Public Opinion and the U.S. Courts of Appeals: The Case of Abortion Christopher D. Johnston Assistant Professor Department of Political Science Duke University Campus Box 90204 Durham, NC 27708 christopher.johnston@duke.edu Maxwell Mak Assistant Professor Department of Political Science John Jay College of Criminal Justice 445 W. 59th Street New York, NY 10019 mmak@jjay.cuny.edu & Andrew H. Sidman Assistant Professor Department of Political Science John Jay College of Criminal Justice 445 W. 59th Street New York, NY 10019 asidman@jjay.cuny.edu Authors are listed in alphabetical order. Abstract Given that a vast majority of cases remain final at the U.S. Courts of Appeals, circuit court jurists should decide in a manner consistent with Supreme Court precedent if the federal judiciary is to function appropriately. Lack of such constraint would pressure the Supreme Court to constantly engage in error correction of lower court decisions, or risk the practical undermining of its authority. While there is no doubt that legal considerations constrain lower court judges (e.g., Benesh 2002; Songer et al 1994), questions remain about the extent to which popular sentiment influences the decisions of the circuit courts, as has been suggested for the Supreme Court (e.g., Epstein and Knight 1998; McGuire and Stimson 2004). To test the impact of public opinion on circuit court decision-making, we construct an original measure of abortion “mood” and examine the effect of popular sentiment on abortion cases decided from 1973 to 2006. We find that the role of public opinion is conditional on the legal context and the ideology of a particular jurist. Specifically, judges are strategic in their uses of public opinion to advance their policy preferences. Our analysis provides an important examination of the sources of constraint on lower court decision-making. All Article III jurists enjoy the constitutional protection of life tenure, which removes any direct electoral accountability as well as provides an institutional insulation from the ebbs and flows of popular sentiment. Through the power of judicial review, judges at all levels of the federal judiciary must constantly encounter and answer questions of constitutionality regarding the actions of the popularly-elected branches. With this ability to strike down actions or laws as inconsistent with the constitution, federal judges are placed in a peculiar position of either validating the positions of the majoritarian branches of government or standing against the position supported by those duly-elected with popular support. The countermajoritarian difficulty is ever present not only for the justices themselves, but also the judges at the U.S. Courts of Appeals. Moreover, as the number of cases at the circuit courts increases, potential collisions with popular-elected branches also increase. As a result, the potential for judges to stand apart from popular sentiment, or public opinion, rises as well. Despite the fact that federal judges do not need to run for reelection, there are several potential explanations as to why public opinion may directly influence the choices judges and justices make.1 First, with neither the power of the purse nor the sword, the federal judiciary is reliant on the coordinate branches of government to carry out its decisions. Without the support of the legislature or the executive, the Court truly can be considered the least dangerous branch. As a result, judges and justices should be mindful of the popular will because the coordinate branches, which are charged with the enforcement of court decisions, listen and adhere to public opinion (e.g., Giles, Blackstone, and Vining 2008; Mishler and Sheehan 1993; McGuire and 1 Norpoth and Segal (1994) provide empirical evidence suggesting that public opinion does indeed have an effect— at least, indirectly through the advice and consent process. Known as the replacement hypothesis (Funston 1975), this indirect influence suggests that the impact of public opinion is seen primarily through the nomination and confirmation process. In other words, judges being placed on the bench by popularly elected officials should be at least somewhat representative of public opinion at the time of their nomination. Thus, as presidents and Senators replace judges within the federal judiciary, public opinion should be mirrored through the policy preferences Article III judges. This paper does not discount the replacement hypothesis as an avenue for popular sentiment to affect decisions within the federal judiciary. Rather, this paper focuses on the direct influence of public opinion. Stimson 2004). Second, and similarly, sustained and prolonged deviations from public opinion may decrease the legitimacy of the institution and, as evinced in several instances, place the federal judiciary in direct confrontation with the majoritarian branches of government (e.g., Hooper 2005; Lindquist and Yalof 2001; Scott 2004). Third, judges are indeed members of the public and may be influenced by popular sentiment through their encounters with legal and extralegal actors (e.g., Epstein and Knight 1998; Slotnick 1984). While these explanations may hold true and explain the influence of public opinion in previous examinations of the Supreme Court (e.g., Giles, Blackstone, and Vining 2008; Mishler and Sheehan 1993, 1996; Stimson and McGuire 2004), few (e.g., Calvin, Collins and EshbaughSoha 2010) have attempted to decipher the influence of popular sentiment at the U.S. Courts of Appeals. Moreover, few if any of these previous examinations have incorporated the most important aspect of judicial decision-making, especially at the circuit courts: the legal context. This paper attempts to resolve both omissions in an examination of the potential influence of public opinion on abortion cases decided at the Courts of Appeals. We argue that extralegal factors such as public opinion influence judges at the Courts of Appeals, but such effects should be conditional on the legal context and the ideological preferences of lower court judges. In other words, judges are strategic, using public opinion as a tool to vote consistently with their policy preferences when voting in accordance with precedent and the legal context would yield a less optimal policy outcome. We test our conditional theory of the influence of public opinion on abortion cases decided at the U.S. Courts of Appeals from 1973 to 2005. With Supreme Court preferences being arguably more liberal than popular sentiment for most of the time period examined, the judicial decision-making environment suggests conservative jurists will be the ones most likely to utilize public opinion as strategic cover to vote consistently with their policy preferences. In contrast, liberal judges, lacking majoritarian support, are more sensitive to the justices’ preferences, attempting to maintain positions closer to their preferred positions. Consistent with these theoretical propositions, the voting behavior of conservative jurists evinces a long-term relationship with public opinion, yet little to no substantive relationship with Supreme Court ideology independent of popular sentiment. Conversely, liberals show both short- and long-term relationships with Supreme Court preferences, but appear unmoved by the ebbs and flows of popular sentiment. Our examination of lower court decision-making in the area of abortion contributes a deeper understanding of the evolution of abortion policy as well as a more refined perspective of the choices lower court judges make in the presence of presence of various constraints. Judicial Decision-Making, Public Opinion and the U.S. Courts of Appeals Judges at the U.S. Courts of Appeals have the policy preferences (e.g., Giles, Hettinger and Peppers 2002; Songer and Haire 1992), hoping to make decisions as consistent with their ideologies. As the court directly below the Supreme Court, judges at the Courts of Appeals, however, are