PowerPoint Slides © Michael R. Ward, UTA 2014 Econ 5313 St. Petersburg Paradox I • I offer you the following gamble: • • • • • I will continue to flip a coin until I get a heads. If I get a heads with the first flip, I will pay $2. If I get my first heads the second flip, I will pay $4. If I get my first heads the third flip, I will pay $8. If I get my first heads the Nth flip, I will pay $2N. • How much is this gamble worth? • How much would you be willing to pay in order to get in on this gamble? Econ 5313 St. Petersburg Paradox II • This problem illustrates issues when dealing with uncertainty • This problem is contrived but it helps us to think about the problems that managers face • Eventually, it helps us to look at ways to help deal with uncertainty and arrive at decisions that will best profit your firm • By modeling uncertainty carefully, you can: • Learn to make better decisions • Identify the source(s) of risk in a decisions • Compute the value of collecting more information Econ 5313 Random Variables • Thinking about random variables • To model uncertainty we use random variables to compute the expected costs and benefits of a decision • A Random Variable represents outcomes that occur with different probabilities. • When different outcomes can occur we define the different possibilities as States of the World (SOW) Econ 5313 States of the World • Before I flip a coin, we know that it could land as heads or tails • The random variable “coin side” has different values in the SOW “heads” and “tails” • After I flip the coin, one of these SOWs is realized and the world proceeds along that “path” • We attach probabilities to each potential SOW before they are realized: 50% “heads” and 50% “tails” • Where do probabilities come from? • Use past experience, reasoning ability, etc. – pretty objective • But must decide if this experience is similar enough to references – ultimately subjective • After SOW is realized, probabilities are 0% and 100% Econ 5313 More Complicated Uncertainty • Before I roll a die, we know that it could land as 1, 2, 3, 4, 5 or 6. These are the possible SOWs (assuming six-sided) • We usually assume each has probability of 1/6 • Is the die “loaded?” • After SOW is realized, probabilities for five SOWs are 0% and one is 100% • Can build up to much more complicated gambles: • • • • Two dice or more 52 cards XYZ Corp. meets earnings expectations Calculating probabilities & outcomes is “just” math Econ 5313 Modeling Uncertainty • Identify the possible States of the World • Mutually Exclusive (can’t have two SOWs at once) • Exhaustive (must include all possible SOWs) • Assign probabilities to each event • Prob(SOW) ≥ 0 for all SOWs • Sum Prob(SOW) = 100% • To represent values that are uncertain: • List the possible values the variable could take • Assign a probability to each value • Compute the Expected Value Econ 5313 Expected Value • The Expected Value (EV) of a gamble is the average outcome that will occur if the gamble were repeated many times • Example Gamble on coin flip with $10 payout on “heads” and $5 cost on “tails.” Two SOWs with probability of 50% each. EV = $10×50% + (-$5)×50% = $2.50 • Example Gamble on roll of die with $9 payout on “1” and $2 cost on all others. Six SOWs with probability of 1/6 each. EV = $9×1/6 + (-$2)×1/6 + (-$2)×1/6 + (-$2)×1/6 + ($2)×1/6 + (-$2)×1/6 ≈ -$0.167 Econ 5313 Back to St. Pete’s I • What are the probabilities? • • • • Heads on first roll = ½ Heads on second roll means tails on first one= ½ × ½ = ¼. Heads on third roll means tails on first two = ½ × ½ × ½ = 1/8. Heads on Nth roll means tails on first N-1 = (½)N. • What is Expected Value? • EV = Prob(1st) × Payout1 + Prob(2nd) × Payout2 + Prob(3rd) × Payout3 + … Econ 5313 Back to St. Pete’s II First Heads 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 17 18 19 20 Prob 0.5 0.25 0.125 0.0625 0.03125 0.01563 0.00781 0.00391 0.00195 0.00098 0.00049 0.00024 0.00012 0.000061 0.000031 0.000015 7.6E-06 3.8E-06 1.9E-06 9.5E-07 Payout 2 4 8 16 32 64 128 256 512 1024 2048 4096 8192 16384 32768 65536 131072 