January 2011 The Making of Policy: Institutionalized or Not? Carlos Scartascini Mariano Tommasi ABSTRACT: This paper attempts to build bridges in the formal study of policymaking across polities of different degrees of institutional development. It explores the reasons why policymaking is fairly institutionalized in some polities but not in others. It suggests extending standard models of institutionalized policymaking to allow for a wider set of actions, including the threat of violence or of damage to the economy. It engages the discussion of institutions as rules and institutions as equilibria, delivering multiple equilibria with different degrees of institutionalization. The likelihood of institutionalized policymaking increases as the cost of alternative political actions increases, as the damage these alternatives cause decreases, and as the economy becomes wealthier. In cases in which the distribution of de jure political power is more asymmetric, it is more likely to observe use of alternative political technologies as well as low degrees of institutionalization. We received valuable comments from Facundo Albornoz, Mariana Chudnovsky, Thad Dunning, Jon Eguia, David Epstein, Alberto Fohrig, Macartan Humphreys, Marcelo Leiras, Johannes Lindvall, Cesar Martinelli, Massimo Morelli, Vicky Murillo, Pablo Pinto, Susan Rose-Ackerman, Frances Rosenbluth, Alejandro Saporiti, Ken Scheve, Ernesto Stein, David Stasavage, Susan Stokes, Kaj Thommson, Razvan Vlaicu, Federico Weinschelbaum, and seminar participants at Columbia, George Washington, the Inter-American Development Bank, Maryland, New York University, Universidad de Salamanca, Universidad de San Andrés, Yale, the Hertie School of Governance, the Latin American and Caribbean Economic Association Meeting in Rio de Janeiro, the Latin American and Caribbean Economic Association Political Economy Group Meeting in Cartagena, and the Yale Conference on Fighting and Voting. We are particularly indebted to three anonymous referees for their criticism and suggestions; to Adam Przeworski for generously sharing his ideas on these issues; to Fabiana Machado for allowing us to draw from our joint ongoing empirical work on protests in Latin America, as well as for valuable suggestions; and to Laura Trucco for extraordinary research assistance, useful comments, and for allowing us to draw freely from joint ongoing work. 1 THE MAKING OF POLICY: INSTITUTIONALIZED OR NOT? Institutional systems differ significantly in their capacity to absorb and process conflict. In some countries, for example Argentina, almost every contentious issue finds thousands of people on the Plaza de Mayo, tractors blocking roads, and pickets cutting a bridge in Neuquén. Yet in other countries, say Costa Rica, almost all conflicts are disciplined by political parties and processed through the Congress, the Presidency, or the Courts. Adam Przeworski 2009 (p. 2) Formal analysis of policymaking within the realm of political institutions has deepened our understanding of how various legislative and electoral institutions shape economic policies. Political economists have built on the foundations laid out early on by political scientists – such as Duverger, Sartori, Rae, Lijphart, Cox and others – on the impact of formal rules on the workings of political institutions to study the impact of political rules on policy outcomes. In almost all of this literature (Persson and Tabellini 2000 is a standard textbook treatment), most or all of the relevant action takes place within the context of these formal institutional rules and relatively formalized institutional arenas (the voting booth, the building of Congress, etc.) That is a very good approximation for policymaking in various countries at some moments in time (many developed countries in the last several decades), but it is a much rougher approximation in other cases. Other than voting, forming political parties, bargaining in the legislature, and the like, there are a number of alternative political technologies (such as threats of violence and of disruption of economic activity) that individuals or groups could utilize in order to influence collective decisions. This paper is an exploration on the implications of an enlarged political action space for the study of institutions and policymaking. We believe this is an important step towards the integrated study of policymaking in polities of different levels of economic and institutional development. There is a tendency to study policymaking in advanced industrial societies and in less developed countries in dichotomous ways, 2 using widely different models by assumption. These differential treatments are imposed exogenously; in this paper we take a step in the direction of studying such different polities within a unified framework that delivers different modes of policymaking as an outcome of the analysis. This paper provides one specific example, extending a standard legislative bargaining model by allowing actors the choice of investing in playing in the legislative arena or in utilizing an alternative political technology (APT) that allows them to threaten to impose costs on society if some demands are not met. We analyze that game, and use the example as motivation to address some broader issues on institutions, institutionalization, and policymaking.1 We investigate the way in which the presence of these alternative political technologies, in interaction with formal political institutions and underlying socioeconomic structures, influences the workings of institutions, policy outcomes, and the use of such technologies in equilibrium. One implication of the model and logic presented here is that different countries might have different degrees of institutionalization in the way in which collective decisions are made. Countries do present a great deal of variation in the way policymaking is conducted, including differences in the degree to which formal institutions such as Congress and political parties are the central locus of 1 In the paper, “political institutions” refers to Constitutional and electoral “rules of the game” that define what political actors can do, as well as to the actors and arenas in charge of official policymaking (Congress, the Courts). The “institutionalization” of policymaking refers to the degree to which arenas such as Congress are indeed the places where societal actors focus their energies when trying to influence policy. One can (as we do in our model) assign a great deal of structure to actions outside the formal institutions of government and in a strict sense call such actions highly “institutionalized.” That said, most people would agree to call bargaining in Congress more institutional behavior than burning tires in the street (no matter how structured the latter activity might be). The founding reference on political institutionalization is Huntington 1968; a seminal application (to the U.S. Congress) is Polsby 1968. See also Blondel 2006 and the discussion below. 3 programmatic demands by socioeconomic actors, and (conversely) the degree to which socioeconomic interests use, instead, alternative political technologies to influence policymaking.2 Actors will concentrate their political investments and actions in the place where they believe crucial decisions are made. Institutions reflect past investments; summarize information, beliefs and expectations; and incorporate self-reinforcement effects. The relevance of specific institutional arenas for policymaking is a self-reinforcement phenomenon, potentially subject to multiplicity if equilibria. 3 When Congress and the political party system are effective conduits of preference aggregation and political bargaining, various relevant actors place their bets (investments) in those institutions, most citizens believe that those are the spaces where relevant decisions are made, and this whole logic reinforces and become self-fulfilling. On the contrary, if such institutional arenas are not taken seriously and everybody knows that the way of getting something out of the political system is to blockade a road or to bribe the president, those investments in the institutionalization of Congress and/or parties are not undertaken and the weakness of formal institutions is reinforced. Polities might be stuck with higher or lower levels of institutionalization. While polities in more institutionalized equilibria will behave as predicted in the “tidy” literature on political institutions and policies, polities 2 These differences are striking in comparing advanced industrial countries with poor developing nations, but also when comparing across polities of similar level of economic development, as the epigraph from Przeworski 2009 reflects. According to O´Donnell (1996), only in Costa Rica, Chile, and Uruguay do the executive branch, congress, parties, and the judiciary function in a manner that is reasonably close to their formal institutional rules, making them effective institutional knots in the flow of political power. The collection in Stein et al 2008 reflects important variation across countries (and some over time) in the institutionalization of policymaking in eight Latin American countries. 3 In pursuing this argument, the paper concurs with an analytical current that views institutions as equilibrium phenomena. Our use of “institutionalization” is quite close to the game theoretic notion of “institutions as equilibria” by authors such as Calvert (1995, 95b), Greif (2006), and Aoki (2001). 