Propositional Definite Clause Logic: Syntax, Semantics and Bottom-up Proofs Jim Little UBC CS 322 – CSP October 20, 2014 Slide 1 Lecture Overview • Recap: Logic intro • Propositional Definite Clause Logic: Semantics • PDCL: Bottom-up Proof Slide 2 Logic: A general framework for reasoning General problem: Query answering • tell the computer how the world works • tell the computer some facts about the world • ask a yes/no question about whether other facts must be true Solving it with Logic 1. 2. 3. 4. 5. Begin with a task domain. Distinguish those things you want to talk about (the ontology) Choose symbols in the computer to denote elements of your ontology Tell the system knowledge about the domain Ask the system whether new statements about the domain are true or false live_w4? lit_l2? Slide 3 Example: Electrical Circuit /down / up Slide 4 /down / up Syntax: are these sentences that a reasoning procedure can process? Semantics: what do these statements say about the world I need to represent? Slide 5 To Define a Logic We Need • Syntax: specifies the symbols used, and how they can be combined to form legal sentences • Knowledge base is a set of sentences in the language • Semantics: specifies the meaning of symbols and sentences • Reasoning theory or proof procedure: a specification of how an answer can be produced. • Sound: only generates correct answers with respect to the semantics • Complete: Guaranteed to find an answer if it exists Slide 6 Propositional Definite Clauses: Syntax Definition (atom) An atom is a symbol starting with a lower case letter Examples: p1; live_l1 Definition (body) A body is an atom or is of the form b1 ∧ b2 where b1 and b2 are bodies. Examples: p1 ∧ p2; ok_w1 ∧ live_w0 Definition (definite clause) Examples: p1 ← p2; A definite clause is live_w0 ← live_w1 ∧ up_s2 - an atom or - a rule of the form h ← b where h is an atom (“head”) and b is a body. (Read this as “h if b”.) Definition (KB) A knowledge base (KB) is a set of definite clauses Slide 7 Propositional Definite Clauses: Semantics Definition (interpretation) An interpretation I assigns a truth value to each atom. Definition (truth values of statements) • A body b1 ∧ b2 is true in I if and only if b1 is true in I and b2 is true in I. • A rule h ← b is false in I if and only if b is true in I and h is false in I. • A knowledge base KB is true in I if and only if every clause in KB is true in I. Definition (model) A model of a knowledge base KB is an interpretation in which KB is true. Similar to CSPs: a model Slide 8of a set of clauses is an interpretation that makes all of the clauses true To Obtain This We Need One More Definition Definition (logical consequence) If KB is a set of clauses and G is a conjunction of atoms, G is a logical consequence of KB, written KB ⊧ G, if G is true in every model of KB. • we also say that G logically follows from KB, or that KB entails G. • In other words, KB ⊧ G if there is no interpretation in which KB is true and G is false. • when KB is TRUE, then G must be TRUE • We want a reasoning procedure that can find all and only the logical consequences of a knowledge base Slide 9 User’s View of Semantics • Choose a task domain: intended interpretation. • For each proposition you want to represent, associate a proposition symbol in the language. • Tell the system clauses that are true in the intended interpretation: axiomatize the domain. • Ask questions about the intended interpretation. • If KB |= g , then g must be true in the intended interpretation. Slide 10 Computer’s View of Semantics • The computer doesn’t have access to the intended interpretation. • All it knows is the knowledge base. • The computer can determine if a formula is a logical consequence of KB. • If KB |= g then g must be true in the intended interpretation. • Otherwise, there is a model of KB in which g is false. This could be the intended interpretation. The computer wouldn't know! Slide 11 Computer’s View of Semantics • Otherwise, there is a model of KB in which g is false. This could be the intended interpretation. The computer wouldn't know I1 I2 p q r s true true true true true true true false p q. KB q. r s. Slide 12 To Define a Logic We Need • Syntax: specifies the symbols used, and how they can be combined to form legal sentences • Knowledge base is a set of sentences in the language • Semantics: specifies the meaning of symbols and sentences • Reasoning theory or proof procedure: a specification of how an answer can be produced (sound and complete) • Bottom-up Proof Procedure for Finding Logical Consequence Slide 13 Proof Procedures • A proof procedure is a mechanically derivable demonstration that a formula logically follows from a knowledge base. • Given a proof procedure P, KB ⊦ P g means g can be derived from knowledge base KB with the proof procedure. • If I tell you I have a proof procedure for PDCL • What do I need to show you in order for you to trust my procedure? That is sound and complete Slide 14 Soundness and Completeness Definition (soundness) A proof procedure P is sound if KB ⊦P g implies KB ⊧ g. sound: every atom derived by P follows logically from KB (i.e. is true in every model) • Soundness of proof procedure P: need to prove that If g can be derived by the procedure (KB ⊦P g) then g is true in all models of KB (KB ⊧ g) Definition (completeness) A proof procedure P is complete if KB ⊧ g implies KB ⊦P g. complete: every atom that logically follows from KB is derived by P • Completeness of proof procedure P: need to prove that If g is true in all models of KB (KB ⊧ g) 15 then g is derived by theSlide procedure (KB ⊦P g) Simple Proof Procedure Simple proof procedure S • Enumerate all interpretations • For each interpretation I, check whether it is a model of KB i.e., check whether all clauses in KB are true in I • KB ⊦S g if g holds in all such models problem with this approach? • If there are n