charged, first and foremost, with the duty of applying legal considerations—as established by the justices—in their decisions (Benesh 2002; Gruhl 1981; Klein 2002; Songer and Haire 1992; Songer, Segal and Cameron 1994). Failure to do so increases the odds that circuit court decisions may be petitioned for review (Songer, Segal, and Cameron 1995) and subject to potential reversal by the nation’s highest court. Aside from the reversal of their decisions, judges under these conditions pay both a reputational and ideological cost in having the reprimand made into national precedent. Under this institutional framework, circuit court judges must be wary of deviating from Supreme Court decisions unless conditions are ripe for such strategic action. Public opinion serves as a potential factor signaling the conditions under which breaking with the Supreme Court may yield two plausible outcomes for a decision that is ideologically congruent with the policy preferences of the jurist. First, the decision will remain final at the U.S. Courts of Appeals because the Supreme Court will deny it certiorari. Or, second, the decision will be upheld by the Supreme Court. Thus, the influence of popular sentiment should not be direct as considered by most previous examinations of the influence of public opinion on judicial decision-making. Rather, by altering the probability that a decision will be overturned by the Supreme Court, public opinion’s impact should be conditional on a given judge’s ideology and the decision-making environment. Increasing ideological divergence between a given judge’s ideology and High Court decision-making should increase the attractiveness of breaking with precedent (Bueno de Mesquita and Stephenson 2002). Circuit court judges, however, cannot deviate from the Supreme Court simply because they ideologically prefer such actions without the increased possibility of review and reversal by the justices. Under these circumstances, a judge that votes in accordance with ideology, fails to adhere to precedent and makes a decision that does not mirror public opinion places himself in harm’s way. Not only did this jurist vote ideologically, but voted ideologically in a manner that deviated from the duties of circuit court judges (i.e., apply legal principles consistent with the nation’s highest court) and would probably fail to garner public acceptance. When ideology and the legal context are divergent, an increase in ideological voting will thus occur if and only if public opinion is in accordance with judicial policy preferences. When public opinion and policy preferences are convergent and therefore predict similar outcomes in terms of judicial voting behavior, it increases the likelihood that such a decision will be acceptable to the public as well as decreases the potential that such a decision will be overturned by the Supreme Court. As Bickel (1962) notes, the Supreme Court must rest its decisions on great and widely accepted principles; we believe that these principles are majoritarian values, expressed through contemporaneous public opinion. Public acceptance of decisions from the federal judiciary increases as such decisions comport and mirror the will of the people. Thus, if a lower court judge deviates from precedent, but has crafted a decision mirroring the positions of popular sentiment, it forces the justices to stand against public opinion in order to remedy such noncompliance or decisions that run counter with the ideological preferences of the Supreme Court. The justices care about the legitimacy of the Supreme Court (e.g., Epstein and Knight 1996); the power of the Supreme Court emanates from diffuse support, or overall belief of the polity in the legitimacy of the institution (Clark 2011). Maintenance of this diffuse support allows the justices to occasionally break with the public will in specific instances. Thus, issue- or case-specific support may increase or decrease depending on the issue, but higher levels of diffuse offers the justices sufficient “cover” from decisions that are inconsistent with majoritarian values and the popular will. Historically, consistent, sustained and systematic deviations from public opinion and majoritarian values have proven to be problematic for the Supreme Court. Examples include the battle over the communism cases from the House Un-American Activities Committee (HUAC). Even though these cases are often perceived as Supreme Court challenges to the majoritarian branches of government, an often overlooked aspect is that these cases were petitioned from Courts of Appeals decisions that supported public opinion at the time. Watkins v. United States (1957) reversed the en banc decision in Watkins v. United States (D.C. Cir. 1956), which upheld a conviction of contempt from Watkins’ refusal to answer questions before a legislative hearing. In the wake of the decision, Congress considered removing the Court’s appellate jurisdiction to review and decide cases emanating from HUAC. By undoing decisions arguably supported by public opinion, the Supreme Court placed itself in direct confrontation with the legislative and executive branches, threatening the legitimacy and policy-making ability of the institution. The D.C. Circuit was ordered to reconsider the question in Barenblatt v. United States (1958) in light of Watkins. If Watkins and therefore the relevant legal context established by the Court were to hold, the D.C. Circuit decision should have reversed a conviction of contempt for Barenblatt, whose circumstances were similar to those of Watkins. Instead, the D.C. Circuit distinguished the factual circumstances from Watkins, affirmed a charge of contempt of Congress and continued to mirror the preferences of popular sentiment. After the petition for the writ of certiorari was granted, the Supreme Court was faced with remedying the inconsistency of Barenblatt with Watkins and again standing against the popular will. Instead, the Court equivocated, upholding the conviction and affirming the D.C. Circuit decision. In sum, lower court judges must be strategic in their deviations of Supreme Courtestablished precedent. When ideologically consistent to do so, siding with public opinion serves as a signal to lower court judges that breaking away from the relevant legal context may yield ideologically favorable outcomes. This allows jurists to vote in accordance with their policy preferences because their decisions will comport with majoritarian values. In doing so, judges will make it more difficult for the justices to undo such a decision, placing the nation’s highest court in a tenuous position of standing against popular sentiment to remedy ideologically or legally inconsistent lower court decisions. As such, the justices may simply avoid reviewing the case or upholding the ruling. The Case of Abortion: The Legal Context and Public Opinion We examine the proposition of strategic applications of public opinion on abortion cases, which is an ideal issue area of empirical verification of the theory advanced above. First, abortion has been one of the most salient and politicized issues in the last thirty plus years, making an examination of decisions handled by the Courts of Appeals important and pertinent. Second, compliance and responsiveness is generally lower for civil rights and civil liberties (Baum 1978); as an example of the latter, abortion cases already may be subject to possible judicial defiance. Lastly, given the politicized nature of abortion, there are serious doubts as to whether circuit court judges would even use the legal context or public opinion in making decisions. It may be the case that ideology is the sole predictor of the choices judges make. In 1973, Roe v. Wade established that strict scrutiny should be the test of constitutionality for abortion regulations; under this standard, judges must determine whether a law advances a compelling government interest and whether that law is the least restrictive