4 in less institutionalized equilibria might behave differently. (One of the factors increasing the likelihood of less institutionalized policymaking is the asymmetry of power within formal institutions). Our contribution is obviously not totally novel; it draws inspiration and insights from various extant literatures. Previous contributions considering the impact of alternative political technologies on some aspects of the workings of formal political institutions include Ellman and Wantchekon’s (2000) study of electoral competition under the threat of political unrest, and Dal Bo and Di Tella (2003) and Dal Bo et al’s (2006) studies of political agency models in which interest groups can harm politicians. Przeworski 2009 is an insightful recent effort motivated by the same questions and Latin American observations as this paper.4 The literature on democratic consolidation is concerned with similar issues at a higher level, where the variable of concern is democracy itself;5 for instance, in the words of Adam Przeworski, “if democracy is to be consolidated, distributive conflict must be institutionalized: all major political forces must channel their economic demands through the democratic institutions and abjure other tactics” (1992: 127). Humphreys 2001 analyzes allocations when the enforcement of bargains cannot be taken for granted; Humphreys defines such environments as “weakly institutionalized.”6 There are very rich literatures studying contentious political actions and political violence, but only recently have these types of political actions started to be studied in an integrated 4 Bueno de Mesquita et al 2003 is an ambitious effort that also goes beyond standard assumptions in order to encompass a (much) broader set of situations than usually studied in the institutional literature. Our discussion is also related to studies of economic agents’ choice whether to produce or to fight, for instance Hirshleifer (2001) and Garfinkel and Skaperdas (1996). 5 Even though this paper touches upon general discussions, our empirical referent is modern day Latin America: countries with intermediate levels of institutional development where electoral democracy is not in question, but where the degree to which “places” such as Congress are effective institutional knots in the flow of political power and policy (O’Donnell 1996) is the variable in question. 6 Levitsky and Murillo (2009) explore related issues, attempting to conceptualize the notion of institutional weakness, and also emphasize the notion of investments in institutions. 5 manner with more institutionalized ones (such as voting, Dunning 2009 and references there). See also Lindvall 2008 for a recent model of protests. The empirical agenda that could move this project forward is a challenging one. One will need to develop convincing measures of the degree of institutionalization of policymaking, and to provide evidence of the superiority of policies generated by more institutionalized environments. One would also need proxies for the parameters highlighted in the model. Some of these measures (such as formal institutional rules) are easy to come by, others are less obvious. While far from offering the last word on these issues, throughout the paper we refer to preliminary attempts at measuring institutionalization variables and relating them to other variables in the theory. (One intriguing stylized fact that shows up in the data is the negative correlation between measures of institutionalization and measures of the use of alternative political technologies.) One of the objectives of the paper is to try to convince other scholars that pursuing such empirical efforts is a worthwhile endeavor. POLICYMAKING WITH FORMAL INSTITUTIONS AND ALTERNATIVE POLITICAL ARENAS Typical models of institutional policymaking such as those summarized in Persson and Tabellini 2000 study policy determination specifying political institutions as the rules of the game in which policies are decided. Such models are quite explicit about those formal rules, but for their analysis to be valid there is also an implicit assumption that actors in the model can only play within those rules and institutions; this would require that alternative actions are either technologically impossible, or somehow forbidden by (enforced) decisions at some other level. That is not a bad approximation to study policymaking in a number of modern polities (at least in normal times), but it seems to miss a very important part of the action in other cases. We suggest extending those models to include alternative political actions undertaken in additional arenas, as well as the interactions among players in different arenas. Borrowing the language in 6 Acemoglu and Robinson 2006, we suggest calling de jure political power the one assigned by formal political institutions, and de facto political power the one assigned by the technologies of alternative political action. For instance, if the alternative to institutionalized decision-making was the threat of violence, such power would be conferred by the capacity to exercise violence. The capacity to function within formal institutions as well as the capacity to be effective through those alternative channels will be, in part, endogenous to ex ante decisions by each player. Actors will have to make an ex ante decision on whether to invest resources in the more institutionalized arenas such as Congress or political parties, or to invest in alternative technologies (such as violence, or corrupting politicians). (In the specific model below the investment stage will be followed by a rather short game, which captures in expected value what is more properly a potentially long sequence of policymaking events given those initial investments.) Classifying a set of various possible political actions (actions to influence collective decisionmaking) into “institutionalized” and “alternative” is to some extent an arbitrary choice. Which way one wants to classify things in practice depends on the exact question at hand. Figure 1 presents some examples of political actions. Some of them, towards the left of the diagram in white, are closer to the more institutionalized end of the spectrum (forming a political party, writing to your congressman), while others, towards the right of the diagram in dark grey, are clearly within the realm of the alternative (road blockades, physical threats). A number of other political actions are harder to classify, including different forms of business and union influence,7 as well as demonstrations to 7 Some forms of lobbying would fit more naturally in the “institutionalized” part of the game—as when Grossman and Helpman (2001: 4) say, referring to the US, “according to the survey findings, the activities undertaken by the greatest numbers of organized interest groups are those intended to educate and persuade lawmakers of the wisdom of the groups’ position.” Other forms of business influence are much closer to the darker part of Figure 1. See Harstad and Svensson 2009 for an 7 inspire sympathy in public opinion. Going into the darker side of Figure 1 and of reality, some strategies we would have no doubt in classifying as “alternative,” such as the one exercised by Colombian drug lords when offering new judges the choice between plata (bribes) or plomo (bullets) – Dal Bó et al 2006. <Insert Figure 1> In the rest of the paper we work at some level of abstraction, focusing on a “black or white” classification in which some actions take place within the institutional realm and others outside formal institutional channels. For concreteness, we will speak as if the alternative political technology (APT) utilized are road blockades,8 but the abstract formulation could also represent other things, such as collective action by some economic sectors to damage the economy. In the model it is assumed that taking the institutional road or the “street” road are indeed alternatives. This is a simplified way of capturing an important point of our argument, which emphasizes the investment component of institutions. Political actions such as voting, campaigning for your favorite candidate, writing letters to your Congressperson, participating in peaceful protests, participating in violent protests, threatening to kill your opponents, and killing Supreme Court Justices need not be substitutes. Under some conditions they are used jointly and under some conditions they insightful distinction between lobbying and bribing. Strategies employed by unions vary from extremely institutionalized actions in Parliament and the constitutionally sanctioned right to strike, to the borderline-criminal physical intimidation utilized in some countries at some points in time. 8 We are thinking about situations as those described in Przeworski’s epigraph in which every contentious issue finds thousands of people in the streets, as it is these days the case in places like Argentina or Bolivia. The distinction between institutional and alternative tries to contrast a way of aggregating preferences and processing conflict that is delegated, temporally and spatially coordinated and relatively orderly, with one that is sporadic, haphazardous, unpredictable, it involves physical risks and different actors doing different things at different moments and places. It is natural to imagine that these two modes of participating in politics lead to different outcomes. 