AN INTRODUCTION TO SOCIAL CAPITAL (NOT TO BE QUOTED. FOR IBD STUDENTS USE ONLY) These notes focus on social capital. Their aim is not to give an organic treatment of this important theoretical concept and of their use in various disciplines. This task would be very difficult to accomplish because social capital is a very controversial concept. It has been defined in several ways (*see note below), not always compatible each other. It has been used in different disciplines within different theoretical frameworks. It has been measured in empirical researches by means of very different proxies. My aims are then less ambitious. First, to introduce the key words in the social capital literature. This will allow you to read literature on social capital knowing the technical language. Second, to give you an idea of the main issues in the debate on social capital. Keep in mind that these issues refer to different disciplines since social capital is a truly interdisciplinary concept. It was born within the sociological discipline, but it has been used, adapted and modified by political scientists, psychologists, economists and biologists. This is of course one of the merits of this concept: to facilitate the dialogue between scholars of different disciplines But it is also the cause of the many difficulties found in reaching a consensus among scholars on the theoretical definition of the concept and on its empirical application. These notes have been organized around three key concepts: network, trust and institutions. Consider however that various topics could be placed indifferently under one or the other of these three concepts. This because network, trust and institutions are concepts strongly interlinked in the social capital literature. (* )Compare the three definitions of social capital proposed by the three founder fathers of social capital theory Bourdieu: “social capital is the sum of resources, actual or virtual, that accrue to an individual or a group by virtue of possessing a durable network of more or less institutionalised relationships of mutual acquaintance and recognition” Coleman: “social capital is defined by its function. It is not a single entity, but a variety of different entities having two characteristics in common: they all consist of some aspects of a social structure and they facilitate certain actions of individuals who are within the structure Putnam: “features of social organization such as networks, norms and social trust that facilitate coordination and cooperation for mutual benefit” NETWORKS VARIOUS TYPES OF NETWORK Networks are sets of social relations. Each individual lives and acts within different sets of relationships. There are various kinds of networks. The most basic form of social network is the family: a small group of people linked by strong natural bonds, sharing resources and helping one another in case of need. A slightly larger social network is composed by relatives and closed friends. In this case too, the bonds linking various members of network are strong even if slightly less strong than in the restricted family. There are many other kinds of network. A club, a volunteer organization, a professional association, a church, a neighbourhood, a local community are all networks where the members share common values or common interests. They may feel a sense of belonging to these networks and develop a sense of common identity. (Keep in mind that since each individual belongs to more than one network, we talk of multiple identities. See Amartya Sen, Identity and violence) STRONG AND WEAK TIES It is clear however that ties linking people in a family network or in relatives’ and close friends’ networks are generally less strong and less binding than in the case of networks composed by members of a club or of a professional association. At a first stage, it is possible to analyse networks by the extension of its linkages, by the strength of ties among members and by the similarity of resources brought in the network by individual members. For instance a family network is characterized by a reduced extension, by similarity of resources and by very strong ties among members. Facebook on the other extreme is a network characterized by an enormous extension, by diversity of resources and by very weak ties among members. COMMON VALUES The actual working of a network may produce a set of common beliefs, values and expectations among members of the network. For instance, members of a family network hold the expectation of a reciprocal help in case of need. The same may occur in some territorial communities where people help each other in the case of negative events hitting some of their members. Members of professional associations may share common values of honesty and trustworthiness. Feeling of loyalty, solidarity and fairness may characterize different types of networks. Networks then are not only a set of interactions among members but include these cultural and moral elements. SANCTIONS Networks may impose a penalty to members who violate these common values and norms or do not behave as socially expected. These penalties can be formal sanctions if contained in legally binding documents. But these penalties can also be informal. A member of a professional network who behaved dishonestly may simply be cut off from future interactions and transactions. The sanction is the actual exclusion or marginalization from the network. This can result in an economic loss but also in a psychological sufferance. NETWORKS AS A FORM OF CAPITAL Why belonging to a social network matters? The social capital literature considers networks as a source of resources from which individuals can draw for improving their own activity. Networks are “capital” in two senses. They may be the result of past investments to the extent that individuals invest in social relations and they can be used to increase the rate or return of present and future activity. LIN DEFINITION OF SOCIAL CAPITAL To understand the utility of networks, we may follow Nan Lin contribution to the theory of social capital. Social capital is defined by Lin as “resources embedded in one’s social network, resources that can be accessed or mobilized through ties in the network. Through social networks an actor may borrow or capture other actors’ resources which can then generate a return for the actor.