of means to advance that interest. Strict scrutiny places the burden of proof on the government, making it more difficult for a restriction on abortion to survive a challenge of constitutionality. The legal context under the compelling interest standard offers the most protection of individual liberties and decisions—more often than not—should be supportive of abortion rights. It should be the case that liberal jurists, who are assumed to prefer supporting abortion rights, adjudicate under a legal context that reinforces their policy preferences. Deviating from strict scrutiny would defy rationality. Thus, if public opinion is to operate as a strategic tool in the aftermath of Roe, conservative jurists should be the ones most likely to break from precedent (i.e., in terms of judicial behavior, voting to uphold restrictions on abortion) and utilize majoritarian sentiments to do so. As such, we hypothesize: (1) Decision-making of conservative jurists will be conditional on public opinion, but not liberals judges. With respect to moderate judges, there are two plausible hypotheses in regards to their voting behavior. First, they adhere to their institutional role being unmoved by popular sentiment. Second, these jurists will be sensitive to shifts in public opinion, but for different reasons than their conservative brethren. Namely, these jurists would most likely adjust decision-making to comport with public opinion not for strategic purposes in deviating from precedent, but rather for the purposes of maintaining consistency of legal decisions with the public good. Abortion jurisprudence also underwent a potential change in Planned Parenthood v. Casey (1992), which established the undue-burden standard as the appropriate level of judicial scrutiny for government restrictions on abortion challenged as unconstitutional.2 Whereas rational basis and strict scrutiny would predict conservative and liberal outcomes, respectively, undue burden places the legal considerations in between. This change allows for a prediction that circuit court judges post-Casey should be less supportive of the right to an abortion, ceteris paribus. This represents an alternative explanation for potential changes in conservative decision-making. In other words, it predicts a change in behavior due to the Court altering its 2 The Supreme Court actually changed to the undue-burden standard in Webster v. Reproductive Health Services (1989). There is, however, uncertainty as to the effectiveness of Webster in shifting abortion jurisprudence. First, only one opinion and one justice (O’Connor) in Webster actually endorsed undue burden. Second, there was no clarification as to what type of provision constitutes an undue burden on a woman seeking an abortion. Third, there was conflict with the opinion (Rehnquist) that received the title “Judgment of the Court” and the opinion (O’Connor) that was the law of the land according to the Marks Doctrine, which was established in Marks v. United States (1977). Clear and unambiguous Supreme Court policies are most likely to elicit compliance at the lower courts (Canon and Johnson 1998). When compared to Casey, Webster arguably does not fall into this category. Due to the multiple ambiguities of the law in Webster, Casey is the appropriate and effective shift in abortion jurisprudence, because it placed undue burden on firmer and surer legal ground. own precedent, rather than circuit court judges deviating strategically using popular sentiment as a guide. Data and Methods Dependent Variable. In order to test the hypotheses discussed above, original data was collected for all abortion cases decided at the U.S. Courts of Appeals from 1973 to 2005. Identification of the population of abortion cases was completed through searches on Lexis/Nexis3, which includes information for some case opinions that were unpublished.4 Crosspetitioned cases were counted as separate cases if they challenged different provisions or aspects of a government regulation seeking to restrict the right to an abortion. Cases containing multiple dockets were also counted as separate cases if the circuit court opinions made note of the controversies as being different for each docket, indicated different provisions from each docket, or arose from different states within the circuit. In order to be included in the population of cases employed in this paper, cases had to pertain to the constitutionality of abortion regulations that seek to limit the right to an abortion in general, as a target of government spending, or as a medical procedure.5 The dependent variable is coded 1 if a judge votes in favor of abortion rights, 0 otherwise. For ease of discussion, we refer to a vote in favor of abortion rights as a liberal vote. 3 While this method does place much discretion in identifying the relevant population of cases, the selection process proceeded quite cautiously to ensure that as many relevant cases were included. First, searches on Lexis/Nexis were completed employing three main search terms: “abortion”, “trimester” and “viability”. Searches employing major Supreme Court decisions in the area of abortion were also completed; they were Roe, Doe v. Bolton (1973), Akron, Webster, and Casey. Second, each case was then screened to ensure that it involved a controversy surrounding a government regulation of abortion. 4 As Songer (1988) cautions, the use of Shepard’s Citations only elicits cases include full citations or case names in the opinion. Lexis/Nexis is a more appropriate source for case selection. Although it occasionally suffers from problems of search over-inclusion as well as under-inclusion, it does offer some information for unpublished opinions. 5 Cases where the controversy began with such a regulation, but the overall question answered by the court focused on standing, justiciability, or jurisdiction, were also included. If one is to accept the possibility of opinions being post-hoc justifications for ideological voting, omission of such litigation and the subsequent decisions would be problematic and bias the results. [Figure 1 here] Abortion Mood. To assess the effects of public opinion on decision-making, we created a new measure of the aggregate preferences of the public on the issue of abortion, which will hereafter be labeled “abortion mood” and is presented in Figure 1. The term “mood” is intended to reflect the latent nature of the variable which we seek to operationalize. The issue of abortion can be complex, and contains a number of qualitatively distinct facets. Our measure represents the public’s general orientation, or tendency, toward the issue, averaging over the idiosyncrasies of the individual facets. In this sense, our approach is in accord with previous research on aggregate opinion which seeks a meaningful “signal” within the noise of many separate polling items, and focuses on changes at the margin rather than the objective level (i.e. percentage support) of opinion on a given issue (Durr 1993; Erikson, MacKuen and Stimson 2002; Mishler and Sheehan 1993; Stimson 1991; Stimson, MacKuen and Erikson 1995). To obtain the marginals for our analysis, we searched Roper’s IPOLL Database using the search query “abortion.” We did not limit our search to a specific time period, and we obtained items for every year spanning the period 1972-2009. We excluded from consideration any items which referenced political figures, parties or other political institutions. We also excluded any items which allowed for multiple responses.6 We restricted our data to major survey organizations. These considerations produced 742 survey marginals for the period. We then examined the items individually, and coded each into one of twenty-three qualitatively distinct categories representing the substantive content of the item. A small number of items suggested membership in more than one category. In such cases, we made a subjective judgment as to the 6 For example, an item which asked respondents