8 are used separately by different actors in different political equilibria. Pending a more general understanding of the conditions under which different actions are taken jointly or separately, this paper emphasizes mechanisms (such as investment under budget or time constraints) that make these actions alternatives.9 Figure 2 suggests that citizens in Latin America tend to view contacting their representatives in Congress and protesting in the streets as alternative political options. <Insert Figure 2> The actors in our game, then, will have to make a prior decision of whether to enter the more formal or the less formal arenas of political action. These decisions at the level of individual actors are then aggregated in equilibrium. Political actors take different roads depending on what the environment has to offer them, and their aggregate choices have an effect on that environment. This bidirectional causality is at the heart of the issues of reinforcement and multiplicity of equilibria, which we elaborate upon after presenting the model. A MODEL: CONGRESS OR THE STREET? Any model within the framework suggested will need to specify three components that will constitute sets of exogenous parameters for comparative statics purposes: (1) policy problem (mapping from feasible policy vectors to utilities of the players, which subsumes aspects of the socioeconomic structure and available policy technologies); (2) political institutions; and (3) alternative political technologies and protocols of interaction among different political arenas. In the example here, the 9 In the specific model presented below, even if one were to allow actors to allocate their unit of investment in a continuous manner across the two political arenas, the choice would still be a corner concentration on one of the two. A more substantive extension, discussed in the conclusion, would incorporate a third “opportunity cost” dimension, allow for further actor heterogeneity, and generate richer predictions at the individual level (who participates and how) and in terms of country equilibria. 9 policy problem (1) is a standard allocation problem of splitting a pie of size π, and political institutions (2) are a simple variant of the well-known legislative bargaining model set forth by Baron and Ferejohn (1989).10 Any assumption about (3) will embed considerations about mappings from alternative actions to utilities, as well as about collective action, commitment technologies, and allocation protocols in informal arenas. Modifying any assumption made at this level constitutes part of the comparative statics agenda we want to promote. For brevity and concreteness in this paper the APT is described as a road blockade (“going to the street”). Participating in a road blockade has an individual cost π. If at least π players protest they can (credibly) threaten to inflict a damage of size πΎ to the economy, with 2 ≤ π and 0 < πΎ < π. If less than π people engage in the blockade, they cannot cause any damage. This simplified damage technology is represented in Figure 3, where π stands for the number of people who choose this alternative. This formulation captures in a stark manner some properties of the framework, in particular it embeds a scale economy / strategic complementarity that will be the seed of multiplicity of equilibria.11 It is also assumed that “The Street” acts as a unified actor, ignoring collective action issues among those blocking the streets (after the threshold π) (assumption A1), it splits whatever it receives equally among its members (assumption A2), and it is endowed with a commitment technology: it can commit ex ante to cause damage or not in response to specified actions by players in the formal (Congress) arena (assumption A3). The latter assumption, 10 It is more straightforward to think about this example as direct democracy, where the players who could go to Congress are the citizens themselves. Alternatively, players can be understood as the underlying constituencies, each of which could be represented in Congress by a perfect agent (if the constituency chooses to invest in that representation). 11 Parameters as π or π will depend on various issues, including “repression technologies” in place. 10 common in the related literature (Ellman and Wanchtekon 2000, DalBo et al 2006), 12 is imposed to avoid a lengthy analysis of the conditions under which such threat would be credible, which would require adding more structure to the extensive form or going to a repeated game altogether to include considerations of reputation. In the context of non-repeated games the threat of damage would be credible when it constitutes a weakly dominant strategy in the final move, something that could be easily adjusted in our model.13 Furthermore, there is an important literature on fairness, altruistic punishment and spitefulness, which argues that punishments are indeed instrumented even when they are costly for the punisher in narrow self-interest terms.14 Those results, often obtained in rather aseptic experiments, are even more likely to obtain in the specific context of our focus: once the piqueteros are out there in the street, it might be easier to enforce “damage in case of unfulfilled demands” than “no damage in case of fulfilled demands”.15 There are also some technologies, such as permanent squatting, where it is more costly to stop inflicting costs to others (leaving) than to continue doing so (staying). <Insert Figure 3> 12 Even in Acemoglu and Robinson 2006, in a different context, exogenous assumptions are imposed in order for the threat of revolution to be credible. 13 That would be more likely if the damage protesters can inflict does not affect them. In the specific formulation in this paper that would be the case if the damage only affects the payoff of players in Congress. Given that we have imposed A3, for notational brevity we will assume that Congress offers protesters a share of the final pie, but it would be trivial to modify that and let them received a fixed amount, in which case causing damage would indeed be weakly dominant. 14 See for instance Bahry and Wilson 2006, Henrich et al 2004, and Levine 1998. 15 As Maurice Thorez, longtime leader of the French Communist Party remarked in 1936, “One has to know how to end a strike” – Przeworski 2009. These issues have been studied in a literature on collective behavior, for instance Marx and McAdams 1994. 11 Let π© = {1,2, … π} be the set of players. The economy is subject to the aggregate constraint ∑ππ=1 π₯π ≤ π. Each player maximizes his or her piece π₯π ≥ 0, net of a possible cost π that they pay in some cases. Each agent is endowed with ππ units of (ex ante) de jure political power, with ππ < ππ+1 , and ∑ππ=1 ππ = 1. The timing of the game, represented in Figure 4, is as follows. <Insert Figure 4> Investment stage: Stage 1: Each player (simultaneously) chooses an action ππ ∈ {0,1}, where ππ = 1 means going to Congress and ππ = 0 going to the street, which carries a cost π. This action represents an investment that enables the player to become effective at one of the two arenas. ∑ ππ will be the aggregate investment in formal institutions, capturing the degree of institutionalization, which we discuss after solving the model. Let π be the number of players who go to the street, and π − π the number of players who go to Congress. Let β³ denote the set of players in the street, and π©\β³ the set of players in Congress. Policymaking stages: Stage 2: Among those that went to Congress, Nature chooses an agenda setter π. Each player π in Congress has an ex post probability ∑ ππ πππ©\β³ ππ of being recognized as the agenda setter. Stage 3: The players in the street can (credibly) threaten to cause damage π as a function of the share π§ of the total pie received by each of them (π = ππ§ denotes the total amount received by those in the street). Let π ≥ 2 be a threshold of critical mass for action in the street. If π < π, the amount of damage they can cause is zero, otherwise it is πΎ.16 16 Let π(π§) be the possible damage function, or feasible damage contract. If π < π, then π(π§) = 0 for all π§. If π ≥ π, π(π§): [0,1] → {0, πΎ}. We assume for brevity that the range of the damage function can only take discrete values, but nothing of substance will change if we let a continuous range. If π = 0 12 Stage 4: After listening to the threat of The Street, the agenda setter in Congress (π = π) proposes an π allocation of the pie, a vector of shares π π (π) = {π π }πππ© , subject to ∑ππ=1 π π ≤ 1 and π π ∈ [0,1]. For brevity we introduce the ex post distributional assumption A2 as an ex ante constraint on the agenda setter’s proposal, by requiring at this stage that the share for each person in the street is the same, that is π π = π§ π ∈ [0, 1⁄π] for all π ∈ β³. π Stage 5: The π − π players in Congress vote on π π . Let ππ ∈ {0,1} denote the choice of congressperson π, where 0 and 1 respectively represent voting against and for π’s proposal. We assume that players in Congress vote only on the basis of their individual share, so that ππ (π π ): [0,1] → {0,1}. To avoid some sources of multiplicity not germane to the objectives of this paper, we assume that in case of indifference, ππ = 1 (assumption A4).17 The outcome of the legislative process, π, will be:18 ππ 1 ππ ∑ ππ ≥ (π − π) 2 πππ©\β³ π= {π π = 0}πππ© { 1 ππ ∑ ππ < (π − π) . 2 πππ©\β³ this stage becomes irrelevant, and the rest of the game reduces to a traditional legislative game with only stages 2, 4, and 5. 17 In this way two sources of multiplicity are eliminated. On the one hand, we are considering only equilibria in which voters do not choose weakly dominated strategies, having them always act as if they were pivotal. On the other, we make the payoff given to members of the winning legislative coalition converge to their status quo payoff. 