“ (But remind that alternative definitions do exist) NETWORKS AS A SOURCE OF SOCIAL CAPITAL Within Lin’s approach social capital and social networks are not equivalent or interchangeable terms. Networks provide the necessary conditions for access and use of embedded resources representing individual’s social capital. The quantity and quality of resources one can draw from networks depend on the specific features of the network itself. Dense and close networks may increase the sharing of resources among participants. Sparse and open networks may facilitate access to better or more varied resources or information, control or influence. Lin for instance identifies three layers of social network, an innermost layer composed by people with very strong ties that share sentiment and provide mutual support, the family being the clearest example; an intermediate layer made of people that share information and resources but with less binding ties; an outer layer characterized by shared membership and identity even though the members may or may not interact among themselves, typical examples are clubs, church or communities. The utility of each of these three levels of layers depends on the purpose of action. For some actions the inner layers are more important because what matters is the strength of ties and the obligation of reciprocity. It is easier for instance to borrow money from a member of your family than from a member of your club. For some other actions, the outer layers are more important because what matters is the diversity of resources that one can access. Your family or your closed friends connections may not be sufficient for instance to get a better job. It is more likely in this case to get help from people belonging to a larger and richer network SOCIAL CAPITAL AS A PRIVATE RESOURCE VERSUS SOCIAL CAPITAL AS A COLLECTIVE GOOD Some scholars have focused on social capital as individual’s resource while other scholars have focused on social capital as a collective resource. A single individual can “use” the resources embedded in a social network (social capital) to achieve goals that otherwise he would not be able to reach (or that he could reach with a greater effort or more costly). For instance many individuals use networks to search and get a job. Statistical studies overall the world have found that the majority of people get jobs mobilizing his personal contacts, relatives and friends first of all. Politicians mobilize the resources of their party to win the elections. A young entrepreneur may use the resources of his professional association to get credit for starting up a new firm. The networks used and the way in which they are used depend of course on the purpose you are pursuing. As we have seen, sometimes binding and bonding networks are more useful but other times you can find the resources you need in more open and sparse networks. At any rate, social capital in all these situations takes the form of a private good. Social capital is used by an individual to get personal benefits. Other members of network are not touched by the individual’s actions. Social capital however can be examined from a different perspective. It may emerge as a collective good rather than a private good. Think for instance to a territorial community (which is a network) made of people with a long historical traditional of cooperation, with a strong sense of identity, with shared value of honesty, industriousness and fairness, with very effective public services. To live and to work in this social environment offer many benefits for its residents. Individuals can exploit these positive features of the community to reach their goals. Citizens can benefit from public services of good quality, employers and workers can benefit from collaborative labour relations and so on. The combination of these features is the social capital of that community. What is relevant however is that social capital in this sense cannot be considered a private good. The fact that an individual benefits of such a favourable environment is not an obstacle for another individual living in the same community to benefit as well of the same resources. Social capital is therefore a public good: non rival and non excludable for residents. ((In some cases, social capital is a club good non rival but excludable for non members of the group). (Keep in mind the distinction between private goods (excludable and rival), public goods (non excludable and not rival), club goods (excludable and not rival) and commons (not excludable and rival)) RELATIONAL AND SYSTEM CAPITAL Some scholars (see Harmut Esser) have emphasized this dual nature of social capital minting two different names: relational capital and system capital. Relational capital can be seen as the resources an actor can employ and use through direct and indirect personal relations with other actors who control those resources to get intentionally a personal benefit. Relational capital can be the result of an explicit individual investment in personal relations and can be used as a private good. System capital can be considered alternatively as a set of characteristics of an entire network such as a fair and effective system of social control, generalized trust, shared moral values, aptitude towards mutual help. Everybody can benefit from system capital but it is not the property of any of the persons who benefit from it. And it does not emerge directly from intentional individual efforts. All actors profit from system capital independently of whether they have invested in it. TRUST WHAT IS TRUST A central concept in social capital theory is that of trust. Some scholars consider trust as a basic component of social capital; others regard it rather as a product of social capital. At any rate the concept has always an important place in social capital theories. Trust is an actor’s belief or expectation that when interacting or cooperating with another person he will not be exploited or defrauded. Technically we call “truster” the person who places trust on someone else, who is called “trustee”. The aptitude of the trustee of being worth of trust is said “trustworthiness”. The action of placing trust on someone is called “entrusting”. When the trustee confirms with his behaviour his trustworthiness is said to reciprocate (or to cooperate) while when the trustee turns out to be untrustworthy is said to exploit (or to defect, not to cooperate) WHY TRUST MATTERS A LOT Trust is important in practically all relationships one engages with other people. It would be almost impossible to interact one another in any aspect of our lives without a minimum level of reciprocal trust. Trust makes cooperation easier or even possible. It makes transactions less costly, specially economic transactions. Trust and trustworthiness have been compared in this sense to a lubricant, oiling the wheels of a variety of social and economic transactions which might otherwise prove extremely costly, bureaucratic and time consuming. Let us focus on economic transactions. Economic transactions are normally carried out through formal contracts containing the reciprocal engagements of the parts and the sanctions for not meeting the agreed requirements. But all contracts are incomplete for the simple reason that it is impossible to foresee and formalize all the possible contingencies. This implies that all economic transactions are based on some degree of trust. In absence of a sufficient level of trust, the transaction will simply not take place. NETWORKS AND TRUST Networks can differ one another, among other things, for the level of trust between its members. Networks characterized by a high level of trust are generally beneficial for single individuals and for the network as a whole. For single individuals it is easier and safer to achieve their own objectives if one can entrust other people being relatively sure of a cooperative answer. For the network as a whole it is easier to achieve