to choose a set from a list of abortion rights would be excluded. dominant theme of the item. The category listings and additional information concerning our selection procedures are contained in Appendices A and B. Most items were naturally in a “Support/Oppose” format, but a meaningful proportion had to be transformed to accommodate a dichotomous operationalization. When items contained an even number of ordered categories, we simply split responses into two groups with an equal number of categories. When an odd number of ordered categories were utilized, we combined the categories to the left and right of the median category. We then transformed each individual item into a ratio which divided the percent falling within the “liberal” category by the percent giving either a “liberal” or “conservative” response. We consider the ratio for a given item in a given year to be a manifestation of (1) the latent, general orientation of the aggregate public to the issue of abortion in that year, and (2) the idiosyncratic characteristics of the item itself. This perspective falls within the domain of psychometrics known as Item Response Theory (IRT; Embretson and Reise 2000). In the typical case, IRT models treat a given observed response as cross-nested within a particular item and a particular unit of observation. The item characteristics include a “difficulty” parameter and a “discrimination” parameter, which in a regression context are equivalent to a constant term and the beta coefficient for the latent variable for that particular item as follows: (1) yijk = αk + βkθj + εijk, for j = 1, …, J units, and k = 1, …, K items. We estimate the model within a Bayesian, multilevel framework which has important advantages in the present context. Specifically, the item parameters are themselves given a probability distribution, and are thus assumed to be random draws from a common population of items. This can be equivalently considered in terms of a prior distribution for these parameters, which serves to “partially pool” estimates to the prior’s mean when the number of observations for a given item is low (Gelman and Hill 2007). This allows us to use all items collected throughout the entire period, even those for which we have only a single observation. For the latter instances, the estimates for the item-specific parameters are simply the means of the common distributions for the difficulty and discrimination parameters respectively. For items with more than one, but relatively few observations, the partial pooling approach generates estimates with greater efficiency. A final consideration for estimation concerns the temporal nature of the latent variable θ. In the typical IRT case, the units of observation are assumed to be exchangeable such that the unit identifiers contain no additional information relevant to estimation. In our case, these identifiers index years, and thus we expect the value of θ in period t to be more related to its value at t-1 than at t-2. We integrate this information into the model by assuming that the θ series represents a “random-walk” process such that θt is a function of the previous period’s value plus some random disturbance. This is operationalized via a prior distribution for the θt with a mean equal to θt-1, and a variance set by the researcher. The variance chosen determines the degree of smoothing of values across time (Martin and Quinn 2002; West and Harrison 1997). The model was estimated via the Gibbs sampler in WinBUGS (Lunn, Thomas and Spiegelhalter 2000). We describe the procedure in greater detail in the Appendix C. As a sanity check on our estimates, we compared our series to the results from two alternative estimation procedures. First, we averaged the values for all General Social Survey abortion items within a given year to create a series which spans the time period 1972-2008 (with a number of gaps). Second, we estimated abortion mood utilizing Stimson’s (1991) recursive algorithm which he developed for similar purposes. The correlations between our series and these alternatives were .63 and .88, respectively. The high correlations of these series, particularly with Stimson’s measure, give us confidence in the validity of our estimation procedure. The lower correlation with the GSS series is also to be expected, given the coarse operationalization. We include plots of all three estimated series in Appendix D. The same basic patterns of opinion are evident in all three series. Judge Ideology. Judge’s ideologies are ideological scores derived from the Giles et al. (2001) coding strategy. A given judge’s ideology takes on the value of the nominating president’s common space score (Poole 1998) if senatorial courtesy is inactive. If senatorial courtesy is in play, a given judge’s ideology takes on the value of the home-state senator of the president’s party; if both home-state senators share the same party affiliation as the nominating president, the judge’s ideology is measured as the average of the senators’ common space scores. Supreme Court Ideology. In addition to the ideology of the judge, we control for the ideology of the Supreme Court and ideology of the remaining panelists on which the appellate judge serves for a given case. To measure Supreme Court ideology, we employ the Epstein, Martin, Segal and Westerland (2006) Judicial Common Space (JCS) scores, which converts the Martin-Quinn ideological scores (Martin and Quinn 2002) for Supreme Court justices into common space scores (Poole 1998), for the median justice. Thus, it is expected that as the Supreme Court Median increases, the likelihood of a liberal vote decreases. Panel Composition is measured as the proportion of the other panelists with an ideology score (as determined by the Giles et al. (2001) coding strategy, which again is “flipped”) less than zero, which is the theoretical midpoint of the common space scores. This measure varies within cases and by each observation. For example, if a judge serves with two judges whose common space scores are less than zero, Panel Composition takes on the value of 1; if both judges have common space scores greater than zero, the variable has a value of 0. If one of the remaining panelists has an ideology score greater than zero and the other’s ideology score is less than zero, the variable is coded 0.5. While this coding strategy to capture panel effects loses the finer details of a continuous measure of ideology, it serves as a parsimonious specification of panel composition akin to the Sunstein et al. (2006) examination, which uses partisanship of the appointing president. This measure does allow for both avenues of collegial influence: (1) the overall behavior; and (2) the impact on ideology in the vote choice. Lastly, we control for case facts in the form of a dummy variable that indicates the presence of a Casey provision. Casey Provision is measured as a dummy variable coded 1 if a case concerns one of the provisions discussed in Casey AND was upheld by the Court in Casey, 0 otherwise. If a government regulation on abortion concerned parental consent, medial recordkeeping, informed consent, or a 24-hour waiting period, the variable Casey Provision was coded 1, 0 otherwise. If the provision pertained to spousal consent, the variable was coded 0 because the Court in Casey regarded this regulation constituted an undue burden and thus fails to comport with the Constitution. It is expected that the presence of a Casey provision will decrease the likelihood of a liberal vote. Analysis We model the likelihood of a liberal vote as a function of public opinion, ideology (of the judge, the Supreme Court, and the panel on which the judge serves), and case facts as follows: (1) Pr(yit =1) = Φ[β0 + β1 Casey Provisionit + Β2 Supreme Court Mediant + β3 Panel Heterogeneityit + Β4 Post-Casey + β5 Abortion Moodt + β6 Ideologyit + β7 Ideology2it Β8 Ideologyit x Panelit + β9 Ideology x Post-Caseyit + β10 Moodt x Ideologyit + β11 