262144 524288 1048576 Econ 5313 Back to St. Pete’s III First Heads 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 17 18 19 20 Prob 0.5 0.25 0.125 0.0625 0.03125 0.01563 0.00781 0.00391 0.00195 0.00098 0.00049 0.00024 0.00012 0.000061 0.000031 0.000015 7.6E-06 3.8E-06 1.9E-06 9.5E-07 Payout EV(SOW) 2 1 4 1 8 1 16 1 32 1 64 1 128 1 256 1 512 1 1024 1 2048 1 4096 1 8192 1 16384 1 32768 1 65536 1 131072 1 262144 1 524288 1 1048576 1 Econ 5313 Back to St. Pete’s IV • Paradox resolved • EV = Sum EV(SOW) • Infinite sum of $1 • EV = $Infinity • Why aren’t we willing to pay $Infinity to play this gamble? • Two possible explanations: • How much do you value $2billion over $1billion? • Need value of the payout not just payout • Do you really trust that I can payoff if it ever hit $1million? • Calculated probabilities not likely accurate Econ 5313 Inferring Probabilities • “Wheel of Cash” example: • The carnival game wheel is divided like a pie into thirds, with values of $100, $75, and $5 on each of the slices • The cost to play is $50.00 • Should you play the game? • Three possible outcomes: $100, $75, and $5 with equal probability of occurring (assuming the wheel is “fair”) • Expected value of playing the game is: 1/3 ($100) + 1/3 ($75) + 1/3 ($5) = $60 • But, if the wheel is biased toward the $5 outcome, the expected value is: 1/6 ($100) + 1/6 ($75) + 2/3 ($5) = $32.50 • If a deal seems to good to be true, it probably is Econ 5313 European Expansion I • For expansion into Europe, your market research has identified three potential market opportunities: UK, France, and Germany UK Probability Great Success Moderate Success Failure Gross Value Great Success Moderate Success Failure 0.5 0.3 0.2 France Germany 0.4 0.4 0.2 0.2 0.5 0.3 $800,000 $1,000,000 $1,500,000 $360,000 $300,000 $420,000 $0 $0 $0 • You can only enter one market and your entry costs are $250,000 regardless of which you enter Econ 5313 European Expansion II • Should you enter? • If so, where? • How much profit should you expect? • Calculate the expected value of each option • Net out the cost of entry • Compare results Econ 5313 European Expansion III • EV[option] = Pr1 × Value1 + Pr2 × Value2 + Pr3 × Value3 UK Probability Great Success Moderate Success Failure Gross Value Great Success Moderate Success Failure Expected Gross Value Great Success Moderate Success Failure Expected Net Value 0.5 0.3 0.2 France Germany 0.4 0.4 0.2 0.2 0.5 0.3 $800,000 $1,000,000 $1,500,000 $360,000 $300,000 $420,000 $0 $0 $0 $400,000 $400,000 $300,000 $108,000 $120,000 $210,000 $0 $0 $0 $258,000 $270,000 $260,000 Econ 5313 European Expansion IV • Should you enter? • In each case, expected net value > 0, so yes • If so, where? • Highest expected net value is in France • Or is it? Can the calculation be more precise than the values going into it? • How precise are our probabilities? • One significant digit in implies 0.3 could be within 0.25 and 0.34 • Or, calculate the size of the probability would have to be to overturn the decision. • Is the difference within your “margin of error?” • This is enough variation to overturn the decision • Do not be lulled into false precision Econ 5313 Reducing Uncertainty • Reduce uncertainty by gathering information • To gather information about the benefits and costs of a decision you can run natural experiments • Natural experiment - A restaurant chain example: • A regional manager wanted to test the profitability of a 10% price increase • To do this, the menu was introduced in the Dallas restaurants but not the Fort Worth restaurants • In comparing sales between the Dallas locations (the treated group) and the Fort Worth locations (the control group) the manager hoped to isolate the effect of the price change on demand (and profit) Econ 5313 Diff-in-Diff • This is a difference-in-difference estimator • The first difference is before vs. after the price change; the second difference is the treatment vs. control groups • Difference-in-difference controls for unobserved factors that can influence changes • Count number of customers: Pre Post