collective goals such as economic growth, social cohesion, quality of public services in an environment characterized by a high level of generalized trust. THE SOURCES OF TRUST: DIFFERENT VIEWS What are the sources of trust? Why some networks are characterized by an high level of trust among members while others display a very low level? Scholars do not hold the same view on the original sources of trust. We may divide the field in a simplistic way between those who think that trust is the result of an actor’s rational strategy aimed at maximizing personal benefits and those who believe that trust is, at least partly, a characteristic of individual’s preferences. STRATEGIC TRUST The first approach is consistent with a more traditional neoclassical economics viewpoint. Perfectly rational economic actors pursue exclusively their personal interest. They do not have altruistic preferences. However they find useful to cooperate in a context of repeated interactions and of networks. Cooperation is not the result of an altruistic attitude but of a self interested strategy. Self interested actors sustain cooperation not because they care about others but because they try to maximize their own gains over time. This view is clearly expressed for instance by Hardin “ It is the high level of trustworthiness of people in my network that generates this benefit from mutual cooperation. Moreover, their trustworthiness is, on the encapsulated-interest account, the result of their having an interest in being trustworthy toward those with whom they have ongoing interactions that are beneficial and are likely to continue to be….” REPUTATION The potential benefits of cooperation at individual level within a network may depend on the necessity to maintain a good reputation among the members of a network. It may be possible that a single member- a trustee- in a specific situation could get advantage from a non cooperative behaviour. But his defection could ruin his reputation of trustworthiness. Other members could retaliate by isolating and marginalizing him. The result would be an overall economic and personal loss. This is the reason why a member of a network is more likely to cooperate than to defect in several occasions. Being embedded in a network, the trustee knows that it is in his interest not to exploit but to reciprocate and to keep the relationship going. Confirming his trustworthiness, he will improve his reputation within the network and other members will be willing to interact more frequently with him. A cooperative behaviour in this case may have nothing to do with altruistic aptitudes but it may result entirely from rational and egoistic calculations REPEATED INTERACTIONS This line of reasoning is confirmed for instance by the theory of games in the case of repeated interactions. When the trustee has to decide whether to reciprocate or not, must take into account the expected relative benefits of cooperation not of only “one shot game” but of an entire, possibly indefinite, sequence of games. He could then discover that the greater profits of “exploitation” (non cooperation) in one shot game would be more than offset by the losses in the successive games. The advantage of cooperation in repeated games emerges for instance from the famous experiment led by Axelrod which finds that the Tit-for-tat strategy (the player cooperates in the first game; after that, he/she does what the opponent did in their previous move) is the one which maximizes the profits of the players. IMPORTANCE OF HISTORY Cooperation is also more likely to prevail in communities or societies that have a long tradition of collective action whose members have learnt to appreciate the benefits of cooperation. On the basis of this experience, they show a strong propensity to cooperate entrusting other people and they have formed the expectation that other people will reciprocate. When most members of this community share this feeling, the prophecy becomes self-fulfilling: since most people entrust other people, most people will reciprocate. This will produce the success of a collective action and will reinforce people propensity to entrust and to reciprocate, creating the premises for new successful collective actions. From this background of historical accumulated experience of cooperation, a set of shared moral values including honesty, fairness, trustworthiness and reciprocation may grow and become a characterizing feature of that community. Experience as a source of trust is not incompatible with a strategic approach to trust. At the roots of trust it is possible to find a rational calculus on private benefits of cooperation. Accumulated experience makes the act of entrusting more automatic and less risky; the emergence of a collective moral based on trustworthiness reinforces the cooperative behaviour; nevertheless cooperation would break and moral values collapse if the individual’s advantages of defection permanently exceeded the individual’s benefits of cooperation. TRUST AS A MORAL VALUE OR AN INDIVIDUAL APTITUDE A second view on trust has been held by Elinor Ostrom, among others, within the framework of the so called second generation theories of collective action. These theories assume that economic actors may have altruistic attitudes. Trustworthiness is a characteristic of people preferences. Actors then may reciprocate even in absence of a selfish interest. In Ostrom’s words: “Trustworthiness refers to the characteristics of individual preferences that facilitates individual cooperative behaviour in social dilemmas even in the absence of structural and institutional incentives to do so”. Cooperation therefore is the result of a more complex mix of motivations, which includes self interest but also personal aptitudes, social norms and moral values. A similar view has been put forward by Uslaner. For him, trust is essentially a moral value. In Uslaner’s words: “moralistic trust is a moral commandment to treat people as if they were trustworthy. The central idea behind moralistic trust is the belief that most people share your fundamental moral values. Moralistic trust is based upon some sort of belief in the goodwill of the other”. He opposes moralistic trust to strategic trust. “Strategic trust depends on information and experience…it reflects our expectations about how people will behave…while moralistic trust is a statement about how people should behave”. TRUST AS INNATE IN THE HUMAN NATURE Many recent findings in experimental economics, in evolutionary biology, in psychological and neurological research support the view that trust, specially generalized trust, and altruistic behaviour can be the result of personal and social aptitudes, rather than of rational and selfish calculations. This research demonstrates that people’s preferences, priorities and strategies are crucially dependent on features of the social context such as norms, identity, status, reputation, social structure. Further, it has shown that cooperative and altruistic behaviours may depend on neurological and biological factors, that they are in some sense rooted in human nature. (see Woolcock and Radin) (See Akerlof and