propositions in the KB, must check all the 2𝑛 interpretations! Goal of proof theory • find sound and complete proof procedures that allow us to prove that a logical formula follows from a KB avoiding to Slide 16 do the above Lecture Overview • Recap Lecture 7 • Logical Consequences and Proof Procedures • Bottom-Up Proof Procedure • Soundness • Completeness Slide 17 Bottom-up proof procedure • One rule of derivation, a generalized form of modus ponens: • If “h ← b1 … bm" is a clause in the knowledge base, and each bi has been derived, then h can be derived. • This rule also covers the case when m = 0. Slide 18 Bottom-up proof procedure C :={}; repeat select clause “h ← b1 ∧ … ∧ bm” in KB such that bi ∈ C for all i, and h ∉ C; C := C ∪ { h } until no more clauses can be selected. KB ⊦ G if G ⊆ C at the end of this procedure The C at the end of BU procedure is a fixed point: • Further applications of our rule of derivation will not change C! Slide 19 Bottom-up proof procedure: example C := {}; repeat select clause h ← b1 … bm in KB such that bi C for all i, and h C; C := C {h} until no more clauses can be selected. a← b c a← e f b← f k c← e d← k e. f← j e f← c j← c {} {e} {c,e} {c,e,f} {c,e,f,j} {c,e,f,j,a} Slide 20 Done. Lecture Overview • Recap of Lecture 6 • Planning as CSP • Logic • Intro • Propositional Definite Clause Logic (PDCL) • Sintax and Semantics • Logical Consequences and Proof Procedures • Bottom Up Proof Procedure • Soundness and completeness Slide 21 Soundness of bottom-up proof procedure BU Definition (soundness) A proof procedure P is sound if KB ⊦P g implies KB ⊧ g. sound: every atom g that P derives follows logically from KB C := {}; repeat select clause h ← b1 … bm in KB such that bi C for all i, and h C; C := C {h} until no more clauses can be selected. What do we need to prove to show that BU is sound ? Slide 22 Soundness of bottom-up proof procedure BU Definition (soundness) A proof procedure P is sound if KB ⊦P g implies KB ⊧ g. sound: every atom g that P derives follows logically from KB C := {}; repeat select clause h ← b1 … bm in KB such that bi C for all i, and h C; C := C {h} until no more clauses can be selected. What do we need to prove to show that BU is sound ? If g C at the end of BU procedure, then g is true in all models of KB (KB ⊧ g) Slide 23 Soundness of bottom-up proof procedure BU What do we need to prove to show that BU is sound ? If g C at the end of BU procedure, then g is true in all models of KB (KB ⊧ g) By contradiction: Suppose there is a g such that KB ⊦ BU g but not KB ⊧ g. • Let h be the first atom added to C that is not true in every model of KB. • In particular, suppose I is a model of KB in which h isn’t true • There must be a clause in KB of form h b1 ... bn where each bi is true in I. • Because h is false in I, this clause is false in I. Slide 24 • Therefore I is not a model of KB => Contradiction Completeness of BU: general idea • Generic completeness of proof procedure: If G is logically entailed by the KB (KB ⊧ G) then G can be proved by the BU procedure (KB ⊦BU G) Sketch of our proof: 1. Suppose KB ⊧ G. Then G is true in all models of KB. 2. Thus G is true in any particular model of KB 3. We will define a model (called minimal model) so that if G is true in that model, G is proved by the bottom up algorithm. 4. Thus KB ⊦ G. Slide 25 Completeness of BU: general idea We define a specific model of our KB, in which • every atom in C at the end of BU is true • every other atom is false This is called minimal model All atoms = {a, b, c, d,e, f, g} C = {e,d, c, f,} Minimal Model = a=F, b=F, c=T, d = T, e=T, f=T, g=F KB a ← e ∧ g. b ← f ∧ g. c ← e. f←c e. d. • Using this model, we’ll then show that, if KB ⊧ G, then G must be in C, that is If g is true in all models of KB (KB ⊧ g) then g C at the end of BU procedure (KB ⊦BU Slide g) 26 Definition The minimal model MM is the interpretation in which - every element of BU’s fixed point C is true - every other atom is false. Claim: MM is a model of KB Proof by contradiction: assume that MM is not a model of KB. • Then there must exist some clause in KB which is false in MM Like every clause in KB, it is of the form h ← b1 … bm (with m 0). • h ← b1 … bm can only be false in MM if each bi is true in MM and h is false in MM. Since each bi is true in MM, each bi must be in C as well. BU would add h to C, so h would be true in MM Contradiction! Thus, MM is a model of KB Slide 27 Completeness of bottom-up procedure If g is true in all models of KB (KB ⊧ g) then g C at the end of BU procedure (KB ⊦BU g) Direct proof based on minimal model: • • • • Suppose KB ⊧ g. Then g is true in all models of KB. Thus g is true in the minimal model. Thus g C at the end of BU procedure. Thus KB ⊦BU g. Done. KB ⊧ g implies KB ⊦BU g Slide 28 Summary for bottom-up proof procedure BU • BU is sound: it derives only atoms that logically follow from KB • BU is complete: it derives all atoms that logically follow from KB • Together: it derives exactly the atoms that logically follow from KB • And, it is efficient! • Linear in the number of clauses in KB Each clause is used maximally once by BU Slide 29 Learning Goals Up To Here • PDCL syntax & semantics - Verify whether a logical statement belongs to the language of propositional definite clauses - Verify whether an interpretation is a model of a PDCL KB. ‾ Verify when a conjunction of atoms is a logical consequence of a knowledge base • Bottom-up proof procedure • Define/read/write/trace/debug the Bottom Up (BU) proof procedure • Prove that the BU proof procedure is sound and complete Slide 30 Lecture Overview • Recap: Logic intro • Propositional Definite Clause Logic: Semantics • PDCL: Bottom-up Proof Slide 31 Next class (still section 5.2) • Soundness and Completeness of Bottom-up Proof Procedure • Using PDC Logic to model the electrical domain • Reasoning in the electrical domain Slide 32