, 2004), 62; C.
Stephen Evans, Faith Beyond Reason: A Kierkegaardian Account (Grand Rapids: Eerdmans, 1998), 129.
4
Law, Evil-god, 369.
5
For a widely recognized argument using the logical problem, please see J.L. Mackie, The Miracle of
Theism: Arguments For and Against the Existence of God (New York: Oxford University Press, 1982), esp.
p.150.
6
Law, 354.
7
Law, Evil-god, 356.
3
(ii) natural beauty in the world
(iii) gratuitous attitude
(iv) families
(v) healthy, beautiful bodies8
These examples form the evidential problem of the good. From here, Law develops
several reverse-theodicies that affirm the existence of evil god despite the fact that
creation clearly has good qualities
I wish to dispute Law’s evil-god hypothesis by exposing holes in his symmetry
between God and evil god. Doing so, I will refer to some of the reverse-theodicies,
especially the reverse-theodicy of free will, throughout the paper.
II
ONTOLOGICAL ASYMMETRIES
I will first discuss ontological and metaphysical asymmetries. In a subsection
discussing moral arguments, Law claims that theists cannot prove an asymmetry between
a good god and an evil god based on morals.9 Here, Law presupposes a metaphysical
equality of good and evil without argument. It will be shown in this section that evil god
must be the moral standard for evil in order that Law’s hypothesis be valid. However,
Law provides no reasonable argument for how good could enter the evil world. Because
Law cannot account for good in his evil world, the only its inhabitants can do good (the
problem of the good) is to have it embedded within their being. Further, I will also argue
that even if we grant an absolute standard of evil in Law’s hypothetical world, the world
is not sustainable as its evil forces would terminate the world’s existence.
God loves all his creation through grace axiomatically despite humanity’s sin.
Even the most evil individual still receives God’s love. That is, the fact that God loves the
8
9
Ibid., 356. Note, Law does not specify the “gratuitous attitude.”
Ibid., 364. Law’s statement is especially aimed at moral furnishings.
4
fallen world does not imply a defect in God’s moral character.10 Rather, God’s love for
the fallen creation is exemplary. William Alston writes that the greatest sin is the selfcentered refusal to make God the center of one’s own life.11 Yet God continues to love
his creation despite this refusal. Could Law reverse this scenario? Like God, would evil
god remain static in response to rebellion?12 It seems implausible. The evil god hates his
creation. There may be a universal standard of hatred at the inception of the evil world.
That is, contra God’s world, individuals in this world are embedded with an ontological
evil. Yet, if evil god’s creation somehow brings forth good (which evil god hates), then it
seems that evil god should hate his creation more. But Law states that his god’s evil is
absolute. An absolute is a quality and cannot be increased or decreased. Thus, evil god’s
tolerance of good is nonsensical.13
Further, Law provides little insight into the ontological status of his possible
world. Law has already admitted that there is not symmetry for the Genesis story.
10
Robert Merrihew Adams, "Must God Create the Best?," in God and the Problem of Evil, ed. William L.
Rowe (Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishers, 2001), 36.
11
William P. Alson, "The Inductive Argument from Evil and the Human Cognitive Condition," in The
Evidential Argument from Evil, ed. Daniel Howard-Snyder (Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press,
1996), 104.
12
The term “static” here implies that God does not change his character in response to rebellion.
13
Evil god’s tolerance of good is nonsensical because evil god has no method of dealing with good.
Despite evil in this world, God’s love remains pure and offered a universal sacrifice for the redemption of
his creation. Furthermore, one could state that Law has adequately inverted the notion of Transworld
Identities (hereafter, TI) to support his hypothesis. TI states that certain objects exist in more than one
world. Thus, it can be stated that God must deal with evil in every possible world. The symmetry could
therefore follow – evil god must tolerate good in every possible world. However, Plantinga states that only
some properties have certain essences that are necessary. Thus, not all objects are necessary for every
possible world. Further, even if an object is necessary for every possible world, the necessitation of the
object does not necessitate that every property of that object is found in all possible worlds. Some
properties are contingent. Thus, X has property P contingently iff there is a possible state of affairs S such
that X would not have P. This is called the Counterpart Theory. This grants that an object may exist in
more than the actual world but all the properties of that object are not necessary for the object in all worlds.