Kranton). This does not imply that trust is not the result of private calculations. But it demonstrates that the motivations behind individual’s choices are complex and include a variety of elements, including private benefits, altruistic feelings, fear of losing reputation, historical tradition of cooperation. GENERALIZED AND PARTICULARIZED TRUST Uslaner makes a further distinction between particularized trust and generalized trust. Particularized trust is faith only in people like yourself, of your own kind. Generalized trust refers to faith in both your own kind and people who are different from you. Generalized trust depends at micro level on education (education broadens one’s perspective on the world and brings one into contact with a wider variety of people), group identity (people who abjure contact with outsiders are less trustworthy, like members of minority groups), collective memory of big events (Vietnam war destroyed trust), family life (to have truster parents is important), early experiences in life (to have a friend of opposite race), an optimistic aptitude to life, a feeling of control of own life. At macro level, the most important determinant of trust is economic equality. It makes the less well off more optimistic in the possibility to improve their own situation and makes easier social relationships all over the society narrowing the distance between different social groups Particularized trust rather is most prevalent among people who: are more pessimistic about the future and their ability to determine their own fate; fear being the victims of crime; are loners with small support networks; have less education; are religious fundamentalists; who did not have warm relations with their parents when they were young; whose parents were not generalized trusters and who warned them not to trust others; and who are members of minority groups Generalized trust, whatever its source, has been found very important in determining the performance of a society and of an economy. Trusting societies have more effective governments, higher growth rates, less corruption and crime, and are more likely to redistribute resources from the rich to the poor. NETWORKS, TRUST AND CIVIC ENGAGEMENT Several authors identify the formation of trust and social capital in civic commitment. The endowment of social capital of a given community depends very much on the amount and quality of civic engagement of its citizens. Putnam, one of the founder fathers of social capital theory, put forward this theory in two famous researches, one on Italy and one on the United Stes. His first contribution to social capital theory was a study on regional government in Italy. Putnam in that study sought to explain regional differences in institutional performance between northern and southern regions of the country with reference to the different level of civic engagement in the two parts of the country. He traced the origins of the beneficial civic virtue back to the activities of the early medieval guilds in the largely autonomous, selfregulating city-states of the north. By contrast, he believed that the origins of the stand-off between state and civil society in the southern regions lay in the period of Norman autocracy which created a culture of mutual suspicion and fear which had stood repeatedly in the way of institutional reform and renewal. A second major contribution by Putnam focused on the United States. In his famous book entitled “Bowling alone”, Putnam supports the thesis of a long run decline in the endowment of social capital in the US, the main manifestation of which was the waning of citizens’ participation to social networks. League bowling served here as a metaphor of a type of associational activity that brings relative strangers together on a routine and frequent basis, helping to build and sustain a wider set of networks and values that foster general reciprocity and trust and in turn facilitates mutual collaboration. At the core of the explanations of different regional performances in Italy and of the decline of social capital in the U.S. , Putnam places “civic engagement”. Civic engagement can take a great variety of forms. It includes participation to different types of networks such as clubs, volunteer organizations, political parties, churches, professional associations, local institutions, neighbourhood organizations and so on. Putnam holds the view that people who actively participate to these different networks develop positive features of sociability: they tend to be more tolerant, informed, trustworthy, open, skilled. These qualities transfer from the individual level to the collective level. A dense network of secondary associations not only produces better citizens but it produces more efficient and democratic governments as well. It emerges here again the dual (micro and macro) nature of social capital. At an individual level, members of voluntary associations behave in a more trusty, democratic and participatory mode. At the societal level, better citizens engaged in dense networks of secondary associations, produce more responsive, fair, democratic and efficient governments. CIVIC ENGAGEMENTS AND DEMOCRACY The concept of civic engagement represents a sort of link between social capital and democracy. Most (but not all) scholars of social capital have supported the thesis of a positive correlation between democracy and social capital. The endowment of social capital has been found richer in countries with democratic governments rather than in authoritarian. Less clear is the direction of causality between these two variables. It is not clear whether democratic regimes favour the growth of social capital or, viceversa, a civil society rich of social capital favours the birth and consolidation of democratic regimes. Very important differences in the endowment of social capital have been however found also between the same democratic regimes. This implies that what makes the difference for social capital is not only the establishment of a democratic regime but how the democracy actually works. For social capital is important citizens’ participation at all levels of social and political life. This is the reason for a strong preference of social capital theorists for participatory democracies (or deliberative democracies). This type of democracies are based on deliberative decision-making processes that provide for a strong institutional involvement of citizens, and hence are more suitable for the production of social capital. The literature on the merits and on the shortcomings of participatory democracies is very wide and fascinating. The issues raised are of great relevance for economic development and specially for local economic development. The design of local policies is normally based on the introduction of decision making processes entailing participation at the bottom level and cooperation between social and institutional actors. Big international organizations, like OECD and World Bank, have embodied the principles of the deliberative democracy in the conception of their polical action. INSTITUTIONS SOCIETY AND INSTITUTION CENTRED APPROACHES TO SOCIAL CAPITAL