Diff Fort Worth Stores 550 625 75 Dallas Stores 560 525 -35 Diff-in-Diff -110 Econ 5313 Understanding Diff-in-Diff • The manager found that sales fell a little from the price increase – but there was an increase for the treatment group too • This is likely due to factors affecting both groups • The raw difference would underestimate the effect of the price change. The diff-in-diff is likely to more accurately measure the effect of the price change • Possible problems with diff-in-diff: • Leakage: Dallasites travel to Fort Worth due to price change • Representativeness: Is Fort Worth a good enough control for Dallas behaviors? Econ 5313 Understanding Biases • Leakage: If Dallasites travel to Fort Worth due to price change how does this affect our experiment? • Implies Fort Worth increase is biased upward • The ‘control’ is not controlling for only ‘other factors’ • Implies the estimate is biased and we can tell the direction • Representativeness: What does it mean for Fort Worth to be a poor control for Dallas behaviors? • Are the ‘other factors’ adequately captured by Fort Worth? • If not, change could be due to unmeasured factor • Could choose Oklahoma City as control • Less leakage but also less representative • Tradeoffs Econ 5313 Data Driven Decision Making • Collecting and analyzing the data from pre-price change to post-price change is good • Comparing the ‘treated’ group to a ‘control’ group is even better • Understanding how biases might still creep into the estimate is better still • Ex Elevator conversation with CEO • Huge increase in “Data Driven Decision Making” Econ 5313 Minimizing Expected Error Costs • Sometimes, when faced with a decision, instead of focusing on maximizing expected profits it can be useful to think about minimizing expected “error costs” • Want to make decisions that accept true hypotheses and reject false ones • But we are not perfect and we make errors • Want to minimize costs of these errors TRUE FALSE Accept OK Type II Reject Type I OK Econ 5313 Product Launch • VP for new product introductions hypothesizes that the product launch would be profitable • Collect cost studies, market research studies and any other pertinent reports to assess the probability, p, that this hypothesis is true • Choose the row with the smaller expected decision error • Accept if (1-p)×(Type II Error Cost) < p×(Type I Error Cost) Truth Decision Launch Product (Accept Hypothesis) Do Not Launch Product (Reject Hypothesis) Profitable (Hypothesis True) Not Profitable (Hypothesis False) No Error Cost Type II Error Cost Type I Error Cost No Error Cost Econ 5313 Decision Maker Incentives • More information on error costs • Can calculate 𝑝 = (Type II Error Cost)/(Type I Error Cost + Type II Error Cost) • Is your estimate of p > 𝑝? • But will the VP be too cautious? • Will her boss know if a launch fails? • Will anyone know if a killed launch would have been successful? • Implies an incentive to be too cautious on decisions • Ex FDA’s drug approval Econ 5313 Too much Information? • Alternatively, the VP can seek more studies to make more certain that p > 𝑝 or p < 𝑝 • Cost of more studies is both expense and delay • Will VP balance value of precision with these costs? • Or will the VP be too cautious again and gather too much information? • Ex FCC on cellphones • Need to encourage people to take chances • “If you never miss an airplane, then you spend too much time in airports” Econ 5313 • • • • • • From the Blog Chapter 17 Facebook Trolls Never Punt Experiments to Fight Poverty Selling Lottery Tickets Estimating via Regressions Econ 5313 Summary of Main Points • Uncertainty means you must replace actual values with expected values. • Identify the SOWs and assign probabilities to each. • Be wary of the information sources for probability estimates. • Don’t be lulled into false precision. • Run experiments (e.g., diff-in-diff ) to uncover uncertain parameter values. Know how to interpret results. • Some decisions lend themselves to minimizing decision errors. Understand the incentives of the decision error minimizer.