Moodt x Ideology2it] Consistent with theory and hypotheses, we expect the marginal effect of public opinion to vary across judge ideology. In the present case, we expect that conservatives will respond more strongly to public opinion over abortion than liberals. This hypothesis is operationalized via interactions between abortion mood and ideology, and mood and ideology-squared. The latter interaction allows the moderating effect of ideology to be non-linear, rather than restricting its functional form. There is no cost to this specification: if the moderating influence of ideology is linear, than the quadratic specification will reduce to it. Results The results of our analysis are shown in Table 1. First and foremost, we find strong evidence in favor of our key hypothesis, namely, the moderated influence of public mood on liberal voting as a function of judge ideology. The two interactions of mood, linear and quadratic, with judge ideology are statistically significant and substantively meaningful. As logit coefficients are difficult to interpret substantively, and the quadratic interaction term further complicates interpretation, we generated the predicted marginal effects of abortion mood on the predicted probability of a liberal vote for conservative, moderate and liberal judges. In other words, we examine the expected change in the probability of a liberal vote for a change in abortion mood, separately for three levels of judge ideology. These findings are reported in Figure X. The entries in this figure represent the expected change in the probability of a liberal vote for a change in public mood from its 25th to its 75th percentile (conservative to liberal) for judges at the 10th, 50th and 90th percentiles of ideology, respectively. The results are largely consistent with expectations. The marginal effect of abortion mood on the probability of a liberal vote is large and marginally significant for conservatives only (B=.17). A change in abortion mood at the aggregate from relatively conservative to relatively liberal increases the probability of a liberal vote for conservatives by .17 points, or close to one-fifth of the probability scale. For moderates, the marginal effect is insignificant, about half the size, and in the incorrect direction, while for liberals the effect is minimal and insignificant. These effects were generated holding all other variables at their central tendencies.7 In addition to our key hypothesis, we find support for our other expectations. First, as expected, ideology is a more important predictor of voting behavior post-Casey than pre-Casey. In lowering the level of scrutiny applied to abortion cases, the Supreme Court created the possibility for greater ideological voting in the 1990s. In addition, we find that the presence of a Casey provision decreases the probability of a liberal vote, as expected. Finally, we find a strong and significant influence of the Supreme Court’s median on the probability of a liberal vote. As this variable is coded in the conservative direction, a positive change in the median implies a decrease in the probability of a liberal vote, all else equal. Replication at the Aggregate: An Error-Correction Model The results above suggest, in the case of abortion at least, a meaningful relationship between public opinion and voting behavior amongst conservative, but not moderate or liberal, judges at the U.S. Courts of Appeals. The models estimated above examine decision making at the level of the individual judge. For the final empirical section of the paper, we reexamine our hypothesis at the aggregate to assess the extent to which, and the qualitative nature of, the relationship between ideology, public opinion, and voting behavior across time. We first divided judges into three groups on the basis of the distribution of the ideology variable. Judges in the first tertile were classified as “conservative,” those in the second tertile 7 To ensure that our results are not idiosyncratic to the chosen model specification, we ran an additional analysis which trichotomized judge ideology. The pattern of results was very similar in substance and significance. were “moderate,” and those in the highest tertile were classified as “liberal.” To operationalize the voting behavior of each group over time, we calculated a moving proportion of liberal votes for each group separately. This was accomplished by simply generating a 5-year moving average of liberal votes. The estimated proportion of liberal votes for a given year is thus the proportion of liberal votes for that group for the year in question, the two previous years, and the two subsequent years. With this operationalization, we have data on aggregate vote proportions for the three ideological groups from 1973 to 2005. To assess the aggregate relationship between mood and voting behavior across ideological groups, we estimated several error-correction models. These models are particularly useful in allowing for the assessment of both “long-term” and “short-term” relationships between variables. A short-term relationship would imply that a change in abortion mood from one year to the next affects the probability of a liberal vote immediately. A long-term relationship would imply that mood and voting behavior are in an equilibrium relationship, and thus a “shock” to the system in the form of a change in public opinion, upsetting this balance, would induce a longterm shift in voting behavior. In other words, the shift in opinion opens a gap in the relationship between opinion and voting which is corrected at a rate which itself is estimated by the model. In addition to estimating the short and long-term relationship between mood and voting behavior, we control for changes in the Supreme Court’s median. We again examine both short and longterm relationships for the median predictor. The model estimated is thus as follows: (2) Lib. Vote Proportiont = β0 + β1 ΔSC Mediant + β2 ΔAbortion Moodt + β4 Lib. Vote Proprtiont-1 + β5 SC Mediant-1 + β6 Abortion Moodt-1 + εt In the error-correction model short-term effects are indicated by the coefficients on the differenced independent variables (β1 and β2). Long-term effects are indicated by the coefficients on the lagged independent variables (β5 and β6). The rate at which gaps in the longterm, equilibrium relationship are corrected is indicated by the coefficient on the lagged dependent variable (β4), and is interpreted as the percentage of the gap which is corrected in each time period. For example, a coefficient on the lagged dependent variable of .5 would indicate that only 50% of the shock-induced gap remains after the first period, 25% after the second period, and so on. We estimated this error-correction model for all judges combined and for each ideological group separately. The results of these estimations are shown in Table 2. We examine each in turn. Looking first at the model for all judges combined, the results are mixed. First, the model shows no short-term relationships between the proportion of liberal votes and either abortion mood or the Supreme Court’s median. There is, in contrast, suggestive evidence of long-term relationships between both independent variables and the proportion of liberal votes. The coefficient for the lagged value of the Supreme Court’s median is in the expected negative direction, and approaches significance. The coefficient for public mood is in the expected positive direction, and also approaches significance. The coefficient on the lagged vote proportion predictor indicates that shocks to the long-term equilibria implied by these two coefficients decay at a rate of about 50% per period. The mixed results for the model including all judges are a result of heterogeneous dynamics across ideological groups. As indicated by the next three models, this heterogeneity is highly consistent with theoretical expectations. Looking first at the model for conservative judges, we find results which