One of the criticisms moved to Putnam’s approach of social capital is of being “societycentred”. Social capital is born and grows in the civil society mainly through people participation to associations at the grassroots level. It then can affect politics, governments and institutions. But the direction of causality goes from civil society to institutions and not the other way around. His approach is mainly bottom-up. The top-down influence on social capital of politics and institutions is completely overlooked in his approach. In contrast to that, the institution-centred approach of social capital theory (see Rothstein and Stolle) claim that for social capital to flourish, it needs to be embedded in and linked to a special set of formal political, administrative and legal institutions. According to this approach, social capital is produced by factors in politics or government and not primarily in the realm of civil society. The central idea of this approach is that government policies and political institutions create, channel and influence the amount and type of social capital in their respective societies. The capacity of citizens to develop broad-based and out-reaching cooperative ties and establish social trust is in this account heavily influenced by the effects of government institutions and policies. INSTITUTIONS AS RULES OF THE GAME AND AS POLITICAL ACTORS To grasp the mechanisms through which institutions produce social capital, it is the case to give a proper definition of institutions. You can find various and not always compatible definitions of institution in the literature. A popular definition has been put forward by the historian economist Douglas North who focuses on the regulatory role of institutions represented as “humanly devised constraints that structure political, economic and social interactions.” Constraints, as North describes, are devised as formal rules (constitutions, laws, property rights) and informal restraints (sanctions, taboos, customs, traditions, code of conduct), which usually contribute to the perpetuation of order and safety within a market or society. Social capital is certainly the product of social interactions but, in turn, social interactions do not take place in a vacuum but within a system of rules, given by the institutional architecture of the State, and are heavily affected by the nature, fairness and efficacy of these rules. While North and others have identified the institutions as “the rules of the game”, other scholars have emphasized the agency role of institutions. Institutions are political and economic actors who interact among themselves and with private actors, intervene in the civil society, promote and manage policies and projects to change things and can operate at national or at local level. Few examples may illustrate the mechanisms through which the actual working of institutions affect the production of social capital. INSTITUTIONS AT WORK IN PRODUCING SOCIAL CAPITAL Effectiveness in the application of law An effective court system transmits to the people the information that non-cooperative behaviours will be sanctioned. This will discourage citizens from exploitative courses of action. On the contrary, non-effective and corrupt institutions transmit the information that semi-legal or illegal conducts would be tolerated favouring the diffusion of opportunistic and improper behaviours. The same role of the courts could be played by informal rules of behaviour inspired to moral values of honesty and integrity prevailing in a group, in an association, in a club. Sanctions in this case would take the form of exclusion or marginalization from the group. Fear of sanctions would favour the diffusion of behaviours congruent with the shared moral values of the group. Fairness in the design and implementation of policies Institutions that design and implement public policies –in fields such as health, education, safety, taxes, other public services- according to principles of impartiality, equality before the law, respect for human rights, equality of opportunity will create a general environment of trust. First of all, citizens will trust institutions guided, in the conception of the rules and in their operative procedures, by such ideals. Secondly, people’s trust towards institutions is very likely to become trust among people themselves, or “generalized” trust. People experiencing on themselves a fair and correct treatment by institutions- the argument runswill have a greater propensity to behave correctly with other people. On the contrary, if citizens systematically experience partial or corrupt behaviour from bureaucrats representing local or national institutions, they are likely to conclude that if these people cannot be trusted, then nor can one trust most other people in society. Further, when institutions behave correctly and efficiently, there is also no need for individuals to resort to unfair practices to access public goods. People know that and know that other people know. People then will avoid to be engaged in practices such as patronages, discrimination and clientelism and will be confident that also other people will behave in the same way Efficiency and skills in coordinating collective actions Institutions play an important role in facilitating collective actions, discouraging and sanctioning free riding behaviours and creating an environment of generalized trust. But they can engage directly in the promotion and management of collective actions. They can, in so doing, reduce the coordination costs that private actors would incur in the promotion of collective goods. The focus is here on institutions as actors with particular skills, experiences and interests. Institutions may give first of all a crucial contribution in identifying the optimum solution of collective actions. Failures of collective actions depend not only on the possibility of free riding but also on the difficulties by private actors to align their preferences and to find the correct solution among various alternatives. Institutions in some cases bear information and skills that private actors do not possess and that can facilitate the emergence and the success of a collective action. Institutions can give incentives to private actors for the start up of a cooperation project and can discourage their early defection ensuring a long term perspective to collective actions. In Communities where institutions are very active and very successful in promoting collective actions, people have learnt the advantages of cooperation and have embodied the values of trust and reciprocity. They are communities, in other words, rich in social capital. SOCIAL CAPITAL AND POLICY The introduction of institutions in the picture, makes possible to deal with an important issue in the debate on social capital: can social capital as a public good be produced by means of policies? Up to now we have focused on social capital as an important input of an hypothetical production function where the output could be many things: from low crime rate, to better institutional performance, to higher economic growth and so on and so forth. But if social