18 This very simple formulation of the legislative bargaining problem is used for brevity. The main logic pursued in the study does not depend on any specific extensive form of the institutionalized game; the crucial individual decisions and equilibrium features depend on comparing the expected values of participating in the institutionalized decision-making process with that of using alternatives. (We are indebted to Massimo Morelli and an anonymous referee for this point.) Nothing of substance will change if the legislative s.q. vector of shares is allowed to be non-zero. This could be an additional source of heterogeneity, which is captured here in an ex ante manner by the vector of π ’s. 13 Stage 6: Those in the street implement the damage announced in 3. Stage 7: The allocation is implemented. If no damage was caused, each player receives π₯π = π π π. If damage was caused, each player receives π₯π = π π (π − πΎ). We are implicitly assuming complete information, a common first modeling step. Interesting additional insights could be obtained by adding asymmetric information. If some aspects of the collective action or damage capacity of protesters were stochastic and unobserved by institutionalized actors, we might have equilibria with occasional outbreaks of violence, a realistic feature shared by models of incomplete information in oligopoly, war, and strikes. SOLVING THE MODEL The model is solved by backward induction.19 Given the assumption of commitment by protesters, stages 6 and 7 are mechanically implemented after decision 4-5 is made. The latter is a standard legislative bargaining game with a small twist. It is easy to show that the agenda setter will give 0 to all other players in Congress and allocate the whole pie (except anything given to the protesters) to herself.20 The novel question is how much to give to the protesters. Clearly, if π < π, the agenda 19 The solution is proven formally in the Appendix. 20 More generally, the allocation among the players in Congress could be defined as π π = 0 for any π not part of the winning coalition, π π = π for those π’s in the winning coalition other than the agenda setter, and the rest for the agenda setter. We follow the standard convention of letting ε go to zero, and of assuming that players who are indifferent between two actions at zero will chose the one they would have chosen for π > 0. As stated, the fact that the other members of Congress get zero is just for simplicity. What actually matters for the relevant decisions is their expected utility in Congress before the agenda setter was selected by nature. This is a reduction of a richer intertemporal structure (where those “included” will eventually get their share) into a one-period model. 14 setter will give nothing to protesters. If π ≥ π , then the amount she will allocate to the protesters will depend on the amount π that they request. If they request π > πΎ, the agenda setter will give them nothing, since it is better to keep (π − πΎ) than (π − π). If they request π ≤ πΎ, then the agenda setter will grant them π. This response will lead the protesters (in stage 3) to request exactly π = πΎ, since they will get nothing if they go above πΎ, and πΎ is preferred to anything below it. Each protester will receive πΎ/π. Given that stage 2 is a move by nature, this brings us to the key choice of arenas in stage 1. Each player has to decide between the two arenas, given his expectation of what he will receive if he goes to Congress and if he goes to the street, taking as given the choices of all the other (π − 1) players. Finding equilibria to the whole game, then, consists of finding the Nash equilibrium to these π individual decisions over ππ . We present the results in the following proposition, which is presented more formally and proven in the Appendix. PROPOSITION 1: (a) There always exists a Full Institutionalization Equilibrium (FIE) in which everybody is in Congress and no alternative arenas are used. (b) For some parameter values, there is also a Low Institutionalization Equilibrium (LIE) in which π∗ actors go to the street. The existence of the FIE is guaranteed by the fact that if only one player chooses to be in the street in order to set a blockade, he will be unable to credibly threaten to cause any damage, and hence receive zero from the agenda setter, getting a final payoff of – π, which is less than what he would expect to receive in Congress. No one would want to deviate unilaterally from a FIE. Figure 5 provides an intuitive representation of the LIE. The figure plots the value of being in Congress (the upward-sloping curve) and the value of being in the street (the downward-sloping 15 curve) from the point of view of an individual player as a function of his or her probability of being the agenda setter (ππ ), under the assumption (which is true in the type of LIE we select, see Appendix) that all players of lower ππ will be in the street, and all players of higher ππ will be in Congress. Let π∗ be the highest integer to the left of the point where these two curves intersect. Players 1 to π∗ (those with the lowest ex ante probabilities of being selected agenda setter in Congress) will go to the street, and players π∗ + 1 to π will go to Congress. The result if fairly intuitive: players with weaker chances of getting what they want in formal political institutions are the ones more likely to utilize alternative political technologies. <Insert Figure 5> The low institutionalization equilibrium takes us back to the world of the models described in the introduction, where the institutionalized part of the game is the only relevant one – public policies are decided in formal arenas (and actors invest in institutional capabilities, as we argue in the next section). The low institutionalization equilibrium, on the other hand, will be characterized by the use of alternative political technologies and by weakness of formal institutional arenas. ON INSTITUTIONALIZATION (AND MULTIPLE EQUILIBRIA) The simple static model above provides glimpses into more general issues we want to raise regarding different degrees of institutionalization of policymaking across polities. In particular, the model captures in a very compressed way (through the initial investment, and through the beliefs about other people’s actions implicit in different equilibria) some richer dynamics characterizing institutions and institutionalization. Institutions reflect past investments, summarize information, beliefs and expectations, and incorporate self-reinforcement effects. Recognizing that there is no agreed terminology with respect to institutions and institutionalization, we would say that “the U.S. Congress is more institutionalized than the Argentine 16 Congress”. The U.S. Congress is a central institution in U.S. policymaking; its members exhibit remarkable longevity and specialize in committees; it engages in considerable oversight of the public bureaucracy, and it is the focus and main entry point of political action by any interest group attempting to influence American policymaking.21 The Argentine Congress does not share any of these features, in spite of the fact that Argentina has a constitutional structure similar to that of the US (Jones et al, 2002). The comparison can also be taken among countries of similar levels of development: the Chilean legislature plays a much more important role in the policymaking process of that country than does its Argentine counterpart (Stein et al, 2008). These different roles in policymaking are associated with various measures of legislators’ and legislatures’ capabilities, which have a clear investment component or that reflect the beliefs of various actors: longevity of legislative careers, legislators’ education, specialization in policy committees, resources available for policy analysis, esteem in the eyes of the public, and appreciation of Congress as an important place in politicians’ careers – Saiegh (2010) builds measures of such characteristics. When Congress and the political party system are effective conduits of preference aggregation and political bargaining, various relevant actors place their bets (investments) in those institutions, most citizens believe that those are the spaces where relevant decisions are made, and this whole logic reinforces and becomes self-fulfilling. On the contrary, if such institutional arenas are not taken too seriously and everybody knows that the way of getting something out of the political system is to blockade a road (or to bribe the president), those investments in the institutionalization of Congress or 21 Polsby 1968 is the authoritative reference on the institutionalization of the U.S. Congress. Our notion of institutionalization shares Polsby’s suggested components of a definition of institutionalization (focused on internal organization), but adds other elements that reflect its importance in the broader equilibrium, including the beliefs about its relevance, along the lines of the “external considerations” emphasized by Blondel (2006). 17 parties are not undertaken and the weakness of formal institutions is reinforced. The logic of selfreinforcement of institutions is central to the concerns of various strands of institutionalism in the social sciences. Scholars in the game theoretic tradition (as well as common usage) refer to institutions “as rules”, and also “as equilibria”. The standard “Northian” definition has become “the rules of the game in a society, the humanly devised constraints that shape human interaction”. A number of scholars have turned to a conception of institutions as equilibrium phenomena. It is ultimately the behavior of others rather than the rules themselves that induces each person to behave (or not) in the way prescribed by the rules.22 The model above captures these two distinct usages of the notion of institutions in a simple manner. On the one hand, it has political institutions as rules in the allocation of de jure political power (the rules of the Baron-Ferejohn game). On the other, it generates different degrees of institutionalization in equilibrium, as captured by ∑ ππ , the aggregate investment in formal institutions (which is a fixed point to the beliefs of all actors with respect to the actions of everybody else). Even within the context of a simplified static model, the result of having multiple equilibria (with different equilibria characterized by its degree of institutionalization) captures an important aspect of institutions. It also opens the door for the very relevant considerations so keen to historical institutionalists (Pierson and Skocpol 2002, Thelen 1999) about the way in which specific temporal sequences, critical junctures, and historically grounded events matter to explain different trajectories.23 22 This view has a long pedigree, but in its modern formulation has been pioneered by Greif (see for instance 2006), Calvert (1995, 1995b) and Aoki (2001). 