Relating back to Law and God’s world, the question is whether or not each problem (of good; of bad) are
transworld ideas. I would make the argument that they are not. However, even if I were to grant that they
are transworld ideas, it does not necessitate that all the properties of evil are transworld properties. See
Alvin Plantinga, “Transworld Identity or Worldbound Individuals?,” in Essays in the Metaphysics of
Modality, ed. Matthew Davidson (New York: Oxford University Press, 2003), 88.
5
Furthermore, Law does not provide a source of good in his evil world. The Christian
tradition has provided arguments for how evil entered into the good world created by
God. I will discuss one, the view of privation, in order to show that Law’s hypothesis
cannot account for good in an evil world.
St. Thomas’s view of the metaphysics of evil is a “privation: the privation of the
good that should be in a thing.”14 St. Thomas appropriates St. Augustine’s view of
privation and evil. St. Augustine emphasized that evil is not an essence or a thing.
However, evil does exist. Evil exists in good insofar as created beings are good –
“depraved of some being or of some good they should have.”15 Evil is contingent on the
existence of good. Goodness does not create evil, rather, evil distorts good like cancer in
a healthy body. Privation, therefore, implies that good and evil are not metaphysically
equal. Good is the standard; evil is the privation of the good.16 The perennial question for
Christianity is regarding the source of this privation.
An accurate description of privation can be found in the works of St. Augustine.
Privation in the Augustinian system, titled The Great Chain of Being, is an ordering of all
created things.17 God, at the top of the chain, is the perfect standard of goodness and
being. At the other end of the continuum is nothingness. All of God’s good creation is
within the continuum, yet at different levels. Angels are higher than humans and humans
are greater than animals and other organic matter. God made humanity good with the
14
Jacques Maritain, St. Thomas and the Problem of Evil: The Aquinas Lecture 1942 (Milwaukee:
Marquette University Press, 1942), 1.
15
Ibid., 2.
16
For a more detailed explanation of privation under the Thomistic system, please see Eleonore Stump,
Wandering in Darkness: Narrative and the Problem of Suffering (New York: Oxford University Press,
2010), 384.
17
For an accurate chart portraying The Great Chain of Being, please see Norman Melchert, The Great
Conversation: A Historical Introduction to Philosophy, 5th Edition (New York: Oxford University Press,
2007), p.241.
6
maximal amount of goodness they could possess. Yet, humanity does not have the perfect
goodness of God. Thus, humanity’s goodness and being are limited.18 It is this threshold
that makes humanity susceptible to sin.
If a perennial question for Christianity is the definition of privation, then the
nagging question for Law’s hypothesis must be the source of good. Can St. Augustine’s
view of privation be reversed to support Law’s hypothesis? I argue that it cannot. In
Law’s reverse-theodicy of free-will, he claims that people in the evil world have freedom
to do good. But Law provides no explanation for the possibility of good in this world; nor
does he give a source of the good.19 The only way I can conceptualize a Great Chain of
Being reversal is if creation is seen backwards for the evil-god hypothesis. Yet, to rebel
against evil, one would have to move towards goodness. Without any source of good (a
reverse-privation) it is implausible (or perhaps impossible) to move towards something
greater.20
Yet, even if such a reversal were possible, Law’s evil world is not sustainable. If
the evil world possessed inherent evil, then the world would ultimately lead to
annihilation, perhaps immediately. Let us pose that humanity in the evil world came
about as one couple (a parallel to the Genesis story). If evil was absolute, man would kill
the woman (or vice versa) leading to the annihilation of humanity on the evil world. Or
nature, likewise, could render the evil world annihilated as well. An earthquake, flood or
some other natural (evil) event would eventually kill humanity or cause destruction of the
18
Saint. Augustine, Enchiridion (On Faith, Hope, and Love), ed. Thomas S. Hibbs (Washington, D.C.:
Regnery Publishing, 1996), Chapter XII.
19
Law, Evil-god, 357.
20
Peter Geach expounds on this point. Geach states that when humanity sinned, the mind became distorted
and became liable to humanity’s uncontrolled passions and desires. From this, it seems unlikely that if one
a rebellious individual would bring about good in the evil world. Rather, through free will the individuals in
the evil world would likely become given over to their evil desires more greatly. See Peter Geach,
Providence and Evil: The Stanton Lecture 1971-72 (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1977), 95.