capital is so important in producing better output on a wide variety of variables, then it is also important to find ways in which we can improve our endowment of social capital. Nobody in the debate has denied explicitly the possibility to produce social capital by proper policies. However, some approaches are clearly more suitable to take into account the possibility to produce social capital by means of public policies The rational approach by Coleman sees individual actors undertaking social interactions for their own interest and certainly not to build social capital. In Coleman’s view then: “social capital arises not because actors make a calculating choice to invest in it, but as a “by product of activities engaged for other purposes”. In Putnam’s view, social capital as a collective goods is mainly the result of individual social interactions at the grass-roots level, its main source lying in people’s participation in voluntary organizations. But civic engagement as such is not aimed to build social capital. Further, in Putnam’s view social capital has a strong pathdependency element. The endowment of social capital of a community depends on long run social and political processes and it proves to be unresponsive to short run changes, unless the occurrence of big events. In Coleman’s and Putnam’s approaches then, social capital is the result of human actions aimed at different ends, (heterogenesis of ends) taken at grassroots level. Under these circumstances it is not clear how public policies can affect the formation of social capital. The insertion in our picture of institutions makes easier to give account of the role of public policies in building social capital. Institutions can be seen as political actors who play an active role in shaping the framework within which citizens decide whether to engage in public sphere and how to do it. As we have seen, institutions may affect the level of generalized trust through fair and clear rules of the game, correct and honest behaviours and an effective system of sanctioning and may contribute to the success of collective actions through their own skills, experience and long run perspective. POLICIES FOR SOCIAL CAPITAL There are a wide range of possible policies for the exploitation and strengthening of social capital. Some policies are national in scope, as they are centrally designed and run and their effects are felt all over the country. They encourage a national context of confidence in the legal system and public institutions. Such policies include measures for strengthening the independence and quality of the legal and law enforcement systems, increasing the transparency and accountability of the public sector, reinforcing the democratic control of the media, and introducing anti corruption measures. The confidence in institutions engendered by this type of policies should translate into generalized trust. Other policies, which can be implemented at regional and local level aim to strengthen the networks between local institutions as well as between local institutions and associations representing civil society or the private sector. Similar policies have the goal of widening the basis of economic development by facilitating local participation in strategic decisions, project implementation and policy monitoring. Other complementary policies aim at facilitating the transmission of information and the sharing of knowledge between local actors for a better design and implementation of local projects. All these policies boil down to the introduction of elements of deliberative democracy in the decision-making processes at local level. Finally some policies with a potential impact on social capital are addressed to private firms. These are policies to promote horizontal relationships between firms of the same sector or vertical relationships along the productive chain, to favour the joint production of services, to encourage participation in professional associations. THE DARK SIDE OF SOCIAL CAPITAL Up to now, we have implicitly assumed that social capital is a collective good benefitting all members of a given network and all people outside that network (or at least being neutral for other people). This assumption is clearly untenable. In principle and as a matter of fact, social capital can be a “social bad” rather than a social good. There are many cases where social capital of a given network benefits people belonging to that network but negative effects on people outside the network; we can say in this case that social capital is associated with negative externalities. There are also cases where social capital springing from a given network produces negative effects even for people belonging to that network. In both cases, we can talk of the “dark side” of social capital. This should not be surprising. Social capital foster mutual cooperation to pursue ends shared by members of the network. But we do not know at the outset if these ends are shared also from people outside the network and we do not know if the achievement of those ends ultimately benefit them. Not only. We can also imagine that common values of a network may damage people belonging to a network. This occurs for instance when the values of a network can be an obstacle to the aspirations and free choices of some of its members A similar problem arises with trust. It is difficult to distinguish between organizations that produce generalized trust, that is trust without exclusionary group boundaries, and those that produce the opposite, namely distrust between groups or strong in-group trust only. Many voluntary organizations and networks are actually built to instil distrust in other people in general and of members of other organizations in particular. Many of these associations and groups are of religious, political, ethnic and gender-based nature and their existence is partially justified on logic of separation or division, i.e. establishing distance bordering on distrust vis a vis competing associations, networks or societal groups. Their raison d’étre is the preservation of a rigid social status, professional and interest groups closure, ethnic and religious divisions and outright criminality. SOCIAL CAPITAL AND INEQUALITY An important line of thought has associated social capital with inequality. The first and most important scholar in this tradition has been Bourdieu, another founder father of social capital theory, with Coleman and Putnam. Bourdieu thesis is very straightforward: social capital can promote inequality in large part because access to different types of networks is very unequally distributed. Everyone can use their connections as a way of advancing their interests, but some people’s connections are more valuable than others’. Social capital can be seen as an asset that is unevenly distributed and as a mechanism that can promote further inequality. Social capital is unevenly distributed because what matters is not the number in itself of social connections but their value. Being of a higher social class, having greater personal income and having more educational qualifications entail the access to more valuable social