23 If the world as seen with game theoretic eyes did not include multiplicity of equilibria, it would be impossible for history to matter. Additionally, the self-reinforcement effects that in a static game theoretic equilibrium appear in a stark and compressed manner, in reality take place in historical sequences, as emphasized by historical institutionalists. 18 Multiplicity of equilibria arises in the model of this paper due to a stark strategic complementarity introduced by the shape of the damage technology. Beyond the specificities of our formulation, an extreme simplification of threshold models of collective action (Oliver 1993, Lohmann 1994, Granovetter 1978), there are a number of reasons to expect strategic complementarities, reinforcement effects, and hence the possibility of multiple equilibria in institutionalization. Unconventional forms of political participation tend to be chosen where institutions are of lower quality, but those very decisions feed back into the weakness of formal institutions. Strategic complementarities are likely to be present in the action choices of players with regards to any given APT (as already present in the model),24 but also with regards to the actions and investment choices within any specific formal institution such as Congresses. Furthermore, there are reasons why alternative activities of one type are likely to induce alternative activities of other types. For instance, Trucco 2009 shows a complementarity between “bribes by the rich” and “street protests by the poor” as countervailing forces that tend to happen together in polities with weaker political institutions. Similarly, there tend to be important systemic effects across various institutionalized arenas. For instance, Stein and Tommasi 2007 and Scartascini et al 2009 show a positive correlation among measures of institutional strength in various domains (Congress, party system, Judiciary, the bureaucracy) across countries. Even though not quite modeled explicitly in this paper, having different degrees of institutionalization of policy making has important welfare consequences. In our simple model the cost of incomplete institutionalization is just ππ∗ . There are various reasons (some of which could be incorporated in a richer dynamic formulation of this model) why more institutionalized collective decision-making arenas tend to lead to better policies and better outcomes. Investing in technologies that increase strength and capabilities in the institutionalized game (such as hiring PhDs in Public 24 Machado et al 2009 finds that the likelihood that any individual would participate in street protests is increasing in the total number of people protesting. 19 Policy) or in technologies that increase strength and capabilities in alternative arenas (such as hiring goons), are likely to have a different impact on the strength and productivity of formal institutions, as well as on the quality of the output the polity generates. Scartascini et al 2009 shows that more institutionalized policymaking environments are associated with better public policies, which in turn induce better economic outcomes. One of the reasons behind that result is likely to be that more institutionalized policymaking arenas provide a better structure for exchange of information and for the agreement and enforcement of intertemporal cooperation. According to Pierson (2004: 107) “political institutions can serve to coordinate the behavior and expectations of decentralized actors (Carey, 2000) and to facilitate bargaining by creating monitoring bodies, issue linkages, and mechanisms for making credible commitments.” Multiplicity of equilibria has important implications in terms of theory, in terms of interpreting and analyzing empirical evidence, and in terms of thinking about possible practical recommendations. Before closing the section we want to say a word regarding the implications of this analysis for crosscountry econometrics on the effects of formal political rules. The effects of constitutional rules on policymaking and performance might be conditional on the type of equilibrium achieved by each polity. The standard predictions in the literature might apply for countries at the full institutionalization equilibrium, but not necessarily for countries with low institutionalization. Caruso et al 2010 explores this issue by clustering the countries into those with high and those with low levels of institutionalization.25 Using those clusters, it reproduces within each cluster the empirical exercises in Persson and Tabellini 2003. All of the results in Persson and Tabellini 2003 are replicated for the 25 The clustering of countries is performed using as proxies for the degree of institutionalization available measures of congressional capabilities, party system institutionalization, bureaucratic capabilities, and judicial independence. 20 high-institutionalization sample, but almost none of the results are significant for the lowinstitutionalization sample of countries. COMPARATIVE STATICS / EMPIRICAL PREDICTIONS One important question is what are the implications of equilibrium multiplicity for attempting to map the predictions of the model into empirical evidence. Fortunately, the simple structure of the model enables us to make some comparative static predictions in spite of having multiple equilibria. Under the maintained assumptions of the model, the FIE always exists, while the LIE exists for some parameter values and not for others. This means that for some parameter values the FIE will be the only equilibrium possible (call that set of parameters F), while for other parameter values both types of equilibrium are possible (call that set of parameters B). If the real world were fully described by this model, then we would expect that in polities characterized by a vector of parameters belonging to F we should observe the characteristics associated with the FIE, while in polities characterized by a vector of parameters belonging to B we could observe either of the equilibria. Assigning in that latter case a non-zero probability to each of the equilibria will be enough to generate empirical predictions. If conducting comparative statics on any given parameter increases the set of other parameters for which LIE is an equilibrium, then we will say that increasing that parameter increases the possibility of observing the Low Institutionalization Equilibrium (and its associated properties). It turns out that in the model any comparative statics exercise that increases the possibility of LIE, also increases the number π∗ of people going to the streets within the LIE (see Appendix), so that the derivative of π∗ with respect to any parameter is a sufficient statistic for the way in which that parameter affects the degree of institutionalization in either interpretation. Using that logic, it is easy to show the comparative static results summarized in Table 1, which we state as conditions under which non-institutionalized politics are more likely to be sustained. 21 <Insert Table 1> Not surprisingly, the probability of being in the LIE increases as the use of APTs becomes less costly, as the potential damage APTs can cause increases, and as the wealth of the economy decreases. More interestingly, the probability of being in a Low Institutionalization Equilibrium increases as the distribution of de jure political power becomes more asymmetric. As the vector of ππ ’s becomes more asymmetric, more actors at the lower end will find participation in formal political institutions less appealing, inducing more street action and lower institutionalization. The model predicts that those less favored by de jure political power are more likely to engage in non-institutionalized actions,26 and furthermore, that the more asymmetric political power is, the greater the numbers taking the outside option and the lower institutionalization in equilibrium. We have undertaken some preliminary steps towards the empirical study of some of the correlations predicted by the theory, using international measures of institutional quality which we believe serve as proxies for the strength of policymaking institutions as understood in the paper. These measures, taken from Scartascini et al 2009, include proxies for the strength and involvement of the legislature in policymaking, some aspects of party system institutionalization, and bureaucratic capabilities. These proxies for institutional strength have been combined with information on a number of political activities from the Cross-National Time-Series Data Archive, often combined under the heading of “Internal Conflict,” which we take as rough measure of the APTs emphasized in this paper. The logic presented above implies that in equilibrium there should be a negative 26 This result has a flavor of “exclusion of the poor”. Yet, the result is more general than that, and it applies to any case in which the de jure power of a relevant set of political actors tends to underrepresent them in comparison to their ability to put collective action together and threaten economic disruption. The very visible 2008-2009 demonstrations of rural producers in Argentina against large increases in export taxes by the government are a case in point. Those demonstrators were not the dispossessed, but an economic sector underrepresented in the Argentine political system. 