converge nicely with the individual-level model above. Specifically, we find no short-term relationships of conservative voting behavior with either the Supreme Court’s median or public opinion, and no long-term relationship with the median. In contrast, we do find a long-term relationship between abortion mood and voting behavior which is marginally significant. Consistent with the individual-level model, a liberal shift in public opinion generates a liberal shift in the voting behavior of conservatives, and vice versa. The coefficient on the lagged vote proportion variable indicates that the gap in the equilibrium relationship decays at a rate of about 33% per period. Thus, the voting behavior of conservatives adjusts to changes in the distribution of public opinion rather slowly. The models for moderates and liberals show results very different from that of conservatives, as implied by the individual-level models above. With respect to moderates, we find no short-term relationships with liberal vote proportion, but a long-term relationship with the Supreme Court’s median which is marginally significant (significant with a one-tailed test). Importantly, however, the long-term relationship with public opinion does not approach significance. Similarly, we find no short or long-term relationship of voting behavior to public opinion amongst liberals. We do, however, find both a short and a long-term relationship of this group’s decision making to the Supreme Court’s median. The long-term portion of the relationship shows decay in shock-induced gaps of about 75% per period. Thus, the relationship between liberal voting and the ideology of the Supreme Court is quite close. Overall, the results of this second analysis are highly consistent with the individual-level results above, as well as with theoretical expectations. Conservatives respond to changes in public opinion over abortion, voting in line with their ideological interests when possible, and reverting to a more liberal voting record when opinion is out of step with preferences. On the other hand, moderates and liberals show no relationship with public opinion, but instead respond to changes in the ideological composition of the High Court. Conclusion This paper examines whether and to what degree public opinion directly influences the choices judges make at the U.S. Courts of Appeals. As the courts directly below the Supreme Court within the judicial hierarchy, circuit court jurists first and foremost are responsible for adjudicating cases consistently with precedent established by the justices. Along with the additional protections of life tenure and a lack of electoral accountability, this role of circuit court jurists should decrease the impact of public opinion as a constraint. Rather, we hypothesized that popular sentiment should function as an additional tool that reinforces judges’ policy preferences. In short, we believe that public opinion’s potential influence is conditional on the legal context and the policy preferences of judges deciding any particular case. This is especially the case for conservative judges. When judicial discretion is low, public opinion should matter little unless it serves to advance the policy-making goals of circuit court judges. When the legal context (i.e., the compelling interest test) and public opinion went against policy preferences, we see conservative jurists voting counter to expectations derived from the attitudinal model. What is most striking about the results is that it appears conservative jurists did indeed follow public opinion to defy the strict scrutiny standard established under Roe. These judges, even when judicial discretion is low, made decisions that closely followed public opinion, which was headed in the conservative direction, to begin making decisions that restrict the right to an abortion. When judicial discretion is high, we observe two phenomena in abortion cases. There are judges that vote in accordance with their policy preferences. Liberals vote liberally and moderates behave like moderates. The behavior of conservatives is slightly different. Conservative jurists, who are free to vote in accordance with their policy preferences under a lower standard of adjudication, are significantly affected by popular sentiment. Yet, what is even more striking, as confirmed by the moving window analysis, is the suggestion that the decisionmaking of these jurists moves with the ebb and flow of popular sentiment. Rather than just voting ideologically and therefore conservatively, these judges appear to adjust decision-making in accordance with the changes in public opinion. We rest our explanation of the phenomena on the extralegal context facing appellate court judges in abortion cases. To generalize these findings, the lesson we draw from these patterns of results is that public opinion is important to judges insofar as it is one of several strategic concerns; along with the composition and preferences of the Supreme Court and the coordinate branches, judges balance against their desire to vote their own policy preferences. References Bartels, Brandon L. 2009. “The Constraining Capacity of Legal Doctrine on the US Supreme Court.” American Political Science Review 103: 474-495. Baum, Lawrence. 1978. “Lower Court Response to Supreme Court Decisions: Reconsidering a Negative Picture.” Justice System Journal 3: 208-19. Benesh, Sara C. 2002. The U.S. Courts of Appeals and the Law of Confessions: Perspectives on the Hierarchy of Justice. New York: LFB Scholarly Publishing LLC. Benesh, Sara C., and Malia Reddick. 2002. "Overruled: An Event History Analysis of Lower Court Reaction to Supreme Court Alterations of Precedent." Journal of Politics 64: 53450. Bickel, Alexander M. 1962. The Least Dangerous Branch: The Supreme Court at the Bar of Politics. New Haven: Yale University Press. Bueno de Mesquita, Ethan, and Matthew Stephenson. 2002. “Informative Precedent and Intrajudicial Communication.” American Political Science Review 96: 755-756. Cardozo, Benjamin N. 1921. The Nature of the Judicial Process. New Haven: Yale University Press. Cross, Frank B. 2007. Decision-making in the U.S. Courts of Appeals. Stanford: Stanford University Press. Cross, Frank B., and Emerson H. Tiller. 1998. “Judicial Partisanship and Obedience to Legal Doctrine: Whistleblowing on the Federal Courts of Appeals.” Yale Law Journal 107: 2155-76. Durr, Robert H. 1993. “What Moves Policy Sentiment?” American Political Science Review 87 (1): 158-170. Embretson, Susan E., and Steven P. Reise. 2000. Item Response Theory for Psychologists. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, Inc. Epstein, Lee, and Jack Knight. 1998. The Choices Justices Make. Washington, D.C.: Congressional Quarterly Press. Epstein, Lee, Andrew D. Martin, Jeffrey A. Segal, and Chad Westerland. 2005. “The Judicial Common Space.” Journal of Law, Economics, & Organization 23: 303-325. Erikson, Robert S., Michael B. MacKuen, and James A. Stimson. 2002. The Macro Polity. New York: Cambridge University Press. Flemming, Roy B., and B. Dan Wood. 1997. “The Public and the Supreme Court: Individual Justice Responsiveness to American Policy Moods,” American Journal of Politics 41: 468-498. Funston, Richard. 1975. “The Supreme Court and Critical Elections.” American Political Science Review 69: 795-811. Gelman, Andrew, and Jennifer Hill. 2007. Data Analysis Using Regression and Multilevel/Hierarchical Models. New York: Cambridge University Press. Giles, Micheal W., Bethany Blackstone, and Richard L. Vining, Jr. 2008. “The Supreme Court in American Democracy: Unraveling the Linkages between Public Opinion and Judicial Decision-making.” Journal of Politics 70: 293-306. Giles, Micheal W., Virginia A. Hettinger, and Todd C. Peppers. 2001. “Picking Federal Judges: A Note on Policy and Partisan Selection Agendas.” Political Research Quarterly 54: 623-641. Gruhl, John. 1981. “Anticipatory Compliance with Supreme Court Rulings.” Polity 14: 294-313. Hettinger, Virginia A., Stefanie A. Lindquist, and Wendy L. Martinek. 