relationships. What we find then is a strong positive correlation between financial capital, cultural capital and social capital. Social capital then reinforces the position of people with an already strong position in the social structure. But social capital is also a mechanism to perpetuate inequalities. Those who have the most valuable connections tend to use them to maintain and advance their interests, and this in turn is a cause of further inequality. The least privileged also tend to form their networks, but they are made up of people in a similar situation to themselves who are therefore of only limited use in accessing new resources. In particular, people facing tough circumstances can and do find their social capital a useful resource. Adversity can help strengthen bonds, particularly among those who face similar experiences of exclusion or danger. Yet while dense and localised networks may well be very homogeneous and close, they do not include many people who come from different background and could give access to new resources that are situated or controlled outside the community. For instance, Zhao, in a study of laid-off workers in China, found that typically they had distinctive networks, which were stronger on kinship ties than those of the population at large, but were also lower on the range of resources that were accessible. TYPES OF SOCIAL CAPITAL Are perverse results the outcome of a particular type of social capital? Several authors (see Woolcock abd Radin) have advanced an analytical distinction between three types of social capital: bonding, bridging and linking social capital. Bonding social capital can be found in networks characterized by strong social ties, feelings of solidarity, obligations of reciprocity, fears of marginalization, cultural homogeneity, closure to the outside world. This type of social capital is often associated with particularized trust, that is trust for specific people for doing specific things. It is more likely to prevail within families, kinship or small communities. Bridging social capital can be more often found in wider networks characterized by weak ties, less strong feelings of solidarity and obligations of reciprocation, openness to new relationships and knowledge, wider diffusion of information. It prevails in larger groups and more modern and innovative communities. Finally linking social capital refers to properties of an entire region or nation. Its main manifestations are people’s perception of living in a well-ruled country, confidence in public institutions, generalized trust. It tends to prevail in countries were the state treats citizens equally, the decision making procedures are highly democratic, the court system is effective, there is a long accumulated history of successful collective action. (This distinction recalls the “three layers” distinction put forward by Nan Lin). Most scholars have associated perverse effects of social capital with particular forms of bonding social capital or with the absence of bridging social capital. Groups or communities characterized by strong internal ties but weak external links are those that more likely pursue interests of their members at the expense of ignoring other people’s interest and that develop feelings of hostility and aversion for outsiders. It may be useful to insert here a brief note on the concept of identity, which has been widely used in the context of local development policies. As in the case of social capital, the concept of identity is double sided. A strong identity of a network’s members, let assume a Community, has always been seen as a positive value associated with social cohesion, attachment to the territory’s historical heritage, respect and love for the homeland. All these elements have generally been considered as functional for a community driven development. But a strong identity can also be a synonymous of closure, intolerance and conservatism that represent powerful obstacles to any form of economic and human development. SOCIAL CAPITAL AND ECONOMICS SOCIAL CAPITAL AND TRANSACTION COSTS Economists were quite suspicious and reluctant to use the concept of social capital when it was first introduced. They were also annoyed by the use of term “capital” drawn from the economic discipline but used improperly according to some eminent economists. Economists are accustomed to work with very precise concepts and with quantitative variables exactly measurable. They do not appreciate vague or flexible concepts and qualitative variables that make difficult to build and use formal mathematical models. It took time then before mainstream economists (few of them up to now) began to use social capital in economic analysis. The most convincing economic backdrop for using this concept in economics is probably the theory of transaction costs and incomplete contracts. Generally speaking, social capital intervenes in the economy when the market fails. Its role is to help to remove the causes of market failure and allow trade which would otherwise not be able to take place. The theory of transaction costs and incomplete contracts states that stipulating a contract involves costs, and that all contracts are necessarily incomplete. There is a trade off between level of completion and cost of contracts. The more complete is a contract, the less risk it presents, but the more it costs. The less complete a contract is, the less it costs, but the more risk is present. So transactions may be hindered because contracts governing them involve excessive transaction costs or because they are too risky in the absence of contractual safeguards. Social capital plays a role in this trade off by reducing the costs and risks of transactions, increasing the opportunities for trade and leading to greater economic efficiency. AGAIN ON COLLECTIVE ACTION Remaining in the field of economics, there is an important set of situations in which social capital is presumed to play an important role: the production of public goods through collective action. Collective action, we remind, is required when for the production of certain goods different subjects need to coordinate their action. This is often the case with public goods which cannot be produced at all or in the sufficient quantity by normal market functioning. Having introduced networks, institutions and social capital, we can come back to the problem of collective action in a more formalized way highlighting the respective role of networks, social capital, institutions and private interest. The typical trust situation in a collective action problem with only two actors represents a version of the prisoner’s dilemma: Subject A must decide whether entrust a subject B or not without having the possibility of finding a formal and binding agreement If A decides not to entrust B, there will not be interactions between A and B and the payoff for both will be nil (0,0) If A decides to entrust B, the transaction starts and B must in his turn to decide whether reciprocate A or exploit A If B decides to reciprocate, the transaction ends with A and B getting a positive payoff equal to f If B decides to exploit, the transaction ends with A