22 correlation between the strength of political institutions and the use of alternative political. Our measures of institutional strength tend to be negatively correlated with the measures of conflict, with the coefficients being statistically significant in univariate and multivariate regressions with standard controls such as GDP per capita, regional dummies, and level of democracy. Figure 6 shows one of these correlations between internal conflict and a combined measure of institutional strength. <Insert Figure 6> The argument presented in this study has also implications for correlations among institutional and conflict variables with some characteristics of policy outcomes; for instance, a positive correlation between weaker institutions, more use of alternative political technologies, and public policies that favor some actors disproportionately. Political institutions that generate more biased policy outcomes are likely to lead to increased use of alternative political technologies and this induces weaker investments in the institutionalization of policymaking. We have also found a positive correlation between the use of APTs and a measure of biases in government policy called favoritism compiled by World Ec. Forum’s GCR, as well as a negative correlation of favoritism and institutionalization.27 CONCLUSIONS AND EXTENSIONS The objective of this paper is to suggest a framework (a modeling strategy) to articulate insights from the rich literature on the effects of political institutions on policy into a broader view of policymaking, by endowing political actors with a larger action space. Such an effort could prove particularly useful for the study of policymaking in developing democracies, as well as for integrating such analyses across countries of different levels of economic and institutional development. 27 This is consistent with observations in O’Donnell (1996) who characterizes many Latin American democracies as having both weak institutions and particularism (a combination that he defines as “another institutionalization”). 23 The model presented in this paper has the following implications. 1. Different countries have different degrees of institutionalization in their policymaking. 2. There is multiplicity of equilibria -this allows similar countries to be stuck at different levels of institutionalization, self-reinforcing dynamics, and the possibility of equilibrium switches. 3. The likelihood of institutionalized policymaking increases as the cost of alternative political actions increases, as the damage these alternatives can cause decreases, and as the economy becomes wealthier. 4. If the distribution of de jure political power is very asymmetric, it is more likely to observe use of alternative political technologies as well as low degrees of institutionalization.28 There are various pending tasks in the agenda described in the paper, such as enriching various aspects of the model to permit comparative static exercises on economic structure, APTs, and formal political institutions. To begin with, one can give more structure to the economy and more specific characteristics to the actors in the policy game. The APT in the model presents a fairly “flat” topography. Costs and potential effects of various forms of collective action are distributed in much more specific manners. The various π(π)’s of different actors could be a function of who else is participating in that activity, facilitating collective action across particular sets of agents, such as workers in sectors with high “damage capacity”. More generally, there are various structural, historical, and perceptual factors that affect specific forms of collective action. π(π)’s as well as potential rewards from such activities will be a function not only of who else protests, but also of the history of organization of such movements, and of the beliefs about the legitimacy of the protest by other actors who might matter for the degree of repression. 28 Ongoing work indicates two additional implications: (5) High costs (for instance due to agency problems) in using formal institutions can lead to the use of APTs and to low institutionalization; (6) there are strategic complementarities across the use of different APTs. 24 An interesting extension would consist of a richer set of APTs with different socioeconomic actors having differential access to each of the technologies. Various technologies used extensively by the well-off in Latin America give them privileged access to policymaking. Trucco (2009) provides a start in that direction, and her results suggest the presence of a strategic complementarity between the uses of bribes and of road blockades. “Bribes by the rich” and “protests by the poor” can be seen as countervailing forces that tend to happen together in polities with weaker political institutions. (Such result is related to the asymmetry result 4 above).29 Other extensions might allow actors to invest in both institutions and alternative technologies and to use the outside threats in their institutionalized negotiations. Including also a “third activity” or opportunity cost, would allow studying the form of political participation by different actors across countries and relating that to institutionalization. Natural extensions might come from moving away from our simple legislative bargaining formulation and fishing in the abundant pond of formal models of political institutions for richer institutional comparative statics. For instance, what would be the effect of alternative electoral rules (proportional versus majoritarian) on the degree of institutionalization of policymaking? (One might hypothesize that PR systems, allowing a better representation of minorities, might lead to more symmetric distributions of de jure political power and hence to more institutionalized behavior.) What would be the effect of regime type (parliamentary of presidential) on the degree of institutionalization of policymaking? To deal with such questions, one will need to move in the direction of representative democracy, with models that permit exploring the electoral connection and agency issues. Another line of useful extensions might come from moving to more dynamic specifications. The paper couches some of its interpretation in terms of the “dynamics of institutionalization”. This is just a heuristic that captures the extent to which institutionalization is a function of shared expectations. 29 Such an extension’s empirical predictions – bribes positively correlated with other APTs as protests, and negatively correlated with institutionalization -- seem consistent with preliminary evidence. 25 (Almost all static game theoretic equilibria are simplified depictions of processes that indeed take place over time.) Another sense of dynamics would be the question of how a country arrives to (or switches towards) a particular equilibrium. Addressing such transitions is an important pending task, which we plan to undertake via theoretically informed narratives of some Latin American experiences. Also, the model has treated constitutional rules as exogenous, a natural first modeling step (Diermeier and Krehbiel, 2003). This can be embedded in a richer game in which such rules are chosen at an earlier stage, having our model here as a continuation subgame. Such modeling strategy would be quite complementary to the Acemoglu-Robinson (2006) logic, providing a bit more structure to their (unmodeled) threat of collective action due to temporary de facto power. There are various possible implications from the results here and from the eventual next steps. To highlight one of them (in light with the results in Caruso et al 2010), the existence of different levels of institutionalization may imply that some influential research in “political economics” is not necessarily applicable to every type of country. Studies on the impact of political institutions on policies should incorporate the possibility that political rules might have different effects depending on the arenas in which policies are determined in each polity; as well as the possibility that the arena itself might depend on political rules. This should also raise a flag for those in the business of recommending institutional reforms for dealing with failing policies. APPENDIX Solution of the Game (and proof of Proposition 1) The parameters of the game are π, π, πΎ, π, π, {ππ }ππ=1 . Let Γ = [β³, π©\β³] denote a partition of the set of players. Take any Γ and any realization of the agenda setter π consistent with that Γ, and call πΊ(Γ, π) the game from stage 3 onwards with partition Γ and agenda setter π. The equilibrium play of that game will generate payoffs ππ (Γ, π) for each player π. We solve the game in two steps: first finding the (subgame perfect) equilibrium for 26 any πΊ(Γ, π), and then the Nash equilibria to the venue choices of all players in stage 1 with πΈπ [ππ (Γ, π)] as continuation payoffs. We focus on pure strategies throughout. Step 1. Solving πΊ(Γ, π). π {π∗ (π§), π π∗ (π), {ππ∗ (π π )} πππ©\β³ } constitute a Subgame Perfect Equilibrium for πΊ(Γ, π) if: π π 1. For all π(π§), π π: ππ∗ (π π ) maximizes payoffs to π, given {ππ∗ (π π )} πππ©\β³\{i} π 2. Given {ππ∗ (π π )} πππ©\β³ π 3. Given {ππ∗ (π π )} πππ©\β³ , for all πππ©\β³. , for all π(π§): π π∗ (π) maximizes payoff to the agenda setter µ. and π π∗ (π): π∗ (π§) maximizes payoffs to The Street. We solve πΊ(Γ, π) by backward induction from stage 5 to stage 3. Stage 5: given the status quo payoffs of zero, assumption A4 assures that any proposal greater or equal to zero will be accepted by all members of Congress. This implies π = ππ . π Stage 4: given π = ππ , π π = 0 ∀π ∈ π©\β³\{μ}, since the agenda setter will try to keep as much of the pie as possible for himself. With regards to how much to give to The Street, the decision depends on the number of players in the street, as well as on the amount they request. If π < π, given π(π§) = 0 ∀z, π§ π = 0. If π ≥ π, the