2006. Judging on a Collegial Court: Influence on Federal Appellate Decision-Making. Charlottesville: Virginia University Press. Howard, J. Woodford, Jr. 1981. Courts of Appeals in the Federal Judicial System. Princeton, New Jersey: Princeton University Press. Kastellec, Jonathan P. 2007. “Panel Composition and Judicial Compliance on the US Courts of Appeals.” Journal of Law, Economics and Organization 23: 421-441. Klein, David E. 2002. Making Law in the United States Courts of Appeals. New York: Cambridge University Press. Lindquist, Stefanie A., and David A. Yalof. 2001. “Congressional Responses to Federal Circuit Court Decisions.” Judicature 85: 61-68. Lunn, D.J., Thomas, A., Best, N., and Spiegelhalter, D. 2000. “WinBUGS -- a Bayesian modelling framework: concepts, structure, and extensibility.” Statistics and Computing 10: 325-337. Martin, Andrew D., and Kevin M. Quinn. 2002. “Dynamic Ideal Point Estimation via Markov Chain Monte Carlo for the U.S. Supreme Court, 1953-1999.” Political Analysis 10 (2): 134-153. McGuire, Kevin T. and James A. Stimson. 2004. “The Least Dangerous Branch Revisited: New Evidence on Supreme Court Responsiveness to Public Sentiment.” Journal of Politics 66: 1018-1035. Mishler, William, and Reginald S. Sheehan. 1993. “The Supreme Court as a Countermajoritarian Institution? The Impact of Public Opinion on Supreme Court Decisions” American Political Science Review 87: 87-101. Mishler, William, and Reginald S. Sheehan. 1996. “Public Opinion, the Attitudinal Model and Supreme Court Decision-making: A Micro-Analytic Perspective,” Journal of Politics 58: 169-200. Norpoth, Helmut and Jeffrey A. Segal. 1994. “Popular Influence on Supreme Court Decisions: Comment.” American Political Science Review 88: 711-716. Poole, Keith T. 1998. “Recovering a Basic Space from a Set of Issue Scales.” American Journal of Political Science 42: 954-993. Segal, Jeffrey A., and Harold J. Spaeth. 1993. The Supreme Court and the Attitudinal Model. New York: Cambridge University Press. Segal, Jeffrey A., and Harold J. Spaeth. 2002. The Supreme Court and the Attitudinal Model Revisited. New York: Cambridge University Press. Slotnick, Elliot E. 1984. “The Paths to the Federal Bench: Gender, Race, and Judicial Recruitment.” Judicature 67: 371-388. Songer, Donald R. 1987. “The Impact of the Supreme Court on Trends in Economic Policy Making in the United States Courts of Appeals.” Journal of Politics 49: 830-41. Songer, Donald R., and Susan Haire. 1992. “Integrating Alternative Approaches to the Study of Judicial Voting: Obscenity Cases in the U.S. Courts of Appeals.” American Journal of Political Science 36: 963-82. Songer, Donald R., Jeffrey A. Segal, and Charles M. Cameron. 1994. “The Hierarchy of Justice: Testing a Principal-Agent Model of Supreme Court-Circuit Court Interactions.” American Journal of Political Science 38: 673-96. Songer, Donald R., Jeffrey A. Segal, and Charles M. Cameron. 1995. “An Empirical Test of the Rational-Actor Theory of Litigation.” Journal of Politics 57: 1119-29. Songer, Donald R., and Reginald S. Sheehan. 1990. “Supreme Court Impact on Compliance and Outcomes: Miranda and New York Times in the United States Courts of Appeals.” Western Political Quarterly 43: 297-319. Stidham, Ronald, and Robert A. Carp. 1982. “Trial Court Response to Supreme Court Policy Changes: Three Case Studies.” Law and Policy Quarterly 4: 215-34. Stimson, James A. 1991. Public Opinion in America: Mood, Cycles, and Swings. Boulder, CO: Westview Press, Inc. Stimson, James A, Michael B. MacKuen, and Robert S. Erikson. 1995. “Dynamic Representation.” American Political Science Review 89 (3): 543-565. Sunstein, Cass R., David Schkade, Lisa M. Ellman, and Andres Sawicki. 2006. Are Judges Political? An Empirical Analysis of the Federal Judiciary. Washington, D.C.: Brookings Institution Press. West, Mike, and Jeff Harrison. 1997. Bayesian Forecasting and Dynamic Models. New York: Springer. Cases Cited Akron v. Akron Center for Reproductive Health, 462 U.S. 416 (1983). Barenblatt v. United States, 252 F.2d 129 (D.C. Cir. 1958). Doe v. Bolton, 410 U.S. 179 (1973). Planned Parenthood of Southeastern Pennsylvania v. Casey. 505 U.S. 833 (1992). Roe v. Wade, 410 U.S. 113 (1973). Watkins v. United States, 233 F.2d 681 (D.C. Cir. 1956). Watkins v. United States, 354 U.S. 178 (1957). Webster v. Reproductive Health Services, 492 U.S. 490 (1989). APPENDIX A. QUESTION SELECTION Sources Questions were obtained from two main sources: (1) searches completed on ipoll.com (Roper Center) and the National Elections Survey cumulative file. We opted to only use survey questions from polls conducted by certain sources. They are as follows: (1) ABC; (2) ANES/NES; (3) Associated Press; (4) CBS; (5) CNN; (6) Fox News; (7) GSS; (8) Harris; (9) LA Times; (10) NY Times; (11) Pew; (12) Roper; and (13) Time Yankelvich. Questions In order for question to be included in the sample, they had to pertain to abortion with a clear ideological direction, which means responses had to be identifiable on a liberal (less restrictive) and conservative (more restrictive) dimension. Thus, questions regarding importance or salience of abortion as an issue would not be included in the sample. Furthermore, questions that allowed respondents to choose “No Opinion” were also not included in the sample. Priming Questions had to be about abstract restrictions on abortion. Questions with proper nouns (i.e., specific candidates, political parties, states, politicians, bills or laws) were not included in the sample. For example, a question that asked if respondents supported President Clinton’s position on a piece of legislation would were not included in this sample. Any questions that make specific mention of dates were also not included. Similarly, any questions that attempted to ask a respondent about their preferences for themselves or for their family members in particular situations were not included in the sample. For example, a question would not be included if a given question prompted a respondent as follows: “Should your daughter get an abortion…” Subpopulations Questions with subpopulations were removed if the subpopulation was not randomly selected. Several examples include, but are not limited to: (1) asked of only of a particular subgroup such as registered voters, only women or only blacks; or (2) asked of individuals who responded in a particular way to a previous question. A full list of all the items used in the estimation is available upon request. APPENDIX B. CODING STRATEGY FOR NESTING OF ABORTION QUESTIONS Frame of the survey question was coded as follows: 1 (access) = if the question pertained to the general access for abortions, including locations, difficulty and bans on abortion in the abstract. 2 (viability) = if the question pertained to the developmental stage of the fetus, the progress of the pregnancy as it advances towards term, the specific stage of pregnancy such as trimester or viability of the fetus. 3 (parent) = if the question pertained to parental consent restrictions on abortion. 4 (doctor) = if the question pertained to the choice of the doctor or the woman seeking the abortion as well as whether or not the abortion decision was to be left to the doctor, the woman or both. 5 (constitution) = if the question pertained to whether there should be a constitutional amendment banning some, any or all aspects of the abortion procedure. 6 (life) = if the question pertained to the life and/or physical health exception. 7 (informed) = if the question pertained to informed consent restrictions on abortion. 8 (spouse) = if the question pertained to spousal consent restrictions on abortion. 9 (partial) = if the question pertained to partial-birth/late term abortions. There must be a specific mention of either the procedure (e.g., D&X) or the use of “partial-birth” or “lateterm.” If the question only mentioned time or stage of pregnancy, it was coded as 2. 