7
ecosystem, ending this world.21 Annihilation is supported from quantum mechanics. If
antimatter were to collide with matter, the two would annihilate each other.22 When the
evil world is contrasted to the actual world, the actual world is one that is homeostatically
sustainable. Even though evil runs ramped in the world, the overarching good makes the
world a livable place. Despite the horrors of murder, natural disasters and evil
individuals, the moral standard given by the good God makes it possible for humanity to
live. Law’s hypothetical world simply cannot achieve this standard. An absolute evil
world is not sustainable. If evil, whether moral, natural or cosmological, were to run
freely amok in a world then the world would soon meet its unkind annihilation. If we
follow Law’s logic to its rational end, this destruction cannot be avoided.
III
FREE WILL PROBLEMS
In the reverse-theodicy of free-will, Law posits that evil god can grant a sense of
morality so his creation can bring about evil. Yet, this also gives the evil creation the
opportunity to do good. This seems flawed as there is no ontological reason for good. If a
god, whether good or evil, is omniscient and omnipotent and grants a sense of morality
then that god must be the moral standard. Christianity has upheld this belief. God is the
standard of goodness.23 Goodness is in God’s Being itself. Even though humanity rebels
against God through sin, his moral goodness remains pure as a standard for human
morality. Human sin (through freedom) does not change God’s Being. If God exists, then
he is necessarily good. As St. Augustine said, “[humanity] can use free will to sin, but we
For an excellent source regarding natural evil’s connection to human sin, please see William A.
Dembski, The End of Christianity (Nashville: B&H Publishing Group, 2009).
22
Note that there is debate as to what happens when matter and antimatter collide. Some (like Albert
Einstein) pose that if the two were to collide then other energies would be produced as a result. But this
does not negate the example. Even if the two opposite forces were to form something new, both original
components would cease to exist.
23
See Nahum 1:7; Zechariah 9:17; Psalm 145:9.
21
8
should not therefore believe that God gave […] free will so that they would be able to
sin.”24 St. Thomas appropriates God’s goodness to his own Being. “Being and goodness
are the same in reference, differing only in sense.”25 Because God is perfectly good,
goodness is a part of his Being. This connection of goodness and Being is applicable to
humanity. The goodness of a being itself will be developed further later. But here, it is
important to note that God’s goodness cannot be separated from his Being.26 Thus, if God
is a necessary being it therefore follows that he is perfectly and necessarily good.
Law’s understanding of morality is flawed insofar as evil god provides the avenue
for rebellion itself. Law cannot adequately provide a source of good in the evil world.
Evil god is the creator. Law posits that evil god is also the source of morality. Based on
Law’s explanations and the lack of any source of good, it seems only logical to deduce
that morality, both evil and good, come from evil god - a self-refuting attribute of an
absolute evil god.
Further, free will within an evil creation will bring about anarchy. Even though
Law’s theory is inept insofar as the moral standard includes both good and evil, the
malicious world would bring about very little (if any) good. Thus, free will based upon
24
Saint. Augustine, On Free Choice of the Will (Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company, 1993), Book
II, Chapter I. Note: Paranthetical notation mine.
From St. Thomas Aquinas’s Summa Theologica Ia.5, esp. a.1. (henceforth ST). Quoted in Eleonore and
Kretzmann, Norman Stump, "Being and Goodness," in Being and Goodness: The Concept of the Good in
Metaphysics and Philosophical Theology, ed. Scott MacDonald (Ithica , NY: Cornell University Press,
1991).
26
The lack of a distinction between God and his attributes is called “diving simplicity.” This view has been
held, in some form or another, by St(s). Augustine, Anselm and Thomas Aquinas. Because divine
simplicity states that God is identical to his attributes, all of his attributes are therefore identical to one
another. Further, God’s nature and existence are identical to his Being. For a detailed examination of divine
simplicity, see the entry on Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy at http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/divinesimplicity. Further, for an opposition to divine simplicity, please see Alvin Plantinga, Does God Have a
Nature? The Aquinas Lecture, 1980 (Milwaukee, WI: Marquette University Press, 1980).
25
9
evil is not sustainable. The evil would only continue to bring about more evil, ending in
the world’s destruction.
When sections II-III are viewed together, it seems that the lack of an ontological
and metaphysical understanding of good in an evil world makes Law’s supposed
symmetry asymmetrical. Law posits that evil god is the moral standard for the evil world.