amount given to The Street by the agenda setter will depend on π(π§). The agenda setter will pick the lowest π§ such that π(π§) = 0, and compare giving at π§ to all players in the street, to giving them 0 and suffering the max{{1 − π × damage π(0). Hence, his problem is π§Μ }π, π − π(0)}, π§ (1) where π§Μ = πππ{π§ ∈ [0,1]|π(π§) = 0}. Stage 3: (The problem for The Street is trivial when π < π; we focus on π ≥ π.) The Street’s problem consists of maximizing π§ subject to (1). Given that in the second option they get zero, their problem reduces to announcing a function π(π§) that: (i) minimizes π − π(0): and (ii) minimizes {1 − π × π§Μ }π, subject to {1 − π × π§Μ }π ≥ π − π(0). (i) implies π(0) = πΎ. (ii) implies πΎ ππ = π§Μ . Any function π(π§) that satisfies those two conditions constitutes a solution to The Street’s problem. For brevity we focus on 27 πΎ π(π§) = { πΎ πππ π§ < ππ 0 πππ π§ ≥ (2) πΎ ππ The above reasoning can be summarized in the following Lemma.30 Lemma 1: under the maintained assumptions of the model, subgame perfect equilibria to G(Γ,µ) will imply the following equilibrium play: π (a) If m<T: the Street announces anything; the agenda setter proposes ππ = {π π }πππ© such that 1 π π π = { 0 π=π ; π≠π all players in Congress accept the proposal; no damage is caused; and the allocation is π π₯π = { 0 π=π . π≠π π (b) If m≥T: the Street announces (2); the agenda setter proposes π π = {π π }πππ© such that 1 − πΎ⁄π π π π = { 0 πΎ⁄ ππ π=π π ∈ π©\β³\{μ} ; π∈β³ all players in Congress accept the proposal; no damage is caused, and the allocation is π−πΎ π₯π = {0 πΎ⁄ π π=π π ∈ π©\β³\{μ}. π∈β³ From Lemma 1 it is easy to compute the continuation values of the different configurations of venue choices in stage 1, before π is realized in stage 2. These expected values from venue choice ππ , as a function of all other players’ choices π−π ,will constitute the elements of the payoff matrix of the stage 1 game. Step 2. Nash Equilibria of Stage 1 Game. There are two types of equilibria in this game: (a) Full Institutionalization Equilibria (FIE) in which all players choose to go to Congress and a standard Baron-Ferejohn game results from stage 2 onwards, and (b) 30 In the case in which , there will be no one in Congress; but it is easy to see that cannot happen in equilibrium, since in that case any player switching venues would become the agenda setter and increase his payoff. 28 Low Institutionalization Equilibria (LIE) in which π∗ > 0 players go to the street. We start by showing that a FIE exists for all parameter values under our assumptions. It is easy to see that if everybody is in Congress, nobody wants to deviate from that, for all the feasible parameters of the game. If everybody was in Congress, and one player was to deviate and go to the street, the number of players in the street would be one, which is smaller than π and hence insufficient to produce any damage. The allocation resulting from that path will lead to π π = 0 for the deviating player. His payoff in the street will then be equal to – π, while his expected payoff in Congress would have been ππ π. This deviation is never profitable. (The continuation of the game in this type of equilibrium is as specified in part (a) of Lemma 1). We now proceed to characterize LIE. Let Γ ∗ denote a partition being considered as possible equilibrium, with β³ its associated set (with measure π∗) of players in the street. In any LIE it has to be the case that no ∗ player wants to switch venues. It is easy to see from Lemma 1(a) that it is not possible to have a LIE in which m*<T; hence in any LIE the continuation game has to be as specified in part (b) of Lemma 1. For a partition to be an equilibrium one, it has to be the case that no player in Congress would rather be in the street. That is, ∀π ∈ π©\β³∗, (π − πΎ) [∑ ππ ∗ ππ π∈π©\β³ ππ ≥ ]≥ πΎ − π, π∗ +1 ∑π∈π©\β³∗ ππ (π−πΎ) which implies πΎ − π∗ +1 ( π) ≡ ππΏ (Γ ∗ ); (3) so that ππΏ (Γ ∗ ) constitutes the lowest possible ππ that will rather stay in Congress for an arbitrary partition Γ ∗ . Condition (3) is necessary for Γ ∗ to be an equilibrium partition. A similar reasoning can be applied to players in the street, only that two situations have to be considered in that case, depending on whether the number of players in the street m∗ induced by Γ ∗ is equal to or greater than π. For Γ ∗ such that π∗ > π to be an equilibrium partition, it has to be the case that ∀π ∈ β³∗ , ππ ], ππ +∑π∈π©\β³∗ ππ (X − K) [ πΎ π∗ −π ≥ which implies πΎ ππ ≤ ∑π∈π©\β³∗ ππ ( ∗ −π) π πΎ (X−K)−( ∗−π) π ≡ ππ (Γ ∗ ). (4) For Γ ∗ such that π∗ = π to be an equilibrium partition, it has to be the case that ∀π ∈ β³∗: 29 πΎ ππ − π ≥ X[ ], π ππ + ∑π∈π©\β³∗ ππ ππ ≤ which implies πΎ π ∑π∈π©\β³∗ ππ ( −π) πΎ π X−( −π) ≡ ππ (Γ ∗ ). (4’) The difference between (4’) and (4) lies in the absence of the term πΎ in the denominator, since when π∗ = π, anyone moving from the street to Congress will make The Street’s threat of damage no longer feasible. Expressions (3) and (4) are necessary and sufficient conditions for Γ ∗ such that π∗ > π to be an equilibrium partition. (3) and (4’) are necessary and sufficient conditions for Γ ∗ such that π∗ = π to be an equilibrium partition. These conditions allow for two types of LIE: one in which the partition is such that the greatest π in β³∗ is smaller than the least π in π©\β³∗ , that is all types in Congress are larger than all types in the street (call those LIE1); and one in which that condition is not satisfied (LIE2). In the rest of this appendix as well as in the text we focus on equilibria LIE1, and reserve the terminology LIE to refer to LIE1. Other than being more intuitive and allowing for a briefer exposition of the subsequent analysis, this choice can be justified by two results (available upon request): (i) for any vector of parameters for which a LIE2 exists, there exists also a LIE1; and (ii) take two partitions that differ only in that one player from each venue is switched to the other: the sum of utilities of those two players will be higher in the partition in which the higher type is in Congress and the lower type is in the Street. We analyze now the parameter values under which LIE exists. We can explain the results with the visual aid of Figure A-1. Let the horizontal axis represent β+ as well as the set of players π ordered from 1 to π. <Insert Figure A1> Take any vector of all the parameters of the game except π. Let ππ·π (π) represent the value of action π ∈ {0,1} for player π when potential damage is π· ∈ {0, πΎ}, under the assumption (from LIE1) that all players to his left are choosing the street (ππ = 0 ∀π < π) and all players to his right are choosing Congress (ππ = 1 ∀π > π). We ππ have then ππΎ1 (π) = (π − πΎ) [∑π π=π ππ ππ ], π01 (π) = π [∑π π=π ππ ], ππΎ0 (π) = πΎ π − π, and π00 (π) = −π. The first three 30 functions are plotted in figure A-1.31 Let π∗ be the largest integer such that ππΎ0 (π) ≥ ππΎ1 (π). The set of parameter vectors for which there is a LIE can be visualized by juxtaposing π with the rest of parameters summarized in the functions plotted in Figure A-1. If π < π∗, then the threat of damage πΎ is credible, the relevant curve for the value of being in Congress is ππΎ1 (π), and we have a LIE in which players 1 through π∗ go to the street and players π∗ + 1 through π go to Congress. If π > π∗ , then the value of being in the street would be π00 (π) = −π, and that cannot be an equilibrium, as already stated. For π = π∗, the relevant comparison for the (now pivotal) player π = π = π∗ is between π01 (π) and ππΎ0 (π). If π01 (π) ≤ ππΎ0 (π), then he chooses the street and we have a LIE. If π01 (π) > ππΎ0 (π), then he would choose Congress and we do not have a LIE. We summarize the analysis in the following proposition, which is the more formal equivalent of (heuristic) Proposition 1 in the text. Appendix Proposition 1:Let π∗ ≡ max{i| π ∈ π© πππ ππΎ0 (π) ≥ ππΎ1 (π)}. (a) A Full Institutionalization Equilibrium in which β³∗ = ∅ and π©\β³∗ = π© exists for all values of parameters. (b) A Low Institutionalization Equilibrium in which β³ = {1,2, … π∗ } and π©\β³ = {π∗ + 1, π∗ + 2, … π} ∗ ∗ exists if T<π∗ or if T=π∗ πππ ππΎ0 (π) ≥ π01 (π) We have established conditions for the existence of LIE, in which players up to π∗ are in the street and players from π∗ + 1 are in Congress. In such cases, the equilibrium conditions ππΎ0 (π∗ ) ≥ ππΎ1 (π∗ ) and ππΎ1 (π∗ + 1) ≥ ππΎ0 (π∗ + 1) are satisfied. For simplicity, in any case of indifference we assign π∗ to the street and π∗ + 1 to Congress. Under those conditions π∗ is unique for any set of parameters for which LIE exists, which facilitates the comparative statics. Comparative Statics 31 The functions are written and plotted as continuous for expositional purposes, even though for a given set of s they are discrete functions. 