getting a negative payoff equals to – n and B getting a positive payoff equals to f + n The essence of a collective action problem arise from the inherent conflict between B’s private interest of exploiting and the collective interest of cooperation. In one shot game with rational and selfish players, the exit of the game is the failure of the collective action. A knows that if he choses to entrust B, the interest of B will be to exploit and that in this case he will get a loss equals to –n. Then A will choose not to entrust B from the beginning and no transactions will take place. The payoff for both players will be nil, lower than the payoff of cooperation for both players. Is there any way out from this situation of impasse? There are various possibilities which can make possible a cooperative solution: a) A and B know that they are bound to interact in the future an indefinite number of times because they belong to the same network. B knows that if A entrusts him and he exploits, then A will not entrust him in the future. The short run profit of exploitation will fall short of the long run losses from missed transactions in the future. A knows that B is aware of that and will entrust B and B will reciprocate b) If the non cooperative behaviour is forbidden by formal rules and if the court system is effective, B will reciprocate for fear of being sanctioned. A knows that and will entrust B in the first place. c) Even in absence of formal rules, shared values, in the network to which A and B belong, of trust and reciprocity may convince B to cooperate for fears of informal sanctions as ostracism or marginalization from the network. In this case the gain from exploitation would be more than offset by relational and psychological losses and not necessarily by economic losses. These shared values may be the result of a long and successful tradition of collective action d) A may chose to entrust B and B to reciprocate because both have a component of altruism in the preference function. They trust each other because they share trust as a moral value. This may depend on individual propensities or may be the result of A and B living in a society characterized by an high degree of generalized trust. The cooperative solution in the case of a) depends entirely on a rational calculus. We do not need either social capital or institutions. The cooperative solution in b) depends crucially on the role of institutions in establishing the rules of the game and enforce them. The solution in c) calls into question, institutions in the form of informal rules and social capital in the form of moral values shared by the community. Finally the possibility of d) depends crucially on the degree of personal and generalized trust prevailing in the society. These various possibilities do not imply that a positive solution of a collective action is easy and straightforward but only that positive solutions are possible. Finally, one should remark that positive solutions of collective actions in most cases of real life come from a combination of private interest, fear of formal and informal sanctions, shared values in the network and altruistic propensity, id est, from a joint evaluation of all factors examined in the four solutions displayed above. SOCIAL CAPITAL AND ECONOMIC DEVELOPMENT Social capital matters for economic development. There are a lot of studies that confirm this thesis. At community level, social capital is associated with higher household incomes in Tanzania villages, with higher levels of household welfare in Indonesia, with development performance in villages of North India. At national level, economic growth is higher overall in countries where trust and social capital are higher. National economic growth benefits from generalized trust in potential trade partners which in turn is linked to confidence in public institutions. Citizens ‘ perceptions that they live in a country where the state treats citizens equally, where justice is impartial and penalties for lawbreakers are effective, are elements that, in theory, facilitate the spread of trust in the widest sense. To use Serageldin and Grootaert words “formalized institutional relationships and structures such as governments, political regimes, the rule of law, court systems and civil and political liberties” can make a difference for national economic performance. They help the economy to function because create a framework of certainties regarding the availability of high-quality public goods and the behaviour of trade partners, reducing the risk of economic choices. The relevant social capital is linking social capital in the form of confidence in the correct and equitable functioning of institutions and more generally the honesty of individual economic actors. Local economic growth is supposed to benefit from both bonding and bridging social capital. Bonding social capital consists of the close ties in small cohesive communities. Opportunistic behaviour is very unlikely with this type of group because the stronger is the cultural conditioning engendering cooperation between members, the easier it is to identify and punish deviation. In this context trust has an almost primitive connotation. But bonding social capital can also hinder economic development (the dark side of social capital). In the first place, group interests may not coincide with overall community interests. Secondly, group cohesion may lead to closure to outside stimuli and conservative behaviour. Bridging social capital and weak ties allow group closure to be opened up to new relationships and knowledge and the wider dissemination of information. Trust in people is no longer a result of generational bonds, but comes to depend on actual knowledge of others, past experience and the specific characteristics of the network. References In writing these notes, I have drawn freely from the book Social Capital by John Field , Routledge, 2003 and from various chapters of the book: Handbook of social capital, edited by Castiglione, Van Deth and Wolleb, Oxford University Press, 2008. More exactly from: The two meanings of social capital, by Harmut Esser, chapter 1 A network theory of social capital, by Nan Lin, chapter 2 Social capital and collective action, by T.K. Ahn and Elinor Ostrom, chapter 3 Trust as a moral value, by Eric M. Uslaner, chapter 4 The nature and logic of bad social capital by Mark Warren, chapter 5 Social capital and civic engagement. A comparative perspective by Sigrfid Rossteutscher, chapter 8 Political institutions and generalized trust by Bo Rothstein and Dietlind Stolle, chapter 10 Introduction to Part 3. Social capital and economic development by Guglielmo Wolleb Social capital in economics by Domenico Cersosimo and Rosanna Nisticò, chapter 14 A relational approach to the theory and practices of economic development by Michael Woolcock and Elizabeth Radin, chapter 15 Social capital and economic development by Anirudh Krishna, chapter 16 Social capital and microfinance by Laura Foschi, chapter 17 Social capital, institutions and collective action between firms by Alessandro Arrighetti, Gilberto Seravalli and Guglielmo Wolleb, chapter 19