Yet it has been shown that there is no plausible method of good entering the evil world.
From this, it seems fair to deduce that the only way individuals in the evil world can
bring forth good is if there is a sense of good embedded within their ontological being.
But, this contradicts the notion of the evil god being the standard for the evil world.
Christianity has defended theories of evil through privation and limited goodness. Law
cannot provide such theories for his evil-god hypothesis. Thus, from an ontological
standard, theistic claims cannot be refuted by the evil-god challenge.
IV
GOODNESS OF CREATION
I now make the argument that an act of creation is inherently good. As a result, it
will be shown that Law’s hypothesis is faulty, because evil god is a creator. An act of
creation, even if creation is meant for a horrible existence, is an inherently good act. That
is, if life is brought into being, then that life is itself good. If both the Christian God and
the hypothetical evil god possess power that is unlimited, it can be stated that they have
the power and freedom to create any possible world.27 However, the assumption that an
all-powerful deity can actualize any possible world appears to be false based on the
perfect moral standards discussed in the previous section. As previously stated, God’s
Being is perfectly and necessarily good. Because God is perfectly good then it would be a
27
Alvin Plantinga, God, Freedom, and Evil (New York: Harper & Row Publishers, 1974), 44.
10
logical contradiction for him to create an evil world. Logical laws limit God’s creative
power.28 Therefore, God cannot create any possible world; God is limited to worlds
containing inherent goodness.29
The Genesis account of creation reiterates that creation is good. The last creative
act in Genesis 1 is the creation of the first humans, Adam and Eve. This act was labeled
“very good” as the first couple resembled God’s Being. Biblically, bringing forth creation
is indeed a good act. As Gregory Boyd says, “God’s gracious decision to create […] the
world can only be conceived of as a self-determining act.”30 Thus, it will be assumed that
any supernatural being, either good or bad, creates invariably by its own volition.31
Norman Kretzmann states that when God created the world and the first humans,
creation did not simply become good because God created. Rather, God knew the
goodness of a created thing prior to its instantiation.32 The concept of creation is therefore
good. The act of creating is an expression of goodness of a supernatural being.
From a Thomistic interpretation, the essence of Being is intrinsically good. This is
based on the intelligence granted by God. Related to Kretzmann’s thought, St. Thomas
28
Ibid., 33.
For a historical and thorough examination of possible worlds, including worlds without evil, please see
Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz, Theodicy, ed. Austin Farrer, trans. E.M. Huggard (Charleston, SC: Bibliobazaar
Publishing, 2007). Also, God limitation to only creating good worlds does not limit nor negate God’s
omniscience of all possible worlds and all counterfactuals.
30
Gregory A. Boyd, Satan and the Problem of Evil (Downers Grove, IL: InterVarsity Press, 2001), 69.
31
Note that just because I posit that God freely created does not negate plausible arguments from necessity.
That is, one could believe that God necessarily creates because creation is a manifestation of God’s nature.
God’s nature is always productive, thus he creates. Thus, my argument is applicable under a necessitarian
system. I do not wish to bring forth necessitarian arguments in this paper as Law himself discusses evil god
as free. But it is worth noting that there are theistic beliefs that God necessarily creates. See Norman
Kretzmann, "A General Problem of Creation: Why Would God Create Anything at All?," in Being and
Goodness: The Concept of Good in Metaphysics and Philosophical Theology, ed. Scott MacDonald (Ithaca,
NY: Cornell University Press, 1991), 208.
32
Norman Kretzmann, "A General Problem of Creation: Why Would God Create Anything at All?," in
Being and Goodness: The Concept of Good in Metaphysics and Philosophical Theology, ed. Scott
MacDonald (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1991), 212.
29
11
states that creatures pre-exist in God as abstract intelligent beings.33 Thus, being itself
comes from God’s Being. God’s intelligent essence is known purely in God himself.
When God actualizes intelligent beings, each person is given their own being that
resembles the Divine Being.34 From this, “[w]hat is true of every good being […] is
eminently true of the Supreme Being which we call God.”35 The creation of beings is
therefore good because they emanate from God’s own Being.
God is restricted to create only what is good. The two questions that must be
answered are (1) whether or not evil god must necessarily create an evil world and (2)
whether the act of creation itself is inherently good. The answer to the first question is
basic. If the evil god is absolutely evil as Law posits, then his world, necessarily, must be
evil. To state otherwise would be a contradiction.