31 We can use Figure A-1 to intuitively visualize comparative statics results from the parameters of the model to π∗. These comparative statics could be interpreted as referring both to the number of people in the street within a LIE, and to the possibility of existence of LIE (vis-à-vis FIE that always exists), where “possibility” is defined in terms of the size of the set of parameters (other than the one being changed) for which the conditions for existence of LIE are satisfied. First, it is clear that a larger π makes LIE less likely. We can see the effect of changing any parameter other than π by shifting the curves ππΎ0 (π) and ππΎ1 (π) in Figure A-1, and by noticing that the larger π∗, the weaker the requirements on all other parameters for the existence of LIE. It is easy to see that an increase in π shifts ππΎ0 (π) down, tending to decrease π∗, hence decreasing the possibility of LIE. Increasing π has the same effect through an upward shift of ππΎ1 (π). Decreasing πΎ also decreases both π∗ and the probability of LIE through leftward shifts in both curves. Comparative statics on the distribution of ππ s can be a bit more involved. Here we prove the effect of increasing the asymmetry of ππ s (the inequality in the distribution of de jure political power) in a particular way. Let π(π) = ∑ππ=π ππ be the cumulative density function counting from π to π. Notice that π(π) decreases in π. Let π be another distribution, with cumulative π(π) = ∑ππ=π ππ . For brevity we will speak as if the functions where continuous, while the proper logic is the discrete equivalent of what we say. We say that π(β) is more unequal than π(β) if π(β) is equally or more elastic than π(β) for all π, and it is strictly more elastic for at least one π. This means that changes in π lead to larger changes in the probability under π than under π. Notice that this implies that π(β) first order stochastically dominates π(β). We show that a more unequal distribution leads to more people in the street. π(β) more unequal than π(β) implies ππ π ππ π | ππ π| ≥ | ππ π| ⇒ ππ π ππ π ≤ ππ π ππ π ⇒ ππ π(π) ≤ ππ π(π) ⇒ ππ π ∑π=π ππ ππ ≤ ∑π π=π ππ . As we can see in Figure A-2, this implies that in the case of more unequal distribution of power, there will be more (or at least not fewer) people in the street. <Insert Figure A2> 32 REFERENCES Acemoglu, Daron, and James A. Robinson. 2006. Economic Origins of Dictatorship and Democracy. Cambridge, United Kingdom: Cambridge University Press. Aoki, Masahiro. 2001. Toward a Comparative Institutional Analysis. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Bahry and Wilson. 2006. “Confusion or Fairness in the Field? Rejections in the Ultimatum Game under the Strategy Method”, Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization 60: 37-54. Baron, David, and John Ferejohn. 1989. “Bargaining in Legislatures.” American Political Science Review 83(4): 1181-1206. Blondel, John. 2006. “About Institutions, Mainly, but not Exclusively, Political” in Rhodes, Binder and Rockman Oxford Handbook of Political Institutions. Oxford: Oxford U. Press. Bueno de Mesquita, Bruce, Alastair Smith, Randolph Siverson, and James Morrow. 2003. The Logic of Political Survival. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Calvert, Randall. 1995. “Rational Actors, Equilibrium and Social Institutions.” In Knight and Sened. Explaining Social Institutions. Ann Arbor, United States: University of Michigan Press. Calvert, Randall. 1995b. “The Rational Choice Theory of Institutions: Cooperation, Coordination, and Communication.” In Banks and Hanushek, Modern Political Economy. Cambridge University Press. Carey, John M. 2000. “Parchment, Equilibria, and Institutions.” Comparative Political Studies 33(67): 735-761. Caruso, Germán et al. 2010 “Are We All Playing the Same Game? The Economic Effects of Constitutions Depend on the Degree of Institutionalization.” Mimeo. Dal Bó, Ernesto, and Rafael Di Tella. 2003. “Capture by Threat.” Journal of Political Economy 111(5): 1123-54. 33 Dal Bó, Ernesto, Pedro Dal Bó and Rafael Di Tella. 2006. “Plata o Plomo?Bribe and Punishment in a Theory of Political Influence.” American Political Science Review 100(1): 41-53. Diermeier, Daniel and Keith Khrebiel. 2003. “Institutionalism as a Methodology” Journal of Theoretical Politics, 15(2): 123-144. Dunning, Thad. 2009. “Fighting and Voting: Violent Conflict and Electoral Politics” Mimeo, Yale. Ellman, Matthew, and Leonard Wantchekon. 2000. “Electoral Competition under the Threat of Political Unrest.” Quarterly Journal of Economics 115(2): 499-531. Garfinkel, Michelle and Stergios Skaperdas. 1996. The Political Economy of Conflict and Appropriation, New York: Cambridge University Press. Granovetter, Mark. 1978. “Threshold Models of Collective Behavior.” American Journal of Sociology 83(6): 1420-1443. Greif, Avner. 2006. Institutions and the Path to the Modern Economy: Lessons from Medieval Trade. Cambridge, United Kingdom: Cambridge University Press. Grossman, Gene, and Elhanan Helpman. 2001. Special Interest Politics. Cambridge: MIT Press. Harstad, Bard and Jakob Svensson.2009. “Bribe or Lobby? Rule Bending, Rule Changing, and Economic Growth” Mimeo, Northwestern University. Henrich et al. 2004. Foundations of Human Sociality. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Hirshleifer, Jack. 2001. The Dark Side of the Force: Economic Foundations of Conflict Theory. Cambridge, United States: Cambridge University Press. Humphreys, Macartan. 2001. “To Bargain or to Brawl.” Mimeo. Huntington, Samuel P. 1968. Political Order in Changing Societies. Yale University Press. Jones, Mark et al. 2002. “Amateur Legislators, Professional Politicians: The Consequences of PartyCentered Electoral Rules in Federal Systems.” American Journal of Political Science 46(3): 656-669. 34 Levine, David. 1998. "Modeling Altruism and Spitefulness in Experiments," Review of Economic Dynamics, 1: 593-622, 1998. Levitsky, Steven and M. Victoria Murillo. 2009. “Variation in Institutional Strength” Annual Review of Political Science 12: 115-33. Lindvall, Johannes. 2008. “A Model of Protests” Mimeo. Dept. of Political Science, Oxford U. Lohmann, Susanne. 1994. “The Dynamics of Informational Cascades: The Monday Demonstration in Leipzig, East Germany 1989-91.” World Politics 47(1): 42-101. Machado, Fabiana et al. 2009. “Political Institutions and Street Protests in Latin America.” Marx, Gary and Douglass McAdams. 1994. Collective Behavior and Social Movements: Process and Structure. Prentice Hall: New Jersey. O’Donnell, Guillermo. 1996. “Another Instititutionalization: Latin America and Elsewhere” Working Paper 222: Kellogg Institute for International Studies, University of Notre Dame. Oliver, Pamela. 1993. “Formal Models of Collective Action” Annual R. of Sociology 19: 271-300. Persson, Torsten, and Guido Tabellini. 2000. Political Economics: Explaining Economic Policy. MIT Press. Persson, Torsten, and Guido Tabellini. 2003. The Economic Effects of Constitutions. Cambridge, United States: MIT Press. Pierson, Paul. 2004. Politics in Time: History, Institutions, and Social Analysis. Princeton, United States: Princeton University Press. Pierson, Paul. and Theda Skocpol. 2002. “Historical Institutionalism in Contemporary Political Science”, in Katznelson and Milner (eds.) Political Science. State of the Discipline, Centennial Edition. New York: W.W.Norton & Co. 35 Polsby, Nelson W. 1968. “The Institutionalization of the House of Representatives. American Political Science Review, 62(1): 144-68. Przeworski, Adam. 1992. “The Games of Transition” in Mainwaring et al Issues in Democratic Consolidation. University of Notre Dame Press. Przeworski, Adam. 2009. “Representative Institutions, Political Conflicts, and Public Policies” Mimeo Saiegh, Sebastian. 2010. “Active Players or Rubber-Stamps? An Evaluation of the Policy-Making Role of Latin American Legislatures.” In Scartascini, Stein and Tommasi. How Democracy Works: Political Institutions, Actors and Arenas in Latin American Policymaking. Cambridge, U.S.: Harvard University, David Rockefeller Center for Latin American Studies. Scartascini, Carlos, Ernesto Stein and Mariano Tommasi. 2009. “Political Institutions, Intertemporal Cooperation, and the Quality of Policies.” WP 676. Washington, DC: IADB. Stein, Ernesto, and Mariano Tommasi. 2007. “The Institutional Determinants of State Capabilities in Latin America.” In Bourguignon and Pleskovic, Annual World Bank Conference on Development Economics Regional: Beyond Transition. Washington, DC: World Bank. Stein, Ernesto et al. 2008. Policymaking in Latin America: How Politics Shapes Policies. Cambridge, U.S.: Harvard University, David Rockefeller Center for Latin American Studies. Thelen, Kathleen. 1999. “Historical Institutionalism in Comparative Politics”, Annual Review of Political Science, 2: 369-404. Trucco, Laura 2009. “Instituciones y Tecnologías Políticas Alternativas en los Procesos de Policymaking.” Buenos Aires: Universidad de San Andrés, Dept. of Economics. MA thesis. 36 Figure 1. Alternative Political Actions More Institutionalized Less Institutionalized forming a political party demonstrations to inspire sympathy writing to your congressman legal strikes road blockades campaign contributions subtle coordination of capital flight coordinated economic disruption clean lobbying bribes (“plata”) violent threats (“plomo”) 37 .3 Figure 2. Congress or the Street? (17 Latin American Countries, 2008) Bolivia .2 .25 Argentina .15 Ec uador Peru Venezuela Honduras Paraguay .1 Nic aragua Panama Uruguay Guatemala Colombia Costa Ric a Mexic o .05 Rep. Dominic ana Brasil El Salvador .02 .04 .06 Percentage who contacted Mem ber of Congress .08 38 Figure 3. Damage Technology 39 Figure 4. Timing of the Game 40 Figure 5. Low Institutionalization Equilibrium (π − πΎ) [ ππ ] π ∑π=π ππ πΎ −π π π∗ max ππ iΟ΅β³ Go to street π∗ + π π π min ππ iΟ΅π©ββ³ Go to Congress 41 Table 1. Comparative Statics Parameter Probability of being in the noninstitutionalized equilibrium (or inverse degree of institutionalization ) ο© Threshold of collective action in the street (π) (-) ο© Cost of using APT (c) (-) ο© Damage potential (K) ο© Wealth (X) ο© Asymmetry distribution of de jure political power (asymmetry distribution of ππ ’s) (+) (-) (+) 42 2 0 -2 Internal Conflict 4 Figure 6. Correlation (Institutional Strength; Use of one particular APT) -2 -1 0 Institutional Strength Index 1 2 * controlling for LnGDPpc and regional dummies 43 Figure A1. Low Institutionalization Equilibria π01 (π) = π [ ππ ] π ∑π=π ππ ππΎ1 (π) = (π − πΎ) [ ππΎ0 (π) = ππ ] π ∑π=π ππ πΎ −π π π π1 π2 π3 π1 π2 π3 π4 π4 π < π∗ → ∃ πΏπΌπΈ = π2∗ → ∃ πΏπΌπΈ = π3∗ → β πΏπΌπΈ > π∗ → β πΏπΌπΈ 44 Figure A2. More Unequal Distribution π Leads to Larger π∗ (π − πΎ) ππ ∑ππ=π ππ (π − πΎ) ππ π ∑π=π ππ πΎ −π π π π∗ (approx.) for distribution π π π∗ (approx.) for distribution π 45