10 (defect) = if the question pertained to general or specific birth defects or fetal health. 11 (economic) = if the question pertained to economic motivations for the abortion decision, which also include private financial support and private insurance coverage. 12 (morality) = if the question pertained to the moral aspects of abortion, which include perceptions of whether or not abortions are morally wrong. 13 (consequences) = if the question pertained to the (un)intended consequences of abortion being illegal. 14 (rape) = if the question pertained to rape and/or incest exceptions to abortion. 15 (unwanted) = if the question pertained to whether the pregnancy was unwanted or where the abortion decision is balanced some other reason not listed above or below. 16 (government) = if the question pertained to government funding of abortions. 17 (unmarried) = if the question pertained to unmarried or single women seeking abortions. 18 (control) = if the question pertained to abortion used as a birth control method 19 (gag) = if the question pertained to the gag rule, which are restrictions on the discussion of abortion by public or private medical practitioners. 20 (education) = if the question pertained to the education of abortions in schools. 21 (pill) = if the question pertained to the abortion pill or RU-486. 22 (mental) = if the question pertained to the mental health of the woman seeking the abortion. 23 (waiting) = if the question pertained to waiting period restrictions on abortion. APPENDIX C. ESTIMATION OF ABORTION MOOD To generate the abortion mood series we adapt the basic Item Response Theory (IRT) framework to the dynamic case of estimating aggregate opinion over time. In the general case, the researcher possesses data for N units (a sample from the population of interest) on K items. The observed response for unit j on item k is assumed to be a function of the item-specific difficulty (αk) and discrimination (βk) parameters, and the unit’s value on a latent trait (θj) assumed to underlie the covariances amongst the various items as follows: (1) yijk = αk + βkθj + εijk εijk ~ N(0, τ) The general case assumes that the θj are independently drawn from a normal distribution, typically with a mean and variance fixed to zero and one respectively to identify the model. This latter assumption of independence fails in the present case, as the θj are not exchangeable given that the unit identifiers denote the temporal sequence of the series, and units closer together in time are related by some evolutionary process. This process must then be integrated into the estimation procedure itself. Our model assumes that the series represents a “random walk” process such that the value of θ for a given time point is a function of (1) the previous time point’s value and (2) some random disturbance: (2) θt = θt-1 + δt δt ~ N(0, Δt), where Δt is known as the evolution variance, set a priori by the researcher, which serves to “smooth” the θt over time (see Martin and Quinn 2002; West and Harrison 1997). In essence, this equation serves as a prior density for the θt, with prior mean equal to the previous period’s value of θ and prior variance determining the degree of smoothing. Larger values of the prior variance represent a more diffuse prior, and thus less pooling of the estimated value of θt to the previous period’s value. At one extreme, an infinite variance implies no smoothing. At the other extreme, a prior variance of zero implies a series which is constant over time. The ratio of the evolution variance to the variance of the “observation equation,” equation (1) above, determines the degree of smoothing for a given model. We estimate our model via the Gibbs sampler in the software package WinBUGS. We assume standard priors for the item-specific parameters as follows: (3) αk ~ N(µα, τα) βk ~ N(µβ, τβ), with uninformative priors for the µ and τ. We assume a random-walk process for the θt as follows: (4) θt ~ N(θt-1, Δt) for t = 2, …, T. Since there is no period “0”, we give the value of θ for the first period a diffuse normal prior, with a mean of zero. As described above, the value of the evolution variance must be fixed a priori by the researcher, and determines the level of smoothing of values of the latent factor over time. We follow Martin and Quinn (2002), and set the value to approximately one-tenth of the variance of the observation equation. We estimated the model with alternative values of the evolution variance, and the basic contours of the series over time remained the same. Substituting estimates from these alternatives into the models estimated in the paper did not fundamentally alter our results. We identified the model by fixing the value of the discrimination parameter for item 1 (β1) to “1.” This ensures that higher values of the latent factor indicate a more pro-abortion orientation in the aggregate (because observations on item 1 represent the ratio of liberal to liberal plus conservative responses), and guarantees a single posterior with non-negligible mass for each θt. The model was run for 100,000 iterations after a 50,000 iteration burn-in period. Standard diagnostics indicated convergence of all parameters to their posterior distributions. 1973 1975 1977 1979 1981 1983 1985 1987 1989 1991 1993 1995 1997 1999 2001 2003 2005 2007 2009 1973 1975 1977 1979 1981 1983 1985 1987 1989 1991 1993 1995 1997 1999 2001 2003 2005 2007 2009 2009 2007 2005 2003 2001 1999 1997 1995 1993 1991 1989 1987 1985 1983 1981 1979 1977 1975 1973 APPENDIX D. COMPARISON TO ALTERNATIVE ESTIMATION PROCEDURES A. Dynamic IRT Model .100 .050 .000 -.050 -.100 -.150 -.200 B. General Social Survey 0.71 0.69 0.67 0.65 0.63 0.61 0.59 0.57 0.55 C. Stimson’s (1991) Algorithm 0.65 0.6 0.55 0.5 0.45 0.4 0.35 Table 1. Results for Judge-Level Voting Behavior _____________________________________________ Variable B SE p _____________________________________________ Casey Provision -.22 .11 .04 SC Median -1.88 .64 .00 Panel Heterogeneity .33 .32 .30 Post-Casey -.55 .24 .02 Abortion Mood Ideology Ideology^2 5.64 -1.92 1.88 2.81 .99 .87 .05 .05 .03 Ideology X Panel Het. Ideology X Post-Casey Ideology X Mood Ideology^2 X Mood -.51 .83 -29.68 27.35 .51 .43 13.15 13.05 .32 .05 .02 .04 .68 .30 .02 Constant Pseudo R^2 .03 N 613 _____________________________________________ Notes: Entries are probit coefficients and standard errors. Table 2. Results for Error-Correction Models ______________________________________________________________________________________ All Judges Conservatives Moderates Liberals _______________ ________________ _______________ ______________ B SE p B SE p B SE p B SE p ______________________________________________________________________________________ Differenced Variables SC Median Mood -.15 .27 .24 .24 .54 .26 .03 .31 .46 .44 .95 .48 -.38 .21 .29 .31 .20 .51 -.35 .26 .16 .25 .04 .31 SC Median Mood Vote Proportion -.26 .31 -.50 .17 .20 .18 .14 .13 .01 -.12 .56 -.33 .22 .34 .11 .58 .11 .01 -.32 -.13 -.42 .18 .21 .15 .10 .53 .01 -.33 .25 -.75 .11 .23 .17 .01 .29 .01 Constant .30 .11 .01 .20 .07 .01 .25 .09 .01 .46 .10 .01 Lagged Variables R^2 .28 .16 .27 .42 N 32 32 32 32 ______________________________________________________________________________________ Notes: Entries are OLS coefficients and robust standard errors. Figure 1. Abortion Mood, 1973-2005 1973 1977 1981 1985 1989 1993 1997 Notes: Estimates from dynamic item response model. 2001 2005 Figure 2. Marginal Effect of Abortion Mood across Ideology Marginal Effect of Abortion Mood .35 .25 .15 .17 .05 .02 -.05 -.09 -.15 -.25 Conservative Moderate Liberal Notes: Entries represent the predicted change in the probability of a liberal vote for a change in abortion mood from its 25th to its 75th percentile. Extended lines are 95% confidence intervals. “Conservatives,” “Moderates,” and “Liberals” correspond with the 10th, 50th and 95th percentiles of ideology respectively.