The answer to the second question is more involved. Because God and evil god
are omniscient and all-powerful, it can be said that their free-will is absolute and
unrestricted. Richard Swinburne states “the more serious the free will and the stronger the
contrary temptation, the better it is when the good action is done.” 36 Thus, when each
deity is thinking of creating, both are forced, yet free, to choose to create (A) or not create
(~A).37 The question that must be answered is related to the good act Swinburne raises.
Thus, is creation a good act for evil god?
33
Etienne Gilson, The Philosophy of St. Thomas Aquinas , ed. Rev. G.A. Elrington, trans. Edward Bullough
(New York: Barnes & Noble Books, 1993), 138. Gilson goes on to state that creation was not once fused
with God. God is his own Being; his own Goodness and his own Perfection. Creation does not possess
these things in themselves, rather , human beings imitate (and are replications) God’s Being.
34
Ibid., 139.
35
Ibid., 141.
36
Swinburne, Providence, 87.
37
“Forced” in the sense that the deity is restricted to choose to create or not create. “Free” in the sense that
the deity can choose either option.
12
Regarding goodness and badness, Swinburne writes, “goodness of good states and
the badness of bad states arise from their being good or bad for someone or something.”38
Swinburne gives an example of a painting. People do not appreciate the beauty of a
painting solely on the painting’s effect on one’s consciousness. Rather, they appreciate
the painting because it has some beautiful feature in itself.39 The beauty of the painting is
contingent. The painting requires an artist that brings the painting into existence. 40 That
is, the artist brings forth the painting because he or she believes it to have some inherent
beauty, some influence that must be noticed. If the artist creates the painting, even if the
content is that of devastation, the painting invokes something in the artist to the extent
that the artist must create. The creation of the painting, then, is good.
Another example, one of historical context, is the massive destruction of life
caused by Adolf Hitler. Hitler’s actions and orders against the Jews were horrific. The
Jews were the recipients of inhumane medical experiments and were killed via torturous
means. Arguably, Hitler is the most vivid manifestation of evil. This example is
appropriate. Hitler did not want to keep the Jews alive to torture them. He wanted to
eradicate them. Hitler wanted the Jews erased from history. He hated their very being.
For Hitler, the termination of being was the most horrific action possible. It would be
unthinkable to claim that if Hitler had the power to create, that he would opt to bring
about a Jewish being. He would never do so. He so greatly hated their existence that he
wanted to rid the world of their being.
38
Swinburne, Providence, 50.
Ibid., 52.
40
Even if the painting was brought into the world for the sole purpose of tormenting people, the painting
was serving its purpose which can imply goodness.
39
13
The point here is to show creation and life as good. Hitler hated the lives of the
Jews. But Hitler was not a god. Law’s supposed evil god is all-powerful. “His depravity
is without limit.”41 Why would this evil god bring about life? Bringing something into
being for a miserable existence is not sufficient for bringing a being into existence. If evil
god truly hates, then it would not create.42 Thus, it is incoherent to believe that evil god
would create. Doing so would be an act of good which would be antithetical to Law’s
thesis. Referring back to Swinburne’s question about free will and action, the more
heinous choice evil god ought choose is the refusal to create.43
VI
CONCLUSION
Law wants his readers to imagine the evidence for God and evil god as set of
weighing scales. Law states the evidence he presents is equally balanced between the two
sides. Thus, because people find it unreasonable to believe in an evil god, then it is also
unreasonable to hold theistic beliefs. Yet, my argument has exposed holes within his
symmetry, lending credence to theism.
Based upon a theme of annihilation, I have formulated arguments on morality,
free will and logic that disprove Law’s hypothesis. His posited symmetry between God
and evil god is asymmetrical because of self-refuting terminologies and arguments. The
41
Law, Evil-god, 356.
If creation is seen as good, the argument can be summed up in a basic modus ponens (P  Q) argument.
Inferentially:
(P) Creation is good
(Q) Evil god creates
(P  Q) Therefore, evil god’s creation is good.
43
As shown in the previous section, an evil world would annihilate itself. It is illogical that evil god would
create something that from its own inception could decimate out of existence. This seems to be supported
by the notion that evil god is all-powerful as Law posits. A world that could logically annihilate itself from
its inception seems to negate the unlimited nature of evil god. If the forces of evil in the evil world can
annihilate itself then it seems that the creation has possessed powers greater than that of its creator, a clear
contradiction. Furthermore, one could object that the most evil that evil god could do is spread evil around
maximally. But doing so still implies the creation of a being. As already shown, being itself is a good thing.
If a being is existent, then it is inherently good, despite the content of that being’s life.
42
14
argument also fails based on the notion of sustainability. Christianity not only gives an
ontological status for good and evil, but the love of God is a source of truth and sustain
despite the existence of evil in the world. The evil-god hypothesis is not a defeater to
Christian claims. Law’s attempt to disprove this truth via the evil-god hypothesis has
resulted in faulty results. The reliability of epistemic and metaphysical arguments within
Christianity far outweigh the conditions that Law presents. Based on these conditions, the
evil-god hypothesis does not refute theistic claims.
15
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Adams, Robert Merrihew. "Must God Create the Best?" In God and the Problem of Evil,
edited by William L. Rowe. Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishers, 2001.
Alston, William P. "The Inductive Argument from Evil and the Human Cognitive
Condition." In The Evidential Argument from Evil, edited by Daniel HowardSnyder. Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press, 1996.
Saint Augustine. Enchiridion (On Faith, Hope, and Love). Edited by Thomas S. Hibbs.
Washington, D.C.: Regnery Publishing, 1996.
____. On Free Choice of the Will. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company, 1993.
Boyd, Gregory A. Satan and the Problem of Evil. Downers Grove, IL: InterVarsity Press,
2001.
Dembski, William A. The End of Christianity. Nashville: B&H Publishing Group, 2009.
Evans, C. Stephen. Faith Beyond Reason: A Kierkegaardian Account. Grand Rapids:
Eerdmans, 1998.
Geach, Peter. Providence and Evil: The Stanton Lecture 1971-72. New York: Cambridge
University Press, 1977.
Gilson, Etienne. The Philosophy of St. Thomas Aquinas . Edited by Rev. G.A.
Elrington. Translated by Edward Bullough. New York: Barnes & Noble Books,
1993.
Kretzmann, Norman. "A General Problem of Creation: Why Would God Create Anything
at All?" In Being and Goodness: The Concept of Good in Metaphysics and
Philosophical Theology, edited by Scott MacDonald. Ithaca, NY: Cornell
University Press, 1991.
Law, Stephen. "The Evil-god Challenge." Religious Studies 46, no. 4 (2010).
Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm. Theodicy. Edited by Austin Farrer. Translated by E.M.
Huggard. Charleston, SC: Bibliobazaar Publishing, 2007.
Mackie, J.L. The Miracle of Theism: Arguments for and Against the Existence of God.
New York: Oxford University Press, 1982.
Maritain, Jacques. St. Thomas and the Problem of Evil: The Aquinas Lecture 1942.
Milwaukee: Marquette University Press, 1942.
16
Melchert, Norman. The Great Conversation: A Historical Introduction to Philosophy.
5th Edition. New York: Oxford University Press, 2007.
Plantinga, Alvin. Does God Have a Nature? The Aquinas Lecture, 1980. Milwaukee:
Marquette University Press, 1980.
____. God, Freedom, and Evil. New York: Harper & Row Publishers, 1974.
____. The Nature of Necessity. New York: Oxford University Press, 1974.
_____. "Transworld Identity or Worldbound Individuals?" In Essays in the
Metaphysics of Modality, edited by Matthew Davidson. New York: Oxford
University Press, 2003.
Plato. Republic. Translated by G.M.A Grube. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing
Company, 1992.
Stump, Eleonore and Kretzmann, Norman. "Being and Goodness." In Being
and Goodness: The Concept of the Good in Metaphysics and Philosophical
Theology, edited by Scott MacDonald. Ithica , NY: Cornell University Press,
1991.
____. Wandering in Darkness: Narrative and the Problem of Suffering. New
York: Oxford University Press, 2010.
Swinburne, Richard. Providence and the Problem of Evil. New York: Oxford University
Press, 1998.
Van Inwagen, Peter. "The Argument From Evil." In Christian Faith and the Problem of
Evil. Grand Rapids: